The Foundations of Analysis A Straightforward Introduction Book 1 Logic Sets and Numbers 1, 2008 Digital Reissue Edition K.G. Binmore
The Foundations of Analysis A Straightforward Introduction Book 1 Logic Sets and Numbers 1, 2008 Digital Reissue Edition K.G. Binmore
The Foundations of Analysis A Straightforward Introduction Book 1 Logic Sets and Numbers 1, 2008 Digital Reissue Edition K.G. Binmore
com
https://ebookname.com/product/the-foundations-of-analysis-a-
straightforward-introduction-book-1-logic-sets-and-
numbers-1-2008-digital-reissue-edition-k-g-binmore/
OR CLICK BUTTON
DOWLOAD NOW
https://ebookname.com/product/the-foundations-of-analysis-a-
straightforward-introduction-book-1-logic-sets-and-
numbers-1-2008-digital-reissue-edition-k-g-binmore-2/
https://ebookname.com/product/my-book-of-numbers-1-30-kumon-
workbooks-kumon/
https://ebookname.com/product/integral-equations-and-
applications-1-reissue-edition-c-corduneanu/
https://ebookname.com/product/linear-and-projective-
representations-of-symmetric-groups-1-reissue-edition-alexander-
kleshchev/
From Kant to Hilbert Volume 1 A Source Book in the
Foundations of Mathematics William Bragg Ewald
https://ebookname.com/product/from-kant-to-hilbert-
volume-1-a-source-book-in-the-foundations-of-mathematics-william-
bragg-ewald/
https://ebookname.com/product/the-enforceability-of-promises-in-
european-contract-law-1-reissue-edition-james-gordley/
https://ebookname.com/product/sets-functions-and-logic-3rd-
edition-keith-devlin/
https://ebookname.com/product/lectures-in-logic-and-set-theory-
volume-1-mathematical-logic-1st-edition-george-tourlakis/
https://ebookname.com/product/lectures-in-logic-and-set-theory-
volume-1-mathematical-logic-1st-edition-george-tourlakis-2/
THE FOUNDATIONS OF ANALYSIS:
A STRAIGHTFORWARD INTRODUCTION
BooK 1
LOGIC, SETS AND NUMBERS
THE FOUNDATIONS OF
ANALYSIS:
A STRAIGHTFORWARD
INTRODUCTION
BOOK 1
LOGIC, SETS AND NUMBERS
K. G. BINMORE
Professor of Mathematics
London School of Economics and Political Science
Published in the United States of America by Cambridge University Press, New York
www.cambridge.org
Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9780521233224
A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library
Introduction pageix
1 Proofs 1
1.1 What is a proof? 1
1.5 Mathematical proof 3
1.7 Obvious 5
1.8 The interpretation of a mathematical theory 5
2 Logic (I) 7
2.1 Statements 7
2.4 Equivalence 7
2.6 Not 8
2.7 And, or 8
2.10 Implies 9
2.12 If and only if 11
2.13 Proof schema 12
3 Logic (11) 14
3.1 Predicates and sets 14
3.4 Quantifiers 16
3.6 Manipulations with quantifiers 17
3.10 More on contradictories 18
3.13 Examples and counter-examples 19
4 Set operations 21
4.1 Subsets 21
4.4 Complements 22
4.7 Unions and intersections 23
4.13t Zermelo~Fraenkel set theory 25
5 Relations 28
5.1 Ordered pairs 28
tThis material is more advanced than the main body of the text and is perhaps best
omitted at a first reading.
V
vi Contents
6 Functions 33
6.1 Formal definition 33
6.2 Terminology 35
6.5 Composition 39
6.6t Binary operations and groups 40
6.8t Axiom of choice 41
8 Principle of induction 54
8.1 Ordered fields 54
8.2 The natural numbers 54
8.4 Principle of induction 56
8.7 Inductive definitions 56
8.10 Properties of N 59
8.13 Integers 60
8.14 Rational numbers 60
12 Cardinality 109
12.1 Counting 109
12.2 Cardinality 110
12.4 Countable sets 112
12.14 Uncountable sets 118
12.17t Decimal expansions 119
12.20t Transcendental numbers 121
12.23t Counting the uncountable 122
12.24t Ordinal numbers 124
12.25t Cardinals 126
12.26t Continuum hypothesis 127
Notation 128
Index 129
INTRODUCTION
This book contains an informal but systematic account of the logical and
algebraic foundations of mathematical analysis written at a fairly elemen-
tary level. The book is entirely self-contained but will be most useful to
students who have already taken, or are in the process of taking, an
introductory course in basic mathematical analysis. Such a course nec-
essarily concentrates on the notion of convergence and the rudiments of the
differential and integral calculus. Little time is therefore left for con-
sideration of the foundations of the subject. But the foundational issues are
too important to be neglected or to be left entirely in the hands of the
algebraists (whose views on what is important do not always coincide with
those of an analyst). In particular, a good grasp of the material treated in
this book is essential as a basis for more advanced work in analysis. The
fact remains, however, that a quart will not fit into a pint bottle and only so
many topics can be covered in a given number of lectures. In my own
lecture course I deal with this problem to some extent by encouraging
students to read the more elementary material covered in this book for
themselves, monitoring their progress through problem classes. This seems
to work quite well and it is for this reason that substantial sections of the
text have been written with a view to facilitating 'self-study', even though
this leads to a certain amount of repetition and of discussion of topics which
some readers will find very elementary. Readers are invited to skip rather
briskly through these sections if at all possible.
This is the first of two books with the common title
Foundations of Analysis: A Straightforward Introduction.
The current book, subtitled
Logic, Sets and Numbers,
was conceived as an introduction to the second book, subtitled
Topological Ideas
and as a companion to the author's previous book
Mathematical Analysis: A Straightforward Approach.
Although Logic, Sets and Numbers may profitably be read independently of
these other books, I hope that some teachers will wish to use the three books
together as a basis for a sequence oflectures to be given in the first two years of a
mathematics degree.
ix
x Introduction
Certain sections of the book have been marked with a t and printed in
smaller type. This indicates material which, although relevant and interest-
ing, I regard as unsuitable for inclusion in a first year analysis course,
usually because it is too advanced, or else because it is better taught as part
of an algebra course. This fact is reflected in the style of exposition adopted
in these sections, much more being left to the reader than in the body of the
text. Occasionally, on such topics as Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory or
transfinite arithmetic, only a brief indication of the general ideas is attem-
pted. Those reading the book independently of a taught course would be
wise to leave those sections marked with a t for a second reading.
A substantial number of exercises have been provided and these should
be regarded as an integral part of the text. The exercises are not intended as
intelligence tests. By and large they require little in the way of ingenuity.
and, in any case, a large number of hints are given. The purpose of the
exercises is to give the reader an opportunity to test his or her under-
standing of the text. Mathematical concepts are sometimes considerably
more subtle than they seem at first sight and it is often not until one has
failed to solve some straightforward exercises based on a particular concept
that one begins to realise that this is the case.
Finally, I would like to thank Mimi Bell for typing the manuscript for me
so carefully and patiently.
n n 3 - 4n 2 + Sn- 1
1 1
2 1
3 5
4 19
5 49
6 101
1.4 Example In the diagram below, the point 0 has been chosen as
the point of intersection of the bisector of the angle A and the perpendicular
bisector of the side BC. The dotted lines are then constructed as shown.
With the help of this diagram we shall show by the methods of elemen-
tary geometry that AB= AC - i.e. all triangles are isosceles.
The triangles AEO and AFO are congruent and hence
AE=AF (1)
OE=OF. (2)
Proofs 3
to specify how these symbols may be put together to make up formulae and
then how such formulae may be put together to make up sentences.
Next, it is necessary to specify which of these sentences are to be called
axioms.
Finally, we must specify rules of deduction which will tell us under what
circumstances a sentence may be deduced from other sentences.
A mathematical proof of a theorem S is then defined to be a list of
sentences, the last of which is S. Each sentence in the list must be either an
axiom or else a deduction from sentences appearing earlier in the list.
