PDF Class in Archaic Greece 1st Edition Peter W. Rose Download
PDF Class in Archaic Greece 1st Edition Peter W. Rose Download
PDF Class in Archaic Greece 1st Edition Peter W. Rose Download
com
https://ebookgate.com/product/class-in-archaic-
greece-1st-edition-peter-w-rose/
https://ebookgate.com/product/the-development-of-the-polis-in-
archaic-greece-1st-edition-lynette-mitchell/
https://ebookgate.com/product/archaic-greece-the-age-of-new-
reckonings-brian-lavelle/
https://ebookgate.com/product/greece-and-rome-at-war-peter-
connolly/
https://ebookgate.com/product/money-and-capital-markets-10th-
edition-peter-rose/
Guest Appearances and Other Travels in Time and Space
1st Edition Peter I. Rose
https://ebookgate.com/product/guest-appearances-and-other-
travels-in-time-and-space-1st-edition-peter-i-rose/
https://ebookgate.com/product/the-splendors-and-miseries-of-
ruling-alone-encounters-with-monarchy-from-archaic-greece-to-the-
hellenistic-mediterranean-nino-luraghi-editor/
https://ebookgate.com/product/rose-henderson-a-woman-for-the-
people-1st-edition-peter-campbell/
https://ebookgate.com/product/class-1-devices-case-studies-in-
medical-devices-design-1st-edition-peter-j-ogrodnik/
https://ebookgate.com/product/neurologic-disease-in-women-2nd-
edition-peter-w-kaplan/
CLASS IN ARCHAIC GREECE
PETER W. ROSE
...,.:.:._,,, CAMBRIDGE
::: UNIVERSITY PRESS
CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS
Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town,
Singapore, Sao Paulo, Delhi, Mexico City
Cambridge University Press
The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge CB2 8Ru, UK
Published in the United States of America by Cambridge University Press, New York
www.cambridge.org
Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9780521768764
Printed and Bound in the United Kingdom by the MPG Books Group
A catalogue record for this publication is avai'4ble fom the British Library
References
Index
Vll
Preface
The origin of this book is on one level very simple: Kurt Raaflaub asked
me to write a short piece on this topic, then when my first draft was
four times too long, encouraged me to consider writing a monograph. His
fellow-editor, Hans van Wees, though I never had the pleasure of meeting
him face-to-face, also gave much helpful advice - not least with his own
excellent offprints. I am indebted as well to David Roselli, James McGlew,
Virginia Hunter, Page duBois, Mark Golden, Arch Christopherson, Rick
Wolff, Tracy Rihle, Steve Tuck, and David Tandy for helpful comments on
earlier drafts or parts thereof. Since I could not bring myself to incorporate
all of their suggestions, I hereby absolve them of all remaining errors.
Special thanks are due to Steve Nimis, who alone among my circuit of
friends and colleagues has read the whole text and offered other sorts of
valued support. Thanks as well to Daniel Tompkins for his insights on the
works of Moses Finley.
I have a unique debt to Walter Donlan, whose advice and encourage-
ment at an early stage played a key role in my decision to attempt this quite
daunting task. Based especially on a grueling three-hour phone conversa-
tion about a draft of my chapter on the Dark Age, I know that the tragic
death of this very dear man soon after I had sketched a fuller version of that
chapter deprived me of what I'm sure would have been a much-needed and
trenchant critique. At a dinner in 2002 with colleagues after a joint session
of CAMWS on recent developments in Homeric scholarship, Walter com-
plained in his playfully churlish way, "I've learned a lot from you guys, but
you've obviously learned nothing from me." This was of course blatantly
untrue. The problem, which may be relevant in my text as well, is that we
have all internalized and taken for granted so much of his compelling work
that we tend to focus on the relatively few areas where we disagree.
Though my training and teaching have been primarily in ancient litera-
ture, my interest in the history of the Archaic Period dates back to the late
1950s when I audited a lecture course on the period by H. T. Wade-Gery,
Vlll
Preface 1X
Xlll
Introduction: theoretical considerations
' I was in the process of correcting an embarrassing number of typos in my "final" read-through of my
chapter on Sparta when a bibliographic note in A. Powell (2001: 256), which I happened to be using
as a text in a course on the Age of Pericles, warmly recommended Cartledge'sAgesilaos for a "full-scale
analysis of Sparta's political, social and educational workings." I have owned a copy of Cartledge's
book for several years but never read it: "judging the book by its cover," I assumed it was confined
to fourth-century developments. Reading the chapter "Agesilaos and the Spartan Class Struggle," I
encountered the sentence I now quote in Chapter Six note 73. This cites Cartledge 1975, which as
a Marxist and Arethusa subscriber I had of course read when it appeared but completely forgotten.
Reading it over was a strange experience: so many of the issues I address in the following introduction
were dealt with there with admirable concision. At the same time I felt a certain sadness: the implicit
promise of classical historians explicitly engaging with Marx's texts has alas not been fulfilled- with
the great exception of de Ste. Croix's work (1981), which, amazingly, Cartledge cites as "forthcoming"
(1975: 79 n. 35) six years before its actual appearance. In a prefatory note (76) he thanks de Ste.
Croix for inspiration and "devastating criticism" - a blessing indeed. In a more recent work (2002:
3) Cartledge decribes how "my historical interests and researches had opportunely shifted away
from the material (social and economic) and the political (broadly interpreted) to the intellectual or
social-psychological ... I had become especially concerned to interpret and understand the mindset
or the mentality of the Greeks."
2 Theoretical comideratiom
these "aristocrats" virtually "commission" (he uses but also balks at the
word 1996: 66) Homer to "reflect" their self-conscious self-congratulation.
He traces a purely aristocratic audience back to Mycenae, but sees only the
prosperity of the late eighth century as the appropriate context in which the
fully self-conscious and optimistic aristocracy wants to embrace its glorious
past heritage (1996: 63 and passim). The only other class he alludes to is the
class of "merchants," called into being - he argues-by the very success of
what he posits as aristocrat-led colonial and trade adventures (Latacz 1996:
57). So too Ian Morris (e.g., 1986a, 1987) among others finds "class" and
class ideology, and clear evidence of class struggle in burials, but devotes
relatively little attention to theorizing the phenomenon of class that plays
so key a role in his analysis. His influential opposition of "ruling class" and
"middling" ideologies (1996) is posited initially as exclusively within the
aristocracy while the rest of society is subsumed in a vaguely hypostatized
''polis," but he subsequently moves to straightforward declarations that
"Most Athenians imagined themselves as middling men" (2000: 153, my
emphasis). 2
Beyond a general tendency of classicists to eschew theory, I believe
that the more than century-and-a-half-long anxiety ("a specter is haunting
Europe"; MECW 6: 482), culminating in the half-century-long Cold War,
associated in people's minds with Marx's dynamic theorization of class in
1847 (Communist Manifesto) and with the turmoils and tragedies led by
self-proclaimed followers of Marx explains more fully the general reluc-
tance to engage theoretically with a concept that classicists seem so often
to find as indispensable as it is troublesome. 3 Thus, Starr, for example,
2 Morris (2000) seems to me to blur this distinction between a ruling class ideology and what
everyone in the polis believes. Kurke, whose enterprise in Coins, Bodies, Games, and Gold {1999)
is explicitly dependent on Morris's ruling class-middling opposition {19--22), has the great virtue
of acknowledging directly her own hypostasis of "the city," but justifies it by "our very limited
real knowledge about who exactly is doing what in this period" {17 n. 46), a genuine problem
to be sure, but one which seems to constitute no barrier to her own very elaborate explorations
of ideological struggles in this same period. In fairness to Morris, whose ongoing quest for new
theoretical paradigms is awesome, I should note that his essay on "Hard Surfaces" (2002) is strikingly
sympathetic to a number ofloosely defined Marxist approaches and even critiques Kurke's approach
as "unable to find an external grounding for economic categories in humanity's ability to appropriate
nature or the equity of the distribution of its fruits" (2002: 18). See below further on Kurke and
Morris.
3 Anton Powell offers a more "delicate" explanation {he is presumably thinking primarily of British
scholars): "Aversion from thoughts of social differences has traditionally been common among
classical scholars, inspired partly by a delicate reluctance {which the Spartan oligarchs might well
have understood) to introduce divisive conversation into their own group" {1989a: 180--1). In another
text he offers a more explicitly political account: "The internal conflict which most threatened Greek
communities was one between rich and poor, and many scholars of recent times have found analysis
in those terms uncongenial because it recalls modern social tensions" (2001: 272). Finley {1967: 201)
Classicists and class 3
whose celebration of the aristocracy of the Archaic Period has much in
common with that of Latacz, goes out of his way to dismiss scornfully any
relevance of "Klassenkampf' (1977: 19). His use of the German term, in a
sense, lets the ideological cat out of the bag: he wants to evoke, without
naming Marx. 4 Another strategy that reveals the same anxiety is the use of
scare quotes around the word "class" (e.g., J. Hall 2007: 127; Foxhall 1997:
120). One of the subordinate goals of the following study is to highlight
on the one hand, the ways in which classical scholars' fear of being dubbed
"Marxists" or - the usual derogatory substitution - "economic determin-
ists" (e.g., Kurke 1999: 12 n. 27) has often mystified the role of class in the
history of this period and, on the other, to emphasize how the analyses of
many non-Marxist classicists both presuppose and confirm some funda-
mental Marxist propositions about the nature and functioning of human
societies.
This is not to suggest that self-proclaimed Marxists have either ignored
classical antiquity or failed to offer theoretical accounts of the nature and
meaning of class in particular periods of that era. On the contrary, Marxists
such as George Thomson (1946, 1955, 1961) and Margaret Wason (1947)
must share a considerable part of the responsibility for non-Marxist ana-
lysts' reluctance to engage in a potentially endless and potentially fruitless
ideological debate about the nature of class and its implications for under-
standing any specific society in any specific historical period. 5 G. E. M. de
Ste. Croix devotes a minimum 6 of ninety-one very large, painstaking pages
(1981: 19-m) to defending the appropriateness of applying Marxist notions
of class and class struggle to the analysis of the ancient Greek world. In
the process he offers not only a detailed exploration of Marx's own texts
but also his detailed critique of what he considers both misguided Marxist
approaches (e.g., Thomson, Wason, Vernant 1988a [1974], cf. Ste. Croix
1981: 41 and 63) and the alternative Weberian focus on statuses advocated
put it more bluntly: "There is effectively a thick wall of silence and contempt which in our world
cuts off Marxist thinking from 'respectable' thinking, at least in the one field which I know well, and
that is the study of ancient civilization." How much the situation has improved since 1967 remains
to be seen.
4 His footnotes (1977: 200---1) do specify Marx. Cf. Donlan, "We must be careful above all not to
import the modern concept of Klassenkampfinto the picture. The Greek tyrant was no popular
revolutionary leading his people against an oppressive aristocracy" (1999 [1980]:189----90, n. 7). For
the context of Donlan's comment see on tyranny below in text.
5 Yvon Garlan (1988: 8---14) summarizes some of the debate over slavery between East and West
German scholars. McKeown (1999: n8---21) treats Eastern European classical scholarship somewhat
more sympathetically.
6 One could reasonably argue that a great deal more of his text is an ongoing polemic for his
methodology.
4 Theoretical comideratiom
by Moses Finley (1973, cf. Ste. Croix 1981: 58 and 85-96) and followed by
most classicists. 7
In the following introduction I will try to explore as many of the over-
lapping lines of argument that dismiss a Marxist approach as seems prac-
ticable. While these arguments will gradually contribute to clarifying my
alternative approach, I will then set forth more directly the key theoretical
assumptions of the following chapters.
