Remedies and Incentives in Private and Public Law - A Comparative
Remedies and Incentives in Private and Public Law - A Comparative
Remedies and Incentives in Private and Public Law - A Comparative
Chicago Unbound
1990
William J. Stuntz
Recommended Citation
Saul Levmore & William J. Stuntz, "Remedies and Incentives in Private and Public Law: A Comparative
Essay," 1990 Wisconsin Law Review 483 (1990).
This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Scholarship at Chicago Unbound. It has been
accepted for inclusion in Journal Articles by an authorized administrator of Chicago Unbound. For more
information, please contact [email protected].
ESSAYS
When civil and common lawyers observe one another's legal sys-
tems from a law-and-economics perspective, they quickly learn the
value of focusing on the properties of legal rules that distinguish various
systems. Thus, Steven Shavell's exploration of the economics of fee-
shifting rules, William Bishop's investigation of the different rules gov-
erning breach of contract, and Mark Ramseyer's inquiry into Japanese
and American water law, all support the conclusion that when com-
peting legal rules survive in different countries it is quite likely that
both rules may be fairly efficient.' Differences between civil and com-
mon law systems are thus interesting (from an economic perspective)
because the differences draw attention to the positive and negative
incentive effects, or other costs and benefits, of inherited rules. In this
Essay, we emphasize such a comparative law-and-economics approach
by drawing on seemingly unrelated areas of law, where civil and com-
mon law rules are generally (but not always) dissimilar, and by arguing
that fundamental and universal incentive problems go a long way
toward explaining both the similarities and the differences among the
various rules. In particular, we choose one theme: the choice between
damages and disgorgement-that is, the question of whether to control
behavior with a rule requiring an antisocial party to pay over damages
or with a rule calling for the restitution of unjust enrichment-and we
show that this choice permeates the law of torts and contracts, the law
governing unreasonable searches for evidence, and the law of govern-
mental takings of private property. With this unifying theme, we try
* This paper was delivered at the 1990 Conference on the Economics of the Civil
Law in Hamburg, Germany.
t Barron F. Black Research Professor of Law, University of Virginia School of Law.
B.A., Columbia, 1973; Ph.D., Yale, 1978; J.D., Yale, 1980.
t Professor of Law, University of Virginia School of Law. B.A., William and Mary,
1980; J.D. Univ. of Virginia, 1984.
1. Shavell, Suit, Settlement, and Trial: A TheoreticalAnalysis under Alternative
Methods for the Allocation ofLegal Costs, I I J. LEGAL STUD. 55 (1982); Bishop, The Choice
of Remedy for Breach of Contract, 14 J. LEGAL STUD. 299 (1985); Ramseyer, Water Law in
Imperial Japan: Public Goods, Private Claims, and Legal Convergence, 18 J. LEGAL STUD.
51 (1989); See also Levmore, Rethinking ComparativeLaw Variety and Uniformity in Ancient
and Modern Tort Law, 61 TUL. L. REV. 235 (1986).
both to provide the basis for positive theories of these areas of law and
to demonstrate the value of comparing legal rules within an incentive-
oriented framework.
2
I. DAMAGES VERSUS DISGORGEMENT IN TORT LAW
be quite profitable to be a victim under such a rule. The problem might be solved by letting
each plaintiff recover only one-tenth of the whole enrichment, although it may be necessary
to give an extra reward to the first plaintiff who identifies the unjustly enriched defendant.
25% likely to cause sixty in harm, and 25% likely to cause no harm,
the required multiplier of 1.33 will, once again, either make it profitable
to be a victim (because 1.33 times fifty is more than sixty) or require
the expenditure of administrative costs in order to tax away part of
the recovery (perhaps to finance compensation for other plaintiffs in-
jured at some future point by the very same defendant or to fund
plaintiffs whose own damages exceed the unjust enrichment of their
defendants). 5 In sum, a restitution system could be substituted for the
tort system but, in order to reproduce the deterrent qualities of the tort
system and to guard against moral hazards, a variety of corrective
devices would be necessary. That a restitution system could only take
the place of the tort system either by sacrificing a good deal of efficient
deterrence or by incurring heavy administrative costs should not dis-
tract us from the fact that restitution might be useful in other areas of
law, where multipliers would be unnecessary or where the damage rem-
edy itself has disadvantages. And, as a comparative matter, we might
expect to find (as we do) that no legal system relies on the restitution
remedy to control tortious behavior, but that disgorgement is used in
other areas of law where the relative advantages of the two remedial
tools are different.