What is more, we demand that all of the processes described above be
specified so clearly and unambiguously that even that arch-idiot of in-
tellectuals, the computer, could be programmed to check that a given list of
sentences is a proof.
Of course, the ideas set out above only represent an ideal. It is one thing
to set a computer to checking a list of several million sentences and quite
another to prepare such a list for oneself. Apart from any other considera-
tion, it would be extremely boring.
1.6 Example The list of sentences given below shows what a formal
proof looks like. It is a proof taken from S. C. Kleene's Introduction to
Metamathematics (North-Holland, 1967) of the proposition 'a=a'. This does
not happen to be one of his axioms and therefore needs to be proved as a
theorem.
(1) a=b =(a=c =h=c)
(2) 0=0 =>(0=0 =>0=0)
(3) (a=b =(a=c =>h=c)} => {[0=0 =(0=0 =0=0)] =>
[a=b =>(a=c =h=c)]}
(4) [0=0 =>(0=0 =0=0)] => [a=b =>(a=c =h=c)]
(5) [0=0 =>(0=0 =0=0)] => l;ic[a=b =>(a=c =h=c)]
(6) [0 = 0 =>(0 = 0 =>0 = 0)] => \;7' b\;7' c[a = b =(a =c =>h =c)]
(7) [0 = 0 =>(0 = 0 =>0 = 0)] => \;7' a\;7' b\;7' c[a = b =(a =c =>b =c)]
(8) \;7' aVbVc[a=b =>(a=c =>h=c)]
(9) \;7' a\;ibl;ic[a=b =>(a=c =h=c)] => VbVc[a+O=b =(a +O=c =>b =c)]
(10) VbVc[a+O=b=(a+O=c=b=c)]
(11) \;7' b\;7' c[a + 0= b =(a+ O=c =>h =c)]=> \;7' c[a + 0 =a =(a+ 0 =c =>a =c)]
(12) Vc[a+O=a=(a+D=c=a=c)]
(13) \;7' c[a +O=a =>(a+O =c =a =c)]=> [a +O=a =(a +O=a =>a =a)]
(14) a+O=a=(a+O=a=a=a)
(15) a+ O=a
(16) a+O=a=a=a
(17) a=a.
Proofs 5
The above example is given only to illustrate that the formal proofs of
even the most trivial propositions are likely to be long and tedious. What is
more, although a computer may find formal proofs entirely satisfactory, the
human mind needs to have some explanation of the 'idea' behind the proof
before it can readily assimilate the details of a formal argument.
What mathematicians do in practice therefore is to write out 'informal
proofs' which can 'in principle' be reduced to lists of sentences suitable for
computer ingestion. This may not be entirely satisfactory, but neither is the
dreadfully boring alternative. In this book our approach will be even less
satisfactory from the point of view of those seeking 'absolute certainty',
since we shall not even describe in detail the manner in which mathematical
assertions can be coded as formal lists of symbols. We shall, however, make
a serious effort to remain true to the spirit of a mathematical proof, if not to
the letter.
1.7 Obvious
The word 'obvious' is much abused. We shall follow the famous
English mathematician G. H. Hardy in interpreting the sentence 'P is
obvious' as meaning 'It is easy to think of a proof of P'. This usage accords
with what was said in the section above.
A much more common usage is to interpret 'P is obvious' as meaning 'I
cannot think of a proof of P but I am sure it must be true'. This usage
should be avoided.
2.1 Statements
The purpose of logic is to label sentences either with the symbol T
(for true) or with the symbol F (for false). A sentence which can be labelled
in one of these two ways will· be called a statement.
2.3 Exercise
Which of the following sentences are statements?
(i) More than 10 000 000 people live in New York City.
(ii) Is Paris bigger than Rome?
(iii) Go jump in a lake!
(iv) The moon is made of green cheese.
2.4 Equivalence
From the point of view of logic, the only thing which really
matters about a statement is its truth value (i.e. T or F). Thus two
statements P and Q are logically equivalent and we write
P~Q
if they have the same truth value. If P and Q are both statements, then so is
P~Q and its truth value may be determined with the aid of the following truth
table.
7
8 Logic (I)
p Q P"""'Q
T T T
T F F
F T F
F F T
In this table the right-hand column contains the truth value of 'P"""'Q' for
all possible combinations of the truth values of the statements P and Q.
2.6 Not
If Pis a statement, the truth value of the statement (not P) may be
determined from the following truth table.
P not P
T F
F T
2.7 And, or
If P and Q are statements, the statements 'P and Q' and 'P or Q'
are defined by the following truth tables.
p Q P and Q p Q P or Q
T T T T T T
T F F T F T
F T F F T T
F F F F F F
The English language is somewhat ambiguous in its use of the word 'or'.
Sometimes it is used in the sense of 'eitherfor' and sometimes in the sense of
'andjor'. In mathematics it is always used in the second of these two senses.
but 'P and (not Q)' is true. On the other hand, 'P or Q' and 'P or (not Q)'
are both true.
2.9 Exercise
There should be eight rows in the table to account for all the possible
truth value combinations of P, Q and R.]
(3) From 2(ii) above it follows that it does not matter how brackets are
inserted in the expressions 'P or (Q or R)' and '(P or Q) or R' and so we
might just as well write 'P or Q or R'. Equally we may write 'P and Q
and R' instead of the statements of 2(iii).
Show by truth tables that the statements '(P and Q) or R' and 'P and
(Q or R)' need not be equivalent.
(4) Deduce from 2(iv) that the statements 'P and (Q 1 or Q 2 or Q 3 )', '(P and
Qd or (P and Q2 ) or (P and Q3 )' are equivalent. Write down similar
results which arise from 2(v), 2(vi) and 2(vii). What happens with four or
more Qs?
2.10 Implies
Suppose that P and Q are two statements. Then the statement
'P implies Q' (or 'P =Q') is defined by the following truth table.
10 Logic(/)
p Q P implies Q
T T T
T F F
F T T
F F T
In simple terms the truth of' P implies Q' means that, from the truth of P,
we can deduce the truth of Q. In English this is usually expressed by saying
'If P, then Q'
or sometimes
'P is a sufficient condition for Q'.
It strikes some people as odd that 'P implies Q' should be defined as true
in the case when P is false. This is so that a proposition like 'x > 2 implies
x > 1' may be asserted to be true for all values of x.
Consider next the following truth table.
Observe that the entries in the third and sixth columns are identical. This
means that the statements 'P implies Q' and ~(not Q) implies (not P)' are
either both true or both false- i.e. they are logically equivalent. Wherever we
see 'P implies Q' we might therefore just as well write '(not Q) implies (not
P)' since this is an equivalent statement.
The statement '(not Q) implies (not P)' is called the contrapositive of 'P
implies Q'. In ordinary English it is usually rendered in the form
'P only if Q'
or sometimes
'Q is a necessary condition for P'.
These last two expressions are therefore two more paraphrases for the
simple statement 'P implies Q'.
2.11 Exercise
(1) Given that the statements 'P' and 'P=Q' are both true, deduce that Q is
true. [Hint: Delete from the truth table for P=Q those rows which do
Logic (J) 11
not apply.] If, instead, you are given that the statements 'Q' and 'P=Q'
are true, show that no conclusion may be drawn about the truth
value of P (unless further information is available).
[Note: The first rule of deduction described above is called 'Modus
Ponens'. To deduce P from 'Q' and 'P=Q' has been called 'Modus
Morons'.]
(2) Given that P=Q is true but Q false, show that P is false.
(3) The great philosopher Descartes based his system of philosophy on the
principle 'cogito ergo sum' (I think, therefore I am). Dr Strabismus
(whom God preserve) of Utrecht has founded a rival system based on
the principle 'Non cogito ergo non sum' (I do not think, therefore I am~
not).
Express both these principles in the form 'P=Q' and hence clear Dr
Strabismus (and the Daily Express, where his thoughts were once
published) from the insinuation that his principle may be deduced from
that of Descartes.
(4) Rain on Tuesday is a necessary condition for rain on Sunday. If it rains
on Tuesday then it rains on Wednesday. But it rains on Wednesday
only if it rains on Friday. Moreover no rain Monday implies no rain on
Friday. Finally, rain on Monday is a sufficient condition for rain on
Saturday.
