Sociological Concept of Law
Sociological Concept of Law
Sociological Concept of Law
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless
you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you
may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.
Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at
http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=black.
Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Cardiff University and Blackwell Publishing are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend
access to Journal of Law and Society.
http://www.jstor.org
JOURNALOFLAW & SOCIETY
VOLUMEIO, NUMBER2 WINTER1983
0263-323 X $3.00
The terms jurisprudence and sociology of law are too vague and refer to
too many diverse objectives and methods of legal analysis to allow
generalisation. For that reason I propose to use a distinction between
normative legal theory - which I take to be a centrally important part of
the territory of contemporary jurisprudence, in a sense its heart - and
empirical legal theory, which I take to be central to the concerns of the
sociology of law. By normative legal theory I mean theory which seeks to
explain the character of law solely in terms of the conceptual structure of
legal doctrine and the relationships between rules, principles, concepts and
values held to be presupposed or incorporated explicitly or implicitly
within it. By empirical legal theory I mean theory which seeks to explain
*
Faculty of Laws, Queen Mary College, London.
241
the character of law in terms of historical and social conditions and treats
the doctrinal and institutional characteristics of law emphasized in norma-
tive legal theory as explicable in terms of their social origins and effects.
a) Juridical Monism
Sociological concepts of law fall into three broad categories, the last of
which needs to be further subdivided. In the first category, law is under-
stood in terms of lawyers' conventional definitions of law. In contemporary
Western societies, therefore, as in many others, law is understood to be, in
essence, the law of the state as recognised by lawyers and state courts and
enforced by state agencies. Whatever the position in stateless societies, in
politically organised societies the effect of this conceptualisation of law is
to remove by definition many problems of the relationship between law
and state. If for Kelsen the state is merely the legal order seen from a
particular point of view[6], for many Marxist analysts law has been the
state seen from a particular viewpoint, or a technical apparatus of state
power. As such, while the state has long constituted an important focus of
Marxist concern, law has, until relatively recently, been of little interest; an
empirical theory of law has seemed unnecessary when knowledge of law is
seen to depend solely on a proper understanding of the nature of the
state.[7] Even contemporary Marxist analyses - whether based in
commodity form, state derivation or relative autonomy theories - of law
in advanced capitalist societies do not consider the possibility or utility of
conceptualising law as potentially or actually wider in scope than lawyer's
law or the law created, interpreted and enforced by what can be under-
244
stood in common-senseterms as state agencies.[8] Conventionaldefini-
tions generallyappear adequate in a traditionof inquirywhich does not
include law as such among its primarytheoreticallyspecified objects of
analysis.
Manynon-Marxistsociologicalapproachesto legal studyadopt a similar
conception of law. Donald Black, who in other respects offers a radical
behaviouralistcritiqueof lawyers'conceptionsof law as doctrine,characte-
riseslew as governmentalsocial control,the normativelife of a state andits
citizens.[9] Adam Podgorecki preserves a practicaldefinition of law as
lawyer,,'law alongsidea theoreticaldefinitionin widerterms.[10] Roberto
Unger[11]offers three concepts of law arrangedin a historicalmatrixof
modernization.Modern law in this view is the official and autonomous
legal orderof the modernstate. In Parsons'majorwritingson law[12],law
is assumed to be the lawyers' law of politically organised societies, a
distinct species of social norms. In these lawyers'law conceptionsother
normativesystemsin a society may be seen as deriveddirectlyor indirectly
from law, or as created or maintainedby "delegation"from it[13], or as
sources influencingthe content of law. They are, however, distinctfrom
and ultimatelysubordinateto it.
