Measures Integration Nice
Measures Integration Nice
2 — Measures
Joel Feldman
1
2 Measures
2.1 A Problem
In an ideal world, we would like to be able to extend the definition “for all a ≤ b, the
length of the interval [a, b] is b − a” by assigning a size µ(E) to every subset E ⊂ R
with the properties that
(i) µ : P(R) = E E ⊂ R → [0, ∞]
(ii) Countable additivity: If Ei i∈N is a sequence of disjoint subsets of R, then
[ X
µ Ei = µ(Ei )
i∈N i∈N
(To get a union of finitely many sets, just make Ei = ∅ for most i’s.)
(iii) Translation invariance: For all E ⊂ R and y ∈ R
µ(E + y) = µ(E) where E + y = x+y x∈E
with the Nr ’s
◦ all disjoint and
◦ all having the same size. Say µ(Nr ) = µN , for all r.
Once we have done so, we will have
X X
1 = µ [0, 1) = µ Nr = µN
r∈Q∩[0,1) r∈Q∩[0,1)
(
0 if µN = 0
=
∞ if µN > 0
0 1
0 N 1 N +r Nr Nr
Then
(a) Nr ⊂ [0, 1) for each r ∈ Q ∩ [0, 1)
(b) if r, s ∈ Q ∩ [0, 1) with r 6= s, then Nr ∩ Ns = ∅ because
if y ∈ Nr , (i.e. y = x + r or x + r − 1 with x ∈ N)
and y ∈ Ns (i.e. y = x′ + s or x′ + s − 1 with x′ ∈ N)
then x − x′ = s − r + (−1 or 0 or 1) ∈ Q
which implies that x ∼ x′
and x 6= x′ (since r 6= s and 0 ≤ r, s < 1 so that −1 < s − r < 1)
so that N contains two different elements from the equivalence class [x]
which is a contradiction
1
An equivalence relation x ∼ y has the properties
x∼x
x ∼ y =⇒ y ∼ x
x ∼ y, y ∼ z =⇒ x ∼ z
2
We’re using the axiom of choice here.
2.2 σ-algebras
Let X be a nonempty set. We denote by P(X) the set of all subsets of X.
Definition 2.2 (Algebras). A nonempty collection A of subsets of X is an algebra
if
(i) A, B ∈ A =⇒ A ∪ B ∈ A
(ii) A ∈ A =⇒ Ac = X \ A ∈ A
5
The “G” stands for “Gebeit”, which is German for “neighbourhood” and the δ stands for
“Durchschnitt”, which is German for “intersection”.
6
The “F ” stands for “Fermé”, which is French for “closed” and the σ stands for “somme”, which
is French for “sum” or “union”.
=⇒ A ∈ M(E)
S
since ρ,σ∈Q
ρ<σ
is a countable union.
(ρ,σ)⊂A
(b), (c) The proofs of all three parts of (b) and (c) are very similar. The proof of
one of the three parts is problem #8 of Problem Set 1.
(d), (e) The proofs of all four parts
(d) and (e) are very similar.
Here is the proof of
′
the first part of (d). Let O = A ⊂ R A open and E = (a, ∞) a ∈ R .
• M(E ′) ⊂ BR :
E ′ ⊂ O ⊂ M(O) = BR =⇒ M(E ′ ) ⊂ BR
• BR ⊂ M(E ′ ): Let E = (a, b) a < b . We already know, by part (a), that
M(E) = BR , so it suffices to prove that E ⊂ M(E ′). Let α < β. Then
\ ∞
c 1
c
(α, β) = (−∞, β) ∩ (α, ∞) = [β, ∞) ∩ (α, ∞) = β − n, ∞ ∩ (α, ∞)
n=1
So (α, β) ∈ M(E ). Hence E ⊂ M(E ), so that, part (a), BR = M(E) ⊂ M(E ′).
′ ′
µ : M → [0, ∞]
such that
(i) µ(∅) = 0
(ii) If {Ej }j∈N ⊂ M is a countable collection of disjoint subsets of X, then
[ ∞
X
µ Ej = µ(Ej )
j∈N j=1
µ(E) = # points in E
Example 2.15 (point mass). If X is any set, x0 ∈ X, and M is any σ-algebra for
X, then (
1 if x0 ∈ E
µ(E) =
0 if x0 ∈/E
is called a point mass or Dirac measure at x0 .
Example 2.16. Let X be any set, M be any σ-algebra for X, and f : X → [0, ∞].