Express each of these statements in the form 'P=Q'. Given that it
rains on Sunday, what can be said about Saturday's weather?
(5) Show that the statement 'P implies Q' is equivalent to '(not P) or Q'.
Deduce that 'P implies Q' is also equivalent to 'not {P and (not Q)}'.
(6) What conclusion (if any) may be drawn from the truth of '(not P)=P'?
Observe that the entries in the fifth and sixth columns are identical. Thus to
say that 'P is logically equivalent to Q' is the same thing as saying
'(P implies Q) and (Q implies P)'.
In ordinary English this statement is usually expressed in the form
'P if and only if Q'
12 Logic (I)
- i.e. '(P only if Q) and (if Q then P)'. Alternatively it may be paraphrased as
'P is a necessary and sufficient condition for Q'.
3.2 Examples
(i) Let the universal set be the set IR of all real numbers. Some examples
of predicates which are meaningful for this universal set are:
(a) x>3 (b) 2x=x 2 (c) x+ y=z.
14
Logic (II) 15
3.3 Exercise
(1) Let the universal set V be the set N of all natural numbers (i.e. 1, 2,
3, ... ). Then, for example, {x: 2 ~x ~4} = {2, 3,4}. Obtain similar identities
in each of the following cases.
(i) {x:x 2 -3x+2=0} (ii) {x:x 2 -x+2=0}
(iii) {x:x 2 +3x+2=0} (iv) {x:x 2 ~3+x}.
(2) Let the universal set V be the set IR1 of all real numbers. If
S={x:x 2 -3x+2~0},
16 Logic (11)
3.4 Quantifiers
A predicate may be converted into a statement by substituting for
the variables objects from their range. For example, the predicate 'x > 3'
becomes the false statement '2 > 3' when 2 is substituted for x.
Another way that predicates may be converted into statements is with the
use of the quantifiers 'for any' and 'there exists'.
For example, from the predicates 'x > 3' and 'x loves y' we may obtain the
statements
'For any x, x> 3'
'For any y, there exists an x such that x loves y'.
These statements may be paraphrased in the more natural forms 'All real
numbers are bigger than three' and 'Everybody can find somebody to love
them'.
It is sometimes convenient to use the abbreviations 'V' instead of 'for any'
and '3' instead of 'there exists'. With this notation the statements above
become
Vx(x> 3)
Vy 3x(x loves y).
3.5 Exercise
(1) Paraphrase in ordinary English the following statements. Venture an
opinion in each case as to whether the given statement is true or false.
(i) 3x(x>3) (ii) Vx(2x=x 2 ) (iii) VxVz3y(x+y=z)
(iv) 3x(x is President) (v) 3xV y(x loves y).
(2) Examine carefully the meaning of the two statements
(i) Vy3x(x<y) (ii) 3xVy(x<y)
and explain why they are not the same.
(3) Introduce the abbreviations V and 3 into the following sentence:
'For any number x, we can find a number z such
that for every number y, xy = z'.
(4) If the universal set U is the set of all natural numbers, find the elements
Logic (If) 17
of the sets
(i) {x: li y(xy= y)} (ii) {x: 3y(xy=12)}.
3.7 Example Let the universal set be the set of all human beings and
consider the statement
li x(God loves x).
This mode of reasoning leads us to the rules embodied in the table below.
Statement Contradictory
Vx P(x) 3x(not P(x))
3x P(x) V x(not P(x))
As we have seen above, these rules only have something new to say in the
case when x ranges over an infinite set.
18 Logic (11)
3.8 Example
Statement Contradictory
Vx(x>3) 3x(x;;:23)
3x(2x=x 2 ) Vx(2x#x 2 )
:Jx V y(x loves y) Vx 3y(x does not love y)
\fx \fz 3y(x+y=z) :Jx :Jz lfy(x+y#z)
The third of these may be obtained in two stages. First one notes that 'not
:Jx Vy(x loves y)' is equivalent to 'V x {not Vy(x loves y)}' which is in turn
equivalent to 'Vx :Jy {not (x loves y)}'.
3.9 Exercise
(1) Write down the contradictories of the following statements in a useful
form.
(i) Vy :Jx(x<y) (ii) :Jx Vy(x<y)
(iii) :Jx(x>3 and x=4)
(iv) Everybody can find someone to love them.
(2) Apart from the rules for forming contradictories discussed above there
are some other rules for use with quantifiers. The table below contains a
list of equivalent statements.
Justify the third of these equivalences in the case when x ranges over a
finite set.
3.11 Examples
(i) The contradictory of the statement 'There exists an x < 1 such that
x 2 =1' is 'For any x<1, x 2 #1'.
(ii) The contradictory of the statement 'For any x<4 there exists a y>2
such that x + y = 3' is 'There exists an x < 4 such that for any y > 2, x + y # 3'.
3.12 Exercise
(1) Write down in a useful form the contradictories of the following
statements:
(i) There exists an x < 3 such that x > 2.
(ii) For any x satisfying 0 < x < 1, x 2 < x.
(iii) For any s > 0 there exists a c5 > 0 such that for any x satis-
fying 0 <x < c5, x 2 <s (i.e. x 2 ~0 as x~o + ).
(iv) Some Montague is hated by every Capulet.
3.15 Example Show that it is false that rxP is irrational for all positive
irrational real numbers rx and p.
20 Logic (11)
4.1 Subsets
If S and T are sets, we say that S is a subset of T and write
SeT
if every element of S is also an element of T - i.e. xE S implies xE T.
4.2 Example Let A= {1, 2, 3, 4} and let B= {2, 4}. Then Be A. Notice
that this is not the same thing as writing BE A (i.e. B is an element of A). The
elements of A are simply 1, 2, 3 and 4 and B is not one of these.
relation SeT. The universal set is represented by the square and the sets S
and T by the shaded regions within the square.
4.3 Exercise
(1) Arrange the sets given in exercise 3.3(1) in a list, each item of which is a
subset of the item which follows it.
21
22 Set operations
(2) Draw a Venn diagram to illustrate the relation 'S is not a subset of T'.
(3) Justify the following
(i) S c U (ii) (/) c S (iii) S c S.
[Hint: Recall that(/) denotes the empty set. Thus, for any x, xE0 is false
and therefore implies anything!]
(4) Prove that S= T if and only if SeT and TcS. [Hint: S= T means
'xES~xET'.]
4.4 Complements
Ifs is a set, its complement es is defined by
S={x:x~S}.
4.5 Example Let the universal set U be the set of all real numbers
and let S={x:x>O}. Then
e S={x:x~O}.
4.6 Exercise
(1) Let U = {1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6}. Write down the complements of the sets {1, 2}
and {1, 3, 5}.
(2) Prove the following.
(i) e (e S)=S (ii) eu=(/) (iii) e(/)=U.
Set operations 23
~SUT
4.8 Examples
(i) {1, 2}u{1, 3, 5} = {1, 2, 3, 5}
(ii) {1, 2}n{1, 3, 5} = {1}.
4.9 Exercise
( 1) We use the notation A \ B to denote the set of all elements of A which
do not belong to B - i.e. A\ B =An e B. Indicate the set A\ B on a
Venn diagram.
(2) Two sets A and Bare called disjoint if they have no elements in common
- i.e. A nB = (j). Illustrate this situation on a Venn diagram.
(3) Use exercise 2.9(2) to obtain the following identities.
(i) An(BnC)=(AnB)nC
(ii) Au(BuC)=(AuB)uC
(iii) Au(BnC)=(AuB)n(AuC)
(iv) An(BuC)=(AnB)u(AnC)
(v) e (AnB)= eAu eB
(vi) e (AuB)= eAn eB.
/
~ e(A UB) :sCAn CB
4.10 Exercise
(1) Illustrate each of the identities of exercise 4.9(3) by means of a pair of
Venn diagrams.
4.11 Examples
(i) Suppose that W contains only three sets, P, Q and R - i.e.
W={P, Q, R}. Then
U S=PuQuR (\ S=PnQnR.