6. See Bishop, supra note 1; DeLong, supra note 2; Schwartz, The Casefor Specific
Performance, 89 YALE L.J. 271 (1979).
7. Note that there will not be too many surprises with regard to Bl's damages
because of the rule which provides that in contract law damages are normally limited to
foreseeable damages. That rule, of course, helps breachers allocate their mitigation efforts.
8. Note that the use of specific performance in United States law for such unique
goods as land is easily explicable because it is especially easy for B2 to find B), by searching
local land records or local realtors.
E. Allan Farnsworth notes that in planned economies without well-developed markets
for substitute goods, the preference is for specific performance, apparently on valuation
grounds. Farnsworth, Damagesand Specific Relief, 27 AM. J. COMP. L. 247 (1979).
9. G. TREITEL, REMEDIES FOR BREACH OF CONTRACT: A COMPARATIVE ACCOUNT
47-51 (1988).
10. The choice between damages and specific performance is even subtler, or closer,
than implied in the text. It is arguable, after all, that the fact that B2 pays more to S than
B) agreed to pay for a good or service does not prove that it is worth more to B2, because
B1 may simply be a superior bargainer. B) may not have revealed her true preferences to S,
despite the fact that revelation would now lead to greater damages because of the foreseeability
rule, because S would then have held out for a higher price. And the foreseeability rule would
not be satisfied by BI informing S of her high potential damages only after the contract is
made (because S then loses the chance to charge an "insurance" premium).
In response to this argument about the ability of the damage rule to support efficient
breaches, it might be said that at least on average there is reason to think that B2 values the
item more than does BI because B) may in fact have been the worse bargainer. Without
further information, there is no reason to think that one is systematically a poorer bargainer
than the other. B) can always go to B2 and start all over again-or, when hearing from S
about the pending breachs, she can induce S to breach with B2 and "resell" to B).
First, such retrieval would interfere with the relatively careful rules
regarding security interests in personal property, under article 9 of the
Uniform Commercial Code, because other creditors have no means of
learning about the contract between S and B. There is a filing system
and a serious order of priorities among creditors, and S is neither
recorded in that system nor otherwise especially deserving. Second,
and more plainly, section 2-702(2) of the Uniform Commercial Code
gives S rights if S discovers that B received the goods (on credit) while
insolvent, and S demands the goods back on these grounds within ten
days of the delivery to B. (S does better if B has specifically lied about
his solvency to this seller within three months before the delivery.)
Since no other section of the commercial code seems relevant, the
implication is that S otherwise has no repossession right, and S is left
to sue for damages.
A more thematic (and perilous) way to reach the same result is to
reason that this is an area of law where symmetry will be found, because
whatever reason a legal system has for preferring damages over specific
performance when S breaches probably carries over to the case where
B breaches. Forcing B to return the goods, or allowing S to repossess,
is, after all, the closest thing to specific performance. And allowing S
to repossess would certainly amount to a restitution rule, because B
will be unjustly enriched by keeping the goods. The symmetry argument
is thus another way of saying that the preference for damages over
restitution might continue unless there are affirmative reasons to prefer
restitution. This is not to say that such symmetry or consistency is
required as a matter of efficiency theory. The original argument, after
all, was that sellers are more easily located by third parties (like B2
above) than are buyers-and this point argues in favor of damages when
S breaches (to sell to B2)-but this says nothing about the case where
B breaches. " But because it would appear that B2 can indeed find B1
quite readily once the goods are already in Bl's possession, the argu-
ment for continuing the logic of the damages regime, so that there are
symmetrical rules, is quite strong. And as a comparative matter, the
remarkable thing is that in Japan, for instance, where B1 has a choice
of remedies when S breaches in B2's favor, it is the case that when BI
breaches, S can choose to retrieve. 12 There is, in short, a kind of sym-
11. Where breach occurs because of a drop in value of the item in question, it is
likely that the seller is in a better position to resell. But in a case where B has simply no
longer a need for the item or, most generally, where B has run out of funds, so that the
damages rule will run into B's insolvency and the seller very much cares whether a specific
performance or a damages rule is in place, S's comparative advantage is less relevant.
12. MrNPO art. 545 (Japan). In France, rescission is also an option. See F. LAWSON,
A. ANTON, & L. BROWN, AMOS AND WALTON'S INTRODUCTION TO FRENCH LAW 197-99
(1963). See generally Cooper, The Reclamation Rights of Unpaid and Unsecured Sellers in
International Trade, 1987 COLUM. Bus. L. REv. 17. (reporting limited rights of reclamation,
with no unifying theory but making no attempt to link the right of reclamation to the remedy
available when the seller breaches).