b) Juridical Pluralism
It might be thought that these standpointson the concept of law are in
many respects obvious and realistic. Yet even in contemporaryconven-
tional Western usage law refers not only to state law but also to the law
createdand appliedby internationalagenciesand to transnationalreligious
law (e.g. canonlaw) and historicallyit has includednumerousformsof law
(customary, territorial, mercantile, personal, ecclesiastical etc.) whose
creation,interpretationand enforcementhas not in any way dependedon
state agencies. Such usage has undoubtedlyinfluenceda second kind of
sociological conceptualisation of law which emphasises "juridical
pluralism".[14]The essence of these concepts of law is that state or
lawyers'law is only one form of law and is not necessarilyto be seen in
sociological terms as dominant. Law exists in various layers or levels
(Gurvitch); it may exist in associations (Gierke, Ehrlich), institutions
(Romano, Hauriou) or social systems of various size and nature. Social
groupsof whateversize may be seen as havingthe same fundamentallegal
needs (Llewellyn). Law may be seen as including unofficial as well as
official and intuitive as well as positive forms (Petrazycki).[15]
What is the significanceof such conceptualisations?Invariablyit is to
claim through the very definition of law that legal ideas and the fun-
damental problems of legal thought with which lawyers are familiarin
some sense pervadesocial life. Thus in Gurvitch'swork a phenomenolog-
ical approachto analysisof law is suggestedby the very definitionof the
juridical sphere. If the state law conception emphasizes the political
importanceof law and the relationshipbetween law and the power of the
state, the juridicalpluralismconceptiontends to stressthe pervasivesocial
245
importanceof legal ideas as responsesto fundamentalproblemsof social
interactionquite independentof the state yet developed at one particular
level in the political life of the state. The fundamentalproblem of most
such pluralistapproachesis that of explainingthe relationshipbetween
levels of law.[16] Hence these conceptsseem to manywritersto be wholly
inadequateto confront the political dimensionsof law, while for others
they imaginativelyopen up the possibilities of interpretingits complex
social dimensions.
DISCUSSION
247
sophisticationin relation to lawyers' law. Some of these problems may
indeed be absent in some other normativesystems. And the specification
of whichof these foci of analysisare centraland whichperipheralto legal
study extending to normativeorders other than state law will depend in
part on the choice of a particularconceptof law. Yet to widen the concept
of law beyond the lawyer'sview of it is to assertthe sociologicalnecessity
of consideringthe possibilitythat legal thoughtor legal processesin various
empiricallyanalysableformsmay be a relativelypervasivefeatureof social
life ratherthan isolated phenomenaof a narrowprofessionalsphere.
The sociology of law may well be best served at the presentstage of its
developmentby a pluralityof approachesto the problemof the conceptof
law. Indeed, it is implicitin whatwas said earlierabout the varietyof aims
of writersin this field that this pluralityis probablyinevitablequite apart
from any question of its desirability. Yet increasing interest in both
phenomenologicaland anarchistapproachesto legal analysissuggests a
reorientationtowards a serious concern with non-state law systems of
regulationin contemporaryWestern societies and with the processes of
social rule formationquite apart from formal law-creatingprocesses.[26]
If, however,the dominantconceptof law in contemporarysociologyof law
remainsthe state-lawconcept the dangeris that the problemsof lawyers'
law may be seen as analyticallydistinct from those of other actual and
potential regulatorysystems. Thus the withering away of law can be
foretold, by some writers,without serious considerationof the possibility
that, like hydra-heads,law and its problems and consequencesmay be
chopped off in their most visible forms (as state law) only to remain or
reappearin other regions of social life which they in fact pervade.
The problemsof an uncompromisingjuridicalpluralismwhich accords
no theoretical primacy to state law have been clearly stated in the
literature[27],and touchedon above. The cruciallyimportantrelationship
between law and state is often treated only peripherallygiven such a
conceptual approach, and the relationshipbetween state law and other
forms of normativeorder remainsan unsolvedproblem.A useful concept
of law today must surely treat lawyers'.law as central, a primaryfocus of
analysis.Yet if analysisis to be developed to explore fully the reach into
society of law as both an instrumentof and a formalisationof powerand as
an ideologicalphenomenon,there seem good groundsfor makingcentral
the hypothesisthat legal thinkingis not merelylawyers'thinking,and that
the characteristicswhich the sociology of law identifies in state legal
institutionsmay not be uniqueto them. One consequenceof this mightbe
to avoid utopianthinkingwhichsuggestswithoutempiricaldemonstration
that the featuresof state law and its institutionswhichthe sociologyof law
identifies will not be replicatedin variousways in informalregulatoryor
adjudicatoryprocesses,or in social systems(e.g. regions,collectives,auto-
nomous or semi-autonomoussocial organisationsor groups)smallerthan
those of the nation state which forms the typical unit of modern legal
jurisdiction.[28]Another consequence might be to raise seriously the
248
possibility that the experience of forms of social organisation quite sepa-
rate from the official state legal system may yield insights into problems of
normative order which are typically considered only in relation to state or
lawyers' law.[29] The experience of "simpler" legal orders of simpler social
systems than that of the nation state may offer legal insights in a manner
somewhat parallel to the insights into complex societies which anthropo-
logists have often claimed as one special justification for the study of
relatively simple societies.