SE"U' SEW
~/ s.w
us ~ ns
'-
" s,U'
Set operations 25
4.12 Exercise
(1) Let W be the collection {A, B, C, D} where A={l, 3, 4}, B={l, 2, 4},
C={2, 3, 4}, D={l, 4}. What are the elements of the sets
(i) u s (ii) n s?
SEW SEW
XEY
and all proofs referred to a single set of axioms - i.e. the axioms of set theory.
26 Set operations
subset of the other. To make the definition useful, another assumption is required.
This is called the axiom of extensionality. Essentially, it asserts that, if x = y, then y
can be substituted for x in any statement without altering the truth value of the
statement.
Zermelo-Fraenkel theory requires two further assumptions which it is convenient
to postpone to later chapters. These are called the axiom of infinity and the axiom of
choice. It is a remarkable fact that the whole of traditional mathematics can be
based on the principles of logic and these six simple assumptions about the
properties of sets.
5 RELATIONS
b - - - - - - - - - -, (a, b)
(0, 0) a X
We say that (a, b) is an ordered pair because the order in which a and b
appear is relevant. For example, (3, 4) does not represent the same point in
the plane as (4, 3).
How can we define an ordered pair in general? We certainly do not wish
to identify (a, b) with the set {a, b}. Both {3, 4} and {4, 3}, for example,
denote the same set. For this reason, the set {a, b} is often called an
unordered pair.
A viable alternative is to define
(a, b)= {a, {a, b}}
- i.e. (a, b) is defined to be the set whose elements are a and the set {a, b},
However, the precise form of the definition is irrelevant for our purposes.
Any definition which ensures that (a, b)= (c, d) if and only if a= c and b = d
will do just as well.
28
Relations 29
AXB
5.3 Relations
Any subset R of A x B defines a relation between A and B. If
(a, b)E R, we say that the relation R holds between a and b and write
a R b.
A XB
B
30 Relations
5.4 Examples
(i) Let A and B both be the set of all human beings and write a R b if and
only if 'a loves b'. In accordance with the remarks above we may identify
the relation R with the set
R={(a, b):a loves b}.
(ii) Let A be the set N of natural numbers and let B be the set 71. of
integers. We write alb if and only if 'a divides b', i.e. b = ma for some integer
m. Some ordered pairs in the set
R={(a, b):alb}
are (2, 6), (3, -21), (1, 7).
5.6 Examples
(i) An example of an equivalence relation on the set A of all human
beings is the relation R defined by a R b if and only if 'a and b have the
same mother'.
Relations 31
5.7 Theorem Two distinct equivalence classes are disjoint (i.e. have no
points in common).
5.8 Orderings
An ordering ~ on a set A is a relation between A and itself which
satisfies the following properties for each a, b and c in A:
(i) a~b or b~a (totality)
32 Relations
5.9 Examples
(i) The set ~ of all real numbers is ordered by the relation ~ of
increasing magnitude. This is the ordering with which we shall be chiefly
concerned in this book.
(ii) If A is a set, its power set S' (A) is the set whose elements are the
subsets of A. For example, if A={l, 2}, then 9'(A)={<P, {1}, {2), {1, 2)}.
Observe that the relation c is a partial ordering on S' (A).
5.10 Exercise
(1) Let A= { 1, 2, 3, 4, 5}. Let R be the relation between A and itself defined
by a R b if and only if a and b have the same remainder when divided by
2. Prove that R is an equivalence relation on A and determine the
equivalence classes it induces on A.
(2) Write aib if a and b are natural numbers and a divides b exactly. Show
that the relation so defined is a partial ordering on N.
(3) Explain why <=> is an equivalence relation on the set of all statements.
t(4) What is wrong with the following argument which purports to show that the
reflexive property for an equivalence relation may be deduced from the other
two properties? By the symmetry property, a Rh and bRa. Taking c =a in the
transitivity property then yields a R a.
Show, however, that the reflexivity property for an ordering may be deduced
from the totality condition.
t(5) LetS' (A) denote the set of all subsets of a set A.
(i) Prove that c is a partial ordering on S' (A).
(ii) Show that the relation R defined on S' (A) by
a R h=lfx(xEA<=>.YEB)
is an equivalence relation on S' (A).
t(6) Let ~ be a total ordering on a set A. Define the associated 'strict ordering'
relation <l by
a<:Jh=(a:;::Jh and a"# b).
Prove that <l is a transitive relation. Is <l a total relation? Is <l antisymmetric?
6 FUNCTIONS
defines a function g: IR: --.IR:. Any value XE IR: substituted in the right-hand
side will yield a unique corresponding value of yEIR: on the left-hand side.
But we shall wish to define functions in more complicated ways than this.
The expressions h(1)= 1 and
AXB
(x, y)
33
34 Functions
several points of B. Each point xEA has a unique image yEB. One
sometimes reads of 'one-many functions' but this is an abuse of language
which we shall rigorously avoid.
6.2 Terminology
If f: A--> B is a function from A to B, we call the set A the domain
off and the set B the codomain off If S c A, we call the set
f(S) = {f(x): XE S}
the image of the set S under the function f In particular, f(A) is called the
range off Note that the range of a function need not be the whole of the
codomain - i.e. it need not be true that f(A) =B.
6.3 Examples
(i) A sequence is simply a function whose domain is the set N of all
natural numbers. The nth term of a sequence f: N -+IR is defined to be
x" = f(n). We use the notation <x") to denote the sequence whose nth term is
x .. Thus the sequence <n 2 + 1) is to be identified with the function g: N -+IR
defined by
g(n)=n 2 + 1 (n= 1, 2, 3, ... ).
The first few terms of this sequence are
2, 5, 10, 17, 26, 37, 50, ....
(ii) The equations
2
u=x +
V=X2- y2
i}
define a function f: IR 2 -+IR 2 • The image of (x, y) under f is
(u, v)=(x 2 + y 2 , x 2 - yZ).
Functions 37
u-v=2y ~0. 2
and hence, for example, the point (u, v) = ( -1, - l) is not the image of
anything under this function. In fact
f(IR 2 )={(u, v):u~v and u~-v}.
Nor is f injective. The equations
2
5=x +
3=xz- Yz
l}
have four solutions for (x, y)- namely (2, 1), (2, -l), ( -2, 1) and ( -2, -1).
y V u=v
I
xz + yz = 5\
f
(iii) Let A= {x: x ~0} and B= {y: y~ 1}. The function[: A --->B defined by
f(x)=x 2 +1 (x~O)
is a bijection and hence has an inverse functionf- 1 : B--->A. Since, for each
x~O and y~ 1,
x =f - 1(y)=-y =f(x),
a formula for f - 1 can be obtained by solving the equation y = x 2 + 1 to
obtain x in terms of y. Because y~ 1, the equation has a solution. Moreover,
as x~O, the solution is unique and is given by x=J(y-1). (Remember
J
that, if z ~ 0, then z denotes the non-negative number whose square is z.)
Thus
38 Functions
f X
X
A B
Note that either graph can be obtained from the other by a rotation about
the line x = y.
6.4 Exercise
(1) Consider the function/: ~ 2 -+~ 2 defined by f(x, y)=(u, v) where
u=x+y}
v=x-y.
Prove that f is a bijection and obtain a formula for its inverse
function. Findf(S) and/- 1 (T) in the case S=T={(x, y):O~x~1 and
O~y~1}.
(2) Let A={O: O<O~tn} and B={<P: -n<<P~n}. A function
g: A x B-+~ 2 is defined by (x, y)=g(8, <P) where
6.5 Composition
Suppose that f: B--+ C and g: A--+ B. Then their composition
fog:A-+C is defined by
fog(x)=f(g(x)) (xEA).
But what was this? Purple Cap, who had gone in last because he was so
confident that he "wasn't worth a run," had cracked the first ball to the ditch
for four and snicked the next for one. Twenty! Well, well, this was not
disgraceful. He had the bowling again. The first ball went over the hedge—
six; the second bounded down the hill towards the valley—four-thirty.
