Lecture Notes
Lecture Notes
1. Thomas Hobbes
Thomas Hobbes, 1588-1679, lived during the most crucial period of early
modern England's history: the English Civil War, waged from 1642-1648. To
describe this conflict in the most general of terms, it was a clash between
the King and his supporters, the Monarchists, who preferred the traditional
authority of a monarch, and the Parliamentarians, most notably led by Oliver
Cromwell, who demanded more power for the quasi-democratic institution of
Parliament. Hobbes represents a compromise between these two factions.
On the one hand he rejects the theory of the Divine Right of Kings, which
is most eloquently expressed by Robert that a king’s authority was invested
in him (or, presumably, her) by God, that such authority was absolute, and
therefore that the basis of political obligation lay in our obligation to obey
God absolutely.
He argues, radically for his times, that political authority and obligation are
based on the individual self-interests of members of society who are
understood to be equal to one another, with no single individual invested
with any essential authority to rule over the rest, while at the same time
maintaining the conservative position that the monarch, which he called
the Sovereign, must be ceded absolute authority if society is to
survive.
The situation is not, however, hopeless. Because men are reasonable, they
can see their way out of such a state by recognizing the laws of nature,
which show them the means by which to escape the State of Nature and
create a civil society.
The first and most important law of nature commands that each man be
willing to pursue peace when others are willing to do the same, all the while
retaining the right to continue to pursue war when others do not pursue
peace. Being reasonable, and recognizing the rationality of this basic precept
of reason, men can be expected to construct a Social Contract that will
afford them a life other than that available to them in the State of Nature.
This contract is constituted by two distinguishable contracts.
In other words, to ensure their escape from the State of Nature, they must
both agree to live together under common laws, and create an enforcement
mechanism for the social contract and the laws that constitute it. Since the
sovereign is invested with the authority and power to mete out punishments
for breaches of the contract which are worse than not being able to act as
one pleases, men have good, albeit self-interested, reason to adjust
themselves to the artifice of morality in general, and justice in particular.
Society becomes possible because, whereas in the State of Nature there was
no power able to "overawe them all", now there is an artificially and
conventionally superior and more powerful person who can force men to
cooperate. While living under the authority of a Sovereign can be harsh
(Hobbes argues that because men's passions can be expected to overwhelm
their reason, the Sovereign must have absolute authority in order for the
contract to be successful) it is at least better than living in the State of
Nature. And, no matter how much we may object to how poorly a Sovereign
manages the affairs of the state and regulates our own lives, we are never
justified in resisting his power because it is the only thing which stands
between us and what we most want to avoid, the State of Nature.
2. John Locke
The State of Nature therefore, is not the same as the state of war, as it is
according to Hobbes. It can, however devolve into a state of war, in
particular, a state of war over property disputes. Whereas the State of
Nature is the state of liberty where persons recognize the Law of Nature and
therefore do not harm one another, the state of war begins between two or
more men once one man declares war on another, by stealing from him, or
by trying to make him his slave. Since in the State of Nature there is no civil
power to whom men can appeal, and since the Law of Nature allows them to
defend their own lives, they may then kill those who would bring force
against them. Since the State of Nature lacks civil authority, once war begins
it is likely to continue. And this is one of the strongest reasons that men have
to abandon the State of Nature by contracting together to form civil
government.
Property plays an essential role in Locke's argument for civil government and
the contract that establishes it. According to Locke, private property is
created when a person mixes his labor with the raw materials of nature. So,
for example, when one tills a piece of land in nature, and makes it into a
piece of farmland, which produces food, then one has a claim to own that
piece of land and the food produced upon it. (This led Locke to conclude that
America didn’t really belong to the natives who lived there, because they
were, on his view, failing to utilize the basic material of nature. In other
words, they didn’t farm it, so they had no legitimate claim to it, and others
could therefore justifiably appropriate it.) Given the implications of the Law
of Nature, there are limits as to how much property one can own: one is not
allowed to take more from nature than one can use, thereby leaving others
without enough for themselves. Because nature is given to all of mankind by
God for its common subsistence, one cannot take more than his own fair
share. Property is the linchpin of Locke’s argument for the social contract
and civil government because it is the protection of their property, including
their property in their own bodies, that men seek when they decide to
abandon the State of Nature.