Then X
µ(E) = f (x) for all E ∈ M
x∈E
P
is a measure, if x∈E is interpreted appropriately. See the definition below.
P
Definition 2.17 (the meaning of f (x)). Let E be any set and f : E → [0, ∞].
x∈E
X
• If f (x) = ∞ for at least one x ∈ E, then f (x) = ∞
x∈E
For the rest of this definition, assume that f : E → [0, ∞). Set
P = x ∈ E f (x) > 0
X
• If P is a finite set, then f (x) is, of course, the sum of the finite number of
x∈E
(strictly positive) numbers in f (x) x ∈ P .
X N
X
f (x) = lim f (xn )
N →∞
x∈E n=1
The right hand side is independent of the choice of ordering. Note that the fact
that f (xn ) ≥ 0, for all n, is critical for this independence of ordering. See problem
#1 on Problem Set 2.
P
• If P is an uncountable set, then x∈E f (x) = ∞. This is reasonable because
there must existSan N ∈ N with PN = x ∈ E f (x) ≥ N1 infinite (because
P
otherwise P = N ∈N PN is countable) and any reasonable definition of f (x)
x∈E
should obey
P X X 1
f (x) ≥ f (x) ≥ =∞
x∈E x∈PN x∈P
N
N
• If
S E1 , E2 , E3 , · · · are all countable, except for Ej0 , which is co-countable, then
j∈N Ej is co-countable so that
=1 =0
X z }| { X z }| { S
µ(Ej ) = µ(Ej0 ) + µ(Ej ) = 1 and µ j∈N j = 1
E
j∈N j∈N
j6=j0
(c) Writing
∞
[ S
∞
En = E1 ∪ j=2 Ej \ Ej−1
n=1
we have
S ∞
X
∞
µ n=1 En = µ(E1 ) + µ Ej \ Ej−1
j=2
Sn
µ E
j=1 j
z n
X
}| {
= lim µ(E1 ) + µ Ej \ Ej−1
n→∞
j=2
= lim µ(En )
n→∞
Subtracting µ(En ) from both sides of µ(E1 ) = µ(En ) + µ(E1 \ En ) (which we are
allowed to do only because we know that µ(En ) is finite), we have µ(E1 \ En ) =
µ(E1 ) − µ(En ) and hence
S
µ ∞ n=1 n = lim µ(E1 ) − µ(En ) = µ(E1 ) − lim µ(En )
F (∗)
n→∞ n→∞
As Fn = E1 ∩ Enc ,
we have
∞
[ S T c T
∞ c ∞ ∞
Fn = E1 ∩ E
n=1 n = E1 ∩ E
n=1 n = E1 \ E
n=1 n
n=1
but ∞
\ T
∞
En = ∅ so that µ n=1 En =0
n=1
Definition 2.22. Let (X, M, µ) be a measure space.
(a) A null set is a set E ∈ M with µ(E) = 0.
(b) If f : X → {true, false} is a statement about points of X and
µ x ∈ X f (x) = false =0
then we say that f is true almost everywhere (with respect to µ). It is
standard to abbreviate “almost everywhere” by “a.e.”.
N ∈ M, µ(N) = 0, Z ⊂ N =⇒ Z ∈ M
So it is possible that µ(Z) is not defined, even though it ought to be zero. That’s
silly.
Here is an extreme example of this.
The entire world has size zero, and yet not a single nontrivial subset has a defined
size.
Z ⊂ N ∈ M, µ(N) = 0 =⇒ Z ∈ M
The following theorem says that the silliness of Remark 2.23 can always be fixed —
any measure can be completed.
Then
(a) M is a σ-algebra.
(b) µ̄ is a well-defined, complete measure on M, called the completion of µ.
(c) µ̄ is the unique extension of µ to M. That is, µ̄ is the unique measure with
domain of definition M that obeys µ̄(E) = µ(E) for all E ∈ M.
X
N′
E
N
Z
Z′
• µ̄ is well-defined :
Let
E, E ′ ∈ M, Z ⊂ N ∈ N, Z′ ⊂ N ′ ∈ N with E ∪ Z = E ′ ∪ Z ′
X=R
S = {∅, R} ∪ (a, b) a, b ∈ R, a < b ∪ (a, ∞), (−∞, a) a ∈ R
ρ(∅) = 0 ρ (a, b) = b − a ρ (a, ∞) = ρ (−∞, a) = ρ R = ∞
so that
nP S∞ o
∗ ∞
µ (B) = inf j=1 ρ(Sj ) Sj j∈N ⊂ S, B ⊂ j=1Sj
nP S∞ o
∞
≥ inf j=1 ρ(S j ) S j j∈N ⊂ S, A ⊂ S
j=1 j = µ∗ (A)
• Countable subadditivity
◦ Let ε > 0. Let, for each n ∈ N, A(n) ⊂ X with µ∗ (A(n) ) < ∞. (The other case
is trivial.)