"Well, he is a one-er," said the scorer, changing his straw to the other side of
his mouth. Panic seized the bowlers; the fielders went farther and farther
out into the landscape. But Purple Cap was insatiable. He seemed not a man
but a hurricane. He leapt at everything with a devouring fury and the ball
flew here, there, and everywhere. Once the stumper appealed, but he had
the wrong umpire for judge. My bat was smashed, but I didn't care. "Send
him more bats," I shouted. The score rose like magic. "A regular pelthoria
of runs," said the publican. Forty—fifty (the match was won)—sixty—
seventy——eighty—eighty-five—then a well-directed throw-in from the
long-field knocked the wicket down. "How's that?" Up went the venerable
umpire's arm like a semaphore at the familiar sound. And Purple Cap came
back to the tussock in triumph.
"It was just as I said," remarked the publican when I saw him standing
before the inn later in the evening. "'Mark my words,' I said, 'there's a dark
horse in that lot somewhere,' and a dark horse there was. I ain't seen
anything like it since my soldiering days in India. Killed a python we did—
dead as a door-nail down to the last two-foot of his tail. I put my arm on his
tail and he closed round it that tight you couldn't pull him away until his tail
was dead too. I ain't seen such a lively tail since until I set eyes on that chap
in the purple cap this evening. He's stirred this place up and no mistake.
They won't forget him in a hurry."
Of course, the bat must remain. It was not a bat, but a living memorial, a
thing that talked to me a joyous private language and seemed to secrete by
some magic the very essence of myself. To destroy it would be a sort of
suicide. As well might Nelson have broken up the timbers of the old Victory
to heat the kitchen fire. I rubbed the dust from its battered face and put it
honourably in the corner.
And what is this vast cover, sticking out, dog-eared, from the lumber?
My old portfolio, given me forty-six years ago as a tribute from admiring
parents to my artistic achievements. How I gloried in its ample blue covers.
Why, Landseer himself, the incomparable Landseer, must have such a
portfolio as that. And I laboured with my pencil to fill it with things worthy
of its dignity, and here they were to-day, old portraits of grandmothers and
aunts and copies of Landseer's dogs and horses and Peter Paul in his big hat,
and the serene Dürer, with his long flaxen curls, and, on each one, in large,
bold, boyish writing, "Drawn by ——" and the date carefully put in lest
posterity should not know that these miracles were done by one so young.
Ay de mi, as old Carlyle used to say. Ay de mi....
Jane observed just now that she was sure the days were drawing out. We
laughed, as we were expected to, at the immemorial remark, but we
cheerfully agreed that there was truth in it. We looked at our watches. It was
past four and the landscape of half a dozen counties still lay, darkening but
visible from the hillside, while in the garden the thrushes were singing as
though it were a summer evening. The moon, which had been faintly visible
long before the sun had set, was beginning to take up "the wondrous tale." It
was that bewitching moment of the day when the two luminaries are about
equally matched and the light of the moon filters through the light of the
day and a new scheme of shadows begins to take shape about you as you
walk.
If I were asked to name the chief difference between living in town (as I
used to do) and living in the country (as I now chiefly do), I think I should
say that it consisted in the place which the moon fills in our everyday life,
especially of course in the dark season of the year. It might almost be said
that we do not discover the moon until we live in the country. In town it is
only another and a rather larger lamp hung aloft the street. We do not need
it to light us on our way and are indifferent to its coming and going. If it
shines, well; if it does not shine, no matter. We go about our business in
either case, and do not consult the calendar to know whether such-and-such
a night will be light enough to go to the theatre or to dinner with Aunt Anne
at Kensington, as the case may be. Nothing but fog can interfere with these
amenities and the calendar is uninformed as to the vagaries of the fog.
But in the country the moon is not an unconsidered and casual visitor
whose movements are of such little account that we do not trouble to study
them. It is, on the contrary, the most important and most discussed
neighbour we have. In town we do not think of the moon in neighbourly
terms. It is something remote and foreign, that does not come within the
scope of our system. We should miss the lamp across the road that sends a
friendly ray through our window-curtains all night, and if we went down to
Piccadilly Circus one evening and did not see the coloured signs twinkling
on the shop-fronts we should feel lonely and bereaved. But if the moon did
not turn up one evening according to plan, hardly one Londoner in a
thousand would notice the fact. He would read about it in the newspapers
next day and talk about it coming up to the City in the tube, but he would
not have discovered the fact himself or have been sensible of any loss.
But it is the moon that is our most precious neighbour. Its phases are as
much a part of the practical mechanism of life as the winding-up of the
clock, and the hour of its rising and setting regulates our comings and
goings. If it failed to turn up one night all the countryside would know
about it. There would be a universal hue-and-cry and no one would sleep in
his bed for watching. When the sickle of the new moon appears in the
sunset sky the cheerful nights set in. There is no need to light the lantern if
we want to go to the wood-shed or to the chicken-run at the end of the
garden to investigate some unfamiliar sound that proceeds from thence. If
there is anything contemplated at the village schoolroom down in the valley
it is fixed for an evening when the moon is high to light us by road or field-
path; and when the moon is near the full we reach the high festival of our
country nights. Then, no matter how busy the day has been or how
comfortable the fireside is, the call of our neighbour the moon to come out
and see the magic he can throw over the landscape is irresistible.
It is irresistible now. While I have been writing, the moon has been
gathering power. The night is clear and full of stars. There is the glisten of
frost on the grass. The wind has fallen and the plain that glimmers below in
the moonlight is soundless. It would be a sin not to be abroad on such a
night. Moreover Ben and Jeff need a run before settling down for sleep.
They love the moonlight too, not for its poetry but for its aid in the
ceaseless, but ever unrewarded, task of exploring rabbit-holes and other
futile hints of sport. "Come, Ben! Come, Jeff! ... Walk."
ON SMILES
If I were to be born into this world again and had the choice of my
endowments I should arrange very carefully about my smile. There is
nothing so irresistible as the right sort of smile. It is better than the silver
spoon in the mouth. It will carry you anywhere and win you anything,
including the silver spoon. It disarms your enemies and makes them forget
that they have a grudge against you. "I have a great many reasons for
disliking you," said a well-known public man to a friend of mine the other
day, "but when I am with you I can never remember what they are." It was
the flash of sunshine that did for him. He could not preserve his hostility in
the presence of the other's disarming smile and gay good-humour. He just
yielded up his sword and sunned himself in the pleasant weather that the
other carried with him like an atmosphere.
Really first-rate smiles are rare. For the most part our smiles add little to
our self-expression. If we are dull, they are dull. If we are sinister, they are
only a little more sinister. If we are smug, they only emphasise our
smugness. If, like the Lord High Everything Else, we were born sneering,
our smile is apt to be a sneer, too. If we are terrible, like Swift, we shall
have his "terrible smile." Only rarely do we light upon the smile that is a
revelation. Harry Lauder's smile is like a national institution or a natural
element. It is plentiful enough to fill the world. It is a continual and
abundant feast that requires neither words nor chorus, and when he laughs
you can no more help feeling happy than he can. Lord Balfour's smile is
famous in another way. It has the untroubled sweetness of a child's, and
there are few who can resist its charm; but it is elusive and seems too much
like a mask that has little to do with the real man. You feel that he would
send you to the scaffold with the same seraphic sweetness with which he
would pass you the sugar. It is not an emanation of the man like that
abundant smile, at once good-humoured and sardonic, with which Mr.
Birrell sets the company aglow.
The most memorable smiles are those which have the quality of the
unexpected. A smile that is habitual rarely pleases, for it suggests policy,
and the essence of a smile is its spontaneity and lack of deliberation.
