Complete Epistemology 1st Edition Richard Feldman PDF For All Chapters
Complete Epistemology 1st Edition Richard Feldman PDF For All Chapters
Complete Epistemology 1st Edition Richard Feldman PDF For All Chapters
com
https://ebookname.com/product/epistemology-1st-edition-
richard-feldman/
OR CLICK BUTTON
DOWNLOAD EBOOK
https://ebookname.com/product/epistemology-1st-edition-richard-
fumerton/
https://ebookname.com/product/the-epistemology-of-development-
evolution-and-genetics-richard-burian/
https://ebookname.com/product/doubt-conviction-and-the-analytic-
process-selected-papers-of-michael-feldman-1st-edition-michael-
feldman/
https://ebookname.com/product/the-messages-we-send-social-
signals-and-storytelling-1st-edition-g-r-f-ferrari/
The Complete Proficiency Practice Tests 1 Self Study
Edition With Key May Peter.
https://ebookname.com/product/the-complete-proficiency-practice-
tests-1-self-study-edition-with-key-may-peter/
https://ebookname.com/product/guide-to-health-informatics-3rd-
edition-enrico-coiera/
https://ebookname.com/product/movement-and-experimentation-in-
young-children-s-learning-deleuze-and-guattari-in-early-
childhood-education-1st-edition-liselott-mariett-olsson/
https://ebookname.com/product/the-edinburgh-companion-to-
twentieth-century-philosophies-first-edition-constantin-v-ed-
boundas/
https://ebookname.com/product/a-linguistic-analysis-of-
diplomatic-discourse-un-resolutions-on-the-question-of-
palestine-1st-edition-germana-dacquisto/
The Cambridge Companion to Boethius Cambridge
Companions to Philosophy 1st Edition John Marenbon
https://ebookname.com/product/the-cambridge-companion-to-
boethius-cambridge-companions-to-philosophy-1st-edition-john-
marenbon/
Prentice Hall
Foundations of Philosophy Series
Richard Feldman
University ofRochester
BD161.F385 2003
121—dc21
2002042533
10 9 8
ISBN 0-13-341L45-3
Kinds of Knowledge 8
Knowledge and True Belief 12
The Traditional Analysis of Knowledge 15
Real Knowledge and Apparent Knowledge 22
Conclusion 23
Evidentialism 41
The Infinite Regress Argument 49
Cartesian Foundationalism 52
VI Contents
Coherentism 60
Modest Foundationalism 70
Index 195
Foundations
of Philosophy
I wish to express my indebtedness to a great many people with whom I have dis
cussed epistemological issues. I first learned about epistemology when I sat in
on the lectures in an epistemology course taught by my brother, Fred Feldman.
That course initiated what has become an enduring interest and also taught me
much of what I know about how to do philosophy. My interest and under
standing were greatly enhanced by a series of seminars with Herbert Heidel-
berger and Roderick Chisholm. I would not have been able to write this book
were it not for what I have learned from countless discussions of philosophy with
John Bennett, David Braun, Stewart Cohen, Jonathan Vogel, Ed Wierenga, and
especially Earl Conee. Todd Long, Dan Mittag, Nathan Nobis, Jim Pryor, Bruce
Russell, Harvey Siegel, and Matthias Steup all gave me helpful comments on
some or all of the manuscript. Many students, who endured courses making use
of preliminary drafts, have provided useful guidance.
And thanks also to Andrea, for helping me to persevere, and for everything
else as well.
ix
CHAPTER ONE
Epistemological
Questions
A. What We Know
Most of us think we know quite a lot. The following list identifies some general
categories of these things and gives examples of each. The categories may over
lap, and they are far from precise. Still, they give us a good idea of the sorts of
things we can know.
i. Morality:
“Gratuitous torturing of infants is wrong.”
“There’s nothing wrong with taking a break from work once in a while.”
j. The future:
“The sun will rise tomorrow.”
“The Chicago Cubs will not win the World Series next year.”1
k. Religion:
“God exists.”
“God loves me.”
There are, of course, many things in each of these categories that we do not
know. Some facts about the distant past are irretrievably lost. Some facte about
the future are, at least for now, beyond us. Some of the areas of knowledge on
the list are controversial. You may have doubts about our knowledge in the
areas of morality and religion. Still, the list provides a fair sampling of the sorts
of things we typically claim to know.
Thus, the first thesis within The Standard View is
B. Sources of Knowledge
If (SV1) is right, then there are some ways we come to know the things it says
we know; there are some sources for our knowledge. For example, if we know
about our immediate environment, then perception and sensation play a cen
tral role in acquiring this knowledge. Memory obviously is crucial in our knowl
edge of the past and also in certain aspects of our knowledge of current facts.
