Module 1 Modern Geometry
Module 1 Modern Geometry
b. apply the various properties of axiomatic systems to the given set of axioms.
The word geometry literally means “earth (geo) measure (metry).” Although this
literal meaning is far too narrow to include the various modern geometries explored in
this text, the idea of earth measure was important in the ancient, pre-Greek
development of geometry. These practical Egyptian, Babylonian, and Chinese
applications of geometry involved measurement, to a great extent, and they were not
complicated by formal proofs. All three civilizations used the correct formulas for the
area of a trapezoid and the volume of a rectangular solid and a cylinder, but all three
also used approximations for the area of a circle.
Two ancient Egyptian papyruses dating from about the same period, the Moscow
papyrus and the Rhind papyrus, contain a total of 26 geometrical problems, most of
which involve various mensuration formulas used for computing land area and the
volume of granaries. Some problems concerned finding the slope of the face of a
During the Greek period, the science of earth measure became more refined.
About 230 B.C., Eratosthenes made a remarkably precise measurement of the size of
the earth.
To many people today, however, the word geometry no longer suggests earth
measures. For example, mathematicians might describe the geometries included in this
text as the study of the properties and relationships of sets of points. To the typical
adult, though, the word geometry probably suggests the high school course taken in
plane geometry or possibly the use of coordinates for points encountered in the study of
algebra or calculus. The ancient Greeks of the period from 500 B.C. to A.D. 100 receive
much of the credit for developing the demonstrative geometry studied at the high school
level. They recognized the beauty of geometry as a discipline with a structure and
understood that the proof of a theorem could be even more exciting than the discovery
of a practical application.
Today, the words axiom and postulate are used interchangeably. In the
development of geometry, however, the word postulate was used for an assumption
confined to one.
1) Primitive or undefined terms are a set of technical terms that are chosen as
undefined and are subject to the interpretation of the reader.
In geometry, the common undefined terms are points, lines, and planes. However, in
this course any terms may be subjected as undefined terms which open to more
interpretation.
2) Defined terms are technical terms which are defined in terms of the primitive and/or
previously introduced definitions.
3) Axioms are unambiguous statements deal with the primitives and definitions of
“Axioms denote as a universal truth which are more general assumptions that applied to
any or all mathematics.” (Smart, 1998, p.3)
(such as geometry).
4) Theorems are unambiguous statements that are proved logically from the
The undefined terms are the committee, members and on. Note that committee
and members are elements, and on is a relation since it indicates some relationship
between committee and members.
The undefined terms are ant, path and has. Note that ant and path are
elements, and has is a relation since it denotes some relationship between ant and
path.
Note that Axiom 3 guarantees the existence of an ant, but no axiom explicitly
states that there is a path. You need to prove the theorem to show the existence of a
path.
Proof.
By Axiom 3, there exists an ant. Now, since each ant must have at least two
paths by Axiom 1, there exists at least one path. ∎
Giving each undefined term within the system with a specific meaning is called an
interpretation of the system.
Example: In geometry, points, lines and planes are undefined terms. Let consider
“points.” To make sense of this undefined term, you need to give meaning to it. Say
“points” will be represented as letter “A.” This means that “point” may be interpreted as
letter “A”. In an exceedingly formal description of “point” in geometry, it describes as a
location with no size, no width, no length and no depth. A point can be illustrated as dot.
An interpretation that produces an axiom true is said to satisfy that axiom. If there
exists an interpretation within which every axiom in a system becomes true, then the
system is said to be satisfiable. If a system is satisfiable, then such an interpretation is
called a model. In other words, if for a given interpretation of a system, all of the axioms
are “correct” statements, then the interpretation is a model.
1. Concrete models have interpretations of the undefined terms adapted from the real
world.
2. Abstract models have interpretations of the undefined terms taken from some other
axiomatic system such as the real number system.
Example 1. Show that the set of axioms has a model. Consider the following axiom sets
for Committee.
Before demonstrating the properties of the given set of axioms, it may be helpful
to make some observations about each statement or axiom. That’s why it is necessary
to understand what the set of axioms all about. This means to know what does each
axiom imply.
First, you need to interpret the undefined terms. From the given set of axioms for
Committee, the undefined terms are member and committee. To interpret the undefined
term “member”, you need to give meaning to it. Let say “members” will be interpreted as
names of individuals like Gladys, Alyzza, Ryza, Leslee, Jennelyn and Fhil. While for
undefined term “committees” will be interpreted as a group of individuals such as
{Gladys, Alyzza, Ryza}, {Gladys, Leslee, Jennelyn }, {Alyzza, Leslee, Fhil} and {Ryza,
Jennelyn, Fhil}. Note that this set of axioms can be illustrated in many ways. The table
below is the results of the interpretation of the given set of axioms.
Second, you need to check whether each axiom in the given set of axioms are
satisfied.
Axiom 2 states that “Each member is on exactly two committees.” To check this
axiom, you look at each member, and list the number of committees they are on. If that
number is 2 for every member, then the axiom is true.
Axiom 3 states that “No two members may be together on more than one
committee.” For this axiom, you have to look at all pairs of members and make sure that
none of the pairs is on more than one committee. So, it is acceptable to have the pair of
members be on zero committee or one committee, but not two or more.
Axiom 4 states that “There is at least one committee.” Since the number of
committees is more than one in a given set of axioms, then the axiom is satisfied.