Archbishop Temple said he hated people who were always smiling, and
then, looking across the luncheon table at the vicar who had been doing his
best to ingratiate himself with the terrible prelate, added: "Look at the vicar
there—he's always smiling." It was a cruel affront, but the smile that has the
quality of an artifice is hard to bear. It was so in the case of Mrs. Barbauld,
of whom it was said that she wore such an habitual smile that it made your
face ache to look at her. One would almost prefer the other melancholy
extreme, illustrated by that gloomy fanatic, Philip II., who is said to have
laughed only once in his life, and that on receiving the merry news of the
massacre of St. Bartholomew. The smiles that dwell in the mind most are
those that break suddenly like sunshine from unexpected places. That was
the quality of the curiously wistful smile that played over the ascetic
features of Lord Morley in conversation. You could forgive all his asperities
when he smiled. But the most delightful example of the unexpected smile
that I know is that of the pianist, Frederic Lamond. The intensity of his
countenance forbids the suggestion of a smile, and at the piano he seems to
descend into unfathomable depths of gravity and spiritual remoteness. But
when the piece is over and the house breaks out into thunders of applause,
he emerges from the depths with a smile that suggests that the Land of
Beulah has broken on his sight. It is so sudden a transition that you almost
seem to catch a glimpse of the Land of Beulah yourself.
WHEN IN ROME...
I have not seen any reply from a certain distinguished Englishman who
has recently been in America to the resolution passed by an American
women's society, and published in the Press, denouncing certain alleged
proceedings of his as a moral affront to public opinion in America. The
allegations were to the effect that he had invited people to drink from his
private store of alcoholic liquor in the ante-rooms of some chapel where he
had been speaking, and that his daughter had smoked cigarettes in public.
Whether the statements were well-founded or an invention of the Press I do
not know, nor for the purpose I have in view does it matter. The incident
interests me, not as a question of morals but of manners. Morals are largely
a local thing, a question of latitude and climate, of custom and time. They
vary with the conditions of life and the habit of thought.
I am not sure that I even like moral missionaries from one country to
another. The offence, if it is an offence, is in a different category from that
of the man who publicly flouts the laws and customs of another land in
which he happens to be a visitor; but it certainly borders on bad manners. I
express no opinion about "Pussyfoot" Johnson's gospel, but I confess I
always feel an irritation at his intrusions here. However much I wanted the
country to be converted to his point of view, I should still wish that he
would stay at home and cultivate his own garden, and leave us to look after
our own morals and practices. And by the same token I should resent the
idea of a person going from this country to America and openly flouting its
public morality, or taking sides in a domestic controversy that happened to
be raging there. In short, it is a question not of morals, but of manners.
I do not think the idea I have in my mind could be better illustrated than
by a famous story of Spurgeon. I daresay it is familiar to some of my
readers, but it is so apposite and so good that they will not object to renew
its acquaintance. In the days of his unparalleled popularity, when the great
preacher filled the Tabernacle from floor to ceiling, it was the custom of the
young bucks sometimes to show by their ill-manners their contempt for
something they did not understand. One night three of them went into the
gallery with their hats on, and refused to remove them when the attendant
requested them to do so. Spurgeon watched the incident, and when the
preliminaries of the service had been concluded and the time came for the
sermon, he prefaced his remarks with something like these words: "In all
the occasions of life it is our duty and should be our pleasure to respect the
feelings of others and the customs of others, even if we do not share them.
The other day I went into a Jewish synagogue and, according to my practice
when entering a place of worship, I removed my hat. But, having done so,
an attendant came to me and reminded me that in the Jewish synagogue it
was necessary that the head should be covered. I thanked him and, of
course, obeyed the reminder. Now" (looking up to the gallery and raising
his voice) "will those three young Jews in the gallery show that respect to
the customs of this place of worship which I showed to theirs?"
But though destiny is much a matter of chins, the Imp of Chance who
comes in and steals our trousers has no small part in determining our lives
and shaping events. I have read that Wallenstein in his youth had a crack on
the head which he, no doubt, felt was a misfortune, but it gave him just the
surgical treatment that converted him from a dullard into a great general.
Loyola got wounded in battle, and, thanks to that circumstance, found his
true vocation and became the creator of the greatest religious order in
history, and, with Luther, perhaps the greatest maker of history for six
centuries. Newton, according to the legend, sees an apple fall and starts a
train of thought that reveals one of the profoundest secrets of the universe. I
suppose no one who has advanced far in life can fail to recall trifles that
shaped the whole course of his career—a broken engagement, a misdirected
letter, a chance meeting. At the time it seemed nothing, and now, in the
retrospect, it is seen to have meant everything. The chin may dictate events
within limits, but the Imp of Chance has as often as not the final word.
It is in this way that the chapter of accidents plays havoc with the affairs
of men. All the woes of Ilium sprang from an elopement, and it is a
commonplace that if Cleopatra's nose had been a shade longer—or shorter,
for that matter—the whole story of the ancient world would have been
altered. I suppose the most momentous political event in the history of the
last thousand years was the rupture between England and America, which is
said to have happened as the result of a shower of rain. But for that rupture,
the British Commonwealth to-day would include the whole North American
Continent, and its word would be sovereign over the earth. Perhaps the seat
of authority would have been in Washington, instead of London, but
wherever it was it would have stabilised this reeling world and given its
people a security that now seems unattainable. The speculation which
attributes the enormous calamity of the loss of America to a shower of rain
is more fanciful, but hardly less reasonable, than that which Mr. Asquith
advances in regard to the European War. The Earl of Bute was the evil
genius of George III., and the inspiration of his disastrous policy. And the
origin of his sinister power was a storm at Epsom which kept the royal
party from going home. The Prince of Wales needed someone to make up a
hand at cards to pass the time while the shower lasted, and Bute, then a
young man, being handy, was selected, and from that incident ingratiated
himself with the Prince and still more with the Prince's wife. She
established his influence over her son whom later, as George III., he led into
the ruinous part of personal government which culminated in the Boston
Tea Party, the War of Independence, and the Republic of the Stars and
Stripes.
Chance does not, of course, always play a malevolent part like this. It
sometimes works as if with a superb and beneficent design. Lincoln, on the
threshold of fifty, regarded himself as having failed in life and he died at
fifty-six, one of the world's immortals. It was the quite unimportant incident
of his debate with Douglas that threw him into prominence on the eve of the
crisis which, but for his wisdom and magnanimity, would have left America
like Europe, a group of warring States. But in the end chance betrayed him.
On the night he was murdered the faithful guardian who had shadowed and
protected him throughout the war was sick, and his place was taken by a
substitute who became absorbed in the play, and allowed Booth to slip
unseen into the President's box and fire the fatal shot. But it might be
argued that even in this felon betrayal, chance only completed the splendour
of its design, for Lincoln's work was done, and it was the circumstances of
his death that threw the nobility of the man into relief for all time.
And while the accidents of life so often seem to take control of events, it
is no less true that our most deeply calculated schemes sometimes turn
round and smite us. When Queen Victoria's eldest daughter married the
King of Prussia's eldest son, it was universally agreed that a grand thing had
been done for the peace of the world, and when later a child was born, the
rejoicings in London, as you may read in the contemporary records, were
like those that welcome a great victory. That child was the ex-Kaiser
William, now an exile in Holland. In the light of to-day those rejoicings of
sixty odd years ago read like a grim comment on this queer and inexplicable
world.
IN DEFENCE OF "SKIPPING"
A few days ago Mr. Chesterton expressed a doubt whether he had ever
read Boswell "through." Knowing Mr. Chesterton, and having a life-long
acquaintance with Boswell, I share his doubt. G.K.C. has an amazing gift
for seizing the spirit and purport of a book by turning over the pages in
handfuls and sampling a sentence here and there. He treats books as the
expert wine-taster treats wines, not drinking them in great coarse gulps, but
moistening his lips and catching the bouquet on his palate. The parallel is
no doubt as misleading as most parallels are apt to be. Good wines have to
be "tasted" in this way, but the better the book the deeper should be the
draught or the more deliberate and patient the mastication. "Chewed and
digested" is Bacon's phrase.
But I am far too much addicted to "skipping" myself to treat the practice
as a crime in others. When I was young and industrious and enthusiastic I
read as solemnly and slavishly as anyone. I was like a dog with a bone. The
tougher the theme the more I exercised my intellectual molars on it. Stout
fellows like Zimmermann On Solitude, and Burke on The Sublime and
Beautiful, and Mill On Liberty were the sort of men for my youthful ardour.