(n) S (n)
◦ For each n ∈ N, there exists Sj j∈N ⊂ S such that A(n) ⊂ ∞ j=1 Sj and
P∞ (n) ∗
j=1 ρ(Sj ) ≤ µ (A
(n)
) + 2εn .
(n) S S (n)
◦ Then Sj j,n∈N ⊂ S and n∈N A(n) ⊂ j,n∈N Sj so that
S ∞
∞
X (n)
X ε
µ∗ n=1 A
(n)
≤ ρ Sj ≤ µ∗ (A(n) ) + n
j,n∈N n=1
2
∞
X
=ε+ µ∗ (A(n) )
n=1
E
T
A S
Remark 2.30.
(a) That µ∗ (E) ≤ µ∗ (E ∩ A) + µ∗(E ∩ Ac ) is always true, by axiom (iii) of Definition
2.26.
(b) That µ∗ (E) ≥ µ∗ (E ∩ A) + µ∗ (E ∩ Ac ) is trivial for µ∗ (E) = ∞. So, to verify
that A is measurable, it suffices to verify µ∗ (E) ≥ µ∗ (E ∩ A) + µ∗ (E ∩ Ac ) for
all E with µ∗ (E) < ∞.
(c) We will show, in Problem Set 4 #2, that if µ∗ is induced from a premeasure
(to be defined - most of our measures will be) and if µ∗ (X) is finite, then A is
µ∗ -measurable if and only if µ∗ (A) + µ∗ (X \ A) = µ∗ (X).
Proof.
• Step 1 : M∗ is nonempty
since ∅ ∈ M∗ since µ∗ (E) = µ∗ (E ∩ ∅) + µ∗(E ∩ ∅c ) for all E ⊂ X.
| {z } | {z }
=0 =µ∗ (E)
• Step 2 : M∗ is closed under complements.
This is obvious since
A, B ∈ M∗ , E ⊂ X =⇒ µ∗ (E) ≥ µ∗ (E ∩ (A ∪ B)) + µ∗ (E ∩ Ac ∩ B c )
(using Ẽ ∩ (A ∪ B) as E)
= µ∗ (Ẽ ∩ A) + µ∗ (Ẽ ∩ B) (∗)
(by subadditivity)
∗
≥ µ (E)
So
S∞both of the ≥’s in the last displayed equation must be equalities and
∗
j=1 Aj ∈ M .
• Step 6 : µ∗↾ M∗ is countably additive.
Just take E = X in Problem Set 3, #2.
• Step 7 : µ∗↾ M∗ is complete.
Let N ∈ M∗ with µ∗ (N) = 0 and let Z ⊂ N. We must show that Z ∈ M∗ ,
i.e. that µ∗ (E) = µ∗ (E ∩ Z) + µ∗ (E ∩ Z c ) for all E ⊂ X. So let E ⊂ X. Then
⊂N ⊂E
z }| { z }| {
µ∗ (E) ≤ µ∗ E ∩ Z + µ∗ E ∩ Z c
(∗∗)
≤ µ∗ (N) + µ∗ (E)
= µ∗ (E)
µ0 (∅) = 0
S X n
n
µ0 j=1 (aj , bj ] = (bj − aj ) for all − ∞ ≤ a1 < b1 < a2 < · · · < bn ≤ ∞
j=1
µ0 (∅) = 0
S X n
µ0 nj=1 (aj , bj ] = F (bj ) − F (aj ) for all − ∞ ≤ a1 < b1 < a2 < · · ·< bn ≤ ∞
j=1
Let’s think about what conditions we need to impose on the function F . Suppose
that we succeed in extending µ0 to a measure µ. I.e. suppose that we find a
σ-algebra M and a measure µ with
(i) A ⊂ M
(ii) µ(A) = µ0 (A) for all A ∈ A.
