Semantics and Pragmatics (All Lectures) 2023
Semantics and Pragmatics (All Lectures) 2023
Table of Contents
Introduction to Semantics ............................................................................................................................... 02
Major Concerns of Semantics ......................................................................................................................... 07
Three Perspectives on Meanings .................................................................................................................... 08
Different Types of Meanings .......................................................................................................................... 08
Semantic Properties ........................................................................................................................................ 21
Evidence for Semantic Properties …………………………………………………………………...............27
Sense Relation……………………………………………………………………………………………….45
Sentential Semantics…………………………………………………………………………………………67
Theories of Meanings………………………………………………………………………………………..87
Pragmatics……………………………………………………………………………………………………92
Reference……………………………………………………………………………………………………109
Speech Acts…………………………………………………………………………………………………112
Glossary……………………………………………………………………………………………………..124
This document contains the lecture notes of Semantics & Pragmatics (Eng-223) for the
students of BS (English) 4th Semester enrolled at Govt. Zamindar College Gujrat.
1
An Introduction to Semantics/ Word Meaning
―First learn the meaning of what you say, and then speak.‖ (Epictetus)
It is expected that by the end of this lecture, the learners will be able to:
i. Define language
ii. Know various levels of language
iii. Describe what Semantics is
iv. Understand the term Semantics
v. Comprehend different areas of Semantics
vi. Describe history, branches, significance and scope of Semantics
Language
Man communicates with the other members of society via language which comprises
of arbitrary signals. Therefore, language is a tool for communication. Sweet (1896) defines
language by saying that language is a tool to express one‘s ideas and thoughts through
speech sounds that are joined into words. Such words are then combined in the form of
sentences. This combination of ideas, in the form of sentences, is stated into thoughts. Bloch
and Trager (1942) are of the view that a language comprises arbitrary vocal symbols which
help a social group to co-operate with each other. Michael Halliday (2003) calls language a
semiotic system i.e., a system of meaning. Every language has various levels.
Levels of Language
2
Here our concern is with Semantics only.
What is semantics?
The noun semantics and the adjective semantic are derived from the Greek word
semantikos (―significant‖). In linguistics, semantics is the subfield that is devoted to the
study of meaning, as borne on the syntactic levels of words, phrases, sentences, and
sometimes larger units of discourse, generically referred to as texts. Semantics is the
technical term used to refer to the study of meaning, and, since meaning is a part of
language, semantics is a part of linguistics. Different scholars have defined Semantics in
different ways. We will limit ourselves to the definitions given by only a few scholars.
Fromkin (2003) is of the view ―The study of the linguistic meaning of morphemes,
words, phrases, and sentences is called Semantics.‖
For Hurford and Heasley (1983), ―semantics is the study of meaning in language.‖
Other scholars define semantics with different or similar perspectives. For example,
Saeed (1997) opines: ―semantics is the study of meaning communicated through
language.‖
Kreidler‘s (1998) definition is also useful: ―Linguistic semantics is the study of how
language organizes and expresses meaning.‖
Simply we can say that Semantics is the branch of linguistics that deals with the study
of meaning, changes in meaning, and the principles that govern the relationship between
sentences or words and their meanings. This branch of linguistics includes how meaning is
constructed, interpreted, clarified, obscured, illustrated, simplified, negotiated, contradicted,
and paraphrased. (Sentences or phrases that convey the same meaning using different wording are called
paraphras) In it, we not only study the meaning(s) of words but how the meaning(s) of words
3
in a sentence are put together to form sentential meaning also. Lastly, it studies meaning(s)
in a systematic and objective (unbiased) way.
Areas of Semantics
Symbol (Any formal item that conveys meaning, especially a conventional piece of a
system. ) and referent ( the person, thing, word or expression denotes, stands for,
or refers to )
Conceptions of meaning ( seven types of meanings)
Words and lexemes (basic unit of meaning)
Denotation (dictionary meanings), connotation (cultural meanings), implication
(inference)
Pragmatics (study of meanings in relation to context)
Ambiguity (Sentence or phrases which create obscurity) Tahir got lunch ready for his son
wearing a summer dress.
Metaphor, simile and symbol
Semantic fields (A semantic field is a set of words (or lexemes) related in meanings)
Synonym, antonym and hyponym(It refers to words that have a more specific meaning than
a general term that can be applied to it. For example, a cat is a hyponym of the general term animal)
Collocation (word(s) that are almost always put together to create a specific meaning),
fixed expressions and idiom
Semantic change (Any change in the meaning of word over the course of time)
and etymology (the study of origin of words)
Polysemy (word or phrase having multiple related meanings)
Homonymy (words with identical pronunciations having same spellings but different
meanings), homophones (words with identical pronunciations but different spellings and
For thousands of years, philosophers have pondered the meaning of meaning, yet
speakers of a language can understand what is said to them and can produce strings of words
that are meaningful to other speakers. Different researches reveal that different disciplines
like psychology, philosophy, etc. have been concerned with the systematic study of
‗meaning‘ for centuries. Although their particular interests and approaches are different, yet
each borrows from and contributes to the others. However, semantics was introduced
formally in literature in the late 1800‘s. Mr. Breal is credited with coining the word
semantics in his Essai de semantique (1883) ‗as a name for philosophical enquiries‘. In
1894 the English word semantics occurred in a paper: ‗Reflected Meanings; a Point in
Semantics’ presented by Charles R. Lanman to the American Philosophical Association.
Later on, after 1930‘s, Leonard Bloomfield tried to form the theoretical basis by equating
semantics to stimulus response formula. Emergence of structuralism on the linguistic scene
marks the watershed in the realm of semantics. In 1966 A.J. Greimas produced Structural
Semantics.
Branches of Semantics
Cruse (2000) lists the followings as the main broadly distinguishable areas of interest
in the study of meaning: lexical semantics, grammatical semantics, logical semantics, and
linguistic semantics. They are not watertight compartments and they may overlap with one
another. Lexical semantics studies the meanings of words; the focus is on 'content' words
like lion, jasmine, selfish and persuade, rather than form/grammatical words like the, of,
than, and so on. Grammatical (phrasal) semantics studies aspects of meaning which have
direct relevance to syntax. For instance, consider the problem of assigning category to the
word yellow. It can be given the category such as adjective, noun and verb as illustrated
below:
5
Logical semantics studies the relation between natural language and formal logical
systems. Linguistic semantics is the study of how languages organize and express meanings.
Significance of Semantics
It is also essential to the study of language change (how meanings alter over time). It
is important for understanding language in social contexts, as these are likely to affect
meaning, and for understanding varieties of English and effects of style. It is thus one of the
most fundamental concepts in linguistics.
The scope of semantics covers a wide range of issues related to meaning . It is a broad
topic with many layers and not all people that study it study these layers in the same way. It
is a very broad field of inquiry. Therefore, semantics is the most diverse field within
linguistics. In addition, semanticists have to have at least a nodding acquaintance with other
disciplines, like philosophy and psychology, which also investigate the creation and
transmission of meaning.
POINTS TO REMEMBER
8
way they are put together. Sometimes, we need to see meaning within the framework of an
academic or scientific discipline; called compositional meanings.
Schools of Thought in Meaning
Both linguists and philosophers agree that meaning is central to semantics. However,
there is considerable disparity (difference of opinion) among different scholars on the exact
conception of meaning. Based on their understanding of the meaning of meaning and
procedures, there are different schools of thought concerning meaning. These are
the naturalists, the conventionalists, and the contextualists.
According to the naturalists with Plato as the chief proponent, the meaning of a word
is the entity or thing it represents. There is an intrinsic relationship between sound and
meaning. The major criticism of this view is that there exist very many words in natural
languages without physical entities.
To the conventionalists, words and their meaning do not necessarily have any direct
link. Whatever connection exists between a word and meaning is through a concept
formed in the minds of the users of the language. Conventionalism is derived from the
works of Aristotle.
According to J. Firth and other contextualists, the meaning of a word derives from its
usage. Each of these approaches has had a profound impact on the practice of linguistics.
Their contributions shall become apparent as the text progresses. Apart from focusing on the
three principal approaches to the study of meaning, there are thematic,
conceptual, and associative types of meaning also.
Types of Meaning
Semantics is concerned with meanings and morpheme, words, phrases and sentences
have meanings, too. So semantics can be defined as the study of the meaning of
morphemes, words, phrases and sentences. While listening to a spoken text or reading a
written text we may feel that there are utterances that convey many types of information or
meaning.
Leech in his book, ‗Semantic- A Study of meaning’ (1981) breaks down meanings
into seven types. They are: conceptual or denotative meaning, connotative meaning,
social meaning, affective or emotive meaning, reflected meaning, collocative meaning
and thematic meaning. He gives primacy (importance) to conceptual meaning. There are
9
three basic types of meaning: thematic, conceptual and associative. Associative meaning can
further be divided into connotative, collocative, affective, reflected and stylistic meaning.
1. Thematic Meaning
Both the sentences have same meanings although the structure is different. In the first
case we give importance to ‗Ali‟ and in the second case we give importance to 'examination'.
In such cases we have thematic meanings. Thematic meaning refers to what is
communicated by the way in which a speaker or a writer organizes the message in
terms of ordering focus or emphasis (Leech 1981). Thematic meaning helps us to
understand the message and its implications properly. The different parts of the sentence also
can be used as subject, object or complement to show prominence. It is done through focus,
theme (topic) or emotive emphasis. Thus a sentence in active voice is different from the
sentence in passive voice though its conceptual meaning is the same. For example, the
following statements in active and passive voice have same conceptual meaning but different
communicative values.
In the first sentence ―who gave away the prize ―is more important, but in the second
sentence ―what did Mrs. Humayun give?‖ is important‖. Thus the change of focus changes
the meaning also. The first suggests that we already know Mrs. Humayun (perhaps through
earlier mention) its known/given information while it is new information.
I like apples most. (It is I not someone else who likes the apples)
10
It is the apples I like most. (APPLES, not the other fruits the subject likes)
Like the grammatical structures, stress and intonation also make the message
prominent. For example, the stress on the word in the following sentence gives prominence
to the information.
Thus sentences or pairs of sentences with similar conceptual meanings differ from
their communicative value. This is due to different grammatical constructions or lexical
items or stress and intonations. Therefore they are used in different contents. In the line ―Ten
thousand saw I at a glance‖, Wordsworth inverts the structure to focus on ‗ten thousand‖,
Sometimes thematic contrast i.e. contrasts between given and new information can be
conveyed by lexical means.
The way we order our message also conveys what is important and what is not. This is
basically thematic meaning. Thematic meaning derives from the organisation of the message
presented in a language. It is the arrangement of the components of communication that
determine the point of emphasis. This arrangement may take the form of passivation,
topicalisation or focus. In the sentences that follow, different items have been made more
prominent by merely re-ordering them.
In sentence (a) the sentence is in the normal subject-verb-object order without any
special meaning. Sentences (b) and (d) tend to lay emphasis on Jamila, the doer of the action
being referred to. In sentence (c), the emphasis is on the house which was bought. Indeed,
11
focused and tropicalized elements in a structure are given prominence within an information
structure. A component of the bit of information can also be made more prominent by
stressing it. Consider further the following:
Conceptual Meaning
Since, conceptual meaning is the essential or core meaning while other six types are
the peripheral. They are peripheral in a sense that they are non-essential. Conceptual
meaning is also called as primary meaning. It is the meaning suggested by the word when it
is used alone. It is the first meaning or usage which a word will suggest to most people when
the word is said in isolation. It is the meaning learned early in life and likely to have
reference to a physical situation. The conceptual meaning of word is its agreed-upon sense -
what it refers to, stands for, or designates. The aim of conceptual meaning is to provide an
appropriate semantic representation to a sentence or statement. A sentence is made of
abstract symbols. Conceptual meaning helps us to distinguish one meaning from the meaning
of other sentences. Thus, conceptual meaning is an essential part of language.
We know that not only the units of language are contrastive but also they are arranged
sequentially. We can build larger units by combining smaller units and again combining the
outcome of the first combination into still larger units and so on. Look at the example given
below. We combine that and man into that man and a and teacher into a teacher; we
interpret the first phrase that man as subject and a teacher as complement. We again
combine is and a teacher into a larger unit is a teacher; we interpret this as predicate. By
combining subject and predicate we construct a sentence. Now we understand that by the
principle of structure, larger units of language are built up out of smaller units or we are able
to analyze a sentence syntactically into its constituent parts hierarchically till we arrive at the
ultimate constituents or smallest syntactic elements. We can represent this information by
means of a tree-diagram as given below:
13
process has been described as componential analysis. It is a major process in structural
semantics.
Associative Meaning
The meaning of a word is affected by the context, background, time and the cultural
realities of the users of language also. This type of meaning is not static. It is variable and
open ended. Certain words, structures and styles are usually employed to arouse some
emotional reactions in the listener. Certain attitudes and forms of behaviour are provoked by
the associative meaning of the words used in communication. These different reactions are
derived from the associations which the words cerate in the minds of language users.
i. Connotative Meaning
ii. Collocative Meaning
iii. Reflected Meaning
iv. Stylistic or Social Meaning
Connotative Meaning
Connotative meaning contains elements of the conceptual meaning of a word and the
individual‘s personal interpretation of what is communicated. That interpretation is based on
the personal experience of the hearer. This means that connotative meaning varies with the
experience of people in communication. It may also vary from society to society.
There are additional semantic features that are associated with connotative meaning.
Thus, a great deal of the meaning of idioms and figurative expressions derive from
connotation. There are symbols in literature which have different connotations in different
cultures. For instance, the fox or jackal is associated with the cunningness, cawing of crow is
associated with the arrival of guest and cat crossing our way is associated with bad omen.
Collocative Meaning
We might have come across words which occur together mostly in utterances. Such
co-occurrence is referred as collation and the outcome of the collocation gives rise to
collocative meaning. Collocative meaning is the meaning which a word acquires in the
company of certain other words. Words collocate or co-occur with certain words only. For
example, big business is acceptable and not large business or great business. Collocative
meaning refers to associations of a word because of its usual or habitual co-occurrence
with certain types of words. Pretty and handsome indicate ‗good looking‘. However, they
slightly differ from each other because of collocation or co-occurrence. The word pretty
collocates with girls, woman, village, gardens, flowers, etc. On the other hand, the word
15
handsome collocates with boys, men, etc. So we have pretty woman and handsome man.
Though handsome woman and pretty man are acceptable, they suggest different kinds of
attractiveness because of the collocative associations of the two adjectives. Hence handsome
woman may mean attractive woman but in a mannish way.
Reflected meaning
We know that a word can have more than one conceptual meaning or multiple
conceptual meaning. If we interpret one meaning for the other, it is known as the
reflected meaning. In such cases while responding to one sense of the word we partly
respond to another sense of the word too. For example, The Comforter and The Holy Ghost
refer to Gabriel (Leech 1981:16). Comforter and Ghost are religious words. They have both
religious and general meaning. But unconsciously even in religious context we may interpret
these terms by their non-religious meaning. We may feel The Comforter sounds warm and
comforting while The Holy Ghost sounds ‗awesome‘ or even ‗dreadful‘. One sense of the
word seems to rub off on another especially through relative frequency and familiarity (e.g. a
ghost is more frequent and familiar in no religious sense.). In poetry too we have reflected
meaning as in the following lines from ‗Futility‘:
We know language is spoken in a society. So it is quite natural the language gives clue
to about the society in which it is being spoken or the social context in which it is spoken.
The meaning conveyed by the piece of language about the social context of its use is called
the social meaning (Leech 1981:14). The decoding of a text is dependent on our knowledge
of stylistics and other variations of language. We recognize some words or pronunciation as
16
being dialectical i.e. as telling us something about the regional or social origin of the speaker.
Social meaning is related to the social situation in which an utterance is used. It is concerned
with the social circumstances of the use of a linguistic expression. For example, some
dialectic words inform us about the regional and social background of the speaker. In the
same way, some stylistic usages let us know something of the social relationship between the
speaker and the hearer. The following socio-stylistic variations are listed by Leech (Leech
1981:14):
For example the utterance I ain‟t done nothing tells we about the speaker and that is
the speaker is probably a black American, underprivileged and uneducated. Stylistic
variation represents the social variation. This is because styles show the geographical region
social class of the speaker. Style helps us to know about the period, field and status of the
discourse.
Emphasis is usually on the different stylistic variations open to language users. Based
on the level of familiarity, users have the following possibilities in making requests:
I wonder if I could see we later today (indirect question) used for extreme politeness)
17
Can I see you later today? (Causal and less formal)
We use language to expresses our personal feelings, including our attitude to the
listener, or our attitude to something we are talking about. Meaning of this type is called as
affective or emotive meaning (Leech 1981:14). It is often conveyed through the conceptual
or connotative content of the words used. For example, home for a sailor/soldier or expatriate
(refugee) and mother for a motherless child and a married woman will have special effective,
emotive quality. In affective meaning, language is used to express personal feelings or
attitude to the listener or to the subject matter of discourse. To Leech, affective meaning
refers to what is conveyed about the feeling and attitude of the speaker through use of
language (attitude to listener as well as attitude to what he is saying).
Affective meaning is related to the feelings and attitudes of the speaker towards
the subject or the audience. This meaning is achieved by the choice of words. Certain
words suggest positive feelings – love, attraction, happiness, exciting etc. Some others stir
up negative reactions – disgusting, nauseating, disappointing, etc. Interjections like ah!, oh!,
uh!, mmn! often suggest the emotional state of the mind. Other words like dear, daddy,
mummy etc. give an impression of endearment.
POINTS TO REMEMBER
i. Nordquist (2018) defines meaning by saying: ―In semantics and pragmatics, meaning is the
message conveyed by words, sentences, and symbols in a context. It may also be called
lexical or grammatical meaning.‖
18
iii. According to the naturalists, the meaning of a word is the entity or thing it represents.
There is an intrinsic relationship between sound and meaning. To the conventionalists, words
and their meaning do not necessarily have any direct link. Whatever connection exists
between a word and meaning is through a concept formed in the minds of the users of the
language. The contextualists opine, the meaning of a word derives from its usage.
iv. Leech in his book, ‗Semantic- A Study of meaning‘ (1981) breaks down meanings into
seven types: conceptual or denotative meaning, connotative meaning, social meaning,
affective or emotive meaning, reflected meaning, collocative meaning and thematic meaning.
19
social norms, cultural values, and social relationships. For example, the use of slang or
formal language can signal different social contexts or identities. Stylistic or social
meaning helps us understand the social dynamics and shades of language use.
h. Affective meaning is related to the feelings and attitudes of the speaker towards the
subject or the audience. This meaning is achieved by the choice of words.
i. There is also figurative meaning, where words are used metaphorically or
symbolically. Like time is money is a metaphor. Butterfly may symbolize being
innocent or fragile.
j. Pragmatic meaning considers the context and intentions behind the use of language.
