Jervis 1988 - Realism, Game Theory and Cooperation
Jervis 1988 - Realism, Game Theory and Cooperation
Jervis 1988 - Realism, Game Theory and Cooperation
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Cambridge University Press and Trustees of Princeton University are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize,
preserve and extend access to World Politics.
http://www.jstor.org
E VER sinceThucydides,
scholarshaveemphasizedthatinternational
politics is shaped by the anarchical contextin which it takes place.
The perniciouseffectof what JohnHerz called the securitydilemma-
the factthatmost of the ways in which a countryseeks to increaseits se-
curityhave the unintendedeffectof decreasingthe securityof others-
also is familiar,and indeed, also can be found in Thucydides: "What
made war inevitable was the growth of Athenian power and the fear
which this caused in Sparta." In view of such dynamics,how can states
cooperate? Recentanalyseshave formalizedtheseproblemsand analyzed
themby means of modern social sciencetechniques.'
The work arisesfromtheintersectionof Realism and game theory.Al-
though common interestsare stressedmore than in some formsof Real-
ism,the basic assumptionsclearlyfitwithinthisschool: thefocusis on the
stateas an actor2and on the strategiesthatcan rationallybe used to fur-
ther its interests.The studies use simple game-theorymodels, or what
Barry O'Neill calls "proto-game theory,"3in order to gain the insights
* I am gratefulfor commentsby Robert Art, JohnConybeare,Jeffrey Frieden, Joanne
Gowa, JosephGrieco, Ernst Haas, StanleyHoffmann,Stephen Krasner,Deborah Larson,
Fred Lawson, Helen Milner,RichardNelson, and JackSnyder.
JohnHertz, "Idealist Internationalism
and the SecurityDilemma," WorldPolitics2 (Jan-
uary I950), I57-80; Thucydides,The PeloponnesianWar,trans.by Rex Warner (Harmonds-
worth,U.K.: Penguin, I954), 25. The recentliteratureis summarizedand extendedin World
Politics38 (October i985), also published as Kenneth Oye, ed., CooperationunderAnarchy
(Princeton: PrincetonUniversityPress, i986). The frameworkused grows out of Robert
Axelrod, The Evolutionof Cooperation(New York: Basic Books, i984); RobertJervis,"Co-
operationundertheSecurityDilemma," WorldPolitics30 (JanuaryI978), i67-214; and Robert
Keohane, AfterHegemony(Princeton:PrincetonUniversityPress, i984). Related arguments
are made by Michael Taylor,Anarchyand Cooperation(New York: Wiley, I976). Although
the subject matteris the same as that treatedin Hedley Bull, The AnarchicalSociety(New
York: Columbia UniversityPress,I977), Bull's approachis different and his work is notcited
in thisliterature.For argumentsthatBull providesa betterfoundationforunderstandingin-
ternationalpoliticsthan does the work analyzed here, see Hayward Alker, Jr.,"The Pre-
sumptionof Anarchyin World Politics,"and RichardAshley,"Hedley Bull and theAnarchy
Problematique,"both in Alker and Ashley,eds.,AfterRealism:Anarchy, Power,and Interna-
tionalCollaboration(forthcoming).
See Charles Lipson, "Bankers' Dilemmas: PrivateCooperation in ReschedulingSover-
eign Debts," WorldPolitics38 (October i985), 200-225, for an analysisof non-stateactors
withinthisframework.
3 O'Neill, "Game Theory and theStudyof DeterrenceofWar," in RobertAxelrod,Robert
Hirschman has noted,in many cases we would not startwhat will prove
to be a fruitfulenterpriseifwe were aware of thedifficultiesat thebegin-
ning.6But ifwe ignorethe problemsin theearlystages,we may overreact
and rejectthe entireapproach when theybecome obvious later.It would
be more productiveif scholars simultaneouslyexplored the potentialof
and the problems with the approach. Since the potentialhas been dis-
cussed elsewhere(see fn. I), I will concentrateon the problems.