These kinds of considerations suggest links between aspects of the con-
cerns of the sociology of law and of the sociology of organisations. Indeed,
at one stage in the recent development of the sociology of law influences
from this other field of social research were manifest.[30] Interestingly a
recent survey of problems of the field of the sociology of organisations has
called for a reorientation of emphases to take account of the increasing
importance of phenomenological perspectives and other recent develop-
ments in theory.[31] Thus Peter Manning notes the failure of sociological
studies to find a way of specifying in objective terms the nature of organis-
ations and calls for a recognition of the importance of the conceptions of
the organisation held by those participating in it. Occupational culture is
thus of great importance. It provides the image of the organisation for
those involved in it; "the framework around which organisational work is
legitimated".[32] It acts as a "grid or screen by which events are defined
and also makes relevant internal rules". [33] Using empirical data on police
organisation as a foundation for analysis, Manning identifies three ele-
ments which constitute occupational culture: principles (the most abstract
statement of culture), working rules ("by which the principles are transl-
ated into the everyday negotiated bases for work"[34]) and actual work
practices. He goes so far as to set out a detailed code of such principles and
rules for the occupational culture of the police he studied in London and in
the United States. It is important to stress that an analysis in terms of the
relation of rules and principles offers only one possible and partial
approach to the problem of analysis of a structure of normative regulation.
Yet the parallel with more familiar issues of legal theory seems obvious.
From an entirely different point of view it might be asked whether a
sociology of law tied to lawyers' conventional definitions of law ties itself to
a form of regulation which may be gradually decreasing in importance.
Numerous forms of bureaucratic regulation and control seem to be
developing or to have developed in close alliance with orthodox legal forms
yet in substantial independence of the reach of analysis of the lawyer.
Much of the ai'alysis of rule and discretion in welfare provision, in prison
regimes and in regulation of the national economy and of particular public
and private enterprises is concerned in various ways with this matter. Much
social theory now foresees the gradual superseding of lawyers' law in its
familiar forms by a variety of technological mechanisms of administration
and control. Whether such analyses have merit is not relevant here.[35]
Neither can it be argued that the sociology of law can usefully consider all
249
aspects of any such transformation and all the varied forms of control
which have been discussed in recent critical literature.[36] Yet it can be
argued that the sociology of law must take sufficient account, as central to
its project, of forms of regulation going far beyond the boundaries of state
or lawyers' law: sufficient, that is, so as to be able to make assessments of
the nature of changes in patterns of regulation fundamentally important to
any judgment of the changing social significance of the lawyers' law of the
state.
The conclusion to which these arguments lead is that, in general terms, a
concept of law which treats state law as central to the concept of law in
modern industrialised societies, but treats certain other normative systems
in these societies as directly comparable and closely related theoretically
within a kind of regulatory continuum, is of particular utility for
confronting contemporary problems posed by theory and empirical
research in the sociology of law. My view, then, is that the kind of
institutional concepts of law discussed earlier which avoid both exclusive
concern with state law and also pure juridical pluralism, and treat state law
as central to but not the exclusive concern of analysis of law in contempor-
ary Western societies, are potentially fruitful.
This is a revised and expanded version of a paper delivered at a seminar at the University of
Edinburgh on February 11th 1983. I am grateful to the Edinburgh Department of Jurispru-
dence for the invitation to present these ideas and to all those who discussed them on that
occasion; also to Peter Fitzpatrick for his helpful comments on a subsequent draft.