To
To infer, it can be said that these different types of meanings assist us understand how
language is used and interpreted.
Terminologies
Lexical semantics: the meaning of words and the relationships among words.
Sentential (Phrasal) semantics: the meaning of syntactic units larger than one word
Compositional Meaning or Semantics: formulating semantic rules that build the meaning of a
sentence based on the meaning of the words and how they combine – Also known as truth-
conditional semantics because the speaker‘s knowledge of truth conditions is central.
Synonymy refers to a type of semantic relations among words. Technically, it occurs when
two or more linguistic forms are used to substitute one another in any context in which their
common meaning is not affected denotatively or connotatively.
Antonymy is one of a set of SENSE relations recognized in some analyses of meaning. In its
most general sense, it refers collectively to all types of semantic oppositeness.
Hyponymy: Hyponymy is the relationship which obtains between specific and general
lexical items, such that the former is 'included' in the latter. For example, a cat is a hyponym
of an animal.
Utterance: In semantics, an utterance is any act of speech. It can consist of a phrase, a
word, or even a partial word, provided it is language and not just sound. Utterances can be
grammatical or ungrammatical, meaningful or meaningless, but must be made by a particular
person at a particular time. That is to say, utterances must be real, not speech acts in the
20
abstract. They can, however, be recorded or transcribed, provided they were spoken at some
point.
For example, a closer look at the following sentences conveys us the idea of being
meaningful or meaningless.
1. The hamburger ate the boy.
21
2. The car speaks to the man.
Although these sentences are grammatically correct but they are giving odd meanings.
After parsing the initial part of the above mentioned sentences from 1 to 5, we notice this
oddness is due to the following reasons:
Semantic properties are often organized hierarchically, with more general properties at
the top and more specific ones at the bottom. For example, the general property of being an
animal encompasses more specific properties such as having fur, being warm-blooded, and
being able to move around. This hierarchical organization reflects the way we categorize the
world and understand the relationships between different concepts.
22
Adult - + - - + +
Besides basic properties of semantics, semantic property is also sometimes used to
describe the semantic components of a word, such as man assuming that the referent
is human, male, and adult, or female being a common component of girl, woman,
and actress.
It can, therefore, be said words and morphemes have meanings too. We shall talk
about the meaning of words, even though words may be composed of several morphemes.
Suppose someone said:
The assassin was stopped before he got to Mr. Thwacklehurst.
If the word assassin is in our mental dictionary, we may know that it was some person
who was prevented from murdering some important person named Thwacklehurst. Our
knowledge of the meaning of assassin tells us that it was not an animal that tried to kill the
man that Thwacklehurst was not likely to be an old man who owned a tobacco shop. In other
words, our knowledge of the meaning of assassin includes knowing that the individual to
whom the word refers is human, murderer and killer of important people. These pieces of
information, then, are some of semantic properties of the word upon which speakers of the
language agree. The meanings of all nouns, verbs, adjectives, and adverbs (the ‗content
words‘) and even some of the ‗function words‘ such as with, or over can at least partially be
specified by such properties. In this sense, semantic properties are used to define
the semantic field of a word or set of words.
The same semantic property may be part of the meaning of many different words. For
example the word ‗female‘ is a semantic property that helps to define
Tigress hen actress maiden
Doe mare debutante widow
Ewe vixen girl woman
The meanings of words have other properties. The word father has the properties of
being ‗male‘ and ‗adult‘, as do man and bachelor; but father also has the property of ‗parent‘,
which distinguishes it from the other two words.
Mare, in addition to ‗female‘ and ‗animal‘, must also denote a property of ‗horseness‘.
Words have general semantic properties such as ‗human‘ or ‗parent‘, as well as more
specific properties that give the word its particular meaning.
23
The same semantic property may occur in words of different categories. ‗Female‘ is
part of the meaning of the noun mother, of the verb breast-feed, and of the adjective
pregnant.
How Do Semantic Properties Help in Making Meanings of Sentence (s)?
The----------is reading a newspaper.
The-----------is teaching the students.
Undoubtedly, in the first sentence it would be a human and in addition it may be a man, a
woman, girl or boy. We would say that ―man‖ [+ human, +adult, + animate – female]. In the
second sentence the answer would be surely a teacher. In addition, if it is a young girl, we
may say ―girl‖ [+ animate, + human+, +female, - adult]
In fact, the semantic features help us know which type of word we have to use and in
which situation it will be used. Through semantic properties we not only can convey our
meaning(s) in a sentence accordingly but we may also use different words at proper places.
Semantic properties also play a crucial role in understanding figurative language, such as
metaphors, idioms, and analogies. Figurative language relies on the use of non-literal
meanings, and understanding the underlying semantic properties is essential to interpret these
expressions correctly. For example, the idiom "break a leg" means "good luck" in the context
of a theater performance. This expression has semantic properties such as being associated
with success and achievement, and we use it to communicate encouragement and support to
someone.
One of the crucial aspects of semantic properties is that they are not fixed or static.
They can change over time, depending on how a word is used and the context in which it is
used. For example, the word "computer" has undergone significant changes in its semantic
properties since its invention in the 20th century. Initially, it referred to a machine that
performed calculations, but now it is associated with a vast array of activities, including
communication, entertainment, and business.
Limitations
For many words this method is not applicable. For example, we may not use it for
feelings [such words are called containers of meanings also] such as happiness, sadness, and
abstract nouns like beauty, advice, threat, etc.
Conclusion
24
To infer, it can be said that semantic properties or features are a part of semantic
analysis. We use semantic features or properties to solve the problems of abnormality in
sentences. These features aid us to distinguish between various lexical items. In addition, we
realize which category of word we have to use and in which situation it will be used. They
are critical for effective communication, and they enable us to understand and use words and
concepts in different contexts. They are dynamic and reflect the way we categorize and make
sense of the world around us. Understanding semantic properties is essential for interpreting
language accurately and effectively, and it is a crucial aspect of language development and
acquisition.
26
To infer, it can be said that semantic properties or features are a part of semantic
analysis. We use semantic features or properties to solve the problems of abnormality
in sentences.
These features aid us to distinguish between various lexical items.
In addition, with the help of these properties, we realize which category of word we
have to use and in which situation it will be used. This is why they are critical for
effective communication.
Lecture06 Evidence for Semantic Properties
One key factor in determining semantic properties is context. The context in which a
word or phrase is used can heavily influence its meaning. For example, the word "bat" could
refer to both a flying mammal and a piece of sports equipment, depending on the context in
which it is used. This context dependency indicates that semantic properties are not fixed or
absolute but rather can vary and be influenced by various factors.
Another piece of evidence for semantic properties is relatedness. Words that share a
similar meaning or concept are often related, such as "big" and "large." The relatedness
between words suggests that the meaning of a word cannot be understood in isolation but
rather must be understood in the larger context of its semantic environment.
Furthermore, the usage of words is also indicative of their semantic properties. For
example, verbs often describe actions or states, whereas adjectives describe features or
attributes of objects. These patterns and conventions of word usage provide additional
evidence for semantic properties.
Lastly, semantic properties can also be observed through the use of imagery and
metaphor. Many words and phrases in language are based on sensory experiences, and these
sensory experiences can be used to convey abstract or intangible concepts, such as emotions.
Metaphors, in particular, can be used to describe complex concepts in terms of more concrete
concepts, further highlighting the importance of semantic properties in language
understanding.
27
In conclusion, there are multiple levels of evidence for semantic properties, including
context dependency, relatedness, word usage conventions, and imagery and metaphor.
Understanding these properties is crucial for natural language understanding in human
communication.
Schematically:
[Utterance
28
In semantics, an utterance is any act of speech. It can consist of a phrase, a word, or
even a partial word, provided that it is language and not just sound. Utterances can be
grammatical or ungrammatical, meaningful or meaningless, but must be made by a particular
person at a particular time. That is to say, utterances must be real, not speech acts in the
abstract. They can, however, be recorded or transcribed, provided they were spoken at some
point.]
Inflections
[walked]
[are walking]
[have walked]
[may walk]
[could be walking]
and modality can be combined, as in were walking, should be walking, would have walked.
These are important semantic elements, but we consider Inflection separately from the
Proposition. A general scheme for a simple sentence, then, has these parts:
Inflection +Proposition (+ Focus)
Tense
Aspect
Modality
The description of a sentence is a syntactic analysis. The description of a proposition
is a semantic analysis. A syntactic analysis is an account of the lexemes and function words
29
in a sentence, describing how these combine into phrases, and showing the functions that
these lexemes and phrases have in the sentence. There are somewhat different ways of doing
syntactic analysis, but generally these sentence functions are recognized: subject, predicate,
object, complement and adverbial.
Argument Structure [An argument refers to the relationship of a name to the simple
proposition of which it is a part]
We may also notice that Predicates (Verbs) differ in terms of the number and types of
NPs they can take as complements. Transitive verbs such as find, hit, chase, and so on take a
direct object complement, whereas intransitive verbs like arrive or sleep do not. Ditransitive
verbs such as give or throw take two object complements as in John threw Mary a ball. In
addition, most verbs take a subject. The various NPs that occur with a verb are its
arguments. Thus intransitive verbs have one argument: the subject; transitive verbs have
two arguments: the subject and direct object; ditransitive verbs have three arguments: the
subject, direct object, and indirect object. The argument structure of a verb is part of its
meaning and is included in its lexical entry. The verb not only determines the number of
arguments in a sentence, but it also limits the semantic properties of both its subject and its
complements. For example, find and sleep require animate subjects. The well-known
colorless green ideas sleep furiously is semantically anomalous because ideas (colorless or
not) are not animate.
The arguments that accompany the predicate have different semantic functions, or
roles, in the proposition. What roles they have depends partly on the nature of the predicate
and partly on their own meanings. The semantic structure of a proposition can be represented
this way:
Semantic roles are a set of abstract concepts that describe the various functions that
nouns and pronouns can serve in a sentence. These roles help us to understand the
relationships between the various elements in a sentence. In fact, thematic role (also called
30
semantic role) is the semantic relationship between the verb and the noun phrases of a
sentence, such as agent, theme, experiencer, location, instrument, goal and source.
[Theta Assignment (thematic role assignment): The ascribing of thematic roles to the
syntactic elements in a sentence]
Thematic roles were introduced in generative grammar during the mid-1960s and early
1970s. In thematic roles, entities are described by the action of the verb. Thematic roles can
be defined as: the roles that referents of the arguments of a verb play in the event or as
the state that the verb denotes. Or
A semantic role is the underlying relationship that a participant has with the
main verb in a clause. Or
The part played by a noun phrase, such as the subject, in a sentence is called
semantic role.
We have already discussed Semantic Roles are also called Thematic Roles. There are
various types of thematic roles. Grammatical relations (subject, object, etc.) are morpho-
syntactic, whereas semantic roles (agent, patient, instrument…) are conceptual notions.
Semantic roles do not correspond directly to grammatical relations.
The first semantic role is called Agent or Doer. An Agent is the doer of an action e.g.
'Ahmad' in the sentence, "Ahmad called me." The second semantic role is called Patient or
Theme. It refers to what is acted upon by the Agent e.g. 'boat' in the sentence, "Jamil steered
the boat." The third semantic role called is Recipient or Receiver. It indicates a receiver in a
situation e.g. 'Ali' in the sentence, "The children sent Ali a postcard." The fourth semantic
role is called Instrument. It identifies the entity that is used to perform an action e.g. 'Razor'
in the sentence, "The boy cut the rope with a razor." The fifth semantic role is called
Experimenter. It is the entity that has the feeling e.g. 'The Boy' in the sentence, "The Boy
feels bad." The sixth semantic role is called Source. It identifies where an entity moves
from e.g. 'The House' in the sentence, "The Boy ran from the house." It is the entity that also
tells us from which something moves, either literally or metaphorically. For example, I took
the pen from the drawer. The seventh semantic role is called Goal. It identifies where an
entity moves to e.g. The Window in the sentence, "The boy walked to the window."
Beneficiary is the entity for whose benefit the action was performed. For example, they
31
baked me a cake. Location is the place where something is situated or has taken place. For
example, the baby was hiding behind the curtain. Stimulus is the entity causing an effect
(usually psychological) during an experience. For example: The noise of the horn frightened
the passengers.
Semantic relations remain the same in the sentences that are paraphrased. In both these
sentences:
Conclusion
To infer, by identifying these semantic roles, we can better understand the meaning
and relationships between the different elements in sentences. This understanding can be
especially helpful for language learners who are trying to master complex sentence structures
in a new language.
Valency
Different predicates verbs, adjectives, prepositions can be described according to the
number of referring expressions, or arguments that can occur with them and the roles these
arguments have. An account of the number of arguments that a predicate has is called
32
the valency of that predicate. Valency theory is a description of the semantic potential of
predicates in terms of the number and types of arguments which may co-occur with them.
Some predicates, such as break, have variable valency: a valency of one in A window broke
and a valency of two in Tom broke a window.
Let‘s consider the following sentences:
It is snowing.
My brother snores.
Chris is making an omelet.
Agnes is writing her mother a letter.
Each of these four sentences is longer than the one before it because it has more arguments.
The verbs snow, snores, make and write have different valencies respectively, valencies of
zero, one, two and three and each of them is typical of a whole group of predicates.
Valency Zero
It is snowing.
(a) The first sentence in the group above has the verb snow, and the subject is it, but it
doesn‘t name anything. The sentence has a subject because English requires a subject, but
this subject does not correspond to anything in the underlying proposition. We say that snow
is a zero-argument verb. Other zero-argument verbs are seen in the following:
It‘s raining.
It sleeted (yesterday).
It has been thundering (in the west).
English requires the presence of it with weather verbs like rain, snow, sleet, thunder,
but it does not refer to anything. These verbs are among the few in the language that do not
require some referent to be named in the sentence. Tense and aspect must be expressed
(rains, rained; is snowing, has been snowing) and indications of time and place can be added
(yesterday, in the west, etc.) but a sentence is complete without anything being named.
Here are similar sentences with weather adjectives as predicates:
It is windy (today).
It was rainy (all last month).
Valency one
My brother snores.
33
This sentence has the verb snore and a subject my brother. A lot of verbs are like snore: they
have a subject but no object. They are intransitive verbs or, in our terminology, one argument
predicates. Other one-argument verbs appear in the sentences below.
{The dog is sleeping.
Larry laughed.
The earth rotates (on its axis).} Group 1
{Grandfather died (last week).
A volcano erupted.
The cake fell.} Group 2
Now let‘s consider the role or roles that the arguments have. In the first group the
predicates sleep, laugh and rotate express actions; they tell what the dog, Larry and the earth
do, respectively. Consequently, each of these arguments names an actor that carries out the
action.
Turning to the second group, it would be possible to say that Grandfather and a
volcano and the cake did something, and the respective predicates tell what they did, but
these predicates are not like those of the first group. The predicates die, erupt, fall tell of an
event, a change in the condition of the entity named by the argument, and the entity named in
the argument undergoes this change, is affected by it.
Valency two
Chris is making an omelet.
Most verbs take a subject and an object; they are two-argument predicates. One of
them is make, illustrated in sentence above. Other examples are need and use. We can‘t
simply say *Chris is making or *I need or *Sue used. A statement with make must contain a
mention of who makes and what is made, and likewise with need and use.
{The cat killed a rat.
I broke the window.
Bert hit Harry.} 1
{The cat dug a hole.
Chris is making an omelet.
Picasso created a masterpiece.} 2
{Jennie crossed the street.
Jenny entered the room.
34
Simon climbed a tree.} 3
The first group of sentences expresses some action by one entity which affects another
entity. The first argument denotes an agent and the second argument names the entity
affected. An agent is involved in an action that has some effect on another entity or entities;
an actor, on the other hand, is involved in some action (e.g. running) that has no necessary
effect on others. In sentences there is a difference. The cat doesn‘t just affect a hole nor
Chris an omelet nor Picasso a masterpiece. The hole, omelet and masterpiece are the result or
effect of the action. They come into existence because of the action. The predicates of the
third group of sentences, also express some action performed by an actor and the action
involves movement with respect to a place. To enter, leave, cross or climb entails some
location (though the place does not always have to be mentioned). The second argument in
each of these sentences has the role of place.
Synopsis
A sentence is defined as a composite of inflection and proposition, and a proposition
consists of a subject and a predicate. Inflection includes agreement and tense; agreement is
the formal bond between subject and predicate, a bond that varies considerably from one
language to another. Tense is a system of contrasts that locates the general meaning of the
proposition in the past, present or future, from the time-perspective of the speaker; and
different languages have quite different tense systems.
Define in detail what are ‗semantic roles‘? How are they useful in understanding the
meaning of an utterance? Explain with help of appropriate examples.
What are the various types of valences? How do they determine meaning in text?
Discuss with the help of appropriate examples.
Students Learning Outcomes: By the end of this lesson, the learners will be able to:
35
i. Define the term noun and comprehend various categories of nouns
ii. Make a distinction between the term componential analysis and semantic feature
iii. Identify the term binary opposition and Find the different binary features of nouns
iv. Know how the terms semantic feature and semantic field are related to each other
v. Tell semantic properties of noun
Abstract noun: An abstract noun denotes one or more entities that do not have physical
existence: idea, problem
Concrete noun: A concrete noun denotes one or more physical entities e.g. Chair, food, etc.
Action noun: A noun that expresses something that somebody does: discovery, swimming.
Affected noun: A noun derived from a verb which names an entity that receives the action
of the verb: advisee.
Agent noun: A noun usually derived from a verb, which names a person who performs the
action of the verb: painter, cook.
Animate noun: Said of a word, especially a noun that denotes some living thing: dog, boy,
In-animate noun denotes some non-living thing(s): stone, happiness.
Characterized noun: A noun derived from an adjective and which expresses an entity of
whom the adjective can be predicated: young youngster.
Collective noun: A noun that refers to a group of entities; army, furniture, luggage.
Common noun: A noun that refers to one or more of a class of objects or concepts: cat,
idea.
Countable noun: A noun that has singular and plural forms and which denotes separable
entities: child(ren), house(s).
Definite noun: Said of a noun phrase that refers to an entity or group of entities whose
identity is presumably known to the addressee.
Effect noun: A noun derived from a verb and which expresses the product or outcome of the
action expressed by the verb: song ¬ sing.
Indefinite noun: An indefinite noun is a type of noun that is not specific in its reference. For
example, "a dog" or "a cat" refers to any dog or cat.
36
Inhabitant noun: A noun like New Yorker which names the inhabitant of a particular place.
Instrument noun: A noun that refers to an inanimate object by which the action of some
verb is accomplished: brush, projector.
Non-countable noun: A noun that has no plural form: mud, misery, etc.
Proper noun: A noun or noun phrase that labels some specific person, place, building,
historic event, etc. and which lacks the grammatical forms of a common noun.