Three strengthsthat have made thisresearchstimulatingand impor-
tantshould be noted,however.First,it builds upon centralcharacteristics
of internationalpolitics-anarchy, the securitydilemma,and the combi-
nation of common and conflictinginterests.Second, the approach is par-
simonious and lends itselfto deductive theorizing.Third, it seeks to
bringtogetherthestudyof conflictand thestudyofcooperation,and tries
to explain a wide range of phenomena encompassingboth securityand
politicaleconomy.The deterringof exploitationmay be as relevantto the
stabilityof monetarysystemsas to armscontrol;strategiesbywhich states
can gain the benefitsof mutual cooperationmay be as importantfornu-
clear posturesas forinternationaltrade.Indeed, as thelinksto the theory
of public goods indicate, the propositionsproduced should apply to a
wide range of cases outside of internationalpolitics.
It is not a good sign,however,thatprisonersconfrontedby a District
Attorneydo not behave as the model would lead us to expect.7In order
to apply the framework,we have toassumemanyoftheelementsof world
politics that in fact are most problematical.The actor's values, prefer-
ences, beliefs,and definitionof self all are exogenous to the model and
must be provided before analysis can begin.8 If they were straight-
forward,the analysis of internationalpoliticswould be much simpler.
They thereforeneed to be investigatedand explained,nottakenas givens.
Adoption of stereotypicalRealist assumptionscan supplysome of the in-
puts the analysisrequires,but I will argue thatthisis not completelysat-
isfactory.
As noted, the central question for the work on anarchy is how co-
operationis possiblewhen actorsare in a Prisoners'Dilemma-i.e., when
theyhave the followingpreferenceorder: exploitingor takingadvantage
of the other,mutual cooperation,mutual defection,and being exploited.
The most importantissue may be not what happens afterthese prefer-
ences have been established,but the preferencesthemselves.Much of the
explanatory"action" takes place in the formationof the preferences;we
cannot affordto leave thistopic offstage.Three questionsneed to be ad-
dressed: How do we know what the actors'preferencesare? What is the
patternof distributionof preferencesover large number of cases? How
are preferencesestablished?
ofConflict(Cambridge:Harvard UniversityPress,i960),
I7Thomas Schelling,The Strategy
265.
i8
This is trueforJervis(fn. i).
SOURCES OF PREFERENCES
29 Van Evera (fn. 28); Van Evera, "The Cult of the Offensive and the Originsof the First
World War," InternationalSecurity9 (Summer i984), 58-i07; JackSnyder,"Civil-Military
Relationsand theCult of theOffensive,I9I4 and i984," ibid.,i08-46; Snyder,The Ideologyof
theOffensive: MilitaryDecisionMating and theDisastersof 1914 (Ithaca,NY: Cornell Univer-
sityPress, i984). For a rebuttal,see ScottSagan, "1914 Revisited:Allies,Offense,and Insta-
bility,"International Securityi i (Fall i986), I5I-76, and theexchangeof lettersbetweenSny-
der and Sagan, ibid., i i (Winter I 986/87),I 87-98.
30 For a discussionof this issue in the domesticcontext, see RobertPutnam,The Beliefsof
Politicians(New Haven: Yale UniversityPress,I973).
3 Simon, "Human Nature in Politics:The Dialogue of Psychology and PoliticalScience,"
AmericanPoliticalScienceReview 79 (June i985), 298; also see William Riker,"The Heres-
theticsof Constitution-Making:The Presidencyin I787, with Commentson Determinism
and Rational Choice," AmericanPoliticalScienceReview78 (March i984), i-i6. In a different
intellectualtradition,Adam Przeworski comes to a similarconclusion:"Marxism and Ra-
tionalChoice," Politicsand SocietyI4 (No. I, i985), 379-409.