7 Ober (1989: 38) is unusual in that he actually attributes his own usage of the term ideology to Finley
{19826: 17, 1983a: 122-41) and offers his own version of a transcendence of class (see Rose 2006: 106--
11). I. Morris cites the Marxists E. P. Thompson and Eric Hobsbawn for what he calls a "heuristic and
analytical" use of "class" but does not elaborate {1987: 177). Of texts I have read recently Manville
{1990) is perhaps the most adroit is skirting the concept of class and substituting status and privilege
despite the heavy emphasis in his major sources ([Aristotle] Ath. Pol. and Plutarch) on open conflict
between rich and poor (cf., for example, 71, 76--7, 159---60, 190--1). Stein-Holkeskamp also implicitly
endorses Finley, who is the only authority she cites for distinguishing between "'Schicht,' 'Klasse,'
'Stand,' und 'Status"' (1989: 8 n. 3). Keith Hopkins, in a volume dedicated "To Moses," emphatically
endorses Finley's "elevation of status ... at the expense of class," which has "drawn the fire of those
Marxists [he names none] who are still trying to milk the rhetoric of class struggle and the dominant
mode of production." He argues that the great virtue of Finley's approach is that it was a rare attempt
to assimilate cultural value into economic analysis" (Hopkins 1983: xiii my emphasis), a comment
that suggests to me that he had read neither Marx nor any serious Marxists. Van Wees's very title,
Status Warriors {1992), accurately reflects the emphasis of his entire analysis of Homeric poetry.
For his part, Finley got his revenge by referring to Ste. Croix's book as "an eccentric, Procrustean
definition of the essential Marxist categories'' in his contribution on "ancient society" to A Dictionary
ofMarxist Thought (Finley 19836: 22). Most recently J. Hall, though he does occasionally offer useful
insights on class, seems far more comfortable with a focus on "status'': he even sums up his view of
the sixth-century emergence of an aggressively self-conscious merchant class by declaring, "While
earlier, landed wealth had- at least in part - derived fom status, there was now an increasing demand
that the acquisition of wealth from other sources should be recognized with a concomitant status . .. "
{2007: 284, my emphasis).
Moses Finley and the dismissal ofclass 5
significant for my project, would entail a very long digression. 8 In 1967,
for example, after a correspondent accused a review he had published of
"ill-applied Marxism" he offered a terse but eloquent - even courageous at
that historical moment - defense, e.g., (1967: 202): "Properly understood,
Marxism is not a dogma. For an ancient historian, it is a way of looking at
men [sic] and events which helps to pose fruitful and significant questions."
I. Morris in his Foreword (1999: xvii-xviii) essentially finesses the problem:
''As a serious student of Weberian sociology, Finley would have made a
strange communist." Momigliano (1987) addresses the problem briefly (see
below) as do Shaw and Saller (1981). My own sense, to be very brief, is
that Marx's own writings deeply impressed Finley, but that the stigma of
Marxism arising from Cold War hysteria and the sheer stupidity of some
Marxist and anti-Marxist polemics - not to mention his own painful expe-
rience with the Internal Security Subcommitte of the U.S. Senate aka the
McCarran Committee (Tomkins 2006: 95) - led him to distance himself
as far as possible from the label and to seek in Weber an acceptable the-
oretical framework for addressing questions raised by Marx such as the
necessity of a proper theory in the writing of history (1981: 3-23, 1985a
[1987] and passim), the role of slavery in ancient society (Finley 1936, 1981:
97-198, 1983b, 1987, 1998 [1980]), the relationship of political to economic
structures (e.g., 1973a, 1981: 24-40, 1983a, 1985a), the nature of imperialism
(1981: 41-61 [= 1978], 1985a: 67-87), etc. While more than half of Weber's
The Agrarian Sociology ofAncient Civilizatiom (1976 = Agrarverhiiltnisse
im Altertum, 1909) is devoted to ancient Greece and Rome, Marx's more
sustained discussion of precapitalist forms in the Grundrisse was first pub-
lished in Moscow in 1939 and only became available in the west in 1953
(Marx 1973: 7). Though Weber categorically dismissed any comprehen-
sive theory of history - Marxist or Hegelian (cf. Giddens 1971: 163, 194,
F. Jameson 1988: vol. 2: rn)-the temptation to separate Weber too radically
from Marx must also be resisted: as Finley himself pointed out, "Marx was
the specter haunting Weber" (1981: 18). Moreover, as Giddens repeatedly
stresses, the Marxism against which Weber reacted most rigorously was
Engels's pseudo-scientific transference of the dialectic to nature, which
"thus obscures the most essential element of Marx's conception" (Giddens
1971: 189, cf. xiv-xv). Giddens is then at pains to stress the fundamen-
tal harmony between much of Weber's analysis of religion and ideology
with Marx's dialectic of subject and object (Giddens 1971: 2rn-12) Finally,
8 In thinking about this problem of Finley's relation to Marxism, however, I would like to acknowledge
again the great help offered by Daniel Tompkins in sharing with me his ongoing work on Finley,
some of which has appeared in print (2006 and 2008).
6 Theoretical comideratiom
109-63), Bendix and Lipset (1966), Wright (1985 and 1989), Poulantzas (1973: 58----98; 1978: 13-35),
Bottomore (1983 s.v.), Carver (1987 s.v.). Chilcote (2000: 89-132) offers a particularly full romp
through the whole range of theories of class, starting with Adam Smith and David Ricardo. As Eric
Roll observes in his history of economic thought, "As ... these doctrines [the theory of classes and
the class-struggle, etc.] have become parts of fiercely-held and as fiercely-attacked, political dogma,
it is not easy without becoming involved in doctrinal battles to formulate them in a manner which
is understandable and makes some sense" (Roll 1992: 231). Thus even the most "neutral" of scholars
would never call Marx's theory of classes "apparently clearcut, unequivocal."
n As Kyrtatas (2002) emphasires, the very concept of economic exploitation was alien to the Greeks,
but that does not mean that the phenomenon did not exist.
12 The image, of course, comes from Aristotle, Pol 1253632-33, "the slave is a living [soul-possessing
empsychon] possession, even as every servant is an instrument taking precedence over [inanimate]
instruments."
'l Applying a term like "variable captital" to antiquity strikes me as hopelessly misleading. Throughout
his varying analyses of capitalism Marx is constantly at pains to historicire the specific preconditions
of the capitalist mode of production by repeated specific contrasts to earlier modes, most commonly
8 Theoretical comideratiom
slave labor and serfdom. The following is perhaps the most concise of many formulations: "This
transformation [into capital] can itself only take place under particular circumstances, which meet
together at this point: the confrontation of, and the contact between, two very different kinds
of commodity owners; on the one hand, the owners of money, means of production, means of
susbsistence, who are eager to valorire the sum of values thay have appropriated by buying the
labour-power of others; on the other hand, free workers, the sellers of their own labour-power,
and therefore the sellers of labour. Free workers, in the double sense that they neither form part
of the means of production themselves, as would be the case with slaves, serfs, etc., nor do they
own the means of production, as would be the case with self-employed peasant proprietors" (Marx
1976: 874, cf. Marx 1973: 463 and 471-72). It is only within this specific market and production
relation between capitalist and worker that the latter can be viewed as "variable capital." What
the capitalist expends on raw materials and instruments of production remains a constant, whereas
"that part of capital which is turned into labour-power does undergo an alteration of value in the
process of production. It both reproduces the equivalent of its own value and produces an excess, a
surplus-value, which may itself vary, and be more or less according to circumstances" (Marx 1976:
317). See below for Marx on Greek slavery.
14 This refers to the end of the fifth century. Elsewhere (189) he suggests that free laborers in mines
might have received a bit more than twice the wage of a slave. However, the inscription for the
building of the Erechtheum for this same period indicates slaves and free workers received exactly
the same pay for the same work (Finley 1982a: 100-1).
15 In another context Finley quotes with apparent approval Sir Keith Hancock: "'The Boers very soon
convinced themselves that the artisans' work and slaves' work were the same thing"' (Finley 1982a:
194). Kyrtatas (2002: 143) states of the Greeks themselves (especially Aristotle): "whenever human
beings worked in a way that the product of their labour belonged to another human being, they
were regarded, for all practical purposes, as slaves." The issue in my view, however, is not ancient
attitudes but the actual relations of production.
Moses Finley and the dismissal ofclass 9
into castes and estates means that economic elements are inextricably joined to
political and religious factors; that economic and legal categories are objectively
and substantively so interwoven as to be inseparable: In short, from neither a Marxist
nor a non-Marxist standpoint is class a sufficiently demarcated category for our
purposes. (Finley 1973a: 50; Lukacs 1971: 55-59, Finley's emphasis)
In his footnote Finley cites the opening essay of Lukacs's text as support for
his hyperbolic description of him as "a most orthodox Marxist." The title
of that essay is indeed "What is Orthodox Marxism?" What Finley does
not indicate is that at the time of its publication (1922, see the 1967 preface
reprinted in Lukacs 1971: xvi) it was a radical defense of the Hegelian
element in Marx, a daring attempt to counter what became the dominant
Stalinist orthodoxy of Marxism as "science," an attempt that led to the
book's condemnation by Bukharin, Zinoviev, and others (Bottomore 1983:
291). 16 But a more relevant omission by Finley is the fact that the primary
goal of the essay from which Finley takes his quote is precisely an analysis
of class consciousness. The chief point of Lukacs's discussion of precapitalist
societies is to stress the reasons why class consciousness did not arise in the
past but can arise under capitalism and must arise if real human liberation
is to be achieved. Lukacs is, however, far from suggesting the irrelevance of
Marx to the analysis of these societies:
'6 In his deathbed interviews Lukacs was asked why he thought History and Class Consciousness still had
an international impact. He replied, "The book has a certain value because in it questions are raised
which Marxism evaded at the time" (1983: 77, my emphasis). Martin Jay also cites the following from
Luka.cs's Preface to the reissue of the text in 1967: "It is undoubtedly one of the great achievements
of History and Class Consciousness to have reinstated the category of totality in the central position
it had occupied throughout Marx's works and from which it had been ousted by the 'scientism' of
the social-democratic opportunists" (Jay 1984: 85; Lukacs 1971: xx). In explaining why he was not
eliminated during the Stalinist purges, he notes among other reasons, "In addition - and this is
perhaps a cynical observation - I had very inferior living quarters that were less attractive to the
NKVD" (1983: 97). This speaks volumes about the mentality of many of the prime movers of those
purges.
IO Theoretical comideratiom
see only conscious, political struggles. 17 The slave who does the minimum
amount of work that will evade punishment or who runs away is, in Marxist
terms, engaging in class struggle - albeit without class consciousness in the
strong sense of the term, a struggle which in certain circumstances (e.g.,
during the Peloponnesian War, cf. Thucydides 7.27.2) may have political
consequences, but by no stretch of the imagination could be termed a
specifically political struggle.
It is also striking that Finley's use of Lukacs aims at supporting his
own version of Polanyi's focus on the "embedded" economy: 18 he seems
to be arguing that if the economy is inextricably conjoined with political,
religious, and legal categories, this somehow invalidates a Marxist approach.