[1] G. Gurvitch, Sociology of Law (1947) 7. Such objectives may offer the greatest prospect
of sympathetic support from lawyers at "the level of mutual service" (Willock (1974) 1
Brit. J. Law and Society 5-6) and help to disarm "powerful antagonists" (Gurvitch op.
cit. 1). See also J. Carbonnier, Sociologie juridique (1978) 369 ff.
[2] See e.g. A. Podgorecki, Law and Society (1974) 47, suggesting sociology of law as an
empirical replacement for jurisprudence. Eugen Ehrlich, Fundamental Principles of the
Sociology of Law (1936), following the tenets of the Freirechtslehre jurists, argues for
sociology of law partly as a substitute for conceptual analysis and partly as its scientific
basis (pp. 339-340). Meehl, "Law and the Fireside Inductions: Some Reflections of a
Clinical Psychologist" in Law, Justice and the Individual in Society (1977; ed. J. Tapp
and F. Levine) is typical of much writing from a psychological perspective. For an early
polemic emphasising the roots of this approach within "realist" jurisprudence see F.
Cohen, "Transcendental Nonsense and the Functional Approach" (1935) 35 Col. L.
252
Rev. 809; "Legal concepts are supernaturalentities which do not have a verifiable
existenceexcept to the eyes of faith" (p. 821).
[3] Cf. D. Nelken, "Sociologyof Law v. Socio-LegalStudies:The False Divide". Paper
presentedat Universityof Kent Conferenceon CriticalLegal ScholarshipApril 1981;
Nelken, "The 'Gap Problem'in the Sociologyof Law:A TheoreticalReview"(1981) 1
Windsor Yearbook of Access of Justice 35-61.
[4] See e.g., Lloyd, Introduction to Jurisprudence (4th ed. 1979) 50-51, 88-90; R. Summers,
"ProfessorFulleron Moralityand Law"in MoreEssaysin LegalPhilosophy(1971;ed.
R. Summers); Symposium on The Morality of Law (1965) 10 Villanova Law Rev. 631.
Cf. Summers,"ProfessorFuller'sJurisprudence andAmerica'sDominantPhilosophyof
Law"(1978)92 Harv. L. Rev, 433, where, in the courseof a sympatheticdiscussion,the
changingattitudeto Fuller'swork in recentcommentariesis noted.
[5] Especially The Behaviour of Law (1976).
[6] General Theory of Law and State (1945) 190-1.
[7] Pashukanis'work providesthe most interestingexceptionto this, where an attemptis
made to combinea Leninistconceptionof the state with a theoryof law derivedfrom
Marx'sanalysisof the fetishismof commodities.But the resultis a vagueandambiguous
analysisof the legal functionsof the state inappropriateto the politicalprojectof Soviet
Marxismat the time in which he wrote, and which providesa major reason for the
rejectionof the theoryin Marxistpolitics.See E.B. Pashukanis,GeneralTheoryof Law
and Marxism(1978)Ch. 5; R. Cotterrell,"CommodityFormandLegalForm:Pashuka-
nis' Outlineof a MaterialistTheoryof Law"(1979) Ideologyand ConsciousnessNo. 6
111-119.
[8] This despitethe fact that severalsophisticatedrecentMarxistanalysesof the state have
deliberatelyrejected its commonsense connotationof governmentagenciesin prefer-
ence for a conceptionwhichstressesthe pervasivenessof state controlsin the "private"
sphere. Most importantin this respect is the work of Poulantzasand Althusser,and
moderninterpretationsof Gramsci'sinsights.Law, however, tends to remainconcep-
tualised in these writings as lawyers' law applied by and to governmentagencies,
although,notablyin Althusser'sconceptof ideologicalstate apparatuses,its pervasive-
ness as ideology throughmany levels social relationsis accepted.
[9] Black,op. cit., 2, See also his "TheBoundariesof LegalSociology"(1972)81 YaleL. J.
1086, where the concept is held to be "moreinclusivethan an Americanlawyermight
deem proper"but to exclude such forms of social control as "bureaucraticrules in
privateorganisations".While the concept undoubtedlylacks precisionand in Black's
view can encompass"any act by a politicalbody that concernsthe definitionof social
order or its defence" it is clear that in research practice it functions as a strictly
behaviouralversionof the state law conception.