For example, my knowledge that the tree that I see through my window is a
maple relies on my perception of the tree and my memory of the way maples
look. Another source of much of our knowledge is the testimony of others. Tes
timony is not here restricted to statements made on the witness stand under
oath. It is much broader than that. It includes what other people tell you, in
cluding what they tell you on television or in books and newspapers.
Three other sources of knowledge deserve brief mention here as well. If per
ception is our awareness of external things through sight, hearing, and the
other senses, then perception does not account for our knowledge of our own
internal states. You may now know that you feel sleepy, or that you are think
ing about what you will do on the weekend. But this is not by means of per
ception in the sense just given. It is, rather, introspection. So this is another
potential source of knowledge.
Next, sometimes we know things by reasoning or inference. When we know
some facts and see that those facts support some further fact, we can come to
know that further fact. Scientific knowledge, for example, seems to arise from
inferences from observational data.
Finally, it seems that we know some things simply because we can “see” that
they are true. That is, we have the ability to think about things and to discern cer
tain simple truths. Though this is a matter of some controversy, our knowledge
4 Epistemological Questions
of elementary arithmetic, simple logic, and conceptual truths seems to fall into
this category. For lack of a better term, we will say that we know these things by
means of rational insight.
Our list of sources of knowledge, then, looks like this:
a. Perception
b. Memory
c. Testimony
d. Introspection
e. Reasoning
f. Rational insight
One might think that it is a matter of how sure a person feels about something
or whether there is general agreement about the matter. As we will see, these
are not good answers to (QI). Something else distinguishes knowledge from its
opposite. (QI), it turns out, is surprisingly hard, controversial, and interesting.
Working out an answer to it involves thinking through some difficult issues.
This will be the focus of Chapters 2 and 3.
According to many philosophers, an important condition on knowledge is
rational or justified belief. To know something requires something along the
lines of having a good reason to believe it, or coming to believe it in the right
sort of way, or something like that. You do not know something if you are just
guessing, for example. This leads us to a second question, one that has been cen
tral to epistemology for many years:
And this will lead us to further questions about the alleged sources of knowl
edge. How do these faculties enable us to satisfy the conditions of knowledge?
How could they yield epistemic justification? This will be the focus of Chapters
4 and 5, as well as parts of Chapters 7-9.
Our beliefs obviously play a central role in determining our behavior. You will
behave very differently toward your neighbor if you believe that she is a trust
worthy friend rather than a dishonest enemy. Given the ability of beliefs to af
fect our behavior, it seems clear that your beliefs can affect your life and the lives
of others. Depending upon your career and the extent to which others depend
upon you, you may have obligations to know about certain things. For exam
ple, a medical doctor ought to know about the latest developments in her spe
cialty. Sometimes, however, knowledge can be a bad thing, as when one learns
of an apparent friend’s disloyalty. These considerations suggest that practical
and moral issues interact with epistemological issues in ways that merit exami
nation. Thus,
04. Do we really have any knowledge at all? Is there any good response
to the arguments of the skeptics?
(Q4) asks, in effect, whether the conditions spelled out in response to (QI)
are actually satisfied. Advocates of The Skeptical View hold that the answer to
each of the questions in (Q4) is “No.” They are inclined to deny both (SV1) and
(SV2).
The questions raised in (QI) through (Q6) are among the central problems in
epistemology. The chapters that follow will address them.
ENDNOTE
1. Cubs fans may not like this example. But those who follow baseball know that, no
matter what happens, the Cubs never win. Neither do the Boston Red Sox.
The Traditional
Analysis of Knowledge
The goal of the next few chapters is to try to get clearer about just what The Stan
dard View says and what implications it has. While doing this we will not call
into question the truth of The Standard View. We will assume that it is basically
correct, reserving discussion of challenges to our commonsense view until later.
I. KINDS OF KNOWLEDGE
The Standard View says that we have a good deal of knowledge and it says some
thing about the sources of that knowledge. One central aspect of getting clearer
about just what The Standard View amounts to is getting clearer on just what it
takes knowledge to be. The Standard View says that we do have knowledge, but
what is knowledge?
8
The Traditional Analysis of Knowledge 9
This list is far from complete. We could add sentences using phrases such as
“knows which,” “knows why,” and so on. But the list we have already will be
enough to bring out the main points to be made here.