This is a particularly odd use of Lukacs, who is especially concerned to
use Marxism to elucidate the "social totality," i.e., "the concrete totality
of the historical world, the concrete and total historical process" (Lukacs
1971: 145, cf. Jay 1984: 81-127). 19 Moreover, Polanyi himself credits Marx
with an important role in the development of the distinction between
embedded and disembedded economies: "Its [the distinction's] sociological
background was first mooted by Hegel in the 1820s and developed by
Karl Marx in the 1840s" (1968: 82). Reading over Polanyi's broad-view
essay "Societies and Economic Systems" (1968: 3-25), I was struck by how
little of it - though based on a great deal of anthropological research
of the twentieth century - Marx would disagree with. Both Marx and
Polanyi are concerned in a major way (see further below) to attack the
ahistoricism of capitalist economists who either project capitalist views of
human nature into the past or simply dismiss the past. Both stress that
'7 In a later work Finley returns to class, and class conflict, and alludes scornfully to "the current bad
habit of pinning the Marxist label on any and every political analysis that employs a concept of
class" (1983a: 9-10). A footnote (10 n. 29) alludes to his earlier case for "status" and assures us, "My
return in the present work to 'class' (in the sense intended in ordinary discourse, not in a technical
sense, Marxist or other) does not imply a change of view." The fact is, however, that the kind of
class conflict he discusses (loosely that of "the rich and the poor") has nothing to do with any sort
of status conflict, which operates primarily within a given class.
'8 "To employ a metaphor, the facts of the economy were originally embedded in situations that were
not in themselves of an economic nature, neither the ends nor the means being primarily material.
The crystallization of the concept of the economy was a matter of time and history. But neither
time nor history have provided us with those conceptual tools required to penetrate the maze of
social relationships in which the economy was embedded" (Polanyi et al. 1957: 242). This seemingly
utterly despairing view of the fruits of "time and history" are then triumphantly answered by the
following: "This is the task of what we will here call institutional analysis" (ibid.)
'9 F. Jameson's chapter (2009: 201-22) on Luka.cs's History and Class Consciousness is particularly
eloquent in sorting out the distortions involved in the postmodern "war on totality" and emphasizing
that in Lukacs "'totality' is not ... a form of knowledge, but rather a framework in which various
kinds of knowledge are positioned, pursued, and evaluated. This is clearly the implication of the
phrase 'aspiration to totality'" (210--n).
Moses Finley and the dismissal ofclass II
Finley's primary grounds for allegiance to the concept of status are para-
doxically based on a special application of the Marxist concept of social
relations that become a "fetter" 21 on the development of productive force.
The ideological commitments of the ruling classes in Greece and Rome,
Finley argued, blocked them from the fullest exploitation of their own
resources and political power: "They lacked the will; that is to say, they
were inhibited, as a group ... by over-riding values" (1973a: 60). 22 To be
20 Polanyi: "it is on this one negative point that modern ethnographers agree: the absence of the
motive of gain" (1968:8); Marx: "Among the ancients we discover no single inquiry as to which form
of landed property, etc. is the most productive, which creates maximum wealth. Wealth does not
appear the aim of production" (1965: 84).
21 ''At a certain stage of development, the material productive forces of society come into conflict
with the existing relations of production or - this merely expresses the same thing in legal terms -
with the property relations within the framework of which they have operated hitherto. From
forms of development of the productive forces these relations turn into their fitters" (MECW 29:
263). Lekas {1988) turns this formulaic statement into a central ground for his critique of Marx's
comments on antiquity. See Konstan's excellent review (1990), which nicely refutes a reading of
Marx as dogmatically committed to "a linear development of forces of production within a given
society such that they come ultimately into conflict with the prevailing form of economic and social
relations" {84). Marx, in a famous passage to be discussed later, certainly laid out such a scenario,
but in the Grundrisse {1973: 106--7), Konstan points out that "Marx, even when he was thinking
of universal history and not just of ancient societies, could produce a sequence of historical stages
that correspond in a broad way to an increase in the forces of production (however loosely defined),
without insisting that each stage causally determines the transition to the next by an evolution of
the productive forces specific to its form of labor" {1990: 87).
22 The relative failure of Greco-Roman civili7.ation to advance technologically is similarly presented
by Finley as due to the ruling class's attitude toward manual labor as a consequence of slavery
(Finley 1982b [1965]: 176--95). See, however, Cuomo {2007: 3-4) for an explicit critique of Finley on
this point and Oleson (2008: 5-6), who refers to Finley and "this now discredited interpretation."
Greene (2000) offers a more sustained focus on Finley and ancient technology.
12 Theoretical comideratiom
2l For a sampling of the debates over the relationship of class to gender - mostly with a contemporary
focus - see Brenner 2000, Vogel 1983, Saf!ioti 1978, Meulenbelt et al. 1984, Mies 1986, Scott 1988,
1996a and b, Okin 1979, Butler and Scott 1992, Hansen and Philipson 1990, Hennessy (1993). On
women in antiquity Pomeroy's classic {1975) is still an excellent starting point, but see Arthur's
[Katz's] thoughtful and learned critique (1976). There are some excellent essays in the two Arethusa
special issues (Sullivan 1973 and Peradotto 1978). In particular Arthur's [Katz's] article {1973: 7----58)
addresses directly relations of class and gender. See also Duby and Perrot (1991), Rabinowitz and
Richlin (1993), Hawley and Levick {1995), Loraux {1995), Humphreys {1993). Apart from Arthur
[Katz] 1973 and Rose {1993), I am aware of very little sustained focus directly on the relationship of
gender to class in recent feminist scholarship on ancient Greece. DuBois 1995: 2, 32 raises the issue
of class, but it does not figure prominently in her analysis of Sappho. So too in duBois 1988: 13, she
makes this tantalizing observation: "The views of Marx and Lukacs on production in capitalism
coexist with and illuminate the theories of gender proposed by psychoanalytic theory and lived by
all of us."
24 Cartledge (2002: 78---104) offers an admirably concise synchronic overview of Greek ideologies of
gender, but does not raise questions of class apart from a parenthetic "women like the wife of
Iskhomakhos are clearly represented as belonging to the Athenian ruling class" (102).
Feminist critiques ofclass 13
rights, equal access to jobs with equal pay, control of their bodies, sexual
freedom, daycare, full political participation, etc. only highlight the severe
constraints under which ancient Greek women lived. More relevant, my
more limited goal in this text is to explain change. 25 In that context I
will argue that class, whatever its inadequacy for explaining everything of
importance about a society, provides the best vehicle.
Departing from the pervasive gender-blindness in Marxist approaches,
Ste. Croix makes a sustained argument for viewing married women at least
as a separate class: "married women (who may be regarded in principle as
monopolizing the reproductive function), have rights, including above all
property rights, markedly inferior to those of men; and they have these
inferior rights as a direct result of their reproductive function, which gives
them a special role in the productive process and makes men desire to
dominate and possess them and their offspring" (1981: 100). 26 He goes on
to insist that many individuals belong to more than one class and that a
woman's class position needs to take account of "whether her economic
and legal condition is very different from that of her menfolk" (ibid.). The
complexity of this formulation, which plays a very small role in his vast text,
suggests some of the difficulty of a merely token effort to combine class and
gender. I also find it hard to move from this more-or-less exclusive focus
on female reproductive power to female slaves, free-born metic prostitutes,
or property-owning Spartan women. Moreover, in this connection (but cf.
180-1) Ste. Croix makes no mention of the very substantial contribution
to material production women characteristically were expected to make
through spinning and weaving27 - not to mention in farm work (e.g.
Hesiod WD 405-6). While I will try to take account of relevant evidence
where issues of gender are clearly implicated in those of class, I make no
pretense to an adequate focus on gender as such.
25 Both Osborne (19976) and Patterson (2007: 168---174, cf. 1986) have argued compellingly that Pericles'
citizenship law of 451 BC had a significant impact on the status of women in classical Athens. But
even this change was a consequence of a male initiative.
26 His argument bears some affinity with the theorization by Harwood (1994: 96), who argues, on
the analogy of Marx's account of the emergence of classes, "Gender arises and individuals become
engendered in the course of struggle for the child. And just as the yarn is also labor (alienated labor
when the yarn is viewed as the capitalist's private property), so is the baby."
27 I like to think that Marx's extensive knowledge of Greek and Latin classics with their repeated
allusions to women weaving at least partly inspired his declaration in The German Ideology that
"slavery cannot be abolished without the steam-engine and the mule jenny [a machine for spinning
textile fibers into yarn], serfdom cannot be abolished without improved agriculture, and ... in
general, people cannot be liberated as long as they are unable to obtain food and drink, housing and
clothing in adequate quality and quantity. 'Liberation' is a historical and not a mental act" (MECW
5: 38).
14 Theoretical comideratiom
Though I do not agree with all of Ste. Croix's arguments, much of his
overall argument for the usefulness of Marxist approaches seems cogent
to me. In any case the work of explicitly Marxist classicists by no means
exhausts the possibilities for a broadly "Marxist" account of antiquity. By
"Marxist" I refer not only to the works of Marx and Engels but as well
to the whole vast body of thought that derives from and is inspired by
the surviving writings of Karl Marx - and to a much lesser degree of
Frederick Engels, whose attempt to present Marxism as a "science" (Anti-
Duhring, 1878, Socialism: Utopian and Scientific, 1880) was responsible for
many intelligent readers rejecting "Marxism." 28 Since the work both of
the founders and the followers is, like any serious body of theory, full of
ambiguities, errors, and divergent developments, 29 I feel free to pick and
choose what makes most sense to me in what I know of this body of
thought. I accept the potential inconvenience of labeling myself a Marxist
in lieu of the drawbacks of having others pin on me a label I might otherwise
be tempted to avoid. This enables me to emphasize openly what I find most
compelling in this tradition rather than devote my primary energies to the
tedious task of spelling out all my disagreements with or qualifications of
this or that statement by any thinker in the tradition. Rather than embroil
myself in all the polemics within Marxism, I will follow my own path and -
to echo Marx echoing Dante - fascia dir le genti. At the same time, the
reader is entitled to some specifics about what to expect from a "Marxist"
account of class in the Archaic Period. This will take the form of addressing
first some of the other serious objections leveled against a Marxist approach
28 The essay "Socialism: Utopian and Scientific" was excerpted from the former, fuller work. See
the Tucker Anthology (Marx-Engels 1978: 683-717). Stalin embraced and imposed the idea of
Marxism as a "natural science" in his - alas - widely read pamphlet, "Dialectical and Historical
Materialism." It opening sentence gives the whole flavor of his approach: "Dialectical Materialism
is the world outlook of the Marxist-Leninist party. It is called dialectical materialism because
its approach to the phenomena of nature, its method of studying and apprehending them is
dialectical while its interpretation of the phenomena of nature, its conception of these phenomena,
its theory, is materialistic" (1940: 5, his emphasis). Though Marx followed developments in the
"hard" sciences, in no sense did he ever assert that his own "scientific" discoveries about the
inner workings of capitalism were applicable to "the phenomena of nature" - a truly preposterous
move! Nicolaus rightly comments, "Marx was sparing to the utmost with the adjective 'scientific"'
(1973: 53).
29 For example, Sahlins (1976: 55-125) offers a compelling analysis of the history of anthropological
theory in precisely these terms. Bettelheim (1985) offers a useful overview and meditation upon
the various shifts, contradictions and errors in Marx's conceptuali7.ations of class and class struggle
through his long writing career. But Bettelheim does so from within a Marxist perspective. So too
Nicolaus in his fine foreword to his translation of Marx's Grundrisse (1973) notes significant shifts
in Marx's formulations.
Marx and precapitalist societies 15
and secondly, a brief summary of what I take to be essential components
of such an approach.