[10] Law and Society 46.
[11] Law in Modern Society (1976).
[12] For example, "The Law and Social Control"in Law and Sociology (1962; ed. W.M.
Evan); Societies (1966); The System of Modern Societies (1971).
[13] Carbonnier,op. cit. 208.
[14] Ibid. 208-218; Carbonnier,Flexibledroit(5th ed 1983) 16-23.
[15] Gurvitch, op. cit., Ehrlich, op. cit., O.v. Gierke, Associations and Law (1977), Political
Theories of the Middle Age (1900), Natural Law and the Theory of Society (1958); S.
Romano, L'ordre juridique (1975); A. Broderick, ed The French Institutionalists:
Hauriou, Renard, Delos (1970); L.Petrazycki, Law and Morality (1955); K. Llewellyn,
253
"The Normative, the Legal and the Law-Jobs"(1940) 49 Yale L.J. 1355, and cf.
Llewellyn'sremarkson "folk-law"in "A RealisticJurisprudence- The Next Step"
(1930) 30 Col. L. Rev 431, 462-463.
[16] P. Fitzpatrick,"MarxismandLegalPluralism"(1982-3) 1 AustralianJournalof Lawand
Society No 2.
[17] M. Rheinstein ed., Max Weber on Law in Economy and Society (1954) 5.
[18] See also e.g. E.A. Hoebel, The Law of Primitive Man (1954) 26; A.R. Radcliffe-Brown,
"Primitive Law" in 9 Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences (1933) 202-206, and "Social
Sanction"in 13 ibid. (1934) 531-534.
[19] R. Abel, "A ComparativeTheoryof DisputeInstitutionsin Society"(1973)8 Law and
Society Rev. 217.
[20] See e.g. Abel, "ConservativeConflictand the Reproductionof Capitalism:The Role of
Informal Justice" (1981) 9 International Journal of the Sociology of Law 245; Z. Bank-
owski and G. Mungham,"Laypeopleand Lawpeopleand the Administrationof the
LowerCourts"ibid. 85. Cf. M. Cainand K. Kulcsar,"ThinkingDisputes:An Essayon
the Originsof the Dispute Industry"(1981) 16 Law and SocietyRev. 375.
[21] See e.g. P. Selznick, Law, Society and Industrial Justice (1969); J. Skolnick, Justice
Without Trial (2nd ed. 1975).
254
OrganizationalAnalysis"(1976)4 AmericanPoliticsQuarterly86, But presentconcerns
seem to be with organisationalproblemsof the state legal systemratherthan with the
regulatoryproblemsof organisationsanalysedas problemsrelevantto legal theory.
[31] P. K. Manning,"OrganisationalWork:Structurationof Environments"(1982)33 Brit-
ish Journalof Sociology 118.
[32] Ibid. 125.
[33] Ibid. 130.
[34] Ibid. 125.
[35] See e.g. D. Nelken, "Is There a Crisisin Law and LegalIdeology?"(1982)9 Journalof
Law and Society177.
[36] See especially Michel Foucault'svarious writings, T. Mathiesen, Law, Society and
PoliticalAction (1980) and J. Donzelot, The Policingof Families:WelfareVersusthe
State(1980).
[37] Pashukanis,op. cit, 83.
[38] Cf. R. B. Ferguson,"TheAdjudicationof CommercialDisputesandthe LegalSystemin
ModernEngland"(1980) 7 Brit. J. Law and Society141, 146.
[39] For a discussionof the significanceof these problemsfor legal theorysee R. Cotterrell,
"Conceptualizing Law:Problemsand Prospectsof ContemporaryLegalTheory"(1981)
10 Economyand Society348, 359-363.
[40] See especiallyP. Hirst, On Law and Ideology(1979) 22-39.
[41] Op. cit. 39.
[42] P. Bachrach& M. Baratz,Powerand Poverty:Theoryand practice(1970)
[43] S. Lukes, Power (1974) 23.
255