A semantic feature is a notational method which can be used to express the existence
or non-existence of pre- established semantic properties by using plus and minus signs [+ / -
]. Semantic properties are those aspects of a linguistic unit, such as a morpheme, word, or
sentence that contribute to the meaning of that unit.
According to Leech (1981: 84), the analysis of word senses is often seen as a process
of breaking down the sense of a word into its minimal components which is known as
semantic features or sense components or componential analysis. The meaning of a word is
made up of a set of abstracted characteristics, known as semantic features, which distinguish
this word from other words.
In Componential Analysis, binary feature is used. A binary feature assumes both the
[+] and [-] features. Girl, woman, sister, wife, queen [+ FEMALE] Boy, man, brother,
husband, king [+ MALE] child, person, sibling, spouse, monarch [sex not specified]
(Lobner, 2002:133)
Since semantic features are established on the basis of binary opposition, e.g. binary
semantic features of nouns are featured by [±common] [±concrete] [±countable] [±animate],
etc. Examples of semantic feature of nouns (man): [+common] [+concrete] [+countable]
[+human] [+adult] [+male] Spinster: [+common] [+concrete] [+countable] [+human]
[+adult] [- male] [- married]
Semantic Field
We may notice that nouns are an essential part of language and play a crucial role in
conveying meaning. They are words that represent people, places, things, or ideas. Each
noun carries its own set of semantic properties that help us understand its meaning.
Semantic properties of nouns can be divided into various classes: specificity, animacy,
gender, kinship, social status, physical properties, and function.
iv. Gender: In English, the four genders of noun are masculine, feminine, common, and
neuter. Masculine nouns refer to words for a male figure or male member of a species (i.e.
38
man, boy, actor, horse, etc.) Feminine nouns refer to female figures or female members of a
species (i.e. woman, girl, actress, mare, etc.) Common nouns refer to members of a species
and don't specify the gender (i.e. parent, friend, client, student, etc.) Neuter nouns refer to
things that have no gender (i.e. rock, table, pencil, etc.)
v. Kinship refers to the words used in a speech community to identify relationships between
individuals in a family. It differs from society to society and culture to culture. All societies
have kinship systems, which can be analyzed in terms of a few semantic features that co-
occur. The features parent, offspring, sibling and spouse are universal. Older and younger
siblings are named differently in some cultures. Gender figures differently in different
systems, so that relations on the mother‘s side may have different names than those on the
father‘s side, and similarly for the bride‘s family as distinct from the bridegroom‘s family.
vi. Social status refers to the honor or prestige attached to one's position in society. It
may also refer to a rank or position that one holds in a group, such as son or daughter,
playmate, pupil, etc. When we talk about the semantic features of nouns, the term "social
status" refers to the position or rank that a noun can indicate within a social hierarchy. It
involves understanding how certain nouns can convey information about a person's social
standing, such as their occupation, education, or societal role. For example, nouns like
"doctor," "professor," or "CEO" indicate a higher social status, while nouns like "janitor,"
"student," or "cashier" may indicate a lower social status. The social status of a noun can
provide important contextual information and contribute to the overall meaning of a sentence
or discourse.
vii. Physical properties refer to how an entity exists in. It can include shape, size, and
material, for example.
viii. The function class of semantic properties refers to noun class markers that indicate the
purpose of an entity or how humans utilize an entity. In relation to the semantic feature of
nouns, the term "function" refers to the role or purpose that a noun serves in a sentence or
within a particular context. It involves understanding how a noun is used and what it
contributes to the overall meaning of a sentence or discourse. For example, a noun can
function as a subject, object, or possessive in a sentence, and its function can affect the
interpretation and meaning of the sentence.
Conclusion
39
In a nutshell, it can be said that nouns are an indispensible part of our communication
and language. They have a vital role in conveying meaning. By understanding these
properties, we can better comprehend the meaning and usage of nouns in language.
Bibliography
Semantic properties of verbs refer to the various aspects of meaning that are
conveyed through the usage of verbs in language. Verbs are one of the fundamental
components of language, and they are used to describe actions and states. In this lecture, we
will explore the semantic properties of verbs and how they convey meaning in language.
Firstly, we will discuss the two categories of verbs: stative verbs and dynamic verbs.
Dynamic verbs (sometimes referred to as "action verbs") usually describe actions we can
take, or things that happen; stative verbs usually refer to a state or condition which is not
changing or likely to change. The difference is important, because stative verbs cannot
normally be used in the continuous (BE + ING) forms.
Dynamic verbs
There are many types of dynamic verbs, but most of them describe activities or events
which can begin and finish. Here are some examples:
40
Dynamic Verb Type Examples
hit momentary action When one boxer hits another, brain damage can
result. (This suggests only ONE punch.)
When one boxer is hitting another, brain damage can
result. (This suggests MANY repeated punches.)
Dynamic verbs, as you can see from the table above, can be used in the simple and perfect
forms (plays, played, has played, had played) as well as the continuous or progressive
forms (is playing, was playing, has been playing, had been playing).
Stative verbs
Stative verbs usually refer to a state or condition which is quite static or unchanging. They
can be divided into verbs of perception or cognition (which refer to things in the mind), or
verbs of relation (which describe the relationships between things). Here are some examples:
Note that we CANNOT use these verbs in the continuous (progressive) forms; you CAN'T
say "*Yasir is owning three cars." Owning is a state, not an action, so it is always in the
simple form.
Example verbs
Here some common stative and dynamic verbs. The lists may help us to understand what
types of verbs are likely to be stative and what types are commonly dynamic.
Stative love; hate; like; see; hear; sound; think (meaning "have an
41
Verbs opinion"); mind (meaning "care about"); recognize; seem; have (meaning
"own"); prefer; doubt; consist of; mean
Dynamic eat; drink; go; type; read; write; listen; speak; watch; say; grow; work; sle
Verbs ep; cook; talk
One of the most important semantic properties of verbs is aspect. Aspect refers to the
way in which verbs depict the temporal structure of events. There are two main aspects in
English: the perfective aspect and the imperfective aspect. The perfective aspect is used to
describe completed events, while the imperfective aspect is used to describe ongoing or
incomplete events.
Another important semantic property of verbs is tense. Tense refers to the way in
which verbs locate events in time. English has three tenses: past, present, and future. The
tense of a verb tells us when the event took place or will take place.
Another important semantic property of verbs is voice. Voice refers to the way in
which verbs indicate the relationship between the subject of the sentence and the action
being performed. There are two main voices in English: active voice and passive voice. The
active voice places the subject as the agent performing the action, while the passive voice
places the subject as the recipient of the action.
It can be further noticed that semantic features are conceptual elements by which a
person understands the meanings of words. Decomposing the meanings of words into
42
semantic features can clarify how certain words relate to other words. This method
represents the meaning of a word in terms of semantic features that make up the word.
Verbs also have other semantic features as part of their meaning. For example, ―cause‖
is a feature of verbs such as darkens, kill, uglify, and so on.
―Go‖ is a feature of verbs that mean a change in location or possession, such as swim, crawl,
throw, fly, give, or buy. Words like swim have an additional feature like ―in liquid,‖ while
crawl is ―close to a surface.‖
Jack swims.
―Become‖ is a feature expressing the end state of the action of certain verbs. For example,
the verb break can be broken down into the following components of meaning: ―cause‖ to
―become‖ broken. Verbal features, like features on nouns, may have syntactic consequences.
For example, verbs can either describe events; such as John kissed Mary/John ate oysters, or
states, such as John knows Mary/John likes oysters. The eventive/ stative difference is
mirrored in the syntax. Eventive sentences still sound natural when passivized, when
expressed progressively, when used imperatively, and with certain adverbs:
Eventives
Statives
Such expressions are called negative polarity items because a negative element such as ―not‖
elsewhere in the sentence allows them to appear Consider these data:
This suggests that verbs such as doubt and despair, but not think and hope, have ―negative‖
as a component of their meaning. Doubt may be analyzed as ―think that not,‖ and despair as
―has no hope.‖ The negative feature in the verb allows the negative feature in the verb allows
the negative polarity item ever to occur grammatically without the overt presence of not.
44
*Negative Polarity Item (NPI): An expression that is grammatical in the presence of
negation, but ungrammatical in simple affirmative sentences. For example; any in ―James
does not have any Money‖ but * James has any money.
In a nutshell, the semantic properties of verbs are multidimensional and can significantly
impact the meaning of a sentence. Aspect, tense, modality, voice, transitivity, events, states,
etc. are all essential aspects of a verb's meaning and should be carefully considered when
using verbs in language.
Words have relationship with other words. In our everyday talk, we often explain the
meanings of words in terms of their relationships. For example, if someone is asked the
meaning of the word conceal, the simple reply might be, ―it is same as a hid,‖ or give the
meaning of shallow as ―the opposite of deep,‖ or the meaning of daffodil as ―a kind of
flower.‖ In doing so, we are characterizing the meaning of each word, not in terms of its
component features, but in terms of relationship to other words. This approach is used in the
semantic description of language and treated as the analysis of lexical relations.
45
Sense relation refers to any of several ways in which the meanings of words may be
related. Words do not have meanings in isolation; instead, the meaning of a word is usually
related in important ways to the meaning of other words. Some of the most prominent of
these relations in meaning are known collectively as sense relations. These relations include:
Synonymy: Synonyms are two or more words with very closely related meanings
Antonymy: Two forms with opposite meanings
Hyponymy: When the meaning of one form is included in the meaning of another
Prototypes: The most common example of a category is called prototype
Homophones: Two or more words with different forms and the same pronunciation
Homonyms: Two or more words with the same form and pronunciation but they have
unrelated meanings
Polysemy: Two words or more with the same form and pronunciation with related
meaning(s)
Metonymy: A container-contents relation
Collocation: Words tend to occur with other words
Paradigmatic and Syntagmatic Relations
From the point of view of structural linguistics, linguistic units can be studied from the
point of two axes: syntagmatic and paradigmatic axes. Similarly meaning of linguistic units
can be studied by means of these two axes oriented relations. Syntagmatic relation is the
relation between words that appear in a sentence. It can be visualized as relation in the
horizontal axis. Paradigmatic relation is the relation between words that can replace a word
that appear in a sentence. It can be visualized as a relation in the vertical axis.
The relation between boy, beat, and dog is syntagmatic relation. The relation between
girl, man and human being that can replace one another or between dog, snake, cat and
animal that can replace one another in a context is paradigmatic relation.
46
Congruence Relations
The four basic relations between classes furnish a model not only for establishing
fundamental group of sense relations, but also for defining a set of systematic variants
applicable to virtually all other paradigmatic sense relations (Cruse, 1986:86). The basic
lexical relations are referred as congruence relations.
A B
A
B
Overlap: class A and class B have members in common but each has members not found in
the other
The paradigmatic sense relations of identity leads to synonymy and the paradigmatic
relations of inclusion leads to hyponymy-hypernymy and meronymy-holonymy relations.
Synonymy
The lexical items which have the same meaning or which share same componential
semantic features are synonyms and the relationship existing between them is synonymy.
Synonymy does not necessarily mean that the items concerned should be identical in
meaning, i.e. interchangeable in all contexts. Synonymy can be said to occur if lexical items
are close enough in their meaning to allow a choice to be made between them in some
47
contexts, without there being any difference in the meaning of the sentence as a whole. Take,
for examples, the following words He plays the violin very well entails and is entailed by He
plays fiddle very well. The following pairs of words can be considered as synonym pairs:
filbert: hazelnut, couch: sofa, big: large, automobile: car, Water: H20.
Two lexemes are synonyms if they can be successfully substituted for each other in all
situations. If so they have the same propositional meaning. Synonymy is a relation between
senses rather than words. Consider the words big and large. We may consider them as
synonyms when we come across the following examples:
But we may hesitate to judge them as synonyms when we come across the following
examples:
The reason is big has a sense that means being older, or grown up; large lacks this
sense. But there are few (or no) examples of perfect synonymy. When reference is made to
lexical relation or close relatedness in the meaning of words, we deal with synonymy. We can
therefore, describe pairs of words that have very close similarities in meaning as synonyms.
For example we can have the following pairs of words as synonyms: Friend: Ally: Boss:
Master; Amiable: Friendly
It has often been observed that words may not always have exact substitutes in all
contexts. This observation means that we may have absolute, complete and total synonyms
when there are exact substitutes as shown by the following examples: everybody: everyone;
bandit: brigand
There are also broad or near synonyms as seen from the following examples: rich:
sumptuous; mature: ripe
Antonymy
Antonyms are words which are opposite in meaning. Different types of relationships
that seem to involve words which are at a time related in meaning yet incompatible or
contrasting, some of them are as follow:
1. Simple Antonyms - the negative of one implies the positive of the other - complementary
pairs or binary pairs.
2. Gradable Antonyms - this is a relationship between opposites where the positive of one
term does not necessarily imply the negative of the other.
3. Taxonomy Sisters -antonym sometimes describe words which are at the same level in
taxonomy. Taxonomies are classification systems e.g. the color adjectives in English (i.e.
red, orange, yellow, green, blue, purple, brown).
4. Reverses - shows reverse relation in between terms describing movements, where one
term describes movement in one direction, and the other the same movement in the opposite
direction, e.g. push/pull, come/go, up/down, in/out, right/left.
5. Converses - describe a relation between two entities from alternate viewpoints, e.g.
own/belong to, above/ below, employer/ employee.
Meronymy
49
that holds between 'wheel' and 'bicycle' is meronymy and the relation between 'bicycle' and
'wheel' is holonymy,
The fact that one object may be described as a part of another object does not imply,
however, that there is a part-whole relation holding in the vocabulary between the lexemes
used in expressions which refer to these entities. For example we can say 'handle is a part of
a door' and 'door is a part of a house'; but it is odd to say 'handle is a part of a house' or 'this
is house-handle' or 'this handle of the house'. We might therefore inclined to set up a part-
whole relationship between 'handle' and 'door' and between 'house' and 'door', but not
between 'handle' and 'house'.
The difference between hyponymy and part-whole relations is clear enough in cases
like 'arm': 'body', 'wheel': 'bicycle'; i.e. when the lexemes in question are nouns denoting
discrete physical objects. Most of the discussion of part-whole lexical relations by linguists
has been restricted to such cases.
Mention should also made here about various kinds of collectives such as 'cattle',
'clergy', 'furniture', 'herd', 'flock', 'family', 'library'. Collective nouns are defined,
semantically, as lexemes which denote collections or groups of persons or objects. In
English, they fall into a number of different grammatical classes. For example, 'cattle' and
50
'clergy' are treated as plural and 'furniture' as singular. We are concerned herewith the place
occupied by collectives in the structure of vocabulary. Many of them serve as superordinates
in relation to a set of quasi-hyponyms. For example, 'cattle' is a superordinate to {'cow',
'bull', 'steer', etc} and 'clergy' is superordinate to {'bishop', 'priest', etc.}. There are many such
collectives in the vocabulary of English and other languages which are superodinate to sets
of lexemes in a hierarchical relationship that is ambivalent with respect to the distinction of
hyponymy and the part-whole relation.
Prototype
The prototype of any category is the member or set of members of a category that best
represents the category as a whole. It explains the meaning of certain words in terms of
resemblance to the clearest example. The term semantic feature assists us identify various
prototypes of any category. For example, the clearest example of the words bird, fruit and
furniture are pigeon, apple and chair respectively.
Hyponymy
When the meaning of one form is included in the meaning of another, we have
hyponymy relation. For instance, included in animals are dogs, elephants, goat, etc. We can
also relate hyponymy to professions to include law, medicine, teaching, banking, etc. There
is always a hierarchical relationship drawing from the general to samples. The general term
is usually referred to as superordinate term while the terms that indicate inclusion are
referred to as hyponyms. Simply then, hyponymy is about relations of inclusion.
As such, we can say that flower is a superordinate term while rose, cauliflower,
sunflower, carnation, forget-me-not, etc. are hyponyms of flower. Co-occurring hyponyms
are referred to as co-hyponyms. Thus, table, chair, cupboard, wardrobe, bookshelf, bedstead
are co-hyponyms while their superordinate term is furniture.
The 2 or more words that share the same superordinate term are co-hyponyms.
Dog & horse are co-hyponyms and their superordinate term is animal.
Hyponyms is a transitive relation. If X is a hyponym of Y and Y is a hyponymy of Z,
then X is the hyponym of Z. For example cow is a hyponymy of 'mammal' and 'mammal' is a
hyponym of 'animal'; therefore 'cow' is the hyponym of 'animal'.
Homophones
Two or more words with different forms and the same pronunciation are said to be
homophones. Examples include, bare/bear, meat/meet, flour/flower, pail/pale, right/write,
hole/whole, to/too/two, etc.
Homonyms
Two or more words which have the same form and pronunciation but they have
unrelated meanings. Followings are some of the examples of homonyms:
Bank (of a river) bank (financial institution)
Mole (on skin) mole (small animal)
Pupil (at school) pupil (in the eye)
Race (contest of speed) race (ethnic group)
Homonyms are words that have separate histories and meanings, but accidently have
the same form and pronunciation.
Polysemy (Poly means many and semy entails meanings)
It refers to the two words or more with the same form and pronunciation, and with
related meanings. For example,
Head = the object on top of your body Head = the person at the top of a company or
department.
Foot = of person/ of bed/ of mountain
52
It is possible for two terms to be distinguished via homonymy and via polysemy.
Date = a thing we eat]
Date = a point in time]
Homonyms
Date = a point in time is polysemous in terms of:
A particular day and month (=on a letter)
The date on the letter was 30th August 1962.
What's today's date?
An arranged meeting (= an appointment)
Let's make a date to come over and visit.
A romantic meeting (=with someone we like)
He has got a date with his cousin tomorrow night.
A person (that person we like)
Can he bring his date to the party?
Polysemy
Collocation
Collocation refers to the tendency for certain words to occur together. A word like
‗clear‘, for example, can be found with a number of nouns, clear sky, clear conscience, clear
idea, clear road. In each term clear has a slightly different meaning because of the word it is
qualifying. It is an arrangement or juxtaposition of words or other elements, especially those
that commonly co-occur, as dead serious, iron will, green with jealously etc.
Bibliography:
2. Trask, R. (2007). LANGUAGE AND LINGUISTICS (KEY CONCEPTS). New York: Routledge.
3. Yule, G. (2020). The Study of Language 7th Ed. Camberidge: Cambridge University Press .
Introduction
Linguistic meaning is a special subset of the more general human ability to use signs
to convey meanings, e.g. traffic lights are the combination of colours to instruct the drivers
and even to warn them. It is believed that human language differs in kind more than a degree
from other languages (Palmer, 1997).
Scholars (e.g. Ferdinand de Saussure, 1974) are of the view that linguistics is a part of
the general study of the use of the sign system, which is called Semiotics. Semioticians have
probed the relationship that may be between the sign and the object it represents or in
Saussure‗s terminology, between signifier and its signified (Saeed, 2004).
• Signifier: Any material thing that signifies, e.g., words on a page, a facial expression, an
image.