If one leaves aside the output of the Cold War cottage industry devoted
to proclaiming Marx was wrong about everything, 30 many readers of Marx
have found his analysis of capitalism compelling but argue that applying
Marxist ideas to precapitalist societies entails an unwarranted imposition
of contemporary conceptions on societies that both conceived of them-
selves and operated on radically different bases. Marx himself responded
to an early version of this critique. In a long footnote to Capital Vol I,
Marx writes, "I seize this opportunity of briefly refuting an objection made
by a German-American publication to my work Zur Kritik der Politischen
Okonomie, 1859." He goes on to quote his now famous/notorious decla-
ration (see below for a fuller account) about "the economic structure of
society" constituting
the real foundation, on which arises a legal and political superstructure and to
which correspond definite forms of social consciousness ... In the opinion of the
German-American publication that is all very true for our own times, in which
material interests are preponderant, but not for the Middle Ages, dominated by
Catholicism, nor for Athens and Rome, dominated by politics. In the first place,
it strikes us as odd that anyone should suppose that these well-worn phrases about
the Middle Ages and the ancient world were unknown to anyone else. One thing
is clear: the Middle Ages could not live on Catholicism, nor could the ancient
world on politics. On the contrary, it is the manner in which they gained their
livelihood which explains why in one case politics, in the other case Catholicism
played the chief part. For the rest, one needs no more than a slight acquaintance
with, for example, the history of the Roman Republic, to be aware that its secret
history is the history oflanded property. And then there is Don Quixote, who long
ago paid the penalty for wrongly imagining that knight errantry was compatible
with all economic forms of society. (Marx 1976: 175-6)
This attempted refutation, with its heavy sarcasm, cryptic brevity, and
apparent crude reflectionism, while it does raise a valid problem inherent
3° A student of mine once quoted his economics professor announcing, "Next time we'll spend fifteen
minutes on Marx. It's more than he's worth, but what the Hell: it's in the textbook." Such a
dismissive attitude toward so rich and influential body of thought is the consequence of many years
of industrious Cold War efforts to demonstrate its absolute irrelevance. Even an author who devoted
a great deal of time to Marx takes a characteristic Cold War patronizing tone: "In fact, by and large
it will appear that strictly speaking Marx was almost never 'right.' His facts were defective by the
standards of modern scholarship, his generalization reckless and sweeping" (Elster 1986: 3). He does
go on to concede, "we may find that a theory can be shot through with errors of detail, even have
basic conceptual flaws, yet remain immensely fertile in its overall conception" (ibid.).
16 Theoretical comideratiom
in the Hegelian habit of trying to understand previous eras exclusively in
terms of their own dominant self-conceptions and in complete neglect of
their mode of production and general social organization, does not directly
address the question of Marx's relevance to precapitalist societies. It is cer-
tainly true that analyzing capitalism was the major focus of Marx's life-work
and the explicit goal of the first volume of Capital - one of the relatively
few works he actually published in his lifetime: "it is the ultimate aim of
this work to reveal the economic law of motion of modern society" (1976:
92). But the subtitle of that work is ''A Critique of Political Economy," by
which he means both serious investigators of the functioning of capitalism
and vulgar apologists of capitalism.31 One of the most consistent targets of
his critique is the attempt by capitalist ("bourgeois") economists to present
capitalism ahistorically as "natural" - as "eternal." Thus he is constantly
insisting that "the bourgeois mode of production [is] a particular kind of
social production of a historical and transitory character" (1976: 174 n. 34,
my emphasis);
these formulas [propounded by bourgeois economists], which bear the unmistak-
able stamp of belonging to a social formation in which the process of production
has mastery over man, instead of the opposite, appear to the political economists'
bourgeois consciousness to be as much a self-evident and nature-imposed necessity
as productive labour itself. Hence the pre-bourgeois forms of the social organiza-
tion of production are treated by political economy in much the same way as the
fathers of the church treated pre-Christian religions. (1976: 174-5)
l' "Let me point out once and for all that by classical political economy I mean all the economists
who, since the time of W. Petty, have investigated the real internal framework [Zusammenhang]
of bourgeois relations of production, as opposed to the vulgar economists who only flounder
around within the apparent framework of those relations, ceaselessly ruminate on the materials
long since provided by scientific political economy, and seek there plausible explanations of the
crudest phenomena for the domestic purposes of the bourgeoisie" (1976: 174-5 n. 34). The most
amusing and - alas - the most tedious portions of the Grundrisse are focused on detailed critiques
of Darimon, Proudhon, Bastiat, Malthus, Ricardo, the Physiocrats, Carey, Rossi, Gallatin, Wade,
Wakefield, as well as Adam Smith, et al.
Economic determinism? 17
religion which is not theirs is an invention of men, while their own is an emanation
of God ... Thus there has been history, but there is no longer any. (1976: 175 n. 35
citing MECW 6.174, my emphasis) 32
Marx, whose knowledge of the classics of Greece and Rome and of
medieval history was absolutely extraordinary (Prawer 1976, Lekas 1988:
55-56, McCarthy 1990) peppers the text of Capital and his Grundrisse with
contrasts between fundamental aspects of capitalism and those of earlier
societies. Contrasting, for example, the mystification oflabor embedded in
capitalist commodities, he points to medieval Europe: "The corvee can be
measured by time just as well as the labour which produces commodities,
but every serf knows that what he expends in the service of his lord is a
specific quantity of his own personal labour-power" (1976: 170). In the
Grundrisse, for example, he is at pains to historicize the category of money:
This very simple category, then, makes a historic appearance in its full intensity
only in the most developed conditions of society. By no means does it wade its
way through all economic relations. For example, in the Roman Empire, at its
highest point of development, the foundation remained taxes and payments in
kind. (1973: 103)
The whole burden of his critique of "bourgeois" political economy is that
it, not he, imposes on the past its own historically contingent categories of
analysis, that his own goal is precisely to appreciate the historical specificities
of the capitalist mode of production by contrast with a wide-range of pre-
capitalist social formations.
ECONOMIC DETERMINISM?
32 This last comment eerily anticipates Francis Fukuyama's The End ofHistory and the Last Man (1992).
33 Giddens in 1971 wrote: "This [Marx's use of the term "materialism"] definitely does not involve the
application of a deterministic philosophical materialism to the interpretation of the development of
society. Human consciousness is conditioned in dialectical interplay between subject and object, in
which man actively shapes the world he lives in at the same time as it shapes him" (21). Yet in 1981
he wrote: "If by 'historical materialism' we mean the conception that the history of human societies
can be understood in terms of the progressive augmentation of the forces of production, then it
is based on false premises, and the time has come to finally abandon it. If historical materialism
means that 'the history of all hitherto existing society is the history of class struggles', it is so patently
erroneous that it is difficult to see why so many have felt obliged to take it seriously" (1-2). He,
however, lays the foundation for his later "third way" with this sop for Marxists: "If Marx's project
be regarded as the furthering, through the conjunction of social analysis and political activity, of
18 Theoretical comideratiom
Quite apart from those ready to dismiss Marx on the basis of second-hand
Cold War assessments, this issue is still hotly debated within Marxism.
Reading over the famous essay on "Contradiction and Overdetermina-
tion" (in Althusser 1969) and the long, Althusser-inspired discussion of the
issue by Wolff and Resnick (1987: 38-108 and passim) - the fullest of which
I am aware - I am struck by what seems to me the impossibility of any
straightforward resolution of the issue. It seems to me that there is a strong
tension in Marx's own words throughout his life between a polemical insis-
tence on the priority of the economic sphere and his nuanced appreciation
of the impact of political, cultural, and ideological elements upon the func-
tioning of what may only analytically be isolated as "economic" elements.
The earliest version is from The German Ideology of 1845-47:
The premises from which we begin are not arbitrary ones, not dogmas, but real
premises from which abstraction can only be made in the imagination. They are
the real individuals, their activity and the conditions of their life, both those which
they find already existing and those produced by their activity. (MECW 5: 31)
He goes on to specify "producing the means of subsistence." But even here
there is room for emphasizing the potential range of what those "conditions
of their lives" include and a strong emphasis on the dialectical interaction
of inherited conditions and potentially transforming human activity. The
mature Marx of Capital I (1867) - the only "real" Marx for Althusser -
still speaks of the "economic law of motion of modern society" (1976: 92,
my emphasis), though he is at pains in his second preface to insist that
economic "laws" are fundamentally different for different historical epochs
(1976: 100-102) and, being historically contingent, are thus fundamentally
different from the laws of nature. The Critique of the Gotha Program
(1875) and the famous posthumously published fragment from Book III
of Capital on the "Realm of Necessity and the Realm of Freedom" are
primarily focused on economic issues. 34
At the same time, for all the obvious appeal to Marx of metaphors from
the hard sciences ("laws of motion," etc.) and his strong polemical sense
of the neglected role of material production, of class, and of the relations
of production, his analyses of concrete historical situations (e.g., The Class
Struggles in France (1848-49), The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Napoleon
forms of human society in which the mass of human beings can attain freedoms and modes of
self-realization in excess of any they may have enjoyed before, who can dissent from it? Certainly I
do not" (24-5). Divorcing Marxist social analysis and activism from a focus on modes of production
and class struggle is a nice trick. See below on the postmodern dismissal of Marx.
34 These late texts, not published before the project of MECW collapsed, are perhaps most easily found
in the Tucker anthology (Marx-Engels 1978: 525-41, 439-42).
Base and superstructure 19
(1851-52), The Civil War in France (1870-71) display a highly nuanced sense
of the mutual interplay of a whole host of "determinations." Indeed, at the
outset of the Grundrisse, in discussing the method of political economy, he
counterposes to its false procedures "a rich totality of many determinations
and relations" (1973: rno).
Let us look briefly at the key passage by Marx which he himself cites in his
refutation (quoted above) of the charge that his approach is only relevant to
the capitalist era. In the Introduction to his 1859 book, A Contribution to the
Critique ofPolitical Economy, Marx offered in summary form an account
of his study of political economy and, most famously or notoriously,
the general conclusion at which I arrived and which, once reached, became the
guiding principle of my studies ... In the social production of their existence,
men inevitably enter into definite relations, which are independent of their will,
namely relations of production appropriate to a given stage in the development of
their material forces of production. The totality of these relations of production
constitutes the economic structure, the real foundation, on which arises a legal
and political superstructure and to which correspond definite forms of social
consciousness. The mode of production of material life conditions the general
process of social, political and intellectual life. It is not the consciousness of men
that determines their existence, but their social existence that determines their
consciousness. (MECW 29: 262-3)
culture in and for itself, but also in relation to its outside, its content, its context, and its space of
intervention and of effectivity. How one does that, however, is never given in advance." This is not to
deny that sociological approaches such as Bryant's (1996) consider this relationship and occasionally
offer useful insights that go beyond simple refl.ectionism, but there is a residual Hegelianism in the
priority that Bryant grants to ideas ("moral codes," "the 'Spirit' of Hellenism," etc.).
37 The term "social formation" rather than "society" is warmly endorsed by Finley (1983b: 21) who
takes it from Perry Anderson (1974: 22 n. 6), who takes it from Poulantzas (1978: 15-16 [French
edition 1968]), both of whom explicitly define themselves as Marxists. In those authors the term
social formation emphasizes that any mode of production entails some combination of different
modes in which one mode is dominant. Thus, for example, in antiquity independent small farmer
production continued alongside production in which slaves were decisive. At a certain point (to be
explored below) the impact of slave production on other aspects of the social totality is such that it
can reasonably be called dominant in the mode of production.
38 In this context I especially like Bruce Trigger's distinction between "constraints" and "determinants"
(1991: 555-61).