2. Either the librarian knows that there is a book byj. D. Salinger in the
library or the librarian knows that there is no book by J. D. Salinger
in the library.3
In this respect, the librarian differs from a patron who does not know whether
there is a book by Salinger there. The patron does not know that there is a
book there and does not know that there is no book there.
The point just made about (1) can be generalized. For any person and any
proposition, the person knows whether the proposition is true just in case either
the person knows that it is true or the person knows that it is not true. A per
son who does not know whether it is true neither knows that it is true nor knows
that it is not.
10 The Traditional Analysis of Knowledge
We can express the point about the connection between (1) and (2) in terms
of a general definition, using the letter “S” to stand for a potential knower and
“p” to stand for a proposition:
is to say that the editor knew, with respect to some particular time, that Salinger’s
book would be published at that time, e.g., she knew that it would be published
in 1950 or that it would be published in 1951, etc. Those who were less knowl
edgeable than the editor were not in this position. For them, there was no time
such that they knew the proposition that the book would be published at that
time.
Again, we can generalize the idea and express it as a definition:
However, it is unlikely that all the things we say using the word knows can be
expressed in terms of propositional knowledge. Consider the first item on our
list: “S knows x.” You might think that to know someone or something is to
have propositional knowledge of some facts about that person or thing. Thus,
we might propose
It is likely that anyone you know is someone you know some facts about. But
knowing some facts about a person is not sufficient for knowing the person.
J. D. Salinger is a reclusive, but well-known, author. Many people do know some
facts about him: they know that he wrote The Catcher in the Rye. They may know
that he does not interact with a great many people. So they know facts about
him, but they do not know him. Thus, knowing a person is not the same as
knowing some facts about a person.
This shows that definition (D3) is not correct. It also illustrates another im
portant methodological point. The example shows that (D3) is not correct be
cause it is a counterexample to (D3): an example showing that the sides of the
definition do not always agree—one side can be true when the other is false.
A clear-cut counterexample refutes a proposed definition. By revising a defin
ition in response to counterexamples, it is possible to get a better understand
ing of the concepts under discussion.5
The counterexample to (D3) shows not only that (D3) is false but that it is not
even on the right track. We cannot make some minor change in order to fix things
up. It would not help to add that S knows lots of facts about x, or that S knows im
portant facts about x. You can have that sort of propositional knowledge and still
not know the person. Knowing x isn’t a matter of knowing facts about x. Instead,
it is a matter of being acquainted with x—having met x and perhaps remember
ing that meeting. No matter how many facts you know about a person, it does not
follow that you know that person. Knowing a person or a thing is being acquaint
ed with that person or thing, not having propositional knowledge about the per
son or thing. So not all knowing is propositional knowing.
Consider next “knowing how.” Suppose that there is a former expert skier
who, after a serious accident leaves him unable to ski, becomes a successful ski
coach. His success as a coach is largely the result of the fact that he is unusually
good at explaining skiing techniques to students. Does the coach know how to
ski? The answer seems to be ‘Yes.” A plausible explanation of this appeals to the
following definition:
This seems to show that “knowing how” can be defined in terms of proposi
tional knowledge.
12 The Traditional Analysis ofKnowledge
The ex-skier knows how to ski in the (D4a) sense, but not in the (D4b) sense.
Just the reverse is true of the young prodigy. So one kind of knowhow is propo
sitional knowledge, but another kind is not.
Co Conclusion
The attempt to explain all the different kinds of knowledge in terms of propo
sitional knowledge is unsuccessful. The most reasonable conclusion seems to
be that there are (at least) three basic kinds of knowledge: (1) propositional
knowledge, (2) acquaintance knowledge or familiarity, and (3) ability knowl
edge (or procedural knowledge).
Even though we cannot explain all knowledge in terms of propositional
knowledge, propositional knowledge does have a special status. We can explain
several other kinds of knowledge in terms of it. Furthermore, many of the most
intriguing questions about knowledge turn out to be questions about proposi
tional knowledge. It will be the focus of this book. And the point of this section
is mainly to get clear about the sort of knowledge that is the topic of our study.
It is propositional knowledge, or knowledge of facts.
People can feel very sure of things that are not true. You might feel sure
that Jefferson was the first president. You might think that you remember
being taught this in school. But you are mistaken about this. (Or your teacher
made a big mistake.) You might even claim to know that Jefferson was the first
president. But he was not the first president, and you do not know that he was.
This is because knowledge requires truth. You know a proposition only if it
is true.
There is a possible objection to the claim that knowledge requires truth. It
is illustrated by the following example:
If you are right when you say (4), then it is possible to know things that are not
true. You knew that the butler did it, but it was not true that the butler did it.