• Sign: The smallest unit of meaning. Anything that can be used to communicate
These terms were introduced by Friedrich Ludwig Gottlob Frege (1848 -1925) in his
treatise entitled ―Uber Sinn und Bedeutung from 1892, translated into English as ―On
sense and reference.
Reference has to do with the relationship which holds between an expression and what
that expression stands for on particular occasions of its utterance (Lyons, 1977). According
to Saeed (2004), Reference is ―relationship by which language looks onto the world is
usually called reference. Thus, reference can be concluded as the meanings of a word in any
language which exist in the real world.
54
In semantics, reference is generally interpreted as the relationships
between nouns or pronouns and objects that are named by them. Hence, the word "John"
refers to the person John. The word "it" refers to some previously specified object. The
object referred to is called the referent of the word. Sometimes the word-object relation is
called "denotation"; the word denotes the object.
According to Saeed (2009), the ―semantic links between elements within the
vocabulary system is an aspect of their sense. It can be concluded that ―sense exists in the
word and this is a word to word relation.
55
in Sentence b, above. Similarly, ―Where can you always find sympathy?‖ ―Washington has
three syllables‖; ―Washington has 600,000 inhabitants.‖ Of course, italics and underlining
have no effect in speech.
2. There is no natural connection between referring expression and referent. Some
ancient philosophers and ancient and medieval etymologists held the opinion that there is or
once was a natural relation between symbol and what is symbolized. But this is simply not
so.
3. The existence of a referring expression does not guarantee the existence of a
referent
in the physical-social world that we inhabit. We can easily use language to create
expressions with fictitious referents such as the skyscrapers of Antarctica, the present
Emperor of Texas, the pain-reliever recommended by 91 percent of all doctors. In fact, we
need such expressions in order to deny the existence of any physical referent.
4. Two or more referring expressions may have the same referent, but they do not
necessarily have the same meaning. Robert Blair the husband of Mildred Stone Blair the
father of Patrick and Robin Blair the city editor of the Morgantown Daily Enquirer, etc. All
these and no doubt other referring expressions may identify the same individual, but they do
not mean the same. Two terms may name the same thing but differ in connotation, like fiddle
and violin, or simply differ in the way they refer. The following example provided by Frege
(1980. In the Northern Hemisphere the planet Venus is visible to the naked eye just before
sunrise at certain times of the year and just after sunset at other times. Consequently, it is
known sometimes as the Morning Star, and sometimes as the Evening Star. These two terms
and also the planet Venus name the same entity, but they do not have the same meaning.
A referring expression is used to identify, but the identification may be valid only
temporarily (the girl in the purple sweater) and it need not be true: you may know who I
mean when I refer to that stupid clown but your ability to identify doesn‘t depend on your
agreeing with my way of referring. We often use metonymy in referring, identifying some
entity, especially a person, by some characteristic associated with the entity, as when we
refer to someone as ‗the horn rimmed glasses‘ or when a waitress asks a group of people
seated at one table, ―Which of you is the tuna salad?‖
Extension and Intension
56
The extension of a lexeme is the set of entities which it denotes. The extension of dog
includes all collies, dalmatians, dachshunds, mongrels, etc., etc. that have ever lived or will
ever live and every fictitious creature that is accepted as being a dog. All the things that can
be denoted by the noun lake are the extension of that lexeme. The lexeme Lake Ontario has a
single item in its extension, and the Dead Sea Scrolls has a single collection of items as its
extension.
The intension of any lexeme is the set of properties shared by all members of the
extension. Thus, everything that is denoted by lake must be a body of water of a certain size
surrounded by land, and everything denoted by island is a body of land surrounded by water
but see below for discussion of some difficulties in applying these definitions. Extension has
to do with reference, but reference, as we know, is not all of meaning: the lexemes violin and
fiddle have the same extension. Extension can change while intension remains the same. The
extension of the referring expression the capital of Australia is a single item, the city of
Canberra. The intension of the same term is ‗city in which the national government of
Australia is located.‘ If the capital should be moved at some future time to another city, the
extension changes but the intension remains the same. The Mayor of Chicago or the Prime
Minister of Great Britain always has the same intension but the extension of each of these
changes from time to time.
In the discussion of hyponymy in the sense relations lecture, we noted that the
denotation of a hyponym like collie is included in the denotation of its superordinate, dog,
but the meaning of the superordinate is included in the meaning of the hyponym. We can
now restate this with the terms ‗intension‘ and ‗extension‘: the extension of the hyponym is
included in the extension of the superordinate (all collies are dogs) but the intension of the
superordinate is included in the intension of the hyponym (the characteristic of being a dog is
part of the
characteristic of being a collie).
Language is a way in which people classify the phenomena in their world, their lives.
The
English language leads us to believe that there is a clear difference between lake and pond,
between bush and tree, hill and mountain, between greenish-blue and bluish-green. Actually,
extensions have fuzzy boundaries because nature does not consist of items discretely
57
separated and clearly differentiated from one another. Sometimes it is the edges that are
fuzzy while from center to center the difference is clear enough.
A prototype is an object or referent that is considered typical of the whole set. Thus, if
we encounter the lexeme door in isolation and immediately think of a door swinging on
hinges rather than one that slides or rotates that kind of door is, for us, the prototype of all
doors. But not everybody is likely to have the same prototype for a particular set. People in
Belize probably do not have the same prototype for tree as people in Scotland.
Some Different Kinds of Referents
The entities that we refer to are of different kinds and a language may have ways of
recognizing different kinds of referents, different reference classes. Three kinds of
differences in referents are:
To some extent the differences are in the referents and to some extent in the way English,
or any language, treats the referents.
60
At the non-countable end of the continuum are nouns that name collections of items—
furniture, jewelry, luggage—which are always non-countable. The specific items included in
these collections are indicated by countable nouns—chair, bed; necklace, ring; trunk,
suitcase. In other instances, there are matching nouns: shrubbery and shrub, rain and
raindrop, snow and snowflake, including some that have no formal relationship: foliage and
leaf.
There are a few nouns which occur only as plurals:
scissors, pliers, tweezers; trousers, shorts, jeans, etc.; shavings, filings, earnings, savings.
This language distinction seems to mirror a distinction found in nature: apples, babies,
coins, leaves and pebbles are isolable, while dirt, sand, milk, rice and water appear to be
continuous entities or composed of such small particles that we don‘t consider the particles
worth counting. However, note the inconsistency of suds, a plural countable, and foam, a
non-countable; of the plural countable oats and the non-countable wheat, rye, barley, corn.
These distinctions concrete/abstract, unique/non-unique, countable/ non-countable
seem to reflect differences that exist in nature, but only partly so. All languages have
reference classes which may be ‗natural‘ to some degree. We take it for granted that
countable nouns should be singular or plural, but nature does not have two categories, a
category consisting of one single item and another category that consists of all numbers from
two to infinity.
Lecture 12 Discourse and Meaning
Introduction
When we use language, we combine words to form phrases and we combine phrases
to form clauses and sentences. Sentences may also be combined to form larger stretches of
61
language known as 'discourse' (for example, conversations, stories, jokes, letters and so on).
Linguists are interested in the ways in which discourse is structured and used.
Discourse analysis studies the meaning in language at contextual level. The meaning
can be analyzed in two kinds of context: the extra-linguistic, which deals with that of the
external world, and the intra-linguistic, where that piece of language occurs. For example,
we can sec that words occur within a sentential context, and sentences occur within a context
consisting of other sentences. In the analysis of language at level of discourse, the intra-
linguistic context is very much significant.
Discourse analysis includes all the three linguistic levels in a sentence, such as sound,
lexis and syntax. We are required to distinguish discourse from sentence because these three
levels are essential for the above two contexts. The sentence is a grammatical aspect formed
with the combination of words under certain rules of grammar. These rules of sentence-
connection create cohesion in the text. Discourse involves meaning and utterance as it is
included in the semantic or pragmatic aspect.
Sentences have a force which is vital for understanding their meaning. These forceful
utterances combine to create coherence. We can say that the text is created by sentence
62
cohesion while the discourse by coherence. Hence, discourse may be defined as a stretch of
language-use which is coherent in its meaning, which includes both grammar and coherence.
Look at the following sentences which are both .cohesive and coherent:
Here, the interchange is cohesive as Peter does not repeat the whole of the first
sentence in his reply. Instead of the whole sentence I can lend you some money today, he
only says Yes, I can, omitting the rest. It shows that the second sentence is linked to the first
in sequential order. It is also coherent because Peter has given an appropriate response to
John's question which implies the sense of request. Look another example:
These sentences are not cohesive because the second sentence is not linked to the first
grammatically and nor they have any connection in apparent way. But they are coherent as
Peter's reply gives some information that 'there is a strike in the bank', and therefore, it is not
possible to fulfill the request of John today. Hence, this exchange is coherent, but not
cohesive.
Discourse is a level higher than that of the sentence. It includes all the other linguistic
levels sound, lexis, syntax. All these continue to make up a discourse. But here we must
distinguish between the grammatical aspect and the semantic/ pragmatic aspect of discourse.
The former creates a text and the latter creates a discourse. In the former, words continue to
form sentences; sentences combine to form a text. Just as there are rules for combination of
words, there are certain relations between sentences and rules by which they may be related.
These rules of sentence-connection create cohesion in the text. At the same time, these
sentences are also utterances, i.e. they have a force which is vital for understanding their
meaning, which are combined to create coherence. Thus we may distinguish between text
and discourse in that text is created by sentence-cohesion and discourse is created by
coherence. A discourse may be defined as a stretch of language-use which is coherent in its
63
meaning, It will of course include grammar and cohesion. The following is an example of
discourse which is both cohesive and coherent:
B: Yes, I can.
The interchange is cohesive because the second sentence does not repeat the whole of
the first sentence. Instead of the whole sentence: 'I can go to Karachi tomorrow', B says only:
I can', omitting the rest. This indicates that the second sentence is linked to the first in
sequential order. It is also coherent because B has given an appropriate response to A from
A's request. However, in the following example:
The two sentences are not cohesive because the second sentence is not linked to the
first sentence in a grammatical sense. There is no repetition or obvious connection between
the two sentences. But they are coherent, because B replies to A's request in a sentence
which gives some information implying that it may not be possible to go to Karachi. Thus,
this exchange is coherent but not cohesive.
The tenor of discourse refers to features relating to the relationship between the
speaker and the addressee in a given situation-these features reflect the formality or
64
informality, degree of politeness, a personal or impersonal touch. Thus, if the relationship is
a polite one, there will be respectful terms of address, e.g. 'Sir', and indirect requests rather
than commands. If the relationship is one of familiarity, the features will include terms of
friendship e.g. 'dear, direct requests and imperatives.
Lastly, field or domain of discourse pertains to the area of activity to which that
discourse belongs, eg. whether the discourse is in the field of religion, science, law.
journalism, advertising. In each field, the discourse will be characterized by a particular kind
of vocabulary and sentence structure, e.g. sports commentary uses present tense: advertising
uses many adjectives. Literary discourse often freely combines features from many kinds of
discourse and occupies a different status from other types of discourse.
Field or domain is involved in the area of activity to which the discourse belongs. The
field of discourse may be that of religion, science, advertising, law, etc. To express each field
of discourse there is a particular kind of vocabulary and sentence structure.
Discourse and meaning are two intertwined concepts that are crucial in understanding
language and communication. Discourse can be defined as a stretch of language use that
pervades a social context and is characterized by a unity of purpose. It is a term used to refer
to the use of language in communication. Discourse can take many forms, such as a
conversation, an argument, a speech, or a written text. What is important about discourse is
that it is not just a collection of words or sentences, but rather a meaningful interaction
between speakers or writers and their audience.
Meaning, on the other hand, is the significance or sense that is conveyed through
language. It refers to the information or message conveyed by language use. The meaning of
language is not fixed or absolute, but rather dependent on the context in which it is used. For
example, the word ‗bank‘ can have different meanings in different contexts, such as a
financial institution, the side of a river, or a hitting action in a game.
Discourse and meaning are interrelated in various ways. The discourse in which
language is used affects the meaning of the language, and vice versa. The meaning of
language is dependent on the discourse context in which it is used. For example, the meaning
of the word ‗bank‘ in a financial discourse context is different from its meaning in an
environmental discourse context.
In addition, meaning can also be shaped and influenced by the social and cultural
contexts in which it is used. This is known as the sociolinguistic aspect of meaning. For
instance, the word ‗kind‘ has different connotations in different cultural settings; in some
cultures, it can refer to physical appearance, while in others, it can refer to personality traits.
66
Furthermore, discourse can be used to create and enforce social norms and values, as
well as to challenge them. This is known as the discursive aspect of meaning. For example,
in a political discourse, the use of certain language can frame an issue in a particular way,
and create a particular understanding of the problem. Similarly, in a social discourse, the use
of certain language can reinforce stereotypes or challenge them.
To infer, discourse and meaning are two intertwined concepts that are crucial in
understanding language and communication. Meaning is dependent on the discourse context
in which it is used, and can be shaped by sociolinguistic and discursive factors. Discourse, on
the other hand, can be used to create and enforce social norms and values, and can frame
issues in a particular way. Understanding the relationship between discourse and meaning is
essential in interpreting language and communication, and in creating effective
communication strategies.
We have studied lexical meaning as the meaning of word without paying attention to
the way that is used or to the words that occur with it. Grammatical meaning refers to that
part of meaning which indicates grammatical relationship or functions, such as tense
meaning, singular meaning, etc. Grammatical meaning consists of word class, for example,
modern (adjective), modernize (verb) and modernization (noun), and inflectional paradigm,
67
for example, grammatical meaning of plurality (e.g. desks, data). Lexical meaning is
dominant is content word, whereas grammatical meaning is dominant is function words, but
in neither grammatical absent. Take for example love, laugh, take and work; they are
different from the point of view of lexical meaning, whereas they are same form the point of
view of grammatical meaning (i.e. all are verbs). Similarly, boy and boys are same from the
point of view of lexical meaning, but are different from the point of view of grammatical
meaning (i.e. boys contain plural marker). Lexical meaning is studied in lexicon whereas
grammatical meaning is studied in grammar. But grammar and lexicon are interrelated.
Grammar reflects the ways in which lexicon operates as means of communication and as
instruments of thought. Part of the meaning of the lexicon is encoded in the grammatical
structure of languages. The grammatical system makes possible the expression of meaning
like the following:
Definiteness
Number
Number is an inflectional category of nouns or noun phrases, which is not found in all
languages. Semantically, number system are concerned, one way or another, with how many
there are of some item. Number system are no to be confused with numerical system, which
are linguistic devices for counting (one, two, forty-three, one hundred and ninety, etc.);
obviously numerals are syntactically and semantically distinct from number markers.
The number system in English has only two terms: singular and plural. A majority of
languages have three-term number system including dual, used for just two things. A very
small minority have four-term systems, in which the fourth term is either a trial (for three
things) or a paucal (for a few things).
69
In linguistics, a mass noun, uncountable noun, or non-count noun is a noun with the
syntactic property that any quantity of it is treated as an undifferentiated unit, rather than as
something with discrete subsets. Non-count nouns are distinguished from count nouns.
Given that different languages have different grammatical features, the actual test for which
nouns are mass nouns may vary between languages. In English, mass nouns are
characterized by the fact that they cannot be directly modified by a numeral without
specifying a unit of measurement, and that they cannot combine with an indefinite article (a
or an). Thus, the mass noun "water" is quantified as "20 liters of water" while the count noun
"chair" is quantified as "20 chairs". However, both mass and count nouns can be quantified
in relative terms without unit specification (e.g., "so much water," "so many chairs"). Some
mass nouns can be used in English in the plural to mean "more than one instance (or
example) of a certain sort of entity"—for example, "Many cleaning agents today are
technically not soaps, but detergents." In such cases they no longer play the role of mass
nouns, but (syntactically) they are treated as count nouns. Some nouns have both a mass
sense and a count sense (for example, paper).
In English (and in many other languages), there is a tendency for nouns referring to
liquids (water, juice), powders (sugar, sand), or substances (metal, wood) to be used in mass
syntax, and for nouns referring to objects or people to be count nouns. This is not a hard-and-
fast rule, however; mass nouns such as furniture and cutlery, which represent more easily
quantified objects, show that the mass/count distinction should be thought of as a property of
the terms themselves, rather than as a property of their referents. For example, the same set
of chairs can be referred to as "seven chairs" and as "furniture"; although both chair and
furniture are referring to the same thing, the former is a count noun and the latter a mass
noun. The Middle English mass noun peas has become the count noun pea by morphological
reanalysis.
For another illustration of the principle that the count/non-count distinction lies not in
an object but rather in the expression that refers to it, consider the English words "fruit" and
"vegetables". The objects that these words describe are, objectively speaking, similar (that is,
they're all edible plant parts); yet the word "fruit" is (usually) non-count, whereas
"vegetables" is a plural count form. One can see that the difference is in the language, not in
the reality of the objects.
70
Many English nouns can be used in either mass or count syntax, and in these cases,
they take on cumulative reference when used as mass nouns. For example, one may say that
"there's apple in this sauce," and then apple has cumulative reference, and, hence, is used as a
mass noun. The names of animals, such as "chicken", "fox" or "lamb" are count when
referring to the animals themselves, but are mass when referring to their meat, fur, or other
substances produced by them. (e.g., "I'm cooking chicken tonight" or "This coat is made of
fox.") Conversely, "fire" is frequently used as a mass noun, but "a fire" refers to a discrete
entity. Substance terms like "water" which are frequently used as mass nouns, can be used as
count nouns to denote arbitrary units of a substance ("Two waters please") or of several
types/varieties ("waters of the world"). One may say that mass nouns that are used as count
nouns are "countified" and that count ones that are used as mass nouns are "massified".
However, this may confuse syntax and semantics, by presupposing that words which denote
substances are mass nouns by default. According to many accounts, nouns do not have a
lexical specification for mass-count status, and instead are specified as such only when used
in a sentence. Nouns differ in the extent to which they can be used flexibly, depending
largely on their meanings and the context of use. For example, the count noun "house" is
difficult to use as mass (though clearly possible), and the mass noun "cutlery" is most
frequently used as mass, despite the fact that it denotes objects, and has count equivalents in
other languages:
Tense, aspect and mood are associated with the verb. Tense–aspect–mood, commonly
abbreviated TAM and also called tense–modality–aspect or TMA, is the grammatical system
of a language that covers the expression of tense (location in time), aspect (fabric of time – a
single block of time, continuous flow of time, or repetitive occurrence), and mood or
modality (degree of necessity, obligation, probability, ability).
