Gordon NagelCamusAbsurd 1984
Gordon NagelCamusAbsurd 1984
Gordon NagelCamusAbsurd 1984
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research
JEFFREY GORDON
The theme of the Absurd, like all great themes in the history of ideas, has
its historical occasion. In the case of the Absurd, it is what Nietzsche's
madman had called "the death of God." Who can read Heidegger's
description of our abandonment in the universe, Camus' depiction of our
confrontation with silence, and Sartre's words about our utter contin-
gency, the absence of justification for our lives, and not hear the reverber-
ations of the fallen God? These existentialist thinkers are responsible for
the prominence of the theme of absurdity, and theirs are the voices of the
desert: their descriptions and judgments would be hardly comprehensible
apart from this landscape of spiritless light. If human existence is now to
I Thomas Nagel's essay, "The Absurd," reprinted in his Mortal Questions (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, I979), was first published in the Journal of Philosophy,
Vol. 68, No. zo (October I97I).
i6 JEFFREY GORDON
' Albert Camus, The Myth of Sisyphus and Other Essays, trans. Justin O'Brien (New
York: Vintage Books, I955), p. 2 3.
3 Nagel, Mortal Questions, p. I7.
4 Ibid., p. 22.
I8 JEFFREY GORDON
II
i. Let us begin by ruling out what Nagel cannot intend by this assertion.
He argues that it is not our inability to justify our ends and values that
constitutes the absurdity of human life. Chains of justification must end,
he writes. If nothing can be justified except in terms of something else, the
demand for justification could never be met and would therefore be vacu-
ous. We need no higher justification, for example, when we change the
direction of our boat to save a drowning man, nor when we remove a
child's hand from a hot stove. I thinkC this insight that there are ends that
do not require justification is essentially correct, though Nagel does not
explore it deeply enough and is at several points guilty of betraying it.5
But what is important at this stage of our inquiry is that if there are ends
that require no justification, as Nagel argues, it cannot be our failure to
justify our ends that constitutes their arbitrariness. Now it may seem that
In Nagel's view, it is one thing to argue for the absurdity of life on the ground that our
projects cannot be justified. The premise here, which rests upon a misconception of
justification, is false (according to Nagel). (See Mortal Questions, pp. IX, I3.) It is quite
another thing, however, to argue that the absurdity of human life derives (in part) from
the fact that the normal standards according to which we justify our projects cannot
themselves be justified. This latter is in fact Nagel's view. (See Mortal Questions, p. I7,
pp. I 8-zo.) But why can't the same objections be made here as were made by Nagel in the
former case? Chains of justification must end. If everything must be justified in terms of
something else, the request for justification would be vacuous. If the first is "a bad argu-
ment," so must be the second.
20 JEFFREY GORDON
6 Nagel, pp. I 7, i 8.
22 JEFFREY GORDON
z4 JEFFREY GORDON
III
z6 JEFFREY GORDON
IV
Z8 JEFFREY GORDON