Base and superstructure 21
In order to survive, a society must produce a sufficiency; in order to cre-
ate a culture, it must produce a surplus, as Engels explained long ago"
(Murray 1990: 3). Walter Burkert, clearly no Marxist, takes for granted in
an almost "vulgar Marxist" way the obvious relevance of beginning with
the economic and technological base and moving from there to a polit-
ical and economic superstructure: "The economic base for the advance
in the third millennium was the intensified cultivation of the olive and
vine, which moved the centre of gravity from the fertile plains of northern
Greece to the mountain slopes of southern Greece and the islands; at the
same time, the art of metal-working arrived from the East. Both innova-
tions demanded and strengthened a central organization of exchange and
political administration" (1985: 20).
Marx does go on to speak of "determination" apropos of consciousness
in a polemically anti-Hegelian formulation, "It is not the consciousness
of men that determines (bestimmt) their existence, but their social exis-
tence that determines their consciousness" (ibid.). This formulation is an
emphatic repudiation of what was at the time the dominant Hegelian model
stressing the priority of ideas and consciousness over specific historical real-
ities. But a clearer version of Marx's conception of the relation of material
conditions to historical developments is the more dialectical formulation
in his Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Napoleon (1852), "Human beings (die
Memchen) make their own history, but they do not make it just as they
please; they do not make it under circumstances chosen by themselves, but
under circumstances directly encountered, given and transmitted from the
past" (MECW 11: 103). These "circumstances" are never conceived of by
Marx as solely "economic."
Engels, in a much-discussed late letter (1890) attempts to counter the
charge of simple economic determinism by what many have seen as a series
of equivocations: ''According to the materialist conception of history, the
ultimately determining element in history is the production and reproduc-
tion of real life. More than this neither Marx nor I have ever asserted.
Hence if somebody twists this into saying that the economic element is
the only determining one he transforms that proposition into a meaning-
less, abstract, senseless phrase." Echoing the passage of Marx on base and
superstructure quoted above, he continues:
The economic situation is the basis, but the various elements of the superstructure-
political forms of the class struggle and its results, to wit: constitutions established
by the victorious class after a successful battle, etc., juridical forms - and even
reflexes of all these actual struggles in the brains of the participants, political,
22 Theoretical comideratiom
juristic, philosophical theories, religious views, and their further development into
systems of dogmas - also exercise their influence upon the course of the historical
struggles and in many cases preponderate in determining their form. (Marx-Engels
1978: 760-65, emphasis in the original}
What these gentlemen [sc. the simple economic determinists and those who accuse
Marxism of mechanical determinism] all lack is dialectics. They always see only
here cause, there effect. That this is a hollow abstraction, that such metaphysical
polar opposites exist in the real world only during crises, while the whole vast
process goes on in the form of interaction - though of very unequal forces, the
economic movement being by far the strongest, most primeval, most decisive -
that here everything is relative and nothing absolute - this they never begin to see.
Hegel has never existed for them. (Marx-Engels 1978: 765)
What differentiates Marx's approach from the vast majority of his critics is a
radically different and dialectical epistemological position, nicely summa-
rized by Giddens in his more sympathetic phase: "Human consciousness is
conditioned in dialectical interplay between subject and object, in which
man actively shapes the world he lives in at the same time that it shapes him"
(Giddens 1971: 21). This epistemological position precludes the simple cause
and effect analyses of traditional empiricism, but it does not - cannot -
predict the specific weight of any given factor in a specific historical devel-
opment, which can only emerge from a concrete analysis. Thus "economic
determinism" in Engels's formulation seems to emerge as both "sometimes
yes, sometimes no" ("everything is relative") and somehow "ultimately" a
stronger element in the interplay of various other determinants. But for
those readers looking for straightforward "causes" impacting on a passive
society of human beings, readers committed to an empiricist cause-and-
effect determinism, no dialectical explanation will ever prove satisfactory:
Base and superstructure 23
hence my initial pessimistic declaration that no "straightforward" solution
to the "economic determinist" debate is possible. 39
Althusser's brilliant critique of Engels's letter attacks precisely the notion
of the "ultimate" - or in his translation of the letter "the last instance" -
status of the economic. In a famous line he argues, "the lonely hour of the
'last instance' never comes" (1969: 113). His alternative, "overdetermina-
tion," a term drawn from Freud's analysis of dream elements, stresses that
the economic contradictions of a society never operate in any independent
or straightforwardly determining way but interact "dialectically" with a
whole array of other factors. What seems to disappear in this otherwise
compelling analysis is any specific analytic value to a focus on class, the
mode of production, and its relations of production.
Resnick and Wolff, inspired by Althusser, offer their own dense formu-
lation of overdetermination as the path out of determinism:
Marxian theory ... is motivated by, focused upon, and aims at an ever deeper
knowledge of a selected subset among the many aspects of the social totality. These
are economic aspects and, in particular, the class processes and their interrelations
within the social totality ... This knowledge aims to specify both how the class
relations it designates as its objects are overdetermined by the nonclass aspects of the
social totality and how these class relations participate in the overdetermination of
those nonclass aspects. This knowledge aims, by means of exactly this specification,
to determine the contradictions in those class relations and the dynamic motion
that those contradictions produce. (Resnick and Wolff 1987: 96-7)
39 Nicolaus (1973: 26--36 and passim) offers a particularly succinct distillation of Hegel's relation to
Marx, a topic scattered through virtually every serious account of Marx (e.g., McLellan 1973, whose
index has thirty-six references to Hegel, mostly with an 'f."). Marcuse's major engagement with
Hegel's philosophy (1960: 3-248) aims "to elucidate those implications of Hegel's ideas that identify
them closely with the later developments in European thought, particularly with the Marxian
theory" (xv). F. Jameson 2009 devotes more than a hundred very heavy pages (3-123) to a defense
of Hegel's dialectic as an essential prerequisite to grasping Marx's use of dialectic.
24 Theoretical comideratiom
on the economic side vis-a-vis our adversaries, who denied it ... " (Marx-
Engels 1978: 762). While few today would actually "deny" the economic
aspects of ancient society, I am struck by the degree to which so many
classical scholars still appear anxious to minimize their importance. 40 As
indicated earlier, in the following text I will try in passing to pinpoint
the rhetorical strategies by which classical scholars have shied away from
concepts of class and class struggle - even when their own analysis points
inexorably in that direction.
4° Finley, in the introduction to the collection he edited on landed property in Greece, remarks
sarcastically on "the curious predilection of students of classical antiquity for not studying in depth
some of the most fundamental aspects of ancient society" (1973b: 9). Seaford, in his dazzling review
of Kurke 1999, points to precisely this gaping lacuna in her elaborate exploration of ideological
struggles in the Archaic Period (Seaford 2002: 158---59). It is symptomatic of J. Hall's gingerly
handling of economic aspects of Greece in the Archaic Period that he takes up the topic of "Making
a Living" in the tenth of his twelve chapters (2007: 235-54), focusing on the issues of peasantry,
trade, and coinage.
41 Marx admittedly used the term in more than one sense, but each sense is compatible with the others
and I believe compatible with the sense in which I use it here. G. A. Cohen (1978: 79-84) offers an
elaborate overview of these different senses.
42 Mann (1986: 185) rightly stresses the difference between rain-watered soils and those of Mesopotamia,
but it is unclear to what extent the shift to iron led to dramatic increases in agriculture: Hesiod,
some two to three hundred years after the introduction of iron to Greece (Snodgrass 1971: 217-
22) still urges on his audience a plow made entirely of wood - as did Thomas Jefferson in 1795
(see discussion in Chapter 4). In defining class relations, can we really say with Mann, "iron plowers
Comcious and uncomcious determinants 25
changes during this period - some, as we shall see, still hotly debated,
such as a gradual shift in emphasis from herding to more intensive agri-
culture, the use of fallow fields vs. more intensive manuring, long-term
deforestation or erosion - were probably not consciously or only dimly
perceived by the producers even as their very engagement in productive
activity impacts upon and eventually transforms their environment. 43 It is
at least debatable how conscious Greeks were of the gradual change from
bronze to iron tools. At the same time, every one involved in and affected
by production must have been acutely aware of who controlled what sort
of productive land and how much land, and what specific crops, were
possible and desirable. This ongoing tension of conscious and unconscious
factors central to Marxist approaches is often ostensibly endorsed by cit-
ing with approval Marx's dictum quoted earlier, that "people make history
but not under conditions of their own choosing," but immediately these
authors are at pains to emphasize "knowledgeable agents" (e.g., Giddens
1981: 16). 44 At the same time, while revolutionary changes in the economic
base may occur with striking and devastating rapidity - as for example
the destruction of the whole Mycenaean redistributive system 45 - Marx
insists that it is in "the legal, political, religious, artistic or philosophic - in
short, ideological forms [that] men become conscious of this conflict and
fight it out" 46 (MECW 29: 203, my emphasis). This emphasis on the more
restrained aristocrats by a loose, communal, and even democratic structure of power" (Mann 1986:
197)? I find it amusing that Mann describes his initial inspiration as the desire to "refute Karl Marx
and reorganize Max Weber" (vii) but ends up offering a most mechanical technologism to explain
historical change. The idea of iron's democratizing potential originates, as far as I know, with the
Marxist archaeologist Gordon Childe (e.g., 1954: 191) and proved unduly optimistic.
4l Many have commented, for example, on the gradual deforestation of Greece as a consequence not
only of the conscious act of cutting down trees but of raising goats - probably without registering
consciously that the goats ate the new trees' shoots and thus precluded natural reforestation (e.g.,
Osborne 2009: 22).
44 I. Morris even goes so far as to endorse Stedman Jones's triumphalist dismissal of Marx, "Marx
famously observed ... that 'Men make their own history, but they do not make it under circum-
stances chosen by themselves, etc... : The great contribution of cultural historians like Stedman
Jones lies in showing how often people have made history as they pleased, with discursive forces"
(Morris 2000: 16). Stedman-Jones ends his article by calling for clearing away "the unsorted debris
left by the death of Marxism" (1996: 33). As Niall McKeown points out, "few theories have had their
death announced quite so often as Marxism" (1999: 103).
45 I am of course using the word "revolutionary" here as Marx usually does in the sense of fundamental
structural change, which may be very rapid or in some cases may take centuries (e.g., the agricultural
"revolution"). I do not mean to imply that the end of the Mycenaean period was the consequence
of a specific political revolution (see Chapter 1).
46 Marx's sense of the power of ideas is well illustrated in one of his earliest published texts: "The weapon
of criticism cannot, of course, replace criticism by weapons, material force must be overthrown by
material force; but theory also becomes a material force as soon as it has gripped the masses"
(MECW 3: 182). "As philosophy finds its material weapons in the proletariat, so the proletariat finds
Theoretical comideratiom
its spiritual weapons in philosophy. And once the lightning of thought has squarely struck this
ingenuous soil of the people the emancipation of the Germans into human being.r will take place"
(ibid. 187, emphasis in original).
47 I find it rather ironic that people who have read very little or no Marx are quick to dismiss him as an
"economic determinist," but feel very comfortable in appealing to Weber, who so much more justly
fits the label: "The Puritan wanted to work in a calling; we are forced to do so. For when asceticism
was carried out of monastic cells into everyday life, and began to dominate worldly morality, it did
its part in building the tremendous cosmos ofthe modern economic order. This order is now bound to
the technical and economic conditions of machine production which today determine the lives ofall
individuals who are born into this mechanism, not only those directly concerned with economic
acquisition, with irresistible force. Perhaps it will so determine them until the last ton of fossilized
coal is burnt. In Baxter's [a seventeenth-century Presbyterian writer on Puritan ethics] view the care
for external goods should only lie on the shoulders of the 'saint like a light cloak, which can be
thrown aside at any moment'. But fate decreed that the cloak should become an iron cage" (Weber
1958: 181, my emphasis) .