Tense
Tense is a term that refers to the way verbs change their form in order to indicate at
which time a situation occurs or an event takes place. For finite verb phrases, English has
just one inflectional form to express time, namely the past tense marker (-ed for regular
verbs). Therefore, in English there is just a contrast between present and past tense. Needless
71
to say, non-finite verb phrases (to-infinitives and –ing forms) are not marked for tense. When
occurring with modals, verb phrases are used in their base form, with no tense marker. Each
tense can have a simple form as well as be combined with either the progressive or perfective
aspect, or with both of them:
(a) I work; I‘m working; I have worked; I have been working (present)
(b) I worked; I was working; I had worked; I had been working (past)
Sentences can also be used in the passive voice (note that the perfect-progressive is not
normally found in the passive):
There are three basic primary tenses, past (event occurs before time of speaking);
present (even occurs concurrently with speaking time, or includes it); and future (event
projected to occur after the time of speaking) (Cruse 2000: 274):
Aspect
In British English, the perfective aspect is much more common than in American English,
since Americans often use the past simple where Britons use the present perfect. Verb
phrases can be marked for both aspects at the same time (the perfect progressive, however, is
infrequent). The following combinations are possible: present progressive; past progressive;
present perfective; past perfective; present perfective progressive; past perfective
progressive:
72
(c) He has been sleeping; He had been sleeping
Progressive aspect
The progressive aspect, either in the present or past tense, generally refers to an action/event
(usually of limited duration) in progress at a particular time, to an uncompleted activity, to a
temporary state of affairs or a temporary habit. The present progressive is formed by the
present tense of the verb be + the -ing form of the lexical verb, the past progressive by
was/were + the -ing form of the lexical verb.
Stative verbs are verbs of ―being‖. Since they refer to ―states‖, they are normally used
with the simple aspect. On the contrary, dynamic (eventives) verbs are verbs of ―doing‖, they
refer to activities, events and processes. They can occur in both the simple and the
progressive aspects, depending on the meaning speakers wish to convey.
Stative verbs indicate possession and describe thoughts, beliefs, feelings, wishes,
preferences, perceptions of the senses, as well as states of being. Verbs that typically occur
with stative senses are:
(1) verbs of perception, such as: appear, feel, hear, see, seem, smell, sound and taste;
(2) verbs that refers to mental, emotional and cognitive states, such as: adore, assume,
believe, care, consider, desire, detest, dislike, doubt, envy, expect, fear, find (meaning
―consider‖), forget, forgive, guess, hate, hear (meaning ―to be told‖), hope, imagine, intend,
know, like, love, mean, mind, notice, prefer, realize, recall, recognize, refuse, regard, regret,
remember, see (meaning ―understand‖), want, wish, wonder;
(3) verbs that contain the idea of ―being‖ and ―having‖, that refer to situations which cannot
easily be imagined ashaving a time limitation: be, have (meaning ―possess‖), belong,
compare (meaning ―be similar to‖), concern, consist, contain, cost, depend, deserve, differ,
equal, exist, fit, hold, include, interest, involve, lack, matter, measure, need, owe, own,
possess, remain, require, resemble, suit.
As we have already stated, dynamic (eventives) verbs indicate activities. They can
occur in both the progressive and non-progressive form. They include verbs indicating a
73
temporary situation or an activity having some duration (for example cooks, jog, live, read,
study, work): I was living in New York at that time. I‘m making a cake
Perfective aspect
The perfective aspect is used to refer to a state or action which has taken place before
the time of speaking, as well as to a state or action (or series of actions) occurring in a period
of time we imagine as continuing until the present or until a certain moment in the past (until
now or until then), or that has just ended. The perfective aspect is also used to indicate the
completeness of an action, to see events as a whole: I have tidied my room. She had just
found a solution to the problem
Some linguists distinguish a counterpart to the perfect, but involving the future, called
the prospective. A gloss of this would be: the present relevance of a future event. Consider
the difference between the following:
One explanation is that the first sentence can be a pure prediction, and can apply to an event
which is not under the control either of Rameez or of the speaker. The second sentence, on
the other hand, implies that the event is under the control of one or the other, and the
decision and arrangements are currently complete. in other words, things are currently in a
state such that, if all goes according to plan, Rameez will leave tomorrow.
Voice
In grammar, the voice (also called diathesis and (rarely) gender (of verbs)) of a verb
describes the relationship between the action (or state) that the verb expresses and the
participants identified by its arguments (subject, object, etc.). When the subject is the agent
or doer of the action, the verb is in the active voice. When the subject is the patient, target or
undergoer of the action, the verb is said to be in the passive voice.
For example, in the following first sentence the verb "ate" is in the active voice.
However, in the second sentence the verbal phrase "was eaten" is passive.
The cat ate the mouse. p/v The mouse was eaten by the cat.
74
In following example, in the first sentence the verb "killed" is in the active voice, and
the doer of the action is the "hunter". A passive version of the sentence is where the verbal
phrase "was killed" is followed by the word "by" and then by the doer "hunter".
Functional roles
Consider the sentence John opened the door. There are two main participants in the
event: John and the door. These, however, have different relationships to the act of opening.
John is the doer, the agent and supplies the force needed to open the door; the door is
passive, is affected by the action, and undergoes the designated change of state. These
relationships are variously called functional roles, case roles, deep cases, participant roles,
thematic roles (Cruse, 2000: 281). In linguistics, grammatical relations (also called
grammatical functions, grammatical roles, or syntactic functions) refer to functional
relationships between constituents in a clause. The standard examples of grammatical
functions from traditional grammar are subject, direct object, and indirect object.
Descriptive adjectives
Antonymy in adjectives
Antonymy is the basic semantic relation that exists among descriptive adjectives. The
word association testes reveal the importance of antonymy in adjectives. As the function of
descriptive adjectives is to express values of attributes, and that nearly all attributes are
bipolar, antonymy becomes important in the organization of descriptive adjectives.
Antonymous adjectives express opposing values of an attribute. For example, the antonym of
‗heavy‘ is ‗light‘ that expresses a value at the opposite pole of the WEIGHT attribute.
Antonymy, like synonymy, is a semantic relation between word forms. The problem is that
the antonymy relation between word forms is not the same as the conceptual opposition
between word meanings.
Similarity in adjective
The adjectives lacking antonyms are similar in meaning to adjectives that do have
antonyms. Swift, dilatory, prompt, sluggish, alacritous, fast, slow, leisurely, quick, tardy,
rapid, laggard, Overwhelmingly, association data and co-occurrence data indicate that big
and little are considered as a pair and large and small are considered as a pair. These pairs
demonstrate that antonymy is a semantic relation between words rather than concepts.
Gradation in adjectives
Contraries are gradable adjectives, contradictories are not. Gradation, therefore must also be
considered as a semantic relation organizing lexical memory for adjectives.
There are two major dichotomies in the classification of adjectives. The first separates
gradable from non-gradable adjectives. This has grammatical consequences, because
prototypically, the degree inflections occur only in connection with gradable adjectives; if an
adjective is basically non-gradable, then it has to be reinterpreted when inflected for degree:
Markedness in adjectives
Binary oppositions frequently have a marked term and an unmarked term. That is, the
terms are not entirely of equivalent weights, but one (the unmarked one) is neutral or positive
in contrast to the other. Marked/unmarked distinction is found in polar oppositions such as :
'high‘: ‗low, 'old': 'young', 'long': 'short, wide: narrow.
Some reference modifying adjectives may have direct antonyms as in the case of descriptive
adjectives.
Colour adjectives
77
Colour terms need to be addressed differently than other adjectives. They can be both
nominal as well as adjectival. As adjectives they can be graded and conjoined with other
descriptive adjectives. But they differ form the descriptive adjectives as the pattern of direct
and indirect anotonymy does not hold good for colour adjectives. Only one color attribute is
clearly described by direct antonyms: LIGHTNESS, whose polar values are expressed by
light: drark
Relational adjectives
Since relational adjectives do not have antonyms, they cannot be incorporated into the
clusters that characterize descriptive adjectives. And because their syntactic and semantic
properties are a mixture of those of adjectives and those of nouns used as noun modifiers,
rather than attempting to integrate them into either structure Tamil word net will maintain a
separate file of relational adjectives with cross references to the corresponding nouns.
Modification
Quantification
78
No Taliban came to the party.
The subject noun phrases in the above are quantified noun phrases; the sentence
express quantification. A quantification requires a quantifier (e.g. no, some, many, all, etc.),
restriction (which indicates the sort of things being quantified, e.g. Tamils) and scope, which
expresses what is true of the items designated by quantified noun phrase.
Paraphrase
Paraphrase is to the sentence what synonymy is to words. This means that the
paraphrase explains a situation in which two or more sentences have one meaning. Indeed, a
sentence can have many paraphrases. There are two types of paraphrases: lexical and
structural paraphrases. In lexical paraphrases, we have two or more sentences fiving the
same interpretation as a result of the replacement of one word or phrase by another. The
following are examples:
In the two sentences above, the change in their structure is as a result of the substitution of a
bachelor for an unmarried man. Both a bachelor and unmarried man are phrases. Consider
further the following sentences:
We have achieved the paraphrase by the substitution of the word agitated for another,
anxious. Structural paraphrase is achieved when we alter the arrangements of the sentences
through transformations. The following are examples:
79
(ii) It was a new apartment that they bought (Cleft)
[A cleft sentence is a sentence in which some part is moved from its normal position into a
different place to give it more emphasis]
Ambiguity
When an expression can be given more than one interpretation ambiguity arises.
Therefore, why polysemy relates to words, ambiguity is concerned with sentences. We have
two types of ambiguity – lexical and structural.
Lexical ambiguity occurs when the presence of just a specific word leads to multiple
interpretations. Consider the following examples:
It should be noted that goals and tables can be interpreted in different easy based on the
contexts.
The ambiguity in the second sentence drives from the possibility of reading the sentence as:
The first interpretation makes boiling water as the subject noun phrase whereas in the second
interpretations, boiling water is the complement.
Presupposition
80
In presupposition, there is usually a piece of information which the speaker assumes
the hearer already knows. This assumption is based on some shared background knowledge
between the speaker and the hearers. An outsider in the circle of communication may be at a
loss. Let us illustrate this situation with the following sentences.
(ii) Peter: That will be splendid. On our way, we shall pick up the drinks.
The presupposition in this conversation is that both John and Peter know who Harry is. They
both have an idea of the drinks, and the source from where to bring them.
Entailment
In entailment, there is usually a pair of sentences and the truth of one derives from the
truth of other. Consider the following sentences:
Sentence (i) derives from the meaning of sentence (ii). This means that if sentence (i) entails
sentence (ii) then, sentence (ii) is necessarily the implication of sentence (i).
Contradiction
Contradictory expressions present two opposing proposition at the same time. Thus, a
person cannot be dead and alive at the same time. Other examples of anomaly are:
Synopsis
81
relation between lexical meaning and grammatical meaning, the meaning of major
grammatical categories, grammatical meaning associated with nouns and noun phrases,
grammatical meaning associated with the verbs, adjectives and their properties and
quantification. Under sentential semantics we have focused our attention on paraphrase,
ambiguity, presupposition, entailment, etc.
Semantics
Semantics is the study of the meaning of language. There are two types of meaning:
the meaning of language itself and the meaning that language has when used in a particular
context. For example, if we consider the following sentence 'Sarah is feeling unwell'. This
sentence means that Sarah is not feeling well. But it would communicate something different
when uttered in response to the question 'Is Sarah coming to the party tonight?‖ (It would
mean something like 'Sarah is not coming to the party') from when it was uttered in response
to the question, ―Is Sarah going to miss work today?‖ Linguists, therefore, distinguish
between what a sentence means ('linguistic meaning') and what an utterance of that sentence
communicates in a given context ('speaker meaning'). Semantics is the study of linguistic
meaning (speaker meaning is studied in pragmatics).
Language has several properties which a theory of semantics must explain. One
important property is that language is infinite, so we are able to understand an unlimited
82
number of sentences, most of which we have never encountered before (e.g. we may have no
problem understanding 'My pet lobster ate three M and Ms today.)
There are many different approaches to semantics. One of the most influential is 'truth-
conditional semantics', which tries to reduce meaning to truth and falsehood. The idea is that
in order to know what a sentence means, we need to know what things would have to be like
in order for the sentence to be true.
Syntax
There is more to the meaning of a sentence than just the meanings of its words. For
example, it is quite clear that the sentence 'Dogs chase cats' means something quite different
from the sentence 'Cats chase dogs', even though they contain exactly the same words. The
point is that sentences are not just sequences of words - they have a certain structure and this
affects their meaning. The study of sentence structure is known as 'syntax'.
Sentences have a hierarchical structure, with words combining to form phrases and
phrases combining to form clauses. A sentence consists of a single clause or a combination
of clauses. Linguists often represent this structure in the form of a tree diagram.
On the basis of the above-mentioned points, we may say that Syntax and Semantics
are two of the basic components of linguistics, and they are closely related and affect one
another. Syntax is the order and arrangement of words and phrases in sentences. Semantics,
on the other hand, is concerned with the meaning of a word, phrase, sentence, or text. The
way that semantics relates to syntax is that words have meaning, and how words are ordered
in a phrase or sentence affects meaning. A quick example that illustrates both syntax and
semantics is the following:
Though the words are the same, the order (syntax) is slightly altered in the second
sentence, and that changes the sentence from ambiguous to clear, changing the meaning
(semantics) of the sentence.
83
According to traditional grammar, sentences consist of words, but not every string of
words constitutes a sentence as we can see in the following example: Lion cage this less in
dangerous is the. A possible analysis is that if we look at this example we know the meaning
of the individual words, but the sequence as a whole does not make sense, so we cannot
consider this structure a sentence. Thus, we can affirm that if a sequence of words is to
constitute a sentence, it must be meaningful, for instance: The lion is less dangerous in this
cage.
The network of relations between the words of a sentence is called its structure. There
are many different aspects that influence the structure of a sentence. A very important one is
word order. The different order of the words in a sentence can bring a difference in its
meaning, as in the following example: Did he say who he was?= Who did he say he was?
But a difference in word order does not always imply a difference in meaning. Sometimes it
simply entails a difference in emphasis: John ran away //A way ran John.
In relation to the words, the structure of the sentence also depends on the individual
meaning of the words or word groups making up the sentence; in the following example the
difference in structure is not due to word order but to the relationship between the words:
Peter was waiting for seven friends. //Peter was waiting for seven minutes.
Then this kind of Grammar deals with the concept of Ambiguous sentences and explains that
the structure of sentences is only sometimes unambiguously derivable from overt marks like
word order, lexical items, etc. Sometimes we come across sentences to which more than one
structure can be assigned, having, therefore, more than one meaning. This type of sentence
receives the name of Ambiguous Sentence, as in the following examples: George likes Susan
more than Joan // Visiting relatives can be tedious.
Only through the context in which these sentences may appear can we know which of
the two possible meanings is intended. Transformational Grammar deals with the idea that a
sentence has a syntactic structure, and it follows this term in order to develop its theory. The
first important point deals with the idea that the evidence for claiming that sentences have a
syntactic structure in language comes from the native speaker‘s intuition about the structure
of sentences in his language. These structural intuitions that native speakers have about the
Syntax of their languages are two types:
1. The constituents: intuitions about how sound sequences in sentences are structured
into larger structural units.
84
[All the words and phrases that make up a sentence are said to be constituents of that
sentence. Every sentence (and every phrase and clause) has constituents. That is to say, every
sentence is made up of parts of other things that work together to make the sentence
meaningful.]
2. Categories: intuitions about whether structural units belong to the same category or not.
So, the following example is going to illustrate this fact:
To analyze the concept of a sentence we can do the following analysis: words are
grouped into lower constituents. For example ―incredibly‖ modifies ―intelligent‚ so the
sequence [incredibly intelligent] is a phrasal constituent of the sentence. Also, following the
analysis, ‗this‖ modifies ―pupil‖, so the sequence [that pupil] forms a single structural unit, a
constituent of the sentence. The same happens in the sequence [that teacher]. But
furthermore, also the sequence [to that teacher] is another constituent. To the
transformational grammar, the phrases [incredibly intelligent] and [to that teacher] both
modify ―then the whole sequence [seem incredibly intelligent to that teacher] is also a
constituent. Thus, all this information can be represented as we see before in diagrammatic
form, that is a tree diagram. Each point in the tree is called a node, and each node represents
a constituent. But, however, since nodes are predictable, later they were suppressed in
subsequent tree diagrams. But a tree diagram does not provide any representation of our
intuitions about which constituents are constituents of the same type. The traditional way of
describing the similarities and differences between constituents is to say that they belong to
categories of various types. And the same happens with the phrases. Finally, to this type of
grammar, the whole sequence [that pupil must seem incredibly intelligent to that teacher] is a
special type of constituent traditionally termed a clause or sentence.
Every sentence can be analyzed at four distinct form levels: the word level, the phrase
level, the clause level, and the sentence level. And this is called the rank scale. Later, after
the explanation of the constituents of a sentence, we will see the different levels and how
they can be analyzed following the same example. Thus, a diagram as provides a visual
presentation of the categorical constituent structure of the sentence. It shows us how a
sentence is structured out of its constituent phrases, and how each of the phrases is structured
out of its component words, and also provides a visual presentation of the phrase structure of
a sentence. The type of labeled tree- diagram used here is referred to as a Phrase-marker (P-
85
marker) because it marks the hierarchical grouping of words into phrases, and phrases into
sentences.
Another method of visual display used in the linguistic literature is to make use of
labeled bracketing. Within this system, we could represent the categorical status of the words
in the structure mentioned before as in the following example:
[D This] [N pupil] [M must] [V seem] [Adv incredibly] [A intelligent] [P to] [D that] [N
teacher]
We could use this system of labeled bracketing to represent the fact that [this pupil]
and [that teacher] are noun phrases, and [to that teacher] is a prepositional phrase. That
[incredibly intelligent] is an adjective phrase, that [seem incredibly intelligent to that teacher]
is a verb phrase, and that [this pupil must seem incredibly intelligent to that teacher] is an
―S‖ = clause. As follows:
[S [NP [D this] [N pupil]] [M must] [VP [V seem] [AP [ADV incredibly][A intelligent]] [PP
[P to][NP [D that] [N teacher] ] ] ] ]
Then the two diagrams represented here contain the same information. Many linguists
prefer tree diagrams as a form of visual representation of syntactic structure because they are
easier to read, and the reason for that is that the information they contain is less condensed.
Thus, diagrams like these provide a virtually complete representation of the syntactic
structure of the sentence. Also, we can find partial tree diagrams or partially labeled
bracketing: for instance, if we take the sentence mentioned before, we can see that it contains
three major constituents: [NP+VP+PP]
In a nutshell, both syntax and semantics are key parts of the philosophy of language
but have unique linguistic meanings. To be more precise, syntax refers to grammar, while
semantics refers to meaning. Syntax is the set of rules needed to ensure a sentence is
grammatically correct; semantics is how one‘s lexicon, grammatical structure, tone, and
other elements of a sentence merge to communicate its meaning. Therefore, it can be said
that syntax helps us put linguistic meanings into sentences.