13. See P. SCHUCK, SuING GOVERNMENT: CITIZEN REMEDIES FOR OFFICIAL
WRONGS 59-81 (1983); Mashaw, Civil Liability of Government Officers: Property Rights and
Official Accountability, 42 LAw & CONTEMP. PROBS. 8, 29-33 (1978).
25. Wong Sun v. United States, 371 U.S. 471 (1963). This rule is modified in one
respect: only the victim of the illegal search (defined as the party whose privacy was invaded)
may invoke the exclusionary rule. Rakas v. Illinois, 439 U.S. 128 (1978). This is problematic
to the extent that the officer may be induced to search illegally in suspect A's house if the
searcher expects to find evidence that will incriminate suspect B. For this problem to exist,
however, the searching officer must be willing to trade off in advance any likelihood of catching
A. Particularly given the premium discussed earlier, this may happen only rarely.
26. United States v. Ceccolini, 435 U.S. 268 (1978).
27. For general English-language discussions of the German exclusionary rule, see
Bradley, The Exclusionary Rule in Germany, 96 HARV. L. REv. 1032 (1983); Pakter, Exclu-
sionary Rules in France, Germany, and Italy, 9 HASTINGS INT'L & COMP. L. REv. 1, 38-48
ers" would reflect a plan of restitution, but to the extent that the gov-
ernment simply funded its liability through taxes on the winners in the
third group, it is convenient to think of either scheme as based on the
restitution, or disgorgement, idea. Such a plan, which through one
means or the other collected from those who were benefited and com-
pensated those who were burdened, would obviously promote the in-
ternalization function of takings law. But inasmuch as modem legal
systems rarely collect or compensate in this manner, such schemes are
mostly of theoretical interest at this point. 32 There is some legal prec-
edent for thinking about the benefits as well as the burdens of govern-
ment activities. In Australia, as elsewhere, there were rules of resump-
tion, under which land grants included a reservation of some percentage
(on the order of six to twenty percent) of land on which the government
could later construct highways (and in some places reservoirs and other
projects) with no requirement for compensation to private property
owners.3 3 Some legal systems simply afforded no compensation for
property taken in order to build roads. 34 It is noteworthy that these
legal rules normally applied in areas with low population densities, and
it is likely that property owners benefited when a highway or reservoir
was built nearby. In other words, the damage or restitution claim that
might have been brought by the landowner whose property was taken
would likely have been offset by a counterclaim for the property owner's
undeserved enrichment (or the absence of net damages). The doctrines
in question might in this way be thought of as rules of thumb meant
to save the administrative costs of actual damage (or enrichment) de-
terminations.
The symmetry that is reflected above in the listing of the second
and third categories of affected property interests is apparent; one can
scarcely imagine extractions of windfalls from the third group (con-
sisting of those who receive windfalls from government projects) with-
out including payments for losses suffered by the second (those who
are burdened, although their property is not physically taken or com-
pletely destroyed). In a transaction-cost-free world, restitution (whether
available directly from the winners in the third group or from the
government itself) would almost surely be a better rule for takings,
because costs and benefits would be incorporated into a government's
calculations. Once the costs of measuring benefits (windfalls) and costs
32. An important strand of the takings literature has favored such transfers. See
WINDFALLS FOR WIPEOUTS: LAND VALUE CAPTURE AND COMPENSATION (D. Hagman & D.
Misczynski 1978).
33. Brown, Compensation for land Acquisition in Australia,in COMPENSATION FOR
COMPULSORY PURCHASE, supra note 29, at 73-74.
34. J. SACKMAN, NICHOLS' THE LAw OF EMINENT DOMAIN § 1.22[l] (1973) (first
statute requiring compensation for road building in colonial America passed in Massachusetts
in 1639).
(burdens) are considered, it is easy to see why takings law has not
experimented much with restitution. In the tort law setting, it is well
known that the damage rule is an excellent means of internalizing cal-
culations of costs and benefits, and we suggested that restitution, or
disgorgement, could come close to doing the same only at great cost.
Here, in takings law, the situation is half reversed, especially because
we need to measure pre-takings values in a post-takings world. The
disgorgement rule, with symmetrical application, is now the great in-
ternalizer, but its implementation costs are also great.
V. CONCLUSION