However, even though people sometimes say things such as (4), it is clear that
these things are not literally true. You did not know all along that the butler
did it. What was true all along was that you felt sure that the butler did it, or
something like that. By saying (4) you convey, in a slightly colorful way, that
you were surprised by the ending. But (4) is not true, and it does not show that
there can be knowledge without truth.
A second condition for knowledge is belief. If you know something, then
you must believe it or accept it. If you do not even think that something is true,
then you do not know it. We are using “belief” in a broad sense here: anytime
you take something to be true, you believe it. Believing thus includes hesitant
acceptance as well as fully confident acceptance. A good way to think about
this is to notice that when you consider a statement, you can adopt any of three
attitudes toward it: belief, disbelief, or suspension ofjudgment. As an analogy,
imagine yourself forced to say one of three things about a statement: “yes,”
“no,” or “no opinion.” You will say “yes” over a range of cases, including the
ones in which you are entirely confident of a statement and the ones in which
you merely think the statement is probably true. You will say “no” when you
think that the statement is definitely or probably false. And you will say “no
opinion” in the remaining cases. Similarly, as we are using the term here, “be
lief” applies to a range of attitudes. It is contrasted with disbelief, which in
volves a similar range, and suspension ofjudgment.
It is clear, then, that knowledge requires belief. If you do not even think that
a statement is true, then you do not know that it is true. There is, however, an
objection to this claim that deserves consideration. We sometimes talk in ways
14 The Traditional Analysis of Knowledge
that contrast knowledge and belief, suggesting that when you know something,
you do not believe it. To see this, consider the following example:
In saying (5), John seems to be saying that this is a case of knowledge and not
a case of belief. The suggestion is that if it is belief, then it is not knowledge. If
he is right, then belief is not a condition for knowledge.
However, again, this appearance is misleading. John surely does accept the
statement that his name is “John.” He does not reject that statement or have no
opinion about it. When he says (5), his point is that he does not merely believe
that his name is “John”; he can say something stronger—that he knows it. And
one of the ways we typically proceed in conversations is to avoid saying the
weaker or more modest thing when the stronger one is true as well. If your
friend were to say to you, “I believe that my name is John,’ ” this would suggest,
but not literally say, that he does not know it. There are many other examples
of the same phenomenon. Suppose that you are extremely tired, having worked
very hard for a long time. Someone asks if you are tired. You might respond by
saying something like:
Taken literally, what you say is false. You are tired. The point of your utterance
is to emphasize that you are not merely tired; you are exhausted. The same thing
goes on in (5). By saying (5), John is not really saying that he does not believe
the statement. So this example is not a counterexample to the thesis that knowl
edge requires belief.
We have now found two conditions for knowledge: To know something, you
must believe it and it must be true.
A little reflection should make it clear that (TB) is mistaken. There are lots
of times that a person has a true belief but does not have knowledge. Here is a
simple counterexample to (TB):
hunch that Denver will win. When the game is finally played, your hunch
turns out to have been correct. So you believed that Denver would win,
and your belief was true.
In Example 2.3 you believe that Denver will win, and this is true. But you did not
know that Denver would win. You just had a guess that turned out to be correct.
Some will say that the fact the belief in Example 2.3 is about the future ruins
the example. But we can easily eliminate that feature without undermining the
point. Suppose you do not watch the game, but instead go to a long movie.
When you get out of the movie, you know that the game is over. You now have
a belief about the past, namely that Denver won. And you are right. You still do
not know that they won. You are still right as a result of a lucky guess. But now
there are no complications having to do with beliefs about the future.
The objections to (TB) are not limited to cases of lucky guesses. Another
sort of example will illustrate the heart of the problem with (TB).
You did have a true belief that it would rain, but you lacked knowledge. (When
the rain starts, you might say, “I knew it would rain,” but you did not really know
it.) The reason you did not know in this case is not that you were guessing.
Your belief is based on some evidence—the weather report—so it is not simply
a guess. But this basis is not good enough for knowledge. What you need for
knowledge is something along the lines of very good reasons or a more reliable
basis, not just a potentially inaccurate weather report.
Philosophers often say that what is needed for knowledge, in addition to true
belief, is justification ior the belief. Exactly what justification amounts to is a mat
ter of considerable controversy. We will spend a good deal of time later in this
book examining this idea. But for now it will suffice to notice that in the examples
of knowledge that we put forth in Chapter 1, the believers had extremely good rea
sons for their beliefs. In contrast, in the counterexamples to (TB), you did not have
very good reasons and you could easily have been wrong. What is missing, then,
in the counterexamples to (TB) and is present in the examples of knowledge we
have described isjustification. This leads us to The Traditional Analysis ofKnowledge.