I cannot honestly say I enjoyed them, but I can honestly say that I read
them, and I can also honestly say that I shall never read them or their like
again. I finished my drudgery long ago, and have become a mere idler
among books, a person who has served his apprenticeship and can go about
enjoying himself, taking a sip here and a longish "pull" there, passing over
this vintage, and returning to that and generally behaving like a freeman
wandering over the estates of the mind, without a duty to anything but his
own fancy.
I, too, doubt whether I have read Boswell through. Why should I read it
through? I have read the conversations a hundred times and I hope to read
them a hundred times more; but I will make no affidavit about the letters. I
suspect that I have been "skipping" the letters unconsciously all my life.
And Paradise Regained? My conscience is clear about Paradise Lost, and I
can still mouth the speeches of the first author of our misfortunes whom the
judgment of time had converted into the hero of that immortal poem. But
can I put my hand on my heart and say I have read the Regained right
through? I cannot. I am not even sure that I have read Shakespeare through.
I have a vague notion that in the lusty youth of which I have spoken I did
read Titus Andronicus and Pericles with the rest, but I am quite prepared to
believe that I only like to believe I did.
There is high precedent for those of us who "skip." Johnson himself was
a famous "skipper," and confessed that he seldom finished a book. It is true
that he performed the amazing feat of rising two hours before his usual time
to read Burton's Anatomy of Melancholy. He was a truthful man, or I should
find difficulty in believing him. Of course the achievement was not so great
as it seems, for though Johnson believed in early rising on principle and
recommended all young men to practise it, he did not himself rise until
noon. But the idea of getting up, if only at ten in the morning, with a
feverish desire to read Burton tries my faith even in Johnson's veracity. It is
pleasant to dip occasionally into that astonishing rag-box of learning, but
most of us are as likely to read Bradshaw's Time Table through as Burton's
Anatomy through. It is not a book; it is a curiosity.
This is not a plea for skimpy reading. It is good for the young to worry
their bone even if there is little meat on it. I would have them serve an
arduous apprenticeship in the great world of books, cleaving their own way
laboriously through the wilderness. The anthology business for the young is
a little over-done. The youthful digestion ought not to be weakened by an
exclusive diet of "elegant extracts," and spoon-feeding robs us of the joys of
discovery and adventure. What delight is there like encountering in the
wilderness some great unknown of whom we have never heard? It is like
coming into a fortune, or rather it is better than coming into a fortune, for
these are "riches fineless" that grow with compound interest and are not
subject to the vicissitudes of things. I found a young maiden of my
acquaintance the other day in a mood of unusual exaltation. She had fallen
in love and was hot with the first rapture of passion. She had encountered
Emma and was aflame with ardour for more adventures in the serene world
that Jane Austen had opened out before her. That is the way, casual and
unsought, that the realms of gold should be invaded. Youth should be
encouraged to fashion its own taste and discriminate for itself between the
good, the better and the best. When that is done we can "skip" as we like,
with an easy mind and a good conscience. We have learned our path
through the wilderness. We know where the hyacinths grow and where we
can catch the smell of the wild thyme, and the copse where the nightingale
sings to the moon. And if with this liberty of knowledge we "skip" some of
the high-brows, and are found more often in the company of Borrow than of
Bacon—well, we have done our task-work and are out to enjoy the sun and
the wind on the heath.
AN OLD ENGLISH TOWN
It was a wish of Seneca's that the wise and virtuous when they slept
could lend their thoughts and their feelings out to less wise and less virtuous
people. It would be equally admirable if we could occasionally let our
spiritual selves take wing and go on holiday, leaving the body at home to
carry on the routine business, receive callers, answer the telephone, pay the
bills, and so on. If it were possible for me to take such a holiday I should go
to Tewkesbury, where the eighth centenary of the famous Norman church of
that town is being celebrated. There was a time when I had no desire to go
to Tewkesbury. It was one of the places I did not want to go to because I
feared that seeing it would destroy the Tewkesbury of my fancy. No one
would hesitate to go to a place like Birmingham or Glasgow, for their
names awaken no emotions in the mind, and experience of them can shatter
no pleasant images.
Observe, not "the field at Tewkesbury" or "of Tewkesbury," but "the field
by Tewkesbury." A subtle difference, but enough to convince anyone who
has been to that field that Shakespeare wandered there in his young days,
perhaps boating thither from Stratford some summer day with Ann
Hathaway. Was it not Tewkesbury's mustard that Falstaff hurled at Poins—
or was it Pistol? "His wits are as thick as Tewkesbury mustard," he said. I
like to think that Falstaff stayed at the "Hop Pole" at Tewkesbury on that
famous recruiting journey into Gloucestershire, when he ate a pippin in
Squire Shallow's orchard, and that it was the mustard he got there that made
his eyes water and stuck in his memory. It was certainly at the "Hop Pole"
that Mr. Pickwick stopped for dinner on his journey from Bath. That is the
last time, I think, that anything important happened at Tewkesbury. Since
then it has slept, and one liked to think it was sleeping in a beautiful
mediæval dream, undisturbed by anything more modern than an occasional
stage-coach or the horn of the red-coated huntsman clattering through the
street.
That was how I liked to think of Tewkesbury, and I stayed away from it,
lest I should find it was all cinemas, fried-fish shops and tin tabernacles.
But one day last summer I was journeying by road from Wales and found
Tewkesbury in my path, and that it was convenient to stay like Mr.
Pickwick at the "Hop Pole." And now I know that Tewkesbury is as good as
its name, and that I can go there and see as perfect a bit of old England as
can be seen from the Tamar to the Tweed. Of course, a city like York will
give you infinitely more, layer on layer of history written on its stones,
telling of the England of the Britons, of the Romans, the Saxons, the
Normans, and so onward.
I was travelling down to Devonshire the other day when I met a man in
the train with whom I fell into conversation. It was a wonderful day. We had
left the fog behind us in London and the countryside glowed, rich and
warm, under the sunshine of a cloudless November day. It seemed an
occasion on which one could have found a thousand agreeable things to talk
about, but I noticed that wherever the conversation with the stranger started
it always got round to the taxation of land values. Now I happen to be in
favour of the taxation of land values. It is a question about which my mind
is as clear as it is about anything in this perplexing world. I am prepared to
vote in favour of it in due season and to speak in favour of it when I think
any useful purpose can be served. But I confess I got painfully bored by this
well-meaning man and that I hailed the opportunity of going to the
restaurant car to lunch with secret thanksgiving. I don't think I shall ever be
caught tête-à-tête with that missionary of the One Idea again. I have got
him on the list of People I Can Do Without.
I am not concerned here with the merits of his obsession. I refer to him
only as an example of those who are ridden by an idea. An idea may be
good or bad, but no idea is good enough to claim one's whole waking
thoughts. We like people who have many facets to their minds, who hold
strong opinions on a variety of subjects and know how to keep them under
control, airing them when they are in season and putting them in cold
storage when they are not of season. We like them to think in many
quantities, to let their thought range over the whole landscape of things, to
have plenty of windows to their mind and to open them in turn to all the
winds that blow. We ought not to be the slave of one idea, but the master of
legions which we should exercise and discipline and from which we should
extract a working philosophy of life. However good the text we ought not
always to be preaching a sermon from it. I remember when I was a boy a
most excellent man, a lawyer, who, every evening in the week, would take
his stand on the plinth of a Sebastopol cannon in front of the Shire Hall that
faced down the High Street of the country town in which I lived, and from
thence would exhort the passers-by to repentance. No one ever heeded him,
no one ever even paused to listen to him, and he lives in my memory a
solitary figure weighed down with the wickedness of men, giving his life
unselfishly to the delivery of his unregarded message, a man whose very
agony had become a town jest.
There is of course another side to the shield of the man with One Idea.
He could make out a good case for himself and I think I could make out a
good case for him. The mere fact that his passion is disinterested is alone
enough to command respect in a world where disinterested enthusiasm is a
rare commodity. He is of the stuff of martyrs. He is prepared to die for his
idea, or what is harder, to take the whips and scorns of men who are often,
spiritually, not fit to black his boots. It is his uncalculating passion that
keeps the flame of ideas burning in a dark world. Without him our moral
currency would be sadly depreciated and the quality of the general life
would lose its salt and savour. I often admire his singleness of purpose. I
sometimes even envy a disinterestedness which leaves me ashamed by
comparison. But I do not want to spend a week-end with him and I will not
travel down to Devonshire with him if I can find a seat in the luggage-van
or standing room in the corridor.