We have learnt that semantics deals with meaning in language. Just like every other
disciplines, there are theories to explain in detail the nature of meaning in a principled way.
We are well aware of the fact that language as a system is organised along the structures of
sound, words, sentences and meanings. Each of these levels can be studied in some details,
following specified formulations or theories. For the purpose of a detailed study of
semantics, the theories we shall explore, are expected to explain the nature of word and
sentence meaning, among several other things.
Semantic theories explain the nature of meaning by utilizing a finite set of rules to
explain a variety of semantic phenomena. Any theory of semantics should provide
statements that explain meaning relationship – such as ambiguity, anomaly, contradiction,
tautology, paraphrase, entailment, synonymy, hyponymy. This means that such a theory
should be able to explain the inherent meaning characteristics of words and sentences.
Any reliable theory of semantics should relate meaning to syntax, highlighting the
relationships between them. This means that the rules of sentence construction and those of
word meaning should relate to explain in full the meanings of the sentence.
1.1 The Ideational Theory of Meaning (Pertaining to the formation of ideas or thoughts of
objects not immediately present to the senses)
This theory holds the view that linguistic meaning is mental: words are used to encode
and convey thoughts, or ideas. Successful communication requires that the hearer correctly
decode the speaker‘s words into their associated ideas. So construed, the meaning of an
87
expression, according to Locke, is the idea associated with it in the mind of anyone who
knows and understands that expression.
This theory was developed by the British empiricist philosopher, John Locke. The
theory explains that the meaning attached to words can be separated from the word
themselves. This means that meaning originates in the mind in the form of ideas. Words are
just sensible signs for the convenience of communication. Language is therefore, a
mechanism for expressing thoughts and thought is viewed as a succession of conscious ideas.
The ideational theory is mentalistic. Thus the meaning of a word is the mental image or
idea of the word or the expression generated in the mind of the speaker or hearer.
The theory may not be able to account for synonymous expressions. It may also be
difficult to use the theory to explain the mental image conjured by sentences. Indeed,
sentences derive their meaning more from the word order.
Reference is an apparent relation between a word and the world. Russell, following the
19th-century British philosopher John Stuart Mill, pursued the intuition that linguistic
expressions are signs of something other than themselves. He suggested that the meaning of
an expression is whatever that expression applies to, thus removing meaning from the minds
of its users and placing it squarely in the world. According to a referential semantics, all that
one learns when one learns the meaning of tomato is that it applies to tomatoes and to
nothing else. One advantage of a referential semantics is that it respects compositionality: the
meaning of red tomato is a function of the meanings of red and tomato, because red tomato
will apply to anything that is both red and a tomato.
But what about expressions that apparently refers to nothing at all, such as unicorn? A
referential semantics would appear to be committed to the view that expressions such as
unicorn, Santa Claus, and Sherlock Holmes are meaningless. Another problem is that two
expressions may have the same referent without having the same meaning. The morning star
and the evening star, for example, refer to the same object, the planet Venus, but they are not
synonymous. As Frege noted, it is possible to believe that the morning star and the evening
star are not identical without being irrational (indeed, the identity of the morning star and the
evening star was a scientific discovery).
This theory is associated with Ogden and Richards (1922). According to the
Referential theory, the meaning of a word is the object it refers to in the external world.
That actual object is the referent. The connection between the words or expressions and
their referents is through the process of thought. The words or expressions are just
symbols.
89
One major criticism of this theory is that there are many words without physical
objects they refer to. Such words are intelligent, ugly, rich, poor etc. Which do not have the
concrete qualities of nouns may not have referents. Again, polysemous words (i.e. words
with more than one meaning) may have the additional problem of having more than one
referent. Items that belong to groups may not have physical objects that are identical. The
referential theory may not have a way to explain the meaning of words in the categories of
adjectives, adverbs, prepositions and conjunctions.
The German scholar, Wittgenstein (1953), developed this theory. It has been
elaborated upon by J. Firth and M.A Halliday. The usage theory is also referred to as the
contextual or operational theory of meaning. According to the theory, the meaning of a word
or an expression is determined by the context of its use. It is the effect created by a linguistic
unit within a given context that expresses its full meaning.
According to this theory, meaning is classified into two broad categories: Contextual
Meaning and Formal Meaning.
Contextual meaning is further divided into thesis, immediate situation and wider
situation. In Formal meaning the relationship between a linguistic item, pattern or term form
a system and other linguistic item, patterns or terms from system belonging to the same level
of language.
Formal meaning can be understood by collocating and contrasting a lexical item with
other lexical items. The lexical item cat, for example, has the potentiality for collocating
with mew, purr, lap, milk, fur, tail, etc. It also contrasts with dog, mouse, kitten, etc. Thus,
the complete description of the formal meaning of a lexical item would involve the statement
of all the items with which it collocates and contrasts. Such items which fall into a context or
set of contexts are referred to as an association field.
90
Basic to this theory is the concept that each word in a language is surrounded by a
network of associations that connect it with other terms.
The field theory visualizes the vocabulary as a mosaic on a gigantic scale, which is
built up of fields and higher units in the same way as fields are built up by words. The
associative field of a word is formed by an intricate network of associations, some based on
similarity, others on continuity, some arising between senses, others between names, others
again between both. The field is by definition open, and some of the associations are bound
to be subjective though the more central ones will be largely the same for most speakers.
Attempts have been made to identify some of these central associations by psychological
experiments, but they can also be established by purely linguistic methods. The identification
of these associations by linguistic methods is done by collecting the most obvious synonyms
and antonyms of a word, as well as terms similar in sound or in sense, and those which enter
into the same habitual associations. Many of these associations are embodied in figurative
language: metaphors, similes, proverbs, idioms, and the link. The number of associations
centered in one word will of course be extremely variable and for some very common terms
it may be very high.
Conclusion
To sum up, the main principles of various well–known theories of meaning, namely
the referential theory to meaning, the non–referential theory to meaning, ideational theory of
meaning, etc. have been discussed. None of them is complete; each of them has strengths and
weaknesses. However, these theories may help formulate some background about meanings.
Lecture 16 Pragmatics
Objectives
i. Pragmatics
ii. Reference
iii. Deixis
91
Pragmatics is concerned with the range of choices and constraints available to users
based on the context. In pragmatics, emphasis is on the pairing of sentences and their
appropriate contexts. The choices made in language have been found to affect the listeners
and their responses. It is possible to observe norms of politeness, appropriateness, formality
and respect in the way language is used. It is believed that pragmatics determines the
appropriate interpretation of sentences since there could be differences between literal and
implied meanings. Differences in meaning are at the instance of the situation, the shared
background and the linguistics context of the expression.
In terms of objectives, pragmatics deals with the totality of the processes through
which utterances convey meaning hearing in mind the context and how participants respond
to the meanings intended. It will therefore be easy to see that the common tie between
pragmatics and semantics is language. However, while semantics is concerned with
language meaning, pragmatics is concerned with language use. This will necessarily mean
that the contextual approach to meaning will be very relevant to pragmatics. Since the full
manifestation of language from the point of use deals on the implied processes, we shall
explore the nature of Implicature.
The linguistic forms or the linguistic means used to identify or designate entities are
called referring expressions, which can be proper nouns (Edison, Bandung), noun phrases
that are definite (the woman, the singer), or indefinite (a man, an island), and pronouns (he,
her, it, them). Noun phrases, proper nouns are called primary referring expressions, while
pronouns are termed secondary referring expressions (Kreidle,1998). In addition, Kreidler
(1998:130) states that referring expression is "a piece of language that is used in an utterance
and is linked to something outside language, some living or dead or imaginary entity or
concept or group of entities or concepts."
Kreidler (1998) further argues that the difference between referent and referring
expression lies in the fact that there is no natural connection between referring expression
and referent. There is no privileged one-to-one relationship between the expression Bill
Clinton and the Bill Clinton, who was the president of the USA. Furthermore, the existence
of a referring expression does not guarantee the existence of a referent in the physical-social
93
world that we inhabit. We can create expressions with referents such as the dragon in my
house, the emperor of Indonesia without necessarily proving the existence of their physical
referent.
Types of Referents
A referent has a unique entity or unique sets of entities if its referring expression has
fixed reference. Thus entities like the Rocky Mountains, the Louvre, the Pacific Ocean,
Germany designate unique entities that can be found only in certain places, and knowledge
of it is part of one's general knowledge. On the other hand, a referent may have a non-unique
entity if its referring expression has variable reference. Entities such as that woman, my
brother, a mountain, are not unique since they are different every time they are used, and
knowledge of it is a matter of specific knowledge. It is the physical and linguistic contexts
that help the speakers to identify those entities.
Concrete referents are denoted by concrete or tangible objects such as book, lamp,
tree, brick, whereas the abstract ones are designated by abstract or intangible entities such as
beauty, democracy, knowledge, philosophy. It is interesting to note that lexemes with
different kinds of denotation generally occur in different kinds of utterances and may have
different effects on other lexemes. Thus the lexeme key has a concrete referent in the phrase
the key to the front door, bearing literal meaning, and an abstract one in the key to success,
bearing figurative meaning.
It is the property of noun phrase that merits the notion countable and non-countable,
both of which can be concrete and abstract. Concrete countable expressions are those that are
separate from one another, and those that can ordinarily be counted one by one. This
includes such entities as pencil, bags, chairs, and watches. Abstract countable nouns include
94
such entities as problem, experience, and suggestion. Concrete non-countable phrases have
three kinds of reference: those that refer to continuous substances (ketchup, sauce, milk, ink),
those that name substances consisting particles not worth counting (rice, sand, sugar), and
those that refer to collections (furniture, jewelry, luggage).The feature that distinguishes
countable noun phrases from non-countable ones is that the former recognize the division
between singular and plural forms while the latter do not. Thus we can say an apple, a hat,
an umbrella, the overt specifier being present preceding the singular nouns, and some apples,
some hats, some umbrella, some apple sauce, some mud, some ink, with a zero specifier
preceding both plural countable and non-countable.
In a language such as English the names of the animals that are countable by nature
become uncountable when referring to food. An instance of this is the lexemes (a)lamb, (a)
chicken, and (a) turkey. Finally, some nouns phrases may have dual class membership in that
it can be countable and noun-countable, depending upon the items it designates. Such entities
as (a) paper, (a) iron, (a) glass, (a) coffee, etc. can be countable and non-countable.
Types of Reference
The discussion of reference has become a central concern in semantics, and the
classification of different types of the ways of referring is relatively uncontroversial and
remains undisputed among semanticists. Lyons (1977), Hofmann (1993), Kreidler (1998),
and Cruse (2000) agree on the following classification of reference types:
The meaning of the notion generic (not really synonymous with general) can be
understood by observing the following:
Each of these sentences may be used to assert a generic proposition that is a proposition
which says something, not about this or that group of cat or about any particular individual
cat, but about the class of cats as such. In other words, the entity cat in the above sentence is
95
reference to a class of referents (Cruse, 2000:311). The fact that the cat in the sentences
above has generic meaning can be demonstrated by proposing the question "which cat (s)?"
Obviously none of the above sentences are the answer of such as question because the
question is not germane. Sentence (1), (2), and (3) are in contrast with sentences (4) and (5)
below.
In that the latter do not have generic reference. They do not necessarily refer to the whole
class of cats. Although they are not the answers of the question "which cat (s)?" either, such
a question is germane in this context. Lyons (1977) and Cruse (2000) identify two sorts of
proposition involving generic reference as argument: either something is predicated of the
whole class referred to, or something is predicated of each member of the class. The former
has collective reference and the latter distributive reference. Sentence (1) has collective
reference, and sentence (2) exemplifies distributive reference.
Kreidler (1998:143) argues that referring expression is definite if the referent from the
physical-social context is identifiable for both speaker and hearer. The directive put the book
on the table contains definite referring expression the book and the table.
Moreover, if the speaker assumes that the addressee can make the necessary
implicature to relate a new reference to a previous one, this is also the case of referring
expression. The utterance I bought a new house in a quiet neighborhood. The kitchen is very
big has a definite expression the kitchen. We can also say that a referent is definite is the
referring expression is fixed and therefore presumably part of the addressee's general
knowledge, like Mount Everest. Finally, referring expression is definite if the referent has a
unique or nearly unique position in the more limited world of the speaker and addressee. For
example, the definite referring expression of this type can be seen in the interrogative have
you received the reports from the doctor?
The central idea of the indefinite referring expression is that the identity of referent is
not germane to the message, and that the hearer has to make a choice from the extension of
96
the noun (Krediler, 1998; Cruse, 2000). It must be emphasized here that indefiniteness is not
restricted to the indefinite article only. The following sentences also contain indefinite
expressions (Cruse, 2000:308):
(10) Every evening at six o'clock a heron flies over the chalet.
The indefinite noun phrase a heron in this sentence can, under one interpretation, be
understood to refer to a specific referent. It refers to a particular heron that the speaker has in
mind. We can further support the specificity of the reference by providing the same context
as follow:
The pronoun It in (11) is co-referential with a heron in (10). Again let us observe the
sentence below:
The referent answer in (12) can be understood to refer to a non-specific reference since
both speaker and hearer are not really sure about the referent being spoken. It should be
admitted, however, that very often we cannot exactly tell whether an indefinite noun phrase
is being used with specific reference or not as it is dependent very much upon how the
speaker/hearer interprets it. Hence, due to the alleged ambiguity of the indefinite noun phrase
in the sentence below, it can be construed as being used specifically or non-specifically:
97
(13) I want to marry a girl with blue eyes.
Under one interpretation, the indefinite noun phrase is used specifically if it implies
the existence of some individual who satisfies the description of having blue eyes, and thus
can be equated to having the same sense as the definite noun phrase the girl with the blue
eyes in the same context. On the other hand, it is used non-specifically provided that no
presupposition or implication exists.
Anaphora
Danny and hamburger are two nouns with exophoric reference, while he and it have
endophoric reference: they refer to Danny and hamburger in the context, and not directly to
real-world entity. Traditionally they are called pronouns. Endophoric reference can be
classified into anaphora and cataphora depending on the position of the antecedent. Observe
the short passage below:
(15) In the film, a man and a woman were trying to wash a cat. The man was holding the cat
while the woman poured water on it. He said something to her and they started laughing.
The pronouns (it, he, her, and they) in the passage are subsequent reference to already
mentioned referents, which are known as anaphoric reference or anaphora. Technically
speaking, the subsequent reference is called anaphor and the initial or already introduced
reference is known as antecedents. Quirk et. al. (1985) states that anaphoric reference is used
where the uniqueness of reference of some phrase the X is supplied by information given
earlier in the discourse. They further distinguish two kinds of anaphora: direct and indirect.
In direct anaphora, the referents have already occurred in the text, and thus can be identified
98
directly, whereas in indirect anaphora the hearer identifies the referents indirectly from his
knowledge by inferring what has been mentioned. Consider the following sentences:
(16) John bought a TV and tape recorder, but he returned the tape recorder.
(17) John bought a car, but when he drove itone of the wheels came off.
Sentence (16) exemplifies the use of direct anaphora where the referent the tape
recorder can be identified directly, while sentence (17) contains the indirect anaphora where
the noun car has been substituted by anaphor it.
the painting
Cataphora
The notion cataphora is less common in use than that of anaphora. Cataphora is the
relation between an anaphoric expression and an antecedent that comes later (Matthews
1997:48). Thus cataphora refers to entity that is mentioned latter in the discourse. Consider
this sentence:
(20) I turned to the corner and almost stepped on it. There was a large snake in the middle of
the path.
The pronoun it (the cataphor) in the sentence can be interpreted as referring forward to a
noun phrase
a large snake, (the antecedent) and is said to have cataphoric reference. Cataphora is also
known as anticipatory anaphora or backward anaphora.
99
Deixis and its types
The notion deixis has become one of the important topics that merits our attention.
Deixis is a semantics notion, which is originally derived from a Greek word meaning
pointing or indicating via language. Any linguistic form used to accomplish this pointing is
called a deictic expression. The adjective deictic (deikticos) has the sense of demonstrative.
When we notice a strange object and ask, "What's that?" we are using a deictic expression
(that) to indicate something in the immediate context. Deictic expressions are also sometimes
called indexical. The notion of what deixis is relatively uncontroversial among the linguists.
Lyons (1977:637) offers the following definition of deixis: "the location and identification of
persons, objects, events, processes and activities being talked about, or referred to, in relation
to the spatiotemporal context created and sustained by the act of utterance and the
participation in it, typically of a single speaker and at least one addressee." Similarly, Yule
(1996:9) argues that deixis is a form of referring that is tied to the speaker's context, with the
most basic distinction between deictic expressions being "near speaker" versus "away from
the speaker." If the referents being referred to are near the speaker, the proximal terms such
as this, here, now are used. By contrast, the distal terms such as that, there, then are
employed provided that the referents are away from the speaker. Matthews (1997:89) states
that deixis is "the way in which the reference of certain elements in a sentence is determined
in relation to a specific speaker and addressee and a specific time and place of utterance."
From the three definitions given above, it can be inferred that the notion deixis involves the
pointing of certain referents that belong primarily to the category of persons (objects),
speaker-addressee relationship, space, and time, context of utterance. Respectively, this
category is termed person deixis, social deixis, spatial deixis, temporal deixis, and discourse
deixis (Cruse 2000: 319). We shall examine each of these in detail.
Person Deixis
Singular Plural
1stperson
I/me we/us
Social Deixis
In many languages the deictic categories of speaker, addressee, and other(s) are
elaborated with markers or relative social status (addressee with higher status versus
addressee with lower status). Expressions that indicate higher status are described as
honorifics. A widely quoted example to describe the social deixis is the so-called TV
distinction, from the French tu (referring to familiar addressee), and vous (referring to non-
familiar addressee). Other languages that make a distinction between the social status are
German with the distinguishing pronoun du and Sie, and Spanish with tu and Usted. In the
social context the higher, older, and more powerful speaker will tend to use the tu version to
a lower, younger, and less powerful addressee, and be addressed by the vous form in return.
Spatial Deixis
The concept of distance is relevant to spatial deixis, where the relative location of
people and things is being indicated. As Cruse (2000:320) puts it "spatial deixis manifests
itself principally in the form of locative adverbs (here and there) and demonstratives or
determiners (this and that).‖ In English the spatial deictic system is indicated by two terms
101
labeled proximal and distal. Such terms as here and this indicate that the location is relatively
close to the speaker, and hence proximal. Conversely, the terms there and that indicate the
relative distant of the location from the speaker, and hence distal. In considering spatial
deixis, Yule (1996) warns that the location from the speaker's perspective can be fixed
mentally and physically. Speakers temporarily away from their home location will often
continue to use here to mean the (physically distant) home location, as if they were still in
that location. Speakers also seem to be able to project themselves into other locations prior to
being in those locations, as when they say "I'll come later" (movement to addressee's
location). This is sometimes described as deictic projection.