Something along these lines can be found in various sources, perhaps going
back as far as Socrates. In Plato’s dialogue Meno, Socrates says:
For true opinions, as long as they remain, are a fine thing and all they do is good, but
they are not willing to remain long; and they escape from man’s mind, so that they
are not worth much until one ties them down by (giving) an account of the reason
why. . . . After they are tied down, in the first place they become knowledge, and
then they r emain in place.7
Ao Belief
To believe something is to accept it as true. When you consider any statement,
you are faced with a set of alternatives: You can believe it, you can disbelieve it,
or you can suspend judgment about it. Recall that we are taking belief to include
a range of more specific attitudes, including hesitant acceptance and complete
conviction. Disbelief includes a corresponding range of negative attitudes to
ward a proposition. At any given time, if you consider a proposition, you will end
up adopting one of these three attitudes.10
For present purposes, think of disbelieving a proposition as being the same
thing as believing the negation (or denial) of that proposition. So disbelieving
that George Washington was the first president is the same as believing that it
is not the case that George Washington was the first president. Suspending
judgment about the proposition is to neither believe it nor disbelieve it.11
One additional point about belief deserves mention here. Suppose a French
child is taught that George Washington was the first president of the United
States. Thus, it becomes true that
7. Pierre believes that George Washington was the first president of the
United States.
The noteworthy thing here is that (7) can be true even if Pierre does not speak
a word of English. He does not have to understand the English sentence
“George Washington was the first president of the United States.” Presumably,
The Traditional Analysis ofKnowledge 17
he would express his belief using a French equivalent of this sentence. Pierre’s
American counterpart, Peter, might believe what Pierre does. Thus,
8. Peter believes that George Washington was the first president of the
United States.
Peter, we may assume, does not speak a word of French. So Peter and Pierre be
lieve the same thing, even though there is no sentence that they both accept.
How can this be?
One way to understand these matters is as follows. Sentences are used to ex
press certain thoughts or ideas. Philosophers use the word proposition to refer
to these items. The English sentence Peter uses and the French sentence Pierre
uses express the same proposition. Belief is fundamentally a relation to a propo
sition. So (7) can be true because Pierre believes the relevant proposition about
George Washington; (8) is true because Peter believes that same proposition.
But they would use different sentences to express that proposition.
There are, then, two important points to extract from this: Sentences differ
from the propositions they are used to express, and belief is fundamentally an
attitude one takes toward propositions.12
B. Truth
The second element of the TAK is truth. People say many complicated and
murky things about truth, but the fundamental idea is very simple. The issue
here is not about which things are in fact true. Rather, the question for now is
about what it is for something to be true. One simple and widely accepted an
swer to this is contained in the correspondence theory of truth.
The central point of the correspondence theory is expressed in the follow
ing principle:
CT. A proposition is true if and only if it. corresponds to the facts (iff
the world is the way the proposition says it is). A proposition is false
iff it fails to correspond to the facts.13
The idea here is extraordinarily simple. It applies to our example about George
Washington in the following way. The proposition that George Washington was
the first president is true just in case it corresponds to the facts as they actually
are. In other words, it is true just in case George Washington was the first pres
ident. The proposition is false if he was not the first president. This should come
as no surprise. The principle applies in analogous ways to other propositions.
It will be helpful to spell out a few consequences of (CT) and to mention a
few things that are not consequences of (CT).
Washington have no bearing on the truth value (i.e., truth or falsity) of the
proposition that George Washington was the first president. The actual facts of
the case determine its truth value.
2) Truth is not “relative.” No single proposition can be “true for me but not
true for you.” I might believe a proposition that you disbelieve. In fact, this is
almost surely the case. Any two people will almost surely disagree about some
thing. However, if there is a proposition they disagree about, then the truth
value of that proposition is determined by the facts.
3) (CT) does not legitimize any kind of dogmatism or intolerant attitude to
ward people who disagree with you. Some people dismiss without consideration
anyone who disagrees with them. That is a nasty and unreasonable way to treat oth
ers. However, if we disagree about something, then, trivially, I think that I am right
and that you are wrong. If, for example, you think that Thomas Jefferson was the
first president and I think that it was George Washington instead, then I think
that you are wrong about this and you think that I am wrong about this. It would
be rash for me to generalize from this case and draw any conclusions about your
other beliefs. But when you disagree with me, I do think you are wrong. If you are
not dogmatic, you recognize your own fallibility. You are open to changing your
mind if new information comes along. There are circumstances in which it might
be rude to tell others that you think they are wrong. And possibly the mere fact
that others disagree provides you with some reason to reconsider your views.14
4) (CT) does not imply that things cannot change. Consider the proposi
tion that George Washington is the president of the United States. That propo
sition is false. But, it seems, it used to be true. What does (CT) say about this?