Since Axioms 1, 2, 3, and 4 are satisfiable, therefore the model for set of axioms
for committee exists ∎
Example 2: What kind of figures or models can be drawn to represent the geometry?
Show your answer.
Figure 1
Although the set of points and lines in figure 1 are such that all the axioms of the
three – point geometry hold, there is still the possibility that the geometry might have
additional lines not shown. This matter is settled by proving two theorems. First,
comparing the wording of axioms 2 and 4, we need to determine whether two distinct
lines might be on more than one point.
We need to prove that each two distinct lines are on at least one point. This
statement can be written in the form of a conditional statement: If two lines are distinct,
then they are on exactly one point.
Proof. By axiom 4, two distinct lines are on at least one point. Assume two lines lie on
more than one point. If lines l and m lie on the points P and Q, then Axiom 2 is
Sets of axioms for Euclidean geometry, as well as for any mathematical system,
should have properties. It is on this lesson that you learn about the properties of the
axiomatic system. It also helps you understand the use of models to verify whether the
axioms possess properties such as consistency, independence and completeness. As
you go through this lesson, you need to take note of the following question: What is a
consistent axiom, independent axiom, and complete axiom?
CONSISTENCY
Definition
Test for Consistency: If there exists a model for a set of axioms, the set of axioms is
consistent. To establish the absolute consistency of a set of axioms, you need to
produce a concrete model
Example 1: *See example set of axioms for committee. Since the model of the set of
axioms for Committee exists, then it is consistent. Furthermore, the interpretation used
in axiomatic system is adapted from real world such as names of people which serve as
model, then the set of axioms has an absolute consistency.
INDEPENDENCE
Definition 1.2
COMPLETENESS
Definition: An axiomatic system is said to be complete if it is impossible to add an
additional consistent and independent axiom without adding additional undefined terms.
THREE-POINT GEOMETRY
Undefined Terms. Point, line, on.
Axiom 1. There exist exactly three points.
Axiom 2. Two distinct points are on exactly one line.
Axiom 3. Not all points are on the same line.
Axiom 4. Two distinct lines are on at least one common point.
Let’s consider the following set of axioms for Three-Point Geometry. We will now
interpret the undefined terms such as point and line of this geometry to determine its
model.
Interpretation: In this geometry, point is interpreted as letter while line is interpreted as
pairs of letters
Point (p) = {A, B, C}
Line (L) = {{A, B}, {A, C}, {B, C}}
Verification: Verify whether each axiom in the given set of axioms is satisfied. This
means that every axiom is true based from its interpretation. If all axioms in the set are
satisfiable, then the model for the set of axioms exist (see Figure 1).
FOUR-LINE GEOMETRY
Axiom 1: There exists exactly four lines.
10 | M e d 2 1 1 – M o d e r n G e o m e t r y
Axiom 2: Any two distinct lines intersect in one point.
Axiom 3: Each point is on exactly two lines.
4L Theorem 1: There exists exactly six points.
4L Theorem 2: Each line contains exactly three points.
Interpretation:
P = {A, B, C, D, E, F}
L = {{A, D, C}, {A, E, F}, {B, D, E}, {B, C, F}}
( 42)= 42∙3 =6
This means there are 6 distinct pairs of lines, and by Axiom 2, each pair intersects in
exactly one point. Therefore, there are 6 distinct intersection points.
Step 3: Confirm the points. Each intersection point is distinct because no two
lines intersect at more than one point (from Axiom 2). Therefore, the six points
are distinct.
Step 4: Verify consistency with Axiom 3. Axiom 3 states that each point lies
on exactly two lines. Since each point is the intersection of two distinct lines, this
condition is satisfied.
Thus, the geometry consists of exactly six distinct points, as required.
11 | M e d 2 1 1 – M o d e r n G e o m e t r y
By axiom 2, each line of the geometry has a point in common with each of the other
three lines, and all three of these distinct points are on the given line. Suppose there
were a fourth point on one line. Then, by axiom 3, it must also be on one of the other
lines. But this is impossible because the other three line already determine exactly one
point with the given line, and by Axiom 2, they can only determine one point. Thus, each
line of the geometry has exactly three points on it.
FOUR-POINT GEOMETRY
Undefined Terms: Point, Line, On.
Axiom 1: There exist exactly four distinct points.
Axiom 2: Any two distinct points are on exactly one line.
Axiom 3: Each line is on exactly two points.
Interpretation: P = {A, B, C, D}
L = {{A, B}, {A, C}, {A, D}, {B, C}, {B,D}, {C, D}}
YOUR TURN!
Five-Point Geometry
Consider the following axioms:
Axiom 1: There exist exactly five points.
Axiom 2: Any two distinct points have exactly one line on both of them.
Axiom 3: Each line has exactly two points.
12 | M e d 2 1 1 – M o d e r n G e o m e t r y
Other Types of Finite Geometries
Fano’s Finite Geometry
Axiom 1: There exists at least one line.
Axiom 2: There exist exactly three points on every line.
Axiom 3: Not all points are on the same line.
Axiom 4: There exists exactly one line on any two distinct points.
Axiom 5: There exists at least one point on any two distinct lines.
13 | M e d 2 1 1 – M o d e r n G e o m e t r y
14 | M e d 2 1 1 – M o d e r n G e o m e t r y