Then
= µ(∅) = 0
and
∞
X
F (0) − F (−∞) = µ0 (−∞, 0] = µ − ∞, 0] = µ (−j − 1, −j]
j=0
∞
X ∞
X
= µ0 (−j − 1, −j] = F (−j) − F (−j − 1)
j=0 j=0
n−1
X
= lim F (−j) − F (−j − 1)
n→∞
j=0
= lim F (0) − F (−n)
n→∞
n
n[ o
A = {∅} ∪ (aj , bj ] n ∈ N, −∞ ≤ a1 < b1 < a2 < · · · < bn ≤ ∞
j=1
µ0 (∅) = 0
S X n
n
µ0 j=1(aj , bj ] = F (bj )−F (aj )
j=1
for all n ∈ N, −∞ ≤ a1 < b1 < a2 < b2 < · · · < bn ≤ ∞
Proof.
• Step 1 : A is an algebra
◦ A is closed under complements
since ∅c = (−∞, ∞] and
S c
n
(a ,
j=1 j j b ] = (−∞, a1 ] ∪ (b1 , a2 ] ∪ · · · (bn−1 , an ] ∪ (bn , ∞]
• Step 2 : µ0 (∅) = 0
by hypothesis.
• Step 3 : µ0 is countably additive where defined.
′
S∞
Let {Im }m∈N ⊂ A with Im ∩ Im′ = ∅ for P∞m 6
= m , and with I = m=1 Im being
in A. We have to show that µ0 (I) = m=1 µ0 (Am ).
The reason that this is not trivial
is that {Im }m∈N could contain a countable
1 1
collection α + 2n+1 , α + 2n , n ≥ n0 , of shorter and shorter intervals that
“accumulate at α ∈ I”. Furthermore, there can be a countable number of
different such “accumulation” points in I.
So
≤F (b) ≤0 ≤0
n
X z }| { z }| {z }| {
µ0 (Im ) = F (bn ) −F (an ) + F (bn−1 ) −F (an−1 ) + F (bn−2 )
m=1 ≤0 ≤−F (a)
z }| { z }| {
· · · −F (a2 ) + F (b1 ) −F (a1 )
≤ F (b) − F (a) = µ0 (I)
P
This is true for all n, so that µ0 (I) ≥ ∞ m=1 µ0 (Im ).
P∞
◦ Step 3b: µ0 (I) ≤ m=1 µ0 (Im ) if a, b are finite
Here is our strategy. Let ε > 0.
· We want to use compactness to replace the infinite sum by a finite sum.
By compactness, any cover by open sets of a compact set has a finite
subcover.
· But I = (a, b] is not compact, so replace it by [a + δ, b] with δ > 0 chosen
so that F (a + δ) − F (a) < ε.
· And Im = (am , bm ] is not open. So replace it by am , bm + δm with
δm > 0 chosen so that F (b + δm ) − F (bm ) < 2εm .
P
· Using compactness, P we will extract a finite subsum from ∞ m=1 µ0 (Im )
that obeys µ0 (I) ≤ j µ0 (Ij ) + 2ε. That will do it.
Here we go.
Then
(a) µ∗ ↾ A = µ0 . That is, µ∗ extends µ0 . That is, µ∗ (A) = µ0 (A) for all A ∈ A.
(b) M ⊂ M∗ and µ ≡ µ∗ ↾ M is a measure that extends µ0 . That is, all sets in
M(A) are µ∗ -measurable and µ(A) = µ0 (A) for all A ∈ A.
(c) If ν is any other9 measure on M such that ν ↾ A = µ0 , then
ν(B) ≤ µ(B) for all B ∈ M
ν(B) = µ(B) if B ∈ M is µ-σ-finite. That is, if B is a countable union of
sets of finite µ-measure.
∞ ⊂A n ∞
X z}|{ X
µ0 (A) = µ0 Bn ≤ µ0 (An )
n=1 n=1
S∞
This is true for any choice of An n∈N
⊂ A with A ⊂ n=1 An , so µ0 (A) ≤ µ∗ (A).
(b) By Carathéodory (Theorem 2.31), M∗ is a σ-algebra and the restriction of µ∗ to
M∗ is a measure. So it suffices to prove that every A ∈ A is µ∗ -measurable.
Let A ∈ A and E ∈ P(X). Let ε > 0. By the definition of µ∗ , there exist
9
See Problem Set 4, #4 for an example of multiple extensions.
µ(A ∩ B c ) ≤ ε
Hence
∈A
S
z }| { S S
n n n
µ(B) ≤ µ(A) = lim µ j=1 Aj = lim µ 0 j=1 Aj = lim ν j=1 Aj
n→∞ n→∞ n→∞
c c
= ν(A) = ν(B) + ν(A ∩ B ) ≤ ν(B) + µ(A ∩ B )
≤ ν(B) + ε
As this is true for all ε > 0, we have µ(B) = ν(B).