There are a few ways to think about this, and a full examination of them
would get into technicalities that are not important for present purposes. One
good approach says that a sentence such as “George Washington is the presi
dent of the United States” expresses a different proposition at different times.
The proposition it expressed back in 1789 is true. The proposition it expresses
in 2003—the proposition that George Washington is president of the United
States in 2003—is false. We can say that the sentence can be used to express a
series of propositions about specific times. You can think of a proposition say
ing that a certain thing has a certain property at one time as a predecessor of
a proposition saying that that same thing has that same property at a slightly
later time. So, when things change, for example, when we get a new president,
one dated proposition is true and its successor proposition is false. There is no
problem for (CT) here, provided we are careful about the propositions in
question.
5) Something similar applies to considerations about location. Suppose some
one in Maine is talking on the telephone to someone in Florida. The person
in Maine says:
9. It is snowing:.
The Traditional Analysis of Knowledge 19
These speakers do not disagree about anything. But what, then, should we say
about the truth value of the proposition that it is snowing? Is it true or is it false?
Once again, there are a variety of ways to think about this. For present pur
poses, a good approach will be to say that by a sentence like (9) the person ex
presses a proposition that might more clearly be displayed by the sentence
Similarly, the person in Florida who says (10) says something that is most clearly
displayed in
We may assume both of these propositions are true. Their truth is objective, in
that it depends upon the weather conditions in the two places.
6) There are puzzles about sentences such as
Exactly what (CT) says about them depends largely on what these sentences
mean. One possibility is that each speaker uses (11) to say, “I like the taste of
yogurt.” If that is the case, then different people use (11) to express different
propositions, each proposition being about what that speaker likes. If a person
who does like the taste of yogurt says (11), then the proposition the person ex
presses is true. If the person does not like yogurt, then the person expresses a
proposition that is not true.
It is not obvious that (11) says something about individual preferences. Maybe
it means something like “Most people like the taste of yogurt.” If that is what it
means, then it does not express different propositions when said by different
people. It expresses one proposition about majority tastes, and that proposition
is true if most people like yogurt and not true if they do not.
According to another interpretation, (11) says that yogurt satisfies some stan
dard of taste that is independent of people’s likes and dislikes. This assumes
some sort of “objectivity” about taste. On this view, (11) could be true even if
hardly anyone actually likes the taste of yogurt. You might find this view strange;
it is hard to understand what objective good taste amounts to.
What is crucial for present purposes is to notice that whichever interpreta
tion of (11) is right, there is no trouble for (CT). The proposition expressed
by (11) will vary from one speaker to another if the first option is right, but
not in the other cases. In all cases, however, the truth value that the proposi
tion (s) (11) expresses depends upon the relevant facts. In this case, the rele
20 The Traditional Analysis of Knowledge
vant facts are either the likes and dislikes of the speaker, the likes and dislikes
of the majority of people, or the objective facts about good taste.
There is no need for us to settle disputes about the right interpretation of
sentences such as (11). That complicated matter can be left to those who study
aesthetics. The crucial point for present purposes is that whichever interpre
tation is correct, there is no good objection here to (CT).
7) (CT) does not imply that we cannot know what is “really” true. Some peo
ple react to (CT) by saying something like this:
According to (CT), truth is “absolute” and what’s true depends upon how things are
in the objective world. Because this world is external to us, we can never really know
what’s true. At most, we can know what is “subjectively” true. This subjective truth de
pends upon our own views about the world. Absolute truth must always be beyond
our grasp.
8) There is one very puzzling issue associated with the correspondence the
ory of truth. Consider a sentence such as
is a borderline case. There simply are not exact boundaries to the heights to
which the word “tall” applies. In other words, “tall” is a vague word.
Many other words are vague, including, “healthy”, “wealthy”, and “wise”.
Vagueness causes numerous problems in understanding exactly how language
works. Fortunately, we can largely ignore those issues while pursuing the epis
temological questions that are our focus. However, issues concerning vague
ness will arise from time to time, so it is important to have a grasp of the idea.