Temporal Deixis
Cruse (2000: 321) asserts that temporal deictic s function to locate points or intervals
on the time axis, using the moment of utterance as a reference point. The time axis can be
divided into three major divisions: before the moment of utterance, at the time of utterance,
and after the time of utterance. The time adverbial that forms a basic concept in temporal
deixis in English includes now and then. Now displays the same capacity for indefinite
extension, which can refer to a precise instant, such as Press the button-now!; or it can
accommodate a wide swathe of time like The solar system is now in a relatively stable phase
(Cruse, 2000:320). However, very often now indicates the time coinciding with the speaker's
utterance; for example, I am reading a novel now (the action done at the moment of the
speaker's utterance).
Then, on the other hand, designate the time period which is distal from the speaker's
utterance. Then is normally interpreted from the context, as the following sentences indicate:
(20) Watching movies at 8.30 tonight? Okay, I'll see you then.
Apart from the time adverbial, there are essentially other types of temporal deixis worth
mentioning here. One type is related to calendric notions that include both clock time as in
[1] and calendar time as in [2].
Other temporal deictic related to calendric system includes such expressions as today,
yesterday, tomorrow, this week, last week, next week, this month, last month, next month,
102
this year, last year, and next year. The last type of temporal deixis in English is related to the
verb tense, as illustrated in the following sentences.
The verb tense in (3) is in simple present and is normally treated as close to (proximal) the
speaker's current situation, whereas in (4) the verb tense is simple past, and is thought as
distant (distal) by the speaker.
Discourse Deixis
(26) Notice is hereby served that if payment is further delayed, appropriate legal action will
be taken.
The deictic expression this in (5) and that in (6) respectively refer to future discourse
element and past discourse element. Similarly, the hereby in (7) points to current discourse.
Finally, the sentence adverb marker in (8) refers to what follows in the future discourse.
Discourse deixis is not, however, to be confused with anaphora, the difference being that the
latter might extract a referent from an extralinguistic entity. Thus the anphor she in sentence
(9) below does not strictly refer to the word Susan itself.
(28) Susan is indeed sexually attractive. She has been admired by many men.
Entailment
Presupposition
103
Implicature
Entailment
Entailment refers to the relationship between two sentences, where the meaning of one
sentence (the entailed sentence) is logically derived or implied by the meaning of another
sentence (the entailing sentence). It indicates that the truth of the entailed sentence can be
inferred from the truth of the entailing sentence. Entailment is a key concept in
understanding the logical and semantic relationships between sentences and plays a crucial
role in various linguistic phenomena.
Here are some key points and examples which may help us to understand the concept of
entailment:
Example:
In this example, if John has a sister, it logically follows that he has a sibling. Therefore, the
truth of the entailing sentence "John has a sister" entails the truth of the entailed sentence
"John has a sibling."
a. Positive Entailment: In positive entailment, the truth of the entailing sentence guarantees
the truth of the entailed sentence.
Example:
104
If Mary owns a dog, it can be concluded that she has a pet. Therefore, the entailing sentence
positively entails the entailed sentence.
Example:
If the car is not blue, it can be inferred that the entailing sentence is true, i.e., the car is red.
Hence, the entailed sentence negatively entails the entailing sentence.
Example:
Presupposition
105
granted. In other words, presuppositions are assumptions that a speaker or writer makes
about their audience's knowledge or background.
Example:
Example:
- The boy who won the game lost three teeth in the process.
- I want to know if you've had a chance to try the new pizza place.
106
Presuppositions can be important to identify and understand, as they can reveal the
underlying beliefs, assumptions, and attitudes of the speaker or writer. They can also have an
impact on how a message is received and interpreted by the audience.
Implicature
Implicature is a term used in linguistics to refer to the meaning that is implied but not
directly stated in a conversation or text. It arises when the speaker intends to communicate a
message that goes beyond the literal meaning of the words used. Instead, they rely on
context, tone, or other non-verbal cues to convey a deeper meaning.
The Gricean Maxims are a set of guidelines for effective communication that were
first introduced by philosopher H.P. Grice in his 1975 book "Logic and Conversation." These
maxims explain how speakers can use implicature to convey meaning to their listeners by
observing certain rules of conversation.
Example:
Example:
107
3. Maxim of Relevance: Speakers should stay on topic and communicate information
that is relevant to the conversation at hand.
Example:
Example:
Implicature is frequently used in literature to create a sense of depth and nuance in the
text. Authors may use it to convey character traits, motivations, or themes without explicitly
stating them.
ii. Jocasta repeatedly tells Oedipus to stop trying to uncover the truth about his origins,
saying "no good comes of such investigation." This implies that Jocasta knows more about
Oedipus' past than she is letting on and is trying to protect him from the devastating truth.
108
iii. When the chorus sings "whoever is the murderer of Laius may he still remain
unknown," this implies that the killer might still be among them and potentially pose a threat
to Oedipus and the citizens of Thebes.
iv. When the messenger says that Polybus, the man Oedipus believed was his father,
has died of natural causes, this implies that Oedipus was not responsible for his death and
therefore not guilty of killing his father.
v. When Oedipus says "I shall not rest until I have cast out the pollution from this
land," this implies that he believes the source of the city's problems lies within himself and
that he must take action to purify the city and himself.
i. When April with its sweet showers has pierced the drought of March, and bathed every
root of every plant with its gentle rain, then people long to go on pilgrimages.
Implicature: Spring brings new life and renewal, leading people to desire spiritual
journeys.
Lecture 18 Reference
109
the noun John and the pronoun him are co-referential, since they both refer to the same
person (John).
Anaphoric Reference
He refers to Muaz.
Anaphoric reference often makes use of the definite article the, because one of the
functions of the definite article is to indicate that something has already been mentioned.
Here‘s another example:
He sat down at the table and took a small box from his pocket. The object felt heavy in his
hands. Inside it was the key to his future.
Both the object and it refer back to a small box in the first sentence.
Cataphoric Reference
110
Here are some examples of cataphoric reference:
Although I phone him every week, Naveed still complains that I don‟t keep in touch often
enough.
The book was there on the table. I‟d never read Moby Dick and I didn‟t intend to do so now.
Exophoric Reference
Exophoric reference occurs when a word or phrase refers to something outside the discourse.
“They„re late again, can you believe it?” “I know! Well, they‟d better get here soon or it„ll
get cold.”
The word “They” refers to some people outside the discourse known to both speakers.
It also refers to something that both speakers know about (perhaps the dinner).
The use of exophoric reference requires some shared knowledge between two speakers, or
between writer and reader(s).
Speech act theory is a fundamental concept in the field of pragmatics, which examines
how language is used in context to accomplish specific communication goals. Developed by
philosophers J.L. Austin and John Searle, speech act theory focuses on the idea that
utterances not only convey information but also perform actions within the social world.
A speech act refers to an utterance or statement that has both meaning and
action. It is an act of communication where the speaker not only conveys information
but also performs a specific function or accomplishes a particular goal through their
111
words (Searle, 1969). For example, when a person says "I apologize," they are not simply
stating that they are sorry but also performing the act of apologizing.
a) Locutionary act: It refers to the actual production of an utterance with a specific meaning
and grammatical structure.
b) Illocutionary act: It represents the intended purpose or force behind the utterance. It
includes various speech acts such as requests, commands, promises, apologies, etc.
c) Perlocutionary act: It involves the effect or impact of the utterance on the listener or the
audience. It focuses on the consequences or intended outcomes of the speech act.
Speech acts can be categorized into several types, based on their intended illocutionary
force or function. Here are some commonly recognized speech acts (Searle, 1969):
a) Assertives: Utterances that express beliefs, facts, or statements that can be judged as true
or false. Example: "The Earth revolves around the Sun."
e) Declarations: Utterances that bring about changes in social reality. Example: "I now
pronounce you husband and wife."
112
Speech act theory is closely related to pragmatic principles that govern language use in
context. Grice's Cooperative Principle and maxims of conversation play a significant role in
speech act analysis (Grice, 1975). These principles include:
b) Maxim of Quality: Speakers should be truthful and provide information that is supported
by evidence.
c) Maxim of Relevance: Speakers should stay on topic and provide relevant information.
d) Maxim of Manner: Speakers should be clear, concise, and avoid ambiguity or obscurity.
To sum up, speech act theory provides a framework for understanding how language
is used to accomplish various communicative goals. It emphasizes that communicative acts
go beyond the transmission of information and involve explicit intentions and actions.
Understanding speech acts is essential for effective communication and for the interpretation
of meaning in social interactions.
A speech act in linguistics and the philosophy of language is an utterance that has
performative function in language and communication. According to Kent Bach, "almost any
speech act is really the performance of several acts at once, distinguished by different aspects
of the speaker's intention: there is the act of saying something, what one does in saying it,
such as requesting or promising, and how one is trying to affect one's audience." The
contemporary use of the term goes back to J. L. Austin's development of performative
utterances and his theory of locutionary, illocutionary, and perlocutionary acts. Speech acts
are commonly taken to include such acts as promising, ordering, greeting, warning, inviting
and congratulating.
113
communication involves linguistic acts. The unit of linguistic communication is not, as has
generally been supposed, the symbol, word, or sentence, or even the token of the symbol,
word, or sentence, but rather the production or issuance of the symbol or word or sentence in
the performance of a speech act." Meaning, then, should be regarded as a species within the
genus intending-to-communicate, since language itself is highly complex, rule-governed
intentional behavior. A theory of language is part of a theory of action. The basic emphasis
of speech act theory is on what an utterer (U) means by his utterance (x) rather than what x
means in a language (L). As H.P. Grice notes, "meaning is a kind of intending," and the
hearer's or reader's recognition that the speaker or writer means something by x is part of the
meaning of x. In contrast to the assumptions of structuralism (a theory that privileges langue,
the system, over parole, the speech act), speech act theory holds that the investigation of
structure always presupposes something about meanings, language use, and extralinguistic
functions.
Austin divides the linguistic act into three components. First, there is the locutionary
act, "the act of 'saying' something." Second, there is the illocutionary act, "the performance
of an act in saying something as opposed to the performance of an act of saying something."
Third, there is the perlocutionary act, for "saying something will often, or even normally,
114
produce certain consequential effects upon the feelings, thoughts, or actions of the audience,
of the speaker, or of other persons." In other words, a locutionary act has meaning; it
produces an understandable utterance. An illocutionary act has force; it is informed with a
certain tone, attitude, feeling, motive, or intention. A perlocutionary act has consequence; it
has an effect upon the addressee. By describing an imminently dangerous situation
(locutionary component) in a tone that is designed to have the force of a warning
(illocutionary component), the addresser may actually frighten the addressee into moving
(perlocutionary component). These three components, then, are not altogether separable, for
as Austin points out, "we must consider the total situation in which the utterance is issued --
the total speech act -- if we are to see the parallel between statements and performative
utterances, and how each can go wrong. Perhaps indeed there is no great distinction between
statements and performative utterances." In contradistinction to structuralism, then, speech
act theory privileges parole over langue, arguing that external context -- the context of
situation -- is more important in the order of explanation than internal context -- the
interrelationships among terms within the system of signs.
The concept of an illocutionary act is central to the concept of a speech act. Although
there are numerous opinions regarding how to define 'illocutionary acts', there are some
kinds of acts which are widely accepted as illocutionary, as for example promising, ordering
someone, and bequeathing.
Following the usage of, for example, John R. Searle, "speech act" is often meant to
refer just to the same thing as the term illocutionary act, which John L. Austin had originally
introduced in How to Do Things with Words (published posthumously in 1962). Searle's
work on speech acts is also commonly understood to refine Austin's conception. However,
some philosophers have pointed out a significant difference between the two conceptions:
whereas Austin emphasized the conventional interpretation of speech acts, Searle
emphasized a psychological interpretation (based on beliefs, intentions, etc.).
Austin (1962) describes the Speech Acts theory as an approach that explains the roles
of utterances in shaping the attitudes of participants in interpersonal communication. Speech
acts reveal the intentions of speakers and the effects the speaker‘s utterances and expressions
have on the hearers. The implication of speech acts is that every utterance has a purpose
which derives from the specific context. It has been observed that language use depends on
such contextual factors as social and physical conditions, attitudes, abilities, beliefs and the
relationship existing between the speaker and the listener.
There may be some confusion regarding types and levels of speech acts. We have
already discussed types of speech acts – representative, declarative, directive, expressive and
commissive. For levels of speech acts, emphasis is on the different stages of interaction
between the speaker and the listener through the use of speech acts. Three distinct levels are
usually observed – locutionary, illocutionary and perlocutionary acts.
Locutionary Acts – These are observed as the processes of producing grammatical and
meaningful utterances which can be recognised by the hearer.
Illocutionary Acts – Illocutionary acts are the force behind the utterances. Indeed, the
speaker performs these acts to achieve the purpose of communication as a statement, a
question, a command, an invitation, a threat, a request, an apology etc. It is possible, for
instance, to use a sentence that has the structure of a statement for the purpose of a warning.
For example:
(i) You will lose all your deposits – (from a financial adviser to a client)
This sentence may be a warning or a piece of advice. Therefore, it is possible to use identical
utterance types for different tokens based on the intentions of the speaker and the context.
116
Perculationary Acts – These are the effects of the speaker‘s utterance on the behaviour
of the hearer. They are the acts performed by the hearer as a result of the effect of the
speaker‘s utterances. It is assumed, for instance, that the hearer will respond to a question of
the speaker in a specific way, or behave in accordance with the demands of the context. It
should be noted that the illocutionary force is the intended effect of an utterance on the
hearer from the point of view of the speaker. The perlocutionary effect is the actual effect of
the speaker‘s utterance on the action, behaviour, attitude or belief of the hearer.
Austin himself admits that these three components of utterances are not altogether
separable.―We must consider the total situation in which the utterance is issued- the total
speech act – if we are to see the parallel between statements and performative utterance, and
how each can go wrong. Perhaps indeed there is no great distinction between statements and
performative utterances.‖ (Austin 1962).
There are different types of speech acts, the most common being the following:
Representative Acts: These acts describe events, processes and states. Usually, the speaker is
committed to the truth of the assertion, claim, report, suggestion, prediction, description,
hypothesis or conclusion.
Declarative Acts: These are acts that immediately change the state of affairs to which they
apply. These acts are used in arresting, christening, marriage, sentencing, acquittal etc.
Consider the following:
117
(29) I discharge and acquit the accused
Directive Acts: In directive acts, the addressee is instructed to carry out some instruction by
responding verbally to an utterance or by performing some physical actions. The acts can be
questions, commands, requests, pleas or invitation. e.g.
Expressive Acts: Expressive acts show the psychological states – feelings and attitudes
towards some events and affairs. These usually occur in greetings, scolding, condoling,
appreciating, thanking, congratulating, apologising, etc. e.g.
Commissive Acts: In Commissive Acts, the speaker is committed to some future action as in
challenging, betting, promising, offering, threatening, vowing, warning, etc. e.g.
It should be noted that commissive acts carry specific performative verbs – promise,
swear,
Performative verbs fall fairly naturally under a small number of headings. It is useful
to group them in this way, as it enables us to gain a picture of the range of functions that
these verbs perform. Searle (1975) has set up the following classification of illocutionary
speech acts:
118
Assertives: Assertives commit the speaker to the truth of the expressed proposition:
Directives: Directives have the intention of eliciting some sort of action on the part of the
hearer: order, command, request, beg, beseech, advise (to), warn (to), recommend, ask, ask
(to)
Commissives: Commissive commit the speaker to some future action: promise, vow, offer,
undertake, contract, threaten
Declaratives: Declaratives are said to bring about a change in reality: that is to say, the world
is in some way no longer the same after they have been said. In an obvious sense this is true
of all the performative verbs: after someone has congratulated someone, for instance, a new
world comes into being in which that congratulation has taken place. The specialty about
declaratives is that they cause a change in the world over and above the fact that they have
been carried out. If someone says, I resign, then thereafter they no longer hold the post they
originally held, with all that that entails. resign, dismiss, divorce (in Islam), christen, name,
open (e.g. an exhibition), excommunicate, sentence (in court), consecrate, bid (at auction),
declare (at cricket)
There is a finite number of explicit performative verbs in English (several hundred), but
there is no reason to believe that there is a theoretically finite set of possible speech acts.
Implicatures
119
altered."Implicature" is an alternative to "implication," which has additional meanings in
logic and informal language.
Implicture, a term coined by H.P. Grice refers to what is suggested in an utterance and
which may not have been expressed. The speaker deliberately breaks the rules of a
conversational maxim to convey additional meaning. For instance, the following could be a
possible question and respond respectively:
The answer implies, among other things that Betty was not telling the whole story. It is
expected of people in communication to obey certain co-operative principles. These
principles have been presented as maxims‘s of quantity, quality, relation and manner.
Maxim of quality
One could argue that the second sub-maxim entails the firs: thee will obviously not be
adequate evidence for a false statement. We can paraphrase this maxim as Do not make
unsupported statements (Cruse, 2000: 355).
Maxim of Quantity
Maxim of quantity is concerned with the amount of information (taken in its broader sense)
an utterance conveys.
Maxim of relation
120
The maxim is very simple: Be relevant. The point of this maxim is not sufficient for a
statement to be true for it to contribute an acceptable conversational contribution. For
example
B: ?I am breathing.
Notice that this maxim is implicated in the Maxim of quantity, which could easily be
reformulated as: [Make] the strongest statement that can be relevantly made.
Maxim of manner
(iv) Be orderly.
It is generally regarded as being less important that the others. There are also conventional
implicatures used for communicating non-truth-conditional meaning for specific linguistic
expressions. It is largely self-explanatory.
Conversational implicature
121
If the speaker is assumed to be following the cooperative principle, in spite of flouting the
Maxim of Relevance, then the utterance must have an additional nonliteral meaning, such as:
"The content of the lecturer's speech was confusing."
2. The speaker‘s desire to fulfill two conflicting maxims results in his or her flouting one
maxim to invoke the other. For instance, a speaker responds to the question "Where is
John?" with the following utterance:
In this case, the Maxim of Quantity and the Maxim of Quality are in conflict. A cooperative
speaker does not want to be ambiguous but also does not want to give false information by
giving a specific answer in spite of his uncertainty. By flouting the Maxim of Quantity, the
speaker invokes the Maxim of Quality, leading to the implicature that the speaker does not
have the evidence to give a specific location where he believes John is.
3. The speaker invokes a maxim as a basis for interpreting the utterance. In the following
exchange:
There‘s a gas station around the corner. The second speaker invokes the Maxim of
Relevance, resulting in the implicature that ―the gas station is open and one can probably get
gas there‖.
Scalar implicature
This sentence implies "I did not eat all of the pie." While the statement "I ate some pie" is
still true if the entire pie was eaten, the conventional meaning of the word "some" and the
implicature generated by the statement is "not all".
Conventional implicature
122
Conventional implicature is independent of the cooperative principle and its four
maxims. A statement always carries its conventional implicature: Donovan is poor but
happy.