∞
X ∞
X
µ(B) = µ(Bn ) = ν(Bn ) = ν(B)
n=1 n=1
Then µF (S) = 0 for all S ⊂ (−∞, 0). In particular every S ⊂ (−∞, 0) is null and
hence measurable. So there are lots of sets that are measurable, but not Borel. On
the other hand the set N ⊂ [0, 1) of Problem set 3, #4 is not measurable. So not all
subsets are measurable.
When faced with such a choice, in this example, we always avoid terminal 1’s (so we
express 31 as 0.0222 · · · rather than 0.1000 · · · ) and keep terminal 2’s (so we express
2
3
as 0.2000 · · · rather than 0.1222 · · · ). Given x ∈ [0, 1] we can generate the xn ’s
inductively by the algorithm
Set n = 0, xn = 0.
n
P
Set εn = x − xp 3−p .
p=0
1
Observe that 0 ≤ εn ≤ 3n
.
1
0 if 0 ≤ εn ≤ 3n+1
1 2
Set xn+1 = 1 if 3n+1 < εn < 3n+1
2 3 1
2 if 3n+1 ≤ εn ≤ 3n+1 = 3n
n = 0 → n + 1.
z 0.1000···
}| {
1/3 = 0.0222 · · · ∈ C
not 000 · · ·
z or 2222
}| · · · {
x ∈ (1/3, 2/3) = 0.1 x2 x3 x4 · · · ∈ /C
2/3 = 0.2000 · · · ∈ C
We have that C is
· compact (C is [0, 1] with an open set removed)
· nowhere dense, i.e. the interior of its closure is empty, i.e. if x ∈ C̄ = C, ε > 0,
then (x − ε, x + ε) 6⊂ C
· totally disconnected, i.e. the only connected subsets are single points (if α < β
were both in a connected subset, then we would have (α, β) ⊂ C, which doesn’t
happen)
· uncountable (by the same argument as for R)
· of Lebesgue measure zero because
m(C) = m [0, 1] − m (1/3, 2/3) − m (1/9, 2/9) + m (7/9, 8/9) − · · ·
1 2 4
=1− − − −···
3 9 27
∞
X 2n 1 1
=1− = 1−
n=0
3 n+1 3 1 − 23
=0
Remark 2.40.
(a) We can generalize this. Let αj j∈N
⊂ (0, 1). Then
(1) Start with [0, 1]. (measure 1)
(2) Remove the middle α1th . (measure 1 − α1 )
(3) Remove the middle α2th of the remaining pieces. (measure (1 − α1 )(1 − α2 ))
(4) And so on.
This gives a set of measure
∞ n
( )
Y Y n
P
(1 − αj ) = lim (1 − αj ) = lim exp ln(1 − αj )
n→∞ n→∞ j=1
j=1 j=1
so that
∞ ∞ ∞ n
X X X εo
ν(E) ≤ µ (an , b′n ) ≤ µ (an , b′n ] ≤ µ (an , bn ] + n
n=1 n=1 n=1
2
( ∞
)
X
= µ (an , bn ] +ε
n=1
≤ µ(E) + 2ε
and ∞
X
ν̃(E) ≤ µ(O) ≤ µ (an , bn ) ≤ µ(E) + ε
n=1
Proof.
• Proof that (a) ⇐⇒ (c):
This is Problem Set 5, #4(b).
• Proof that (b) =⇒ (a):
As V is Gδ it is in BR ⊂ Mµ . As µ∗ (N1 ) = 0, N1 is µ∗ -measurable (see part (c)
of Carathéodory, Theorem 2.31) and hence is in Mµ . So E = V ∩ N1c ∈ Mµ .
• Proof that (a) =⇒ (b):
By Theorem 2.41(b), there is, for each k ∈ Z and j ∈ N, an open set Oj,k
such that E ∩ (k, k + 1] ⊂ Oj,k and
1
µ(Oj,k ) ≤ µ E ∩ (k, k + 1] +
2j+|k|
1
=⇒ µ E ∩ (k, k + 1] + µ Oj,k \ E ∩ (k, k + 1] ≤ µ E ∩ (k, k + 1] +
2j+|k|
1
=⇒ µ Oj,k \ E ∩ (k, k + 1] ≤
2j+|k|
Set open
covers E
∞
\ z[ }| {
V = Oj,k ∈ Gδ
j=1 k∈Z