Because Locke did not envision the State of Nature as grimly as did Hobbes,
he can imagine conditions under which one would be better off rejecting a
particular civil government and returning to the State of Nature, with the aim
of constructing a better civil government in its place. It is therefore both the
view of human nature, and the nature of morality itself, which account for
the differences between Hobbes' and Locke’s views of the social contract.
3. Jean-Jacques Rousseau
Rousseau has two distinct social contract theories. The first is found in his
essay, Discourse on the Origin and Foundations of Inequality Among Men,
commonly referred to as the Second Discourse, and is an account of the
moral and political evolution of human beings over time, from a State of
Nature to modern society. As such it contains his naturalized account of the
social contract, which he sees as very problematic. The second is his
normative, or idealized theory of the social contract, and is meant to provide
the means by which to alleviate the problems that modern society has
created for us, as laid out in the Second Discourse.
The normative social contract, argued for by Rousseau in The Social Contract
(1762), is meant to respond to this sorry state of affairs and to remedy the
social and moral ills that have been produced by the development of society.
The distinction between history and justification, between the factual
situation of mankind and how it ought to live together, is of the utmost
importance to Rousseau. While we ought not to ignore history, nor ignore the
causes of the problems we face, we must resolve those problems through
our capacity to choose how we ought to live. Might never makes right,
despite how often it pretends that it can.
The Social Contract begins with the most oft-quoted line from Rousseau:
"Man was born free, and he is everywhere in chains" (49). This claim is the
conceptual bridge between the descriptive work of the Second Discourse,
and the prescriptive work that is to come. Humans are essentially free, and
were free in the State of Nature, but the ‘progress' of civilization has
substituted subservience to others for that freedom, through dependence,
economic and social inequalities, and the extent to which we judge ourselves
through comparisons with others. Since a return to the State of Nature is
neither feasible nor desirable, the purpose of politics is to restore freedom to
us, thereby reconciling who we truly and essentially are with how we live
together. So, this is the fundamental philosophical problem that The Social
Contract seeks to address: how can we be free and live together? Or, put
another way, how can we live together without succumbing to the force and
coercion of others? We can do so, Rousseau maintains, by submitting our
individual, particular wills to the collective or general will, created through
agreement with other free and equal persons. Like Hobbes and Locke before
him, and in contrast to the ancient philosophers, all men are made by nature
to be equals, therefore no one has a natural right to govern others, and
therefore the only justified authority is the authority that is generated out of
agreements or covenants.
The most basic covenant, the social pact, is the agreement to come together
and form a people, a collectivity, which by definition is more than and
different from a mere aggregation of individual interests and wills. This act,
where individual persons become a people is "the real foundation of society"
(59). Through the collective renunciation of the individual rights and freedom
that one has in the State of Nature, and the transfer of these rights to the
collective body, a new ‘person', as it were, is formed. The sovereign is thus
formed when free and equal persons come together and agree to create
themselves anew as a single body, directed to the good of all considered
together. So, just as individual wills are directed towards individual interests,
the general will, once formed, is directed towards the common good,
understood and agreed to collectively. Included in this version of the social
contract is the idea of reciprocated duties: the sovereign is committed to the
good of the individuals who constitute it, and each individual is likewise
committed to the good of the whole. Given this, individuals cannot be given
liberty to decide whether it is in their own interests to fulfill their duties to
the Sovereign, while at the same time being allowed to reap the benefits of
citizenship. They must be made to conform themselves to the general will,
they must be “forced to be free” (64).