32 For a general discussionof changingpreferences, see JamesMarch and HerbertSimon,
Organizations(New York: Wiley, I958), I4I; Michael Cohen and RobertAxelrod,"Coping
with Complexity:The Adaptive Value of Changing Utility,"AmericanEconomicReview74
(March i984), 30-42; Barbara Farnham, "Value Conflictsand Political Decision-Making"
(Ph.D. diss. in progress,Columbia University).
eds., U.S.-SovietSecurityCooperation:
Achievements,Failures,Lessons(New York: OxfordUni-
versityPress, forthcomingi988). Also see Raymond Garthoff,Detenteand Confrontation
(Washington,DC: BrookingsInstitution,i985), 480. For an argumentthatpeople's prefer-
ences are oftenformedby theirbehavior,see Daryl Bem, "Self-PerceptionTheory,"in Leon-
ard Berkowitz,ed., Advancesin ExperimentalSocial Psychology, VI (New York: Academic
Press, I972); foran applicationto internationalpolitics,see Deborah Larson, The Originsof
Containment (Princeton:PrincetonUniversityPress,i985).
37Rothstein, "Consensual Knowledge and International Collaboration:Some Lessons from
theCommodityNegotiations,"International Organization38 (Autumn i984), 732-62.
38 See Mary Parker Follett,DynamicAdministration: The CollectedPapersof Mary Parker
Follett,H. C. Metcalfand L. Urwick,eds. (New York: Harper & Row, I942); RichardWalton
and RichardMcKersie,A BehavioralTheoryofLabor Negotiations (New York: McGraw-Hill,
i965), I26-83; ErnstHaas, BeyondtheNation-State(Stanford,CA: StanfordUniversityPress,
I 964), 86-I 25.
39For a discussionof the ways in which changesin technologyinfluencedAmericanatti-
tudes toward antisatelliteweapons, particularlyby providingsatelliteswithoffensiveas well
CONCEPTS
47For one effortat doing so, see RobertJervis,"From Balance to Concert:A Studyof In-
ternationalSecurityCooperation,"WorldPolitics38 (October i985), 58-79,at 62-64. For a fur-
ther discussion,see Jervis,"Cooperation Under Anarchy: Problems and Limitations,"in
Alker and Ashley(fn. i).
48 Arnold Wolfers,"The Balance of Power in Theory and Practice,"in Wolfers(fn. 2I),
I22-24; Waltz (fn. 24), I25-28; Stephen M. Walt, "Alliance Formationand the Balance of
World Power," International Security9 (Spring i985), 3-43,and The OriginsofAlliances(Ith-
aca, NY: Cornell UniversityPress,i987); JackSnyderand RobertJervis, eds.,Strategic
Beliefs
and SuperpowerCompetition in theAsianRimland,forthcoming.
The Quarterly Review 129 (October i870), 553. I am gratefulto Marc Trachtenbergforpoint-
ing me to thisarticle.
ropean countries and now also in some [American] states ..., helping
othersin certainkinds of extremeneed is requiredby law."9'
Applying the same reasoning,Robert Trivers argues that evolution
should selectforpeople who reciprocatealtruism.Emotionssuch as anger
at those who do not reciprocate,and guilt over one's own cheatingare
also functionalbecause they bolster reciprocity.Short-runcalculations
might lead people to ignore the transgressionsof others(or to replyto
them only mildly),or to shirk reparationswhen theyhave been caught
cheating.But over the long run,such behavioris destructive.Dispropor-
tionate retributionfor cheating,called up by anger, can induce future
compliance: "it seems plausible ... thatthe emotionof guilthas been se-
lected forin humans partlyin order to motivatethe cheaterto compen-
sate his misdeed and ... thus to preventthe ruptureof reciprocalrela-
tionships." Because these emotions may sustain long-run cooperation
more than calculationwould,
CONCLUSIONS
The queries and objections raised here are not all of the same type.
Some are assertionsthat the anarchyframeworkleads us to concentrate