Furthermore, the existence of vague sentences may have some bearing on the
adequacy of (CT). Recall the distinction between sentences and the proposi
tions they express. As just noted, vagueness is a feature of sentences. Sentence
(12), it seems, is vague. But now consider the proposition (12) expresses on a
particular occasion, such as the one just described. If that proposition is vague,
or indefinite in truth value, then (CT) needs revision. (CT) says that every
proposition is either true or false, depending upon whether it corresponds to
the way the world is. But if there are vague propositions, then there are propo
sitions that partially correspond to the way the world is. One might say that
there is a third truth value—indeterminate—in addition to the original two—
true and false. One might even say that there is a whole range of truth values,
that truth comes in degrees. These are complex matters that cannot easily be
resolved. We will not attempt to resolve them here. It is enough to realize that
(CT) may require modification in order to deal with vagueness.
C. Justification
The third, and final element of the TAK is justification. Justification (or ratio
nality or reasonableness) will be the focus of a large part of this book. This sec
tion will introduce some preliminary ideas.
Justification is something that comes in degrees—you can have more or less of
it. Consider again Example 2.4, in which you pessimistically believed that it would
rain on the day of your picnic on the basis of a forecast saying that the odds of its
raining were slightly greater than half. Here you have some justification for think
ing that it will rain. It is not as if you simply made it up, with no reason at all. But
your reasons were far from good enough to give you knowledge. So what clause
(iii) of the TAK requires is very strongjustification. In the circumstances described,
you do not have it for the belief that it will rain. If the day of the picnic comes and
you look out the window and see rain, then you do have strong enough justifica
tion for the belief that it will rain. Under those circumstances you would satisfy
clause (iii) of the TAK. So clause (iii) should be read to require strong justifica
tion, or adequate justification. This may be a bit imprecise, but it will do for now.
You can be justified in believing something without actually believing it.
Clause (iii) of the TAK does not imply (i). To see how this works, consider the
following example:
the next day. Mr. Insecure has studied hard, taken and done well on the
practice exams, found the questions on the actual exam similar to the ones
he had studied, and so on. He has excellent reasons to think that he passed
the exam. But Mr. Insecure is insecure. He never believes that he has done
well and does not believe that he has done well on this exam.
Even though Mr. Insecure does not believe that he has passed the exam, he is
justified in believing that he passed the exam. So condition (iii) of the TAX'is
satisfied, but condition (i) is not. To be justified in believing a proposition is,
roughly, to have what is required to be highly reasonable in believing it, whether
one actually believes it or not.
What is justified for one person may not be justified for another. You have
many justified beliefs about your private life. Your friends and acquaintances
may have little or no justification for beliefs about those matters. And what is jus
tified for an individual changes over time. A modification of Example 2.4 illus
trates this. A week before the picnic, you may not have had justification for
believing the proposition that it would rain on Saturday. But by Saturday morn
ing, you might acquire ample justification for that proposition.
It is important not to confuse being justified in believing something from
being able to show that one is justified in believing that proposition. In many
cases we can explain why a belief is justified; we can formulate our reasons.
However, there are exceptions to this. For example, a child might have many
justified beliefs but be unable to articulate a justification for them.
V. CONCLUSION
(QI) from Chapter 1 asked what it took to have knowledge. This chapter has
introduced an answer to that question based on The Traditional Analysis ofKnowl
edge, according to which knowledge is justified true belief. This analysis has a
long history. It seems to fit very well with The Standard View. The examples of
knowledge endorsed by The Standard View seem to be cases ofjustified true be
lief. And cases in which we lack knowledge seem to be cases in which we lack
at least one of these three factors.
There is, however, a significant objection to the TAK. We turn next to it.
ENDNOTES
1. The following examples show general patterns of various kinds of statements, with
an example showing how each pattern could be filled out. The patterns make use
of variables that can be replaced by specific terms. Following standard practices,
“S” is used as a variable to be replaced by a name or description of a person, “x” is
used as a variable to be replaced by a name or description of any object (including
people), “p” is to be replaced by a full sentence expressing a fact or purported fact
(a proposition), and “A” by a description of an action.
2. For discussion ofjust what is meant by the word “proposition,” see Section III, Part
Al of this chapter.
3. It is important to understand the difference between (2) and
2a. The librarian knows either that there is a book by Salinger in the library or that
there is not a book by Salinger in the library.
(2a) is true; (2a) reports knowledge of a disjunction (an “or” statement) and every
one can have this knowledge. But the librarian must possess special knowledge if
(2) is true. She must know which of the disjuncts (the parts of the “or” statement)
is true.
4. “~p” means “not-p”, or the negation of p. The negation of “There is a book by
Salinger in the library” is “It is not the case that there is a book by Salinger in the
library.”