.S As noted earlier F. Jameson 2009 (210-14) focuses on the postmodern critique of precisely this
aspiration to totality; see also below. Postmodernist theorists who passionately denounce the existence
of"extra-discursive domains" (e.g., Stedman Jones 1996: 30) seem to ignore as well a whole range of
unconscious behaviors and developments. Stedman Jones grudgingly acknowledges that phenomena
like urbanization or population growth "far exceeded what could be grasped by an examination of
individual intentions" (27-8), but instead of seriously theorizing such phenomena he simply returns
to his diatribe against Foucault.
49 Here I fully agree with Finley: "we have the right to study such economies, to pose ques-
tions about their society that the ancients themselves never thought of" (197µ: 23). Marx,
of course, went further and argued that only the historical process makes some key analytic
Separating out the economic 27
Any analysis of the past that is to be relevant to our era is bound to pose
the questions that are meaningful to our era whether or not they attracted
the attention of the periods under consideration. The alternative, after all,
is to take the past at its own word. 50 More specifically Marx attacked the
readiness of Hegelian historians - and they are still around 5' - to
detach the ideas of the ruling class from the ruling class itself and attribute to
them an independent existence ... If we thus ignore the individuals and world
conditions which are the source of the ideas, then we can say, for instance, that
during the time the aristocracy was dominant, the concepts of honor, loyalty,
etc., were dominant ... Once the ruling ideas have been separated from the ruling
individuals and, above all, from the relations which result from a given stage of
the mode of production ... it is very easy to abstract from these various ideas 'the
Idea', the thought, etc., as the dominant force in history ... Whilst in ordinary life
every shopkeeper is very well able to distinguish between what somebody professes
to be and what he really is, our historiography has not yet won this trivial insight.
It takes every epoch at its word and believes that everything it says and imagines
about itself is true. (MECW 5: 60-62)
concepts - e.g., the concept of labor in general as opposed to specific types of labor, or the
concept of value - available. He cites Aristotle repeatedly in this connection, e.g.: "Aristotle there-
fore himself tells us what prevented any further analysis: the lack of a concept of value ... The secret
of the expression of value, namely the equality and equivalence of all kinds of labour and because
in so far as they are human labour in general, could not be deciphered until the concept of human
equality had already acquired the permanence of a fixed popular opinion. This however becomes
possible only in a society where the commodity-form is the universal form of the product of labour,
hence the dominant social relation between men as possessors of commodities. Aristotle's genius is
displayed precisely by his discovery of a relation of equality in the value-expression of commodities.
Only the historical limitation inherent in the society in which he lived prevented him from finding
out what 'in reality' this relation of equality consisted of' (Marx 1976: 151-2). The passage is also a
good example of Marx's conception of the intimate but not mechanically determinist relationship
between a mode of production and the production of concepts (c£ his more elaborate comments
in the Grundrisse 1973: 103--6). Polanyi, without mentioning Marx, is clearly following his lead in
his focus on Aristotle (1968: 17-18, c£ 78---n5).
50 J. Hall's normative dictum that "it should be the specific character of the available evidence rather
than the theoretical or ideological preferences of the historian that dictate the most appropriate
method to apply to a body of material" (2007: 287) is on one level merely common sense: one
cannot, as he well argues, build an account around a series of events if there are virtually no reliably
attested events. But on another level Hall comes perilously close to falling back on the empiricist
delusion that the data speak for themselves. At the same time he himself in fact eloquently defends
the use of anthropological theoretical models to make plausible reconstructions from very partial
data (e.g., 2007: 283).
51 I. Morris 2000 struck me as peculiarly "Hegelian" in the sense that he repeatedly gives priority to his
alleged concept of to meson. He claims, for example, "to meson . .. provided the values which made
democracy thinkable. To understand Greek democracy, we must first understand this worldview"
(2000: n3). This appears at least to dismiss both politics and economics as relevant contributing
factors, considerations of which are largely absent throughout Morris's text, which bizarrely, in my
view, projects the middling ideology back into the early Iron Age. To be sure, I also suggest that
the origins of democracy might be seen in a putative egalitarian, meritocratic phase of the early Iron
Age. But one would still need to account for the emergence of a whole array of social, political, and
economic factors countering that phase. Moreover, such a phase is at best one possible inference
from the spotty archaeological record (see discussion in Chapter 1).
Theoretical comideratiom
This is not to deny that discourses construct versions of reality. But their
power in context does not exempt them from critical testing in the light of
material realities they are often designed to obscure.
The second analytic problem is a consequence of separating out for anal-
ysis any aspect of what one recognizes as a complex totality, which of course
any human society is. While Marx unquestionably placed heavy emphasis
on material production, even in the first early sketch of his overall concep-
tion of society and history, the German Ideology (1845-47), he is careful to
insist that what he sets out analytically first among three "premises of all
human existence" is not temporally separate from the other two: "These
three aspects of social activity are not of course to be taken as three different
stages, but just as three aspects . .. which have existed simultaneously since the
dawn of history and the first men, and which assert themselves in history
today" (MECW 5: 41-43, my emphasis). Yet even a generally sympathetic
critic of Marx can cite the first sentences of this section of the German Ide-
ology to indict Marx for granting primacy to the economic: "Experience is
first of all, and always primarily, the production of necessities: 'life involves
before everything else eating and drinking, a habitation, clothing and many
other things. The first historical act is thus the production of the means
to satisfy these needs, the production of material life itself'" (Sahlins 1976:
140, his emphasis). The analytically first premise is transformed by Sahlins's
context and emphasis into an absolute and temporal priority. Sahlins fails
to point out that the second premise "that the satisfaction of the first need,
the action of satisfying and the instrument of satisfaction which has been
acquired, leads to new needs" is also called by Marx "the first historical act"
(loc. cit.). Moreover, the third premise, sexual reproduction and the family,
has obviously just as clear a claim analytically to "priority'' as a premise of
human existence.
Sahlins, like Finley (as noted above), Donlan, I. Morris, and many others,
was heavily influenced by Polanyi's notion of an "embedded" economy
(Tandy and Neale 1994: 16) and seems to consider the embeddedness of an
economy to constitute a ground for dismissal of Marx. Yet no less a figure
than Levi-Strauss rightly defended Marx and Engels's clear understanding
of this phenomenon:
Actually Marx and Engels frequently express the idea that primitive, or allegedly
primitive, societies are governed by 'blood ties' (which today we call kinship
systems) and not by economic relationships ... The temporal category applicable
to them has nothing to do with the one we employ to understand the development
of our own society. Nor does this conception contradict in the least the famous
dictum of the Communist Manifesto that 'the history of all hitherto existing society
Foucault and the limits ofoverdetermination 29
is the history of class struggles.' In the light of Hegel's philosophy of the state, this
dictum does not mean that the class struggle is co-extensive with humanity, but
that the ideas of history and society can be applied, in the full sense which Marx
gives them, only from the time when the class struggle first appeared. (1967: 333) 52
52 Elsewhere in the same text Levi-Strauss comments bitterly in response to a critic named Jacques
Revel, "Marx and Engels knew incomparably more anthropology almost a hundred years ago than
Revel knows today" (1967: 336).
53 In a 1983 interview Foucault declares categorically, "I have never been a Freudian, I have never
been a Marxist, and I have never been a structuralist" (1988: 22). James Miller notes apropos of
Althusser: "He nevertheless proved to be a spellbinding teacher, a quality that helped him recruit
an unprecedented number of normaliens [i.e., his students at the Ecole Normale Superieure],
including Foucault, into the Communist Party." He goes on to quote a comment by Foucault:
"In the immediate postwar period the Communist Party exercised ... a triple legitimacy: historical,
political, and theoretical. .. Over anyone who pretended to be on the left, it 'laid down the law'.
One was either for, or against; an ally, or an adversary" (Miller 1993: 57).
54 I well understand that this apparent dismissal of Foucault constitutes a heresy. Robin Osborne, for
example, in his introduction to a collection of papers from Past and Present, writes: "This volume
records the impact made, directly or indirectly, upon Greek and Roman history by the work of
Michel Foucault ... It is Foucault's more general influence on the field that is at issue here. That
influence stems from his perception that all social relations are power relations" (Osborne 2004:
2). First of all it strikes me that only a group of scholars who have never troubled to read Marx
seriously would be surprised to learn that "all social relations are power relations": this is implicit and
explicit in all of Marx's analyses of relations of production. But as F. Jameson has argued apropos
of Foucault, "For Marxism, indeed, the categories of power are not the ultimate ones, and the
trajectory of contemporary social theory (from Weber to Foucault) suggests that the appeal to it is
often strategic and involves a systematic displacement of the Marxian problematic. No, the ultimate
form of the 'nightmare of history' is rather the fact of labor itself, the intolerable spectacle of the
backbreaking millennial toil of millions of people from the earliest moments of human history.
The more existential versions of this dizzying and properly unthinkable, unimaginable spectacle -
as in horror at the endless succession of 'dying generations,' at the ceaseless wheel of life, or at the
irrevocable passage of Time itself - are themselves only disguises for this ultimately scandalous fact
of mindless alienated work and the irremediable loss and waste of human energies, a scandal to
which no metaphysical categories can give meaning. The scandal is everywhere known, everywhere
repressed - un secret de tous connu" Qameson 1988c: II 162).
30 Theoretical comideratiom
obeying certain rules ... It is not an interpretative discipline" (1972: 138-9,
his emphasis). He declares, "In our time history aspires to the condition
of archaeology, to the intrinsic description of the monument" (1972: 7, my
emphasis). 55 Foucault's notion of "description" presupposes the immense
glut of data from or about all levels of society surviving from the seventeenth
century to the present. At the same time his emphasis on "discontinuity"
seems to displace or at least defer the question of explanation.5 6 Lemert and
Gillen are at pains to warn us against seeing Archaeology ofKnowledge "as
Foucault's methodological program" (1982: 48) and point out that "most
of its vocabulary disappears thereafter" (ibid.: 55-6). To be sure, at other
times Foucault's model seems to be a Nietzschean "genealogy'': "One has
to dispense with the constituent subject, to get rid of the subject itself,
that's to say, to arrive at an analysis which can account for the constitution
of the subject within an historical framework. And this is what I would
call genealogy, that is, a form of history which can account for the consti-
tution of knowledges, discourses, domains of objects, etc., without having
to make reference to a subject which is either transcendental in relation to
the field of events or runs in its empty sameness throughout the course of
history" (1980: 117, cf. 1977: 139-64).
At the same time Foucault's thought is so permeated with Marxist
thought, with which he is in a more or less constant polemical dialogue,
that it would take at least a book-length study (e.g., Poster 1984, 1989, who
is a strong partisan of Foucault) to sort out what is in the spirit of Marx
and what entails a radical rejection of Marx. I will give only one exam-
ple. For all his emphasis on the centrality of discourses, repudiating the
"linguistic turn," he argues in terms very congenial to a Marxist approach:
"I believe one's point of reference should not be to the great model of
language (langue) and signs, but to that of war and battle. The history
which bears and determines us has the form of war rather than that of
55 I found quite amusing Stedman Jones's ferocious denunciation of Foucault's residual Marxism
(1996), cited with apparent enthusiasm by I. Morris (2000: 15-16), who nonetheless returns to a
more "Marxist" position by citing a study ofland distribution and invoking Geertz's "hard surfaces''
(16--17). Stedman Jones, as noted earlier, is scarcely the first or doubtless the last to proclaim
triumphantly "the death of Marxism" (1996: 33).