This sentence implies poverty and happiness are not compatible but in spite of this Donovan
is still happy. The conventional interpretation of the word "but" will always create the
implicature of a sense of contrast. So Donovan is poor but happy will always necessarily
imply "Surprisingly Donovan is happy in spite of being poor".
Implicature vs entailment
This can be contrasted with cases of entailment. The statement "the President was
assassinated", for example, not only suggests that "the President is dead" is true, but requires
this to be so. The first sentence could not be true if the second were not true; if the President
were not dead, then whatever it is that happened to him would not have counted as a
(successful) assassination. Similarly, unlike implicatures, entailments cannot be cancelled;
there is no qualification that one could add to "the president was assassinated" which would
cause it to cease entailing "the president is dead" while also preserving the meaning of the
first sentence.
It is always common to hear people argue over what is meant, and what is implied. This
means that there could be differences between what a speaker says and how the listener
interprets it. However, success in communication depends on how well the meaning intended
by the speaker and the implicature of the listener converge. This is usually possible when
participants in communication obey principles of conversational implicature.
SUMMARY
Here in this lecture, we have discussed about speech acts. We have learned about
Austin's speech act theory and Searle's classification of speech acts. Lastly, we have
discussed about implicature. We have learned about Grie's conversational maxims and
conversational implicatures.
Glossary of Semantics
Abstract/ Concrete nouns: An abstract noun denotes one or more entities that do not have
physical existence: idea, problem; a concrete noun denotes one or more physical entities e.g.
123
Chair, food, etc.
Accent The heaviest stress on one syllable in a phrase or sentence, giving the word in which
the syllable occurs greatest emphasis.
Accomplishment verb: A verb that takes an object and denotes a change in the status or
condition of what that object refers to: I broke the window.
Achievement verb A verb that indicates a change in the status or condition of the referent of
the subject: We moved away.
Acronym A word made from the initial letters of the words of a phrase: North Atlantic
Treaty Organization ® NATO.
Action noun An abstract noun, often derived from a verb, that expresses something that
somebody does: discovery, swimming.
Active-subjective/passive-objective adjectives: An active-subjective adjective is derived
from a verb and describes what its subject does: She is very attractive; a passive-objective
adjective is derived from a verb and describes what may be true of the object of such a verb:
breakable.
Active Voice see Voice
Activity verb: A verb that expresses action without expressing an end to the action: They
ran.
Actor role:
Addition The process of creating words by putting meaningful elements together: mean-ing-
ful.
Adjective A word that expresses some attribute of a noun and is modified by very, more and
other qualifiers: a very nice day.
Adjective phrase: An adjective along with any modifiers it may have: very nice; five feet
tall.
Affected noun: A noun derived from a verb which names an entity that receives the action
of the verb: advisee.
Affected role, Affecting role
Affirmative see polarity
Affix A meaningful form that is attached to another form; it may be a prefix as un- in unkind
or a suffix like -ness in kindness.
124
Agent noun: A noun, usually derived from a verb, which names a person who performs the
action of the verb: painter, cook.
Agent role See Thematic Role
Ambiguity The condition whereby any linguistic form has two or more interpretations:
Club=a heavy stick; a social group.
Animate Said of a word, especially a noun that denotes some living thing: dog, boy, an
inanimate noun denotes some non-living thing(s): stone, happiness.
Anomalous sentence: A meaningless sequence of words which deviates from the rules for
sentence formation.
Antonym: A word that is opposite in meaning to another word; good and bad are antonyms.
Arbitrariness: The characteristic of language such that there is no natural relation between a
word, for example cat, and what it stands for.
Aspect: The expression of some temporal characteristic of a predicate; includes ingressive,
durative, egressive, prospective, and retrospective.
Aspectual verb: A verb such as start or continue which tells the aspect of the main verb that
follows.
Attitudinal predicate: A verb or adjective that expresses the feelings of the subject: I hate
this music; I‟m fond of swimming.
Auxiliary verb: A verb used with a lexical verb to make grammatical modifications, as in
are working, have seen, will go.
Binary antonym:s Two lexemes such that, if used as predicate for the same subject, only
one can be true: dead, alive.
Blend: The result of two clipped forms put together to make a compound: smog=smoke+fog.
Causative verb: A verb that expresses an action which results in the status or activity of
some entity: insert X in Y=cause X to be in Y.
Characteristic adjective: An adjective derived from a noun and which expresses the quality
of that noun: gold ® golden.
Characterized noun: A noun derived from an adjective and which expresses an entity of
whom the adjective can be predicated: young ® youngster.
Clause: A construction of words that expresses a proposition but forms part of a sentence
rather than being a sentence in itself: She told us she will wait.
125
Clipping: A process of word formation in which a new word is made by shortening an
existing word: laboratory ® lab.
Co-hyponyms: Two or more lexemes that have the same superordinate: collie, dachshund
and poodle (among others) are co-hyponyms.
Collective noun: A noun that refers to a group of entities; army, furniture, luggage.
Collocation: Words occurring together in a phrase or sentence.
Command: A type of sentence in which someone is told to do or not do something: Wait.
Don‟t go.
Commissive predicate: A verb that expresses the commitment of the subject to the
performance or non-performance of an action: I pledge to carry out all orders given to me.
Common noun: A noun that refers to one or more of a class of objects or concepts: cat,
idea. Cf. proper noun.
Complement: Any form that follows a predicate and completes its meaning: I made a
mistake; She looks nice; They‟re afraid of the dark.
Compound: A word made of two or more independent words: armchair.
Compound verb (as used here) A combination of verb+particle or verb+preposition, which
acts as a single semantic unit: stand up, listen to.
Concrete noun see abstract/concrete nouns
Conjunction A word that connects two linguistic expressions: John and Mary, now or at
five o‟clock.
Connotation: The personal associations produced by words; cf. denotation.
Containing adjective: An adjective derived from a noun and which expresses the presence
of some quantity of what is expressed by the noun: color® colorful.
Context: The linguistic environment of a form in a sentence; the social, spatial, temporal
situation in which a form is produced.
Contradiction: The relation between two propositions such that if one is true, the other must
be false: of the two propositions represented by John is here and John is not here, each is the
contradiction of the other.
Converse antonyms: Two lexemes so related that either one presupposes the
other: If A gives X to B, B receives X from A.
Conversion: A type of word formation in which, without change, a word of one class
becomes also a word of another class: hammer is both noun and verb.
126
Co-referents: Two expressions that denote the same entity.
Countable noun: A noun that has singular and plural forms and which denotes separable
entities: child(ren), house(s). See non-countable noun.
Counterfactive predicate: A verb that, whether affirmative or negative, communicates
that the following predication is untrue: pretend.
Creativity: The characteristic of language which makes it possible for us to produce and
understand utterances we have never heard or produced before.
Declarative sentence see statement
Definite: Said of a noun phrase that refers to an entity or group of entities whose identity is
presumably known to the addressee.
Deletion: The omission of some language element.
Demonstrative: Applied to forms that have the function of identifying by proximity to the
speaker: this, that.
Denotation: The objective relationship between a linguistic form and its referent.
Derivation: Any process whereby one word is formed from another: writer from write.
Determiner A word that occurs before a noun to express number, quantity, or (in)
definiteness: a, the, some, all.
Directive: An utterance intended to get the addressee(s) to do or not do something:
Wait, I wish you‟d wait.
Directive predicate: A predicate that can occur in an overt directive utterance: I ask you to
wait.
Discourse: A continuous stretch of spoken or written language, consisting of at least one
sentence and usually more than one.
Displacement: The ability of language to refer to contexts which differ from the time and
place of an utterance.
Distribution The total set of linguistic contexts in which a lexeme can occur.
Durative aspect: The expression of continuance of an action or permanence of a status: He
kept running; They stayed at home.
Dynamic verb: A type of verb that expresses activity or change of state: They‟re moving.
Cf. stative verb.
Effect noun: A noun derived from a verb and which expresses the product or outcome of the
action expressed by the verb: song ¬ sing.
127
Ellipsis: The omission of part of a sentence, where the missing part is understood from
context: Where are you going? Out.
Embedding: Inserting one sentence into another sentence: I believe you‟re right.
Enabling predicate: A verb or adjective which tells that the following predicate is made
possible: We allowed the car to pass.
Environment: The parts of an utterance that are adjacent to a lexeme; in The dog is barking
the environment of bark is The dog is ____ing.
Euphemism: An expression used in place of one considered unpleasant: pass away instead
of die.
Extension: The class of entities which a lexeme denotes; the extension of Albert Einstein is
a single individual, while the extension of scientist is a large number of individuals.
Extra-linguistic: Said of anything outside of language to which language can refer.
Focus: Special attention to one element in a sentence: Henry in Henry is the one I told what
you said; in speech focus it is often accomplished through accent: I told Henry what you
said.
Function: The role played by a word in a sentence; in George saw me and I saw George the
word George has different functions.
Generic Used to refer to a whole class of entities: A child can do that (= any chil, all
children); The Child from Three to Six (= children in general).
Gerund The form of a verb ending in -ing used as (part of) a noun phrase: I enjoy swimming,
She accused me of telling lies.
Goal: The role that expresses what is affected by the action of a predicate: Roger gave Ellen
a present. Ellen received a present.
Gradable: Said of an adjective that can be compared or intensified: hot ® hotter, very hot.
Grammar: The rules by which a language operates, and therefore the implicit knowledge
that speakers of that language have which makes them competent to use the language; also,
an account of the rules.
Habitual: Said of a form, especially a verb that expresses customary, repeated activity: He
smokes a pipe.
Head: The main word in a phrase on which other elements depend and which controls the
function of the phrase: all those dirty clothes in the corner.
128
Homonyms: Words with the same pronunciation but different meanings: club ‗a heavy
stick‘ and club ‗a social organization.‘ homophones=homonyms that sound the same but
have different spellings.
Hyponym: A word whose referent is included in the referent of a more general word, called
the superordinate: rose is a hyponym of flower, and flower is a superordinate of rose.
Implicative verb: A verb that expresses something about the truth of the predication that
follows in the sentence: We didn‟t hesitate to accept the offer implies that we accepted the
offer.
Implicature: A meaning derived not from what is said but deduced from the necessary way
of interpreting what is said.
Inanimate see animate
Inceptive: Said of a form that expresses the beginning of a status or action: arrive; begin
running.
Indefinite see definite
Infinitive: A non-finite form of a verb; in English often, but not always, consisting of to+the
verb: I want them to go, I let them go.
Information: The content of a message.
Inhabitant noun: A noun like New Yorker which names the inhabitant of a particular place.
Instrument noun A noun that refers to an inanimate object by which the action of some
verb is accomplished: brush, projector.
Intention: What a speaker or writer wants to communicate in producing an utterance.
Interpretation: The message that a hearer or reader gets from an utterance.
Intonation: The system of melodies with which utterances are spoken and which can make
differences of meaning.
Lexeme: A minimal form that conveys one meaning and can be used in reference or
predication: the word cat, and the ‗idiom‘ put up with are both lexemes.
Lexicon: The vocabulary of a language, together with information about the pronunciation,
use, and meaning of each item in it.
Linguistic meaning: The meaning conveyed by linguistic forms, as distinct from meanings
conveyed by the circumstances of an utterance, which is speaker meaning.
Locution An utterance, that is, what is said as distinct from the intention of the speaker
(illocution) or the interpretation of the hearer (perlocution).
129
Meta-language: The language used in talking about language.
Metaphor: A figurative expression in which a notion is described in terms usually used for a
different kind of notion.
Metonymy: A way of denoting an entity by using some characteristic of that entity, e.g. blue
eyes as a way of referring to a person with blue eyes.
Modal verb: An auxiliary verb that expresses permission, probability or necessity: can,must.
Modality The expression of necessity, possibility and probability, often through modal
verbs.
Morpheme The smallest contrastive unit of meaning: a single word like cat or an affix such
as un- and -ness in unhappiness.
Negation: A process that expresses the denial or contradiction of some part, or all, of a
sentence.
Non-binary antonyms: Two lexemes that have opposite meanings but for which there are
intermediate degrees of the same quality: hot and cold.
Non-countable noun: A noun that has no plural form: mud, misery.
Non-verbal: Said of communication that does not use words.
Noun: A class of words with a naming function, showing contrasts of countability and
number.
Noun phrase: A phrase with a noun as head; hence, a noun alone may be a noun phrase.
Number The grammatical category that expresses the distinction of singular and plural.
Object: The noun phrase that names the entity which receives the action of the verb: John hit
Bill.
Paradigmatic: The relation of items that can substitute for one another at the same place in a
sentence. Cf. syntagmatic.
Paralanguage: Characteristics of the voice, apart from the words spoken, which can
communicate something about the speaker‘s attitude.
Paraphrase: An alternative way of expressing the content of a sentence.
Participle: A non-finite form of a verb, either present (amusing) or past (amused).
Particles Words that combine with verbs to make compound verbs: in, out, on, off, up,
down, over, away, through.
Passive voice see voice
Perceptual predicate: A verb that expresses the activity of any of the five senses.
130
Performative verb: A verb that may be used to state the actual performance of an action;
declare.
Period adjective: An adjective derived from a noun that expresses some period of time:
monthly ¬ month.
Person: A grammatical category of reference, in English expressed with pronouns, referring
to the speaker and perhaps others (1st person: I, we), the addressee(s) (2nd person: you), or
others (3rd person: he, she, it, they).
Phatic: Said of utterances used mainly to establish social contact.
Phoneme: A unit in the sound system of a language, which combines with other such units
to form syllables and words; English cash and shack have the same three phonemes
differently arranged.
Phrase: A group of words smaller than a clause, forming a grammatical unit.
Plural see number
Polarity: The contrast of affirmative and negative.
Possessive: A language category that indicates possession: my, your.
Pragmatics: The study of language in use, including the ways in which we derive meanings
from the context and from knowledge of speakers apart from the linguistic meanings of what
is said.
Preposition: One of a class of function words that ties a following noun phrase to the rest of
the sentence: at, for, with.
Presupposition: The information that must be assumed in order for a sentence to be
meaningful; ―Have you stopped beating your wife?” presupposes that the addressee has been
beating his wife, which presupposes that the addressee is married and that the addressee is an
adult male.
Preventing predicate: A verb which states that its subject is the agent causing the non-
occurrence of the predication that follows: I kept the ball from rolling away.
Privative verb: A verb that expresses removal of something: undress.
Productive process: A means of making new words which is frequently used at the present
time: adding -er to verbs to make nouns like driver.
Productivity: The ability of humans to produce and understand constantly new utterances.
131
Progressive: The extended verb form composed of forms of be and the present participle,
expressing the duration or incompleteness of what the verb signifies: He is running, They
were waiting.
Pronoun: One of a small class of words that can substitute for a noun phrase: he, somebody,
who.
Proper noun: A noun or noun phrase that labels some specific person, place, building,
historic event, etc. and which lacks the grammatical forms of a common noun.
Proposition: The meaning of any sentence that is asserted to be true or false.
Prospective verb: A verb that expresses some action or attitude oriented toward a later time:
We expect to go.
Qualifier: A word or phrase that modifies another word, thereby limiting the reference of
that word: very nice, big enough.
Quantifier/quantifying determiner: A word or phrase that expresses the amount of what is
expressed by another word: all, several, a dozen.
Reciprocal: A relationship that can be expressed by each other or one another.
Redundant: Said of any item that is more than necessary in a message for conveying the
meaning.
Reference: The relation between a language form and some physical entity, which is the
referent of that sign.
Reflexive: A verb or a construction in which the subject and the object have the same
referent: She hurt herself.
Retrospective verb: A verb that expresses an action or attitude oriented toward a previous
time: We regretted having gone there.
Reversive verb: A verb that expresses the reversing or undoing of what is expressed by
another verb: disconnect is the reversive verb that corresponds to connect.
Rhetorical question: A question for which no answer is expected.
Semantic field/set: A group of lexemes that are defined with respect to one another: kinship,
colors, etc.
Semantics: The study of meaning expressed by language.
Sense relations: The relations of meaning between words, as expressed in synonymy,
hyponymy, antonymy, etc.
Sentence: A grammatical construction that is complete in itself.
132
Sign: Any formal item that conveys meaning, especially a conventional piece of a system.
Simple sentence: A sentence that contains only one clause.
Simple verb: A finite verb that has no auxiliary and so consists of just one word.
Singular see number
Speaker meaning see linguistic meaning
Speech act: An utterance defined in terms of the speaker‘s intention and the effect on the
audience.
Statement: A sentence that tells something.
Stative verb: A verb that expresses some state of affairs, rather than an action or event.
Structural semantics: The study of the sense relations between words.
Structure: A system of interrelated elements that have repeatable relations to one another
and which are defined by their relations to one another.
Subject The noun phrase about which something is stated; John and I are ready.
Synonym: A word that is equivalent in sense to another word (in a particular context or
contexts); select is a synonym of choose in ―Will you help me choose a new suit?‖ (but not
in ―I don‘t choose to wait.‖).
Syntagmatic: The relation of words to one another when they form a construction.
Syntax: The study of how words go together to form sentences.
Tense: The expression of time in a verb; in English a verb has two tenses, present (play) and
past (played).
Utterance: A stretch of speech by one person; it may consist of a single word, a single
sentence, or numerous sentences.
Valency: The number of arguments (noun phrases) that a predicate takes in one sentence.
Verdictive predicate: A verb that occurs in a sentence which expresses the speaker‘s
Judgment of some presumed action by the addressee: I blame you for what happened.
Voice: the relation of the action of the verb to its subject; either active, as in She loves me, or
passive, as in She is loved by me.
Weather predicate: An adjective like rainy or a verb such as snow which occurs with the
empty subject it.
Oft-Repeated Long Questions
1. What is presupposition? Discuss different types of presupposition with examples
2. “The Sense of an expression can be thought of as the sum of its sense
133
properties and sense relation” discuss.
3. What Felicity Conditions in relation to Speech Act Theory are required.
Elaborate.
4. What are thematic roles? Discuss in detail.
5. What are the Semantics properties? Elaborate property noun and verb with
examples.
6. What are SEMANTIC PROPERTIES? Discuss in detail their role in
establishing the meaning of words?
7. Write an exhaustive note on SEMANTIC ROLES?
8. Write detailed note n SPEECH act theory?
9. Semantics is the study of meaning. What are different types of meaning?
10.What is PRESUPPOSTION? How it is different from ENTAILMENTT?
11.Write a detailed note on all semantic relations along with suitable examples?
12.Write a brief note on the following?
a. The Word
b. Presupposition
c. Entailment
d. Implicature
13.What is Discourse? How can we understand discourse meaning?
14. Define Antonyms. Discuss their types in detail?
15. What are semantics properties? Discuss their role in establishing the meaning
of words in detail.
16. Speech Acts
17. Grice’s Cooperative Principles
134