5. The methodology used here will be important in what follows. One important test
of a proposed definition is that there are no counterexamples to it.
6. This definition may need some refinement, but it does capture at least the basic
idea under discussion.
1. From Meno, translated by G. M. A. Grube. Reprinted in Plato: Complete Works, edited
byJohn M. Cooper (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Co., 1997), p. 895.
8. A similar idea is presented in another dialogue, Theatetus, translated by M. J. Levett,
revised by Myles Burnyeat. Reprinted in Plato: Complete Works. See p. 223.
9. Roderick Chisholm, Theory ofKnowledge (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1966),
p. 23.
24 The Traditional Analysis of Knowledge
10. There is an alternative way to think about these matters. Instead of saying that there
ar e three options, you can say that you can believe a proposition to a greater or lesser-
degree. You can think of these degrees of belief as arranged along a scale. When you
accept a proposition with absolute conviction, you believe it to the fullest degree. When
you completely and totally reject a proposition, you have the lowest possible degree of
belief in it. And in the usual cases, your degree of belief falls somewhere in between.
Suspension ofjudgment is right in the middle.
11. If you have never even consider ed a pr ©position, then you neither believe it nor dis
believe it, but you do not suspend judgment either. Perhaps suspending judgment
is best characterized as considering a proposition but neither believing it nor dis
believing it.
12. There are hard questions about exactly what kinds of objects propositions are. We
can safely ignore those questions here.
13. The term “iff” abbreviates “if and only if.” Sentences of the form “p iff q” are true
just in case the truth values of p and q agree, that is, just in case both are true or both
are false.
14. This topic will be discussed in detail in Chapter 9.
15. At this point you might observe that we might be in a situation like the ancients, in
which our claims to knowledge are mistaken. We will take up this issue when we
consider The Skeptical View.
16. It is possible that some of the attractiveness of The Relativistic View, mentioned in
Chapter 1, results from confusing apparent knowledge and real knowledge.
Modifying The .
Traditional Analysis
of Knowledge
A. The Counterexamples
In this section we will examine three examples all designed to illustrate a prob
lem in the TAK. The point behind all the objections is the same, but the dif
ferent examples help to make the issue clearer. The first example is a modified
version of one Gettier originally presented.
"They are so in their way, but that way is not ours," said
my mother; "and even were the advantages they offer
greater than I think them, I do not believe my child would
wish to leave her mother for their sake."
"Oh, no, no!" I cried, feeling for the moment all I said.
"Not for worlds."
"I must warn you not to judge him by the outside, for
he is a vain little fellow in some ways," said Andrew,
smiling; "but he is in truth a good man, and his wife is a
bright little body."
Of course my mother could say no less than that we
should esteem the visit an honor, and the next morning
they came. I had thought my uncle's dress wonderful fine,
but it was nothing to that of Mr. Pepys, though I must say
the latter was both richer in itself and better fancied. His
wife was a pretty, black woman, who spoke French very
nicely, and indeed it was in some sort her native tongue. Mr.
Pepys bought some of my mother's lesser jewels himself,
especially a diamond in a clasp which his wife fancied, and
promised to find a purchaser for the rest—a promise which
he fulfilled to our great advantage.
"You must not think, madame, that all the ladies about
the court are like these," said Mr. Pepys. "There are many
who bring up their families in all virtue and godly living, like
my good Lady Sandwich and others I could name. But I am
quite of your mind as to Mrs. Genevieve, and if I were so
happy as to be blessed with a daughter, she should, if
possible, grow up in the country. His Majesty is a most
noble prince—Heaven bless him, with all my heart!—but his
example in some things hath done our young people little
good."
"But you must have your wits about you, child," said my
aunt. "'Tis a dreadfully uncivil thing not to return a salute.
Mr. Butler will think you a little rustic."
"How and when did you leave home?" was naturally the
first question.
CHAPTER XI.
TRE MADOC.
"You look well, my child," said she, holding out her hand
to me. "Have not the lines fallen to us in pleasant places?
Even Jeanne admits that the Cornish folk are Christian
people, since, though they cannot speak French, they know
how to make cider."
Andrew laughed.
"Trees are the great enemies over there," said he. "It
did look terribly wasteful to me to see great logs of bard
maple, chestnut, and oak, rolled into heaps and burned in
the field, just to get rid of them."
"I should prefer that she should have her own way in
the matter," answered Andrew shortly, and there the
discussion ended for the time; but we were no sooner in the
house than Betty began it again, appealing to her mother to
say if it would not be much better for me to be called by my
English name now I was come to live in England.
CHAPTER XII.
MISCHIEF.