56 In the famous interview entitled "Truth and Power" Foucault expresses his shock and annoyance at
being characterized as "a philosopher who founds his theory of history on discontinuity." Offering a
sophisticated account of a "whole new 'regime' in discourse and forms of knowledge," he argues, "it
was these different regimes that I tried to identify and describe in The Order of Thing.r, all the while
making clear that I wasn't trying for the moment to explain them, and that it would be necessary to
try to do this in a subsequent work" (1980: n1-13, my emphasis). Yet he did not, as far as I know,
write this subsequent work of explanation. Nonetheless he does hint at various points that the needs
of capitalism required new regimes of medical practice, discipline, and sexuality.
The postmodern dismissal ofMarx 31
language: relations of power, not relations of meaning" (1980: 114). Later
in the same interview he returns to the idea of war only to distance himself
from unthinking Marxist invocations of "class struggle": "it's astonishing to
see how easily and self-evidently people talk of war-like relations of power
and class struggle without ever making it clear whether some form of war
is meant, and if so what form" (ibid. 123). Still later in the same interview,
asked about the role of intellectuals, he argues in favor of abandoning
a "universal" focus and concentrating struggles "within specific sectors,
at the precise points where their own conditions of life or work situate
them ... They have met with problems that are specific, 'non-universal',
and often different from those of the proletariat or the masses. And yet
I believe intellectuals have actually been drawn closer to the proletariat
and the masses, for two reasons. Firstly, because it has been a question of
real, material, everyday struggles, and secondly, because they have often
been confronted, albeit in different form, by the same adversary as the
proletariat, namely, the multinational corporations, the judicial and police
apparatuses, the property speculators, etc." (ibid. 126).
In dealing with the Archaic Age, and especially with its immediate
antecedents, the evidence is so sparse, fragmentary, and ambiguous, that it
is perhaps impossible to talk of "explanation" but rather what one hopes are
not completely implausible conjectures that do not violate that evidence.
Yet the kind of "archaeology" of knowledge advocated by Foucault (e.g.,
1970, 1972) - for all its appeal to a "post-structuralist" sensibility - entails
a fundamental break with the notion of historiography as explanation
and comes perilously close - for all its sophisticated theorization - to
Henry Ford's vision of history as "just one damned thing [or episteme]
after another."57 While the injunction to avoid superficial totalizations is
salutary, to me a conception of history as the deployment of the "space of
a dispersion" (Foucault 1972: rn) is not enough.
While there is a very full and complex body of work - much of it also
inspired by Althusser - that defines itself as "postmodern Marxism" (e.g.,
Resnick and Wolff 1987, Callari et al. 1995, Kellner 1989a), Foucault
Lyotard is, after all, writing in the wake of a certain French "post-Marxism,"
that is, an enormous reaction on all levels against various Marxist and Commu-
nist traditions in France, whose prime target on the philosophical level is the
Hegel/Lukacs concept of 'totality' (often overhastily assimilated to Stalinism or
even to the Leninist party on the political level). (F. Jameson 1984b: x)
I wanted to ask questions. At every step, I would have liked to have had a long
discussion with him and his friends and asked them to respond to questions I
felt necessary. The fact is - as strange as it might seem - this discussion never
took place. And yet we lived in the same "house," where we were colleagues for
twenty years and his students, and friends were often, in another context, mine.
Everything took place underground, in the said of the unsaid. It's part of the
French scene and is not simply anecdotal. (2002: 158)
59 Derrida (2002: 164), tells chis damning anecdote about Alchusser and the Party in 1956: "With the
repression in Hungary in 1956, some of chose communist intellectuals began to leave the Party.
Gerard Genette, who was a Party member until 1956, told me chat he went to see Alchusser after the
Hungarian revolc to impart his distress, anguish, reasons, and probably to ask his advice. Alchusser
supposedly told him: 'But if what you say were true, then the Party would be wrong!' This seemed
to Alchusser to be precluded, and he proceeded to demonstrate ad absurdum chat what Genette was
saying needed to be corrected." J.-P. Vernant, who fought in the Resistance and had been a member
of the Jeunes Communistes, also left the Party at chis point (personal conversation).
60 I base chis in part on many conversations over many years with pupils of Derrida. It is striking chat
in Peggy Kamuf's Derrida Reader (1991) of more than 600 pages, there is one footnote reference to
Marx (481 n. 14), where he is lumped with Socrates, Descartes and Freud as a seeker after "truth."
Michael Ryan's heroic effort to fuse Marxism and Deconstruction (1982) notes chat "in early texts he
[Derrida] suggests chat Marxism itself is subject to deconstruction, chat it belongs to the metaphysics
of presence" and traces a gradual process by which Derrida expressed more sympathy for Marx.
Spivak in two extremely difficult essays (1984 and 1993) explores some grounds for parallels. In the
earlier essay she cites an interview from 1980 in which Derrida declares "though I am not and have
never been an orthodox Marxist, I am very disturbed by the antimarxism dominant now in France
so chat, as a reaction, through political reflection and personal preference, I am inclined to consider
myself more Marxist than I would have done at a time when Marxism was a sort of fortress" (Spivak
1984: 245 n. 14). This last phrase of course alludes to the dominant role of the French Communist
Party in the years following the end of World War II. Poster (1975: 36-41) underlines both the
post-war prestige of the Party due to its wartime role in the Resistance and its positivistic "scientific"
and Stalinist orientation.
34 Theoretical comideratiom
a fault not to read and reread and discuss Marx - which is to say also a
few others - and to go beyond scholarly 'reading' or 'discussion'. It will be
more and more a fault, a failing of theoretical, philosophical, and political
responsibility" (1994: 13). Was this a sincere change of position, or was
this perhaps only said in the confidence that Marx's "grand narrative" and
insistence on the primacy of production will be easily recognized as the
illusions of an era safely dismantled by floating signifiers, absent centers,
chains of arbitrary contingencies, and the irreducible plurality of struggles?
Whatever Derrida's own final position was on the relevance of Marx as
an analytical approach, the political influence of deconstruction is most
obvious perhaps in the work of Ernesto Laclau and Chantal Mouffe (1985).
They describe their project with a rhetorical question:
Why should we broach this task through a critique and a deconstruction of the
various discursive surfaces of classical Marxism? Let us first say that there is not
one discourse and one system of categories through which the "real" might speak
without mediations. In operating deconstructively within Marxist categories, we
do not claim to be writing "universal history," to be inscribing our discourse as
a moment of a single, linear process of knowledge. Just as the era of normative
epistemologies has come to an end, so too has the era of universal discourses. (1985:
3, my emphasis)
Their intentions, like those of Anthony Giddens with his "third way"
(1998), are admirably directed toward bringing about a better form of
society on the assumption that Soviet Marxism, which is so often mis-
leadingly described as "classical Marxism," was so total a failure 61 that
virtually nothing beyond a vaguely conceived project of human liberation
is worth salvaging from the vast body of Marx's work, while accepting as
"realistic" the dominant structures of modern capitalism. As Slavoj Zizek
has rightly observed, the proponents of this dismissal of class, "as a rule,
leave out the resignation at its heart - the acceptance of capitalism as 'the
only game in town', the renunciation of any real attempt to overcome the
existing capitalist liberal regime" (Zizek 2000: 95). Subsequently he makes
perhaps the more relevant point that this very shift in perspective on class
requires historicizing: "The passage from 'essentialist' Marxism to post-
modern contingent politics (in Laclau) ... is not a simple epistemological
progress but part of the global change in the very nature of capitalist society"
61 The brilliant work of Boris Kagarlitsky (e.g., 1988, 1995, 1999, 2002), who was jailed under Brezhnev
for "anti-Soviet" activities, as well as under Yeltsin, offers a more balanced and complex insider's
critique and evaluation of the Soviet experience than is usually available in the West. See also
F. Jameson's thoughtful chapter on "Actually Existing Marxism" (2009: 367-409).
The Archaic Period: attempting explanation vs. radical skepticism 35
(ibid: 106). 62 Fortunately my own project does not entail charting the future
course of capitalism, which happens not to look very bright at the current
moment. But Zizek's approach has some affinity with Jameson's somewhat
different analysis, which is precisely to historicize the postmodern turn by
the application of Marx's fundamental analytical concept of the mode of
production, as is clear from his subtitle, Postmodernism, or The Cultural
Logic ofLate Capitalism (1991). It is the work of Fredric Jameson, beginning
with his Marxism and Form (1971) - primarily focused on the Frankfurt
School and Sartre - that perhaps more than any other contemporary work
has convinced me that the Marxist categories of mode of production and
class, whatever the complexities and valid questions raised about their
application to contemporary capitalism, offer viable modes of analysis for
precapitalist societies.
62 For a fuller discussion of the relation of Marxism to postmodernism see F. Jameson 1991 and 1988c,
Wood 1986, Wood and Foster 1997, Eagleton 1996a.
Another random document with
no related content on Scribd:
not in his or her “line of business.” The hero had to be given to the
“leading man” and the heroine to the “leading woman.” The villain—
and in the dramas of those distant days there was likely to be a
villain of the deepest dye—was assigned to the heavy man; while
the brisk young fellows fell to the lot of the juvenile lead or of the
light comedian. The broadly comic parts were assigned to the low
comedian; and there were frequently two of him, the first low
comedy and the second low comedy. Strongly marked characters
went to the character-actor, who had to be a master of make-up.
The elderly characters were in the hands of the old man and the old
woman; there was sometimes also a second old man, altho if the
character-actor was both versatile and obliging he could be prevailed
upon to play one of the more aged characters. The serving maids
were attributed to the singing chambermaid, who would have her
best chance when a farce or extravaganza was in the bill.
VII
II
The first actor whom I came to know was one of the most
companionable, the genial John Brougham. In 1869, as a boy I had
been present at the opening and at the closing nights of his brief
management of the little playhouse in Twenty-fourth Street, behind
the Fifth Avenue hotel—a playhouse which not long after became
the Fifth Avenue Theater of Augustin Daly and which was rebuilt as
the Madison Square Theater by Steele Mackaye. At Brougham’s I
had seen his ever-delightful burlesque, ‘Pocahontas,’ in which he
himself was the rollicking King Powhatan; and I saw also a later
burlesque of his, ‘Much Ado about a Merchant of Venice,’ in which he
was an amusing but rather Hibernian Shylock. So it was that when I
was elected to the Lotos Club, in the spring of 1871 (while I was still
an undergraduate at Columbia College) I seized the earliest
opportunity to make Brougham’s acquaintance.
He was not a great actor, that I knew already, altho he was a
competent performer; but he had a charming personality, and when
he chanced to be cast for a character with which his personality
coincided, he was entirely satisfactory. Of course he appeared to
best advantage in Irish parts, The O’Grady in Boucicault’s ‘Arrah-na-
Pogue’ and Off-lan-aghan in Lester Wallack’s ‘Veteran,’ and above all
Sir Lucius O’Trigger in Sheridan’s ‘Rivals.’ I doubt if Sir Lucius has
been more sympathetically impersonated by any performer of the
second half of the nineteenth century than it was by Brougham. I
have seen the character undertaken by W. J. Florence and by Nat
Goodwin, actors of a far more opulent equipment than Brougham,
yet neither of them succeeded so well in bringing out the
gentlemanly simplicity of this lovable character. Goodwin was too
completely an American of the nineteenth century to be able to
assume the part of an Irish gentleman of the eighteenth century;
and Florence, excellent as he was in Irish characters of another kind,
bestowed on Sir Lucius a rather finicky affectation, quite out of
keeping with the part.
In those distant days the dramatist was sadly underpaid.