TO AN UNKNOWN ARTIST
So I saw him cut away row after row of the brickwork on which he
stood. There was a drop of fifty feet, "straight as a beggar can spit," back
and front of him—not an inch of room for the play of his feet. Every
movement had to be true to the fraction of an inch. Every piece of
brickwork he removed involved a new problem within the same inexorable
limits. The slightest mistake, and he would plunge down to the rubbish
below, and a coroner's jury would say "Accidental death," and that would be
the end of his story. Perhaps there would be two lines about him at the
bottom of a newspaper column, but nobody would read it, for everybody
would be so busy reading how Mr. Kid Lewis put Mr. Frankie Burns to
sleep, and how Abe Mitchell did the fourth hole in two, and why Hobbs or
somebody else was not caught in the second over.
And this man, rising and falling with the blows of his pick-axe up there
on the fragment of wall, is not doing this perilous job occasionally. He is
doing it every day. All his working life is spent on some such giddy task as
this, swaying to and fro with his axe between a drop of fifty feet on one side
and fifty feet on the other. He must never forget—for a moment. He must
never be dizzy—for a moment. He must be prepared for any sudden gust of
wind that blows. As I watched him he seemed to assume the proportions of
a great artist. He seemed to become heroic—a figure carrying his life lightly
on that frail ledge of the vertical cliff. I daresay it had never occurred to him
to think of himself in either rôle. Yet the mere skill of the man was more
delicate than the skill of the rather dull cricketers I saw at Lord's on
Saturday. There were 12,000 people standing round hour by hour to watch
Lee and Haig pile up the stupendous total of fifty runs inside two hours. I
do not blame the spectators. I was one of them myself, and very dull I found
it. But nobody bothered to give a glance at the figure swaying to and fro on
the crumbling wall. Yet as a mere exhibition of skill it was not inferior to
the pedestrian play at Lord's or to a skipping match between Carpentier and
Dempsey at £1000 a minute. And remember, he was not engaged in a sham
fight. He had a drop of fifty feet back and front. Instant death on either side
all the time.
But then he was only doing useful work. I wondered what he got for
risking his life every hour of every day. Perhaps as much in a week or a
month as the Star will pay me for writing this article about him. Perhaps as
much in a year as an eminent counsel will pocket for a day's "refresher."
Perhaps as much in a lifetime as Monsieur Carpentier will take for ten
minutes' running exercise with Dempsey in the ring, winding up with a tap
in the stomach, a count-out, a handshake (and a wink). No; on second
thoughts, not half that, not quarter that.
When I passed through Piccadilly Circus in the evening the man had
gone. So had the fragment of wall on which he stood. You may see the mark
of the place where the wall rose on the side of the "Criterion." It is the mark
of an unknown artist to whom I offer this tribute of my admiration.
For some time past I have noticed on the hoardings of London a placard
illustrated with the picture of an American gentleman named Rutherford,
who is represented lifting a prophetic fist in the manner of the
advertisements of Horatio Bottomley before that prophet of the war had the
misfortune to be found out, and declaring that there are "thousands in this
city who will never die." I have not had the curiosity to attend his meetings
or to inquire into the character of his revelation. I do not know, therefore,
whether I am likely to be one of the people whom Mr. Rutherford has his
eye upon. But the threat which he holds over my head has led me to look
the possibility in the face. I suppose Mr. Rutherford is satisfied that it is an
agreeable possibility. He would not have come all the way from America to
tell us about it if he had not thought it was good news that he was bringing.
All our goings and comings are enriched with the sense of mortality. All our
experiences are coloured by the thought that they may return no more. Rob
us of the significance of the last words of Hamlet and the realm of poetry
would become a desert, treeless and songless. It is because "the rest is
silence" that the smallest details of our passage through life have in them
the power of kindling thoughts such as these:
It is not alone the beauty of the sunset that touches us with such
poignant emotion: it is because in the passing of the day we see the image
of another passing to which we move as unfalteringly as the sun moves into
the shadow of the night. When in these autumn days we walk in the
woodlands amid the patter of the falling leaves, it is the same subtle
suggestion that attunes the note of beauty to a minor key. Through the
stillness of the forest there echo the strokes of a distant axe felling some
kingly beech. For seventy, perhaps a hundred years it has weathered the
storms of life, and now its hour has come and in its falling there is the
allegory of ourselves. I think it is that allegory that makes my neighbour so
passionately conservative about his trees. They stand too thick about his
grounds, but he will not have the axe laid to one of them.
No, Mr. Rutherford, you have mistaken us. We do not want your
revelation. The play is worth seeing, though I wish it were more good-
humoured and the players a little more friendly; but we do not wish to
watch it for ever. We like to know that the curtain will fall and that, a little
weary and sleepy, we shall be permitted to go home. We are in no hurry, sir,
but we like to know that the curtain is there.
ON INITIALS
But I refer to Mr. Blodgett's letter not because of his request, but
because of his manner of addressing me. He writes to me as "Reginald S.
Thomson, Esq." I cannot deny that my name (for the purpose of this article)
is Reginald. I wish I could. What possessed my revered parents—peace to
their ashes—to call me Reginald I do not know. Perhaps it was out of
respect for the memory of the saintly Heber, whose precocious piety was set
before me, with not much success, for my youthful imitation. But whatever
its origin, I cannot recall the time when I did not loathe the name of
Reginald. I took the earliest opportunity of disowning it, and for fifty years
I have passed through the world under the sign of R. S. Thomson. Our
English habit of using initials only for our Christian names was a source of
solace to me. It enabled me to forget all about Reginald, and to leave the
world in darkness about my disgraceful secret. I left it to suppose, if it
supposed at all, that behind the R. there lurked nothing more offensive than
Robert, or Richard, or, at the worst, Rufus.
No doubt others have suffered in the same way. It would not surprise me
to learn that Mr. H. G. Wells is known from Boston to Los Angeles as Mr.
Hannibal G. Wells. Nobody in England knows what lurks behind "H. G."
Mr. Wells keeps the secret from his closest friends, but I daresay it is
babbled all over America, and that there is not an intelligent schoolboy who
does not discuss the latest book of Hector G. Wells or H. Gascoigne Wells,
or Horatio Gordon Wells, as the case may be. No doubt Mr. Wells has
excellent reasons for not publishing his front names to the world. He may
dislike them as much as I dislike Reginald. Parents who give us our names
immediately we appear in the world are naturally liable to do us an injury.
They have, let us say, been stirred by some royal wedding, and call their
poor infant "Lascelles" in a fervour of loyalty. And perhaps Lascelles grows
up into a fierce Communist who would prefer the L. to stand for Lenin.
What is he to do but to take refuge in initials? And since he alone is
concerned, why should we pry into the secrets which those initials conceal?
It would be a simple way of relief if our baptismal names were
temporary, and each of us chose the names by which he desired to be
known on coming of age. Then they would fit us more happily than
Reginald fits me or Hannibal—if it is Hannibal—fits Mr. Wells.
PLANTING A SPINNEY
Then one day someone said "The Spinney," and in sheer desperation
everyone else said, "Why, of course, 'The Spinney.' Perfect. The very
thing." The only objection that was made was that there was no spinney.
But a good name could not be sacrificed to so negligible a consideration.
Moreover, what had we been about to forget to plant so desirable a thing as
a spinney? There, below the house, just out of the line of view so as not to
blot out the landscape of four counties, was the very spot, and in the garden
there were plenty of trees, pine, spruce, chestnut, beech, and lime of twelve
or fifteen years' growth ready to hand. It would have been safer and simpler
to have set young saplings, but that would not have satisfied the elders. It
would have been starting a spinney for another generation to enjoy, and we
wanted a spinney that we could sit under ourselves.
If you plant saplings, I think you ought to do it in your youth so that you
and the trees can grow to maturity and age together. I often regret that I did