Brougham told me once that his price for writing a play for a star
was three thousand dollars, payable on delivery of the manuscript, a
sum smaller than a month’s royalty on a successful play of to-day.
And yet more than one of the vehicles Brougham put together for
this modest price, ran like the One Hoss Shay. The stage-version of
the ‘Old Curiosity Shop,’ in which Lotta doubled Little Nell and the
Marchioness, must have been performed several hundred times; and
only less successful were other of the made-to-order pieces he
composed for Mr. and Mrs. Barney Williams and for Mr. and Mrs.
Florence. These last were congenial labor, since they dealt with Irish
themes, more or less in imitation of Boucicault’s more solidly built
‘Arrah-na-Pogue’ and ‘Colleen Bawn.’
Where Boucicault was dominating, not to say domineering,
Brougham was yielding and unambitious. Their early disagreement
over the authorship of ‘London Assurance’ did not prevent their
professional association in later years. When ‘Arrah-na-Pogue’ was
revived in 1873 at Booth’s Theater, Brougham played The O’Grady,
supporting Boucicault as Shaun the Post and Mrs. Boucicault as
Arrah. And when Boucicault in 1879 was strangely ill-advised to
undertake ‘Louis XI,’ in his own adaptation of the play which Casimir
Delavigne had made out of ‘Quentin Durward,’ Brougham was
Coitier; and I can testify that on this occasion the honors were
divided, or at least the laughs, for I never listened to any dialog
more ludicrous than that between a French king with a pronounced
Irish accent and a French physician with an equally persistent
brogue. These, as Beau Brummel’s valet explained, “these are our
failures.”
Brougham had his full share of Irish wit, more spontaneous than
Boucicault’s and less likely to be borrowed. He had also the more
English delight in punning. In ‘Pocahontas,’ after the opening song
Powhatan thanks his attendant braves:
Well roared, my jolly Tuscadoras!
Most loyal corps, your king encores your chorus.
And in the same burlesque when John Smith is tied down and
about to be put to death, Pocahontas rushes in, crying, “For my
husband I scream!” Whereupon the endangered hero raises his head
and inquires “Lemon or vanilla?”
These be but airy trifles floating like bubbles atop the dark wave
of forgetfulness, which has engulfed many things far more precious.
An airy trifle also is Brougham’s remark when Pat Hearn (a once
notorious gambler) drove past the Ocean House at Newport one
summer afternoon with a very pretty woman by his side. “Isn’t that
Pat Hearn and his wife?” somebody asked; and Brougham replied at
once, “That’s Hearn, I know; but I can’t say whether or not she is
his’n.”
III
It was also at the Lotos that I got to know John T. Raymond. This
was probably in the fall of 1874, when he was appearing as Colonel
Sellers in Mark Twain’s ‘Gilded Age.’ The actor and the author
quarreled after a while, quarreled bitterly and never made up their
quarrel. No doubt, Mark knew his own creature better than any one
else and certainly better than the rather shallow Raymond. But
Raymond gave us at least all the external characteristics of the
inspired visionary with his inexpugnable optimism, always about to
acquire wealth beyond the dreams of avarice and yet for the
moment reduced to a frugal dinner of turnips and water, with only a
candle to light up his modest store. I have an impression that the
cause of the breach with Mark was Raymond’s unwillingness to
forego two or three easy effects which were always rewarded with
thoughtless laughter but which were not really in keeping with the
character. Raymond was unduly inclined to skylark even on the
stage; I have seen him, in the last act of the ‘Gilded Age,’ match
silver dollars with a friend he had recognized in the audience. Of
course, he chose a moment for the flip of his coin when the
attention of the spectators was bestowed upon some other
performer, and only a few of them detected his inexcusable
pantomime. These lapses from the standard of propriety may not
have been frequent, but they occurred far too often; and they could
not but be offensive to the author of the play in which the actor was
appearing.
When Raymond indulged in tricks of this sort he displayed a lack
of respect alike for his audience and for his art. The art had to suffer
in silence; but the audience might at any time be moved to protest. I
recall that when Raymond was playing Ichabod Crane in 1879 he
sent me a box, to which my wife invited three or four of her young
friends. In the last act Ichabod comes out into the garden to ask
Katrina into the house, where there was merrymaking. To the
startled astonishment of our party, Raymond said “Come on in,
Katrina! There’s lots of fun! Brander Matthews has brought a whole
boxful of pretty girls!”—a speech which nobody in the house—except
the boxful—seemed to hear or at least to apprehend, probably
because it had no relation to the story being acted on the stage.
None the less was Raymond an accomplished comedian, brisk,
lively, laughter-compelling and authoritative. Like many another
comic actor, he longed to play pathetic parts; and unlike most of
those who have this ambition, he did possess the power of drawing
tears. I had first seen him as Asa Trenchard in Paris during the
Exposition of 1867, when Sothern had ventured across the Channel
to disclose Lord Dundreary to the unresponsive French; and I have
never forgotten the simple and manly pathos of the scene in which
Asa burns the will leaving him the fortune which would otherwise go
to the girl he is in love with. Audiences are always ready to
appreciate a brief pathetic episode when the comic character
unexpectedly turns his serious side to the spectators. But they are
resentful when the funny man whom they have gone to laugh with,
and even to laugh at, is presented in a play wherein he is
persistently pathetic and not even intermittently humorous.
Raymond lost money for himself and for his managers when he
impersonated a dreary sobseeker in a dull domestic drama, ‘My Son,’
derived from a tearful Teutonic tale of woe.
In collaboration with H. C. Bunner I put together a rather
boisterous farce called ‘Touch and Go,’ which Raymond liked enough
to contract to produce but not enough for him ever to set about its
production. In its place he had brought out in succession two plays
in which the fun was less acrobatic—‘In Paradise’ and ‘For Congress.’
After these pieces had run their course, G. H. Jessop (who was a
part author of ‘In Paradise’) came to me with an idea for a comic
drama for Raymond and asked me to join him in working it out. It
was to be called ‘A Gold Mine’; and having in mind Raymond’s Asa
Trenchard in the ‘American Cousin,’ I suggested that we lay the
scene in London, so as to repeat the contrast of an American with
the British. We also decided to develop our plot so that at the end of
the second of our three acts Raymond should have a chance to be
pathetic if only for a brief moment.
When our play was read to Raymond he was delighted with it; the
character suited him and he rejoiced that he was to have an
opportunity to show that he could be serious when the situation
required it. During his annual tour he tried out our comedy in one of
the smaller Western cities on a Friday night. He sent us a glowing
report of the reception of our play and of his own triumph at the end
of the second act. And in less than a fortnight thereafter we read in
the morning paper that he had had a sudden seizure which had
carried him off within twenty-four hours.
IV
VI
VII
If it was difficult for Booth fifty years ago and for Irving thirty
years ago to find well-graced and well-trained actors to sustain the
secondary characters in Shakspere’s comedies and tragedies, it is far
more difficult to-day, when our dramatists, even when they are
poets, are rarely tempted to write plays in five acts and in blank
verse. Our modern drama is composed in pedestrian prose; and the
men and women of our theaters have little or no occasion to speak
the language of the gods. They are used to a dialog which aims at
an apparent reproduction of the speech of everyday life; and
therefore they have not been called upon to acquire the art of
delivering the rhythmic utterance of tragic heroes and heroines.
They are all striving to be “natural,” as befits a stage whereon the
scenery and the furnishings are as far as may be those of real life.
They are likely to have a distaste for blank verse, which cannot but
seem to them artificial, stilted, “unnatural.”
Of course, no stage-dialog can be natural, strictly speaking. It
must be compact and significant; it must flow unbroken in the
shortest distance between two points. But to-day actors and
audiences alike are so accustomed to the picked and polished prose
of Barrie and Pinero, of Clyde Fitch and Augustus Thomas, that this
appears “natural” to them, because they do not note its divergence
from the average talk that falls on their ears outside the theater,
whereas they cannot help feeling that the steady march of ten-
syllabled iambics is a violent departure from our habitual manner of
communicating information and of expressing emotion. In other
words, even if our stage-dialog to-day is “unnatural,” as stage-dialog
always has been and always will be, it is far less obviously
“unnatural” than blank verse. A long and severe self-training is
necessary before a performer can feel at home in blank verse, and
before he can impart colloquial ease to it.
Yet it is a fact that we who speak English have a tendency toward
the iambic rhythm when we seek to move an audience. This rhythm
may be unconscious and it may be irregular; but it is unmistakable in
the death-bed scenes of Dickens, for example, where he was
insisting on the pathetic, and in the orations of Ingersoll, where he
was making his most powerful appeal. The Kembles were so
subdued to what they worked in on the stage that they were prone
to drop into blank verse on occasions when it was not appropriate.
Mrs. Siddons is said to have startled the salesman who was showing
her a piece of goods by asking, “And will it wash?” The first time she
met Washington Irving after he had published the ‘Sketch-Book,’ she
said to him, “Young man, you’ve made me weep”; and when she
next met him after he had published another book, she said “Young
man, you’ve made me weep again!”
Her brother, John Philip Kemble, was a great friend of Sir Walter
Scott; and once when they were crossing a field together, they were
chased by a bull. “Sheriff,” said the actor to the author, “methinks I’ll
get me up into a tree.” Fanny Kemble, whose reading of Shakspere’s
plays Longfellow commemorated in a noble sonnet, was the
daughter of Charles, another brother of Mrs. Siddons. Once when
she went on the platform to read, she found that a cane-bottomed
chair had been provided for her. She turned majestically to the
gentleman who was escorting her and inquired, “And would you give
my velvet gown the small-pox?” When her remote kinswoman, the
fragile amateur, who called herself Mrs. Scott-Siddons, came to
Fanny Kemble for professional guidance, she begged for advice
about making points; and she was not a little frightened by the force
of the swift retort: “Points, girl? I never was a point actress!”
This, all this, was long, long ago; and a great deal of water has
gone under the bridge since those distant days. I have to confess
that I never caught Edwin Booth or Henry Irving lapsing into blank
verse off the stage.
(1920)
TRANSCRIBER’S NOTE
Obvious typographical errors and punctuation errors have been corrected after
careful comparison with other occurrences within the text and consultation of
external sources.
Some hyphens in words have been silently removed, some added, when a
predominant preference was found in the original book.
Except for those changes noted below, all misspellings in the text, and
inconsistent or archaic usage, have been retained.
Pg 46: ‘were also accusaable’ replaced by ‘were also accusable’.
Pg 59: ‘Racine, immitagably’ replaced by ‘Racine, immitigably’.
Pg 78: ‘had helpt to’ replaced by ‘had helped to’.
Pg 133: ‘two diferent tongues’ replaced by ‘two different tongues’.
Pg 141: ‘first apparance as’ replaced by ‘first appearance as’.
Pg 142: “Flore et Zephyr” replaced by ‘Flore et Zephyr’.
Pg 144: ‘qualties of the’ replaced by ‘qualities of the’.
Pg 152: ‘if may be recorded’ replaced by ‘it may be recorded’.
Pg 217: ‘unpublisht, and I’ replaced by ‘unpublished, and I’.
Pg 269: ‘or less Shakespere’ replaced by ‘or less Shakspere’.
*** END OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK PLAYWRIGHTS ON
PLAYMAKING ***
1.D. The copyright laws of the place where you are located also
govern what you can do with this work. Copyright laws in most
countries are in a constant state of change. If you are outside
the United States, check the laws of your country in addition to
the terms of this agreement before downloading, copying,
displaying, performing, distributing or creating derivative works
based on this work or any other Project Gutenberg™ work. The
Foundation makes no representations concerning the copyright
status of any work in any country other than the United States.