MaWa ClassificationDefinition
MaWa ClassificationDefinition
net/publication/226134293
CITATIONS READS
34 1,593
2 authors:
Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:
CALL FOR PAPERS: SI on Argumentation schemes (Argument & Computation) View project
Special Issue on Boundaries between dialogic pedagogy and argumentation theory View project
All content following this page was uploaded by Fabrizio Macagno on 06 December 2020.
Abstract In this paper we analyze the uses and misuses of argumentation schemes
from verbal classification, and show how argument from definition supports argu-
mentation based on argument from verbal classification. The inquiry has inevitably
included the broader study of the concept of definition. The paper presents the schemes
for argument from classification and for argument from definition, and shows how the
latter type of argument so typically supports the former. The problem of analyzing
arguments based on classification is framed in a structure that reveals the crucial role it
plays in the persuasion process. The survey of the literature includes the work of
Hastings, Perelman, Kienpointner and Schiappa, but still finds much of value in
Aristotle. Lessons drawn from Aristotle’s Topics are shown to be useful for devel-
oping new tools for assessing definitions and arguments from definition.
D. Walton (&)
Department of Philosophy, University of Winnipeg, Winnipeg, Canada R3B 2E9
e-mail: [email protected]
F. Macagno
Department of Linguistics, Università Cattolica del Sacro Cuore, Milan, Italy
e-mail: [email protected]
123
82 D. Walton, F. Macagno
be named and linguistically organized in order to talk about it. Moreover, verbal
classification is in many ways the subtlest and most powerful argumentative tool.
Accepting a verbal classification, that is, the use of a particular word to denote a
fragment of reality, requires accepting the classified object’s possession of certain
properties. The acceptance of these properties, without the audience (respondent)
realizing it, may, by inference, warrant the acceptance of a conclusion. In this paper we
will look at several examples from which lessons can be drawn. In particular, we will
show how the process of ‘‘naming reality’’ or classifying it can be used in inferences
leading to value judgments.1 For instance, the conclusion ‘‘This is a bad company’’ can
be supported by a factual premise such as ‘‘It has monopolized the market’’. Schiappa
(2003, p. 131) and Zarefsky (2006, p. 404) call this strategy argument by definition
(Zarefsky uses also the name ‘persuasive definition’) and represent it as a pattern of the
following kind: x is P, therefore x is good/bad. These argumentation patterns, both
based on endoxical propositions, can be used fallaciously by manipulating the
commitments (or endoxa) of the interlocutor.
The modern concept of classification or naming describes the effects of a process of
inference grounded on a semantic link between premises and conclusion called in the
ancient tradition ‘‘locus a definitione’’, namely topics from definition. Definition, in
other words, describes the semantic reason linking a premise such as P, ‘‘Bounce—O
Company controls the manufacture of all ping-pong balls in the U.S.’’ to the
conclusion C ‘‘Therefore Bounce—O company is a ping-pong ball monopoly’’
(Windes—Hastings 1965, p. 160). The logical link between the classification
conclusion to the premise can be described by the missing premise ‘‘monopoly is
control of the market’’, namely a definition of the concept of ‘‘monopoly’’.
If the argument from verbal classification shows how the conclusion is a
classification of a fragment of reality based on some characteristics (namely how C
follows from P in virtue of a link of classification), it does not show the semantic-
ontological reason why the premises and the conclusion are linked (namely why
‘‘monopoly’’ and ‘‘control of the market’’ are connected, and how). The concept of
definition, grounded in the Aristotelian semantic system, can help understand the
missing relation between the logical aspects of the reasoning, based on a logical
relationship, and the reasons of its reasonableness.
123
Reasoning from Classifications and Definitions 83
the issue at stake. If two parties in a dialogue do not share the same understanding of
the problem, there is a risk that the goal of the argumentation will not be achieved.
In other words, the interlocutors can talk about the same words without talking
about the same concepts. Aristotle highlighted this fundamental role of definition
(Sophistical Refutations, Topics) taking into consideration the concept of polisemy
and fallacies from ambiguity. Definitions however play other functions in
argumentation and in particular they can be powerful instruments of persuasion,
as emerges from the theories of Perelman, Stevenson, and Schiappa. In particular,
definition is the instrument of naming reality, namely the aspect of shared
knowledge allowing one to give a name to a fragment of reality. However, naming
in many cases is not an argumentatively neutral process. On the contrary, names can
constitute powerful instruments of persuasion and manipulation.
123
84 D. Walton, F. Macagno
the emotive meaning. Some terms, in fact, are emotively charged because their
referent is positively considered by the community of speakers. On the other hand, in
some cases, such as ethical terms (the adjective ‘‘good’’ for instance), the two
meanings cannot be distinguished. At the same time, these terms signify certain
properties and evoke a certain behavior. This linguistic foundation is basic to
understanding the strategies of persuasive definitions and quasi-definitions. In cases of
persuasive definitions, a term that has a descriptive and an emotive meaning is re-
defined in order to change its denotation. Its denotation can be restricted or enlarged, in
order for the emotive reaction to apply to the categorization of a particular fragment of
reality. The emotions of the interlocutors are directed towards the desired object. For
instance, a positively valued term such as ‘‘culture’’ can be re-defined as being
grounded on the fundamental property of ‘‘originality’’, and thereby including in this
positive category of ‘‘cultured’’ people who have no wide knowledge. The mirror
image of the persuasive definition is the quasi-definition. In this argumentative
technique, the descriptive meaning is left unaltered, while the emotive meaning is
changed. For instance, the positive emotive attitude elicited by the word ‘‘virtue’’ may
be changed by the quasi definition ‘‘virtue is an antiquated rubbish which robs a man of
all individuality’’. In this case, a positively connoted term can be used to express a
negative emotive attitude that, in effect, works as an unstated premise in an argument.
Another interesting approach to definitions and to their use in argumentation is
Schiappa’s pragmatic theory. Schiappa refuses to recognize that words have an
essential meaning, and instead defends a ‘‘social constructionist’’ conception of reality
and language. He develops this position to support the conclusion that defining reality
means advocating a theory and a point of view. Defining, in his opinion, is describing
the use of a word to refer to objects according to the way that they are conceived by
people. Every definition is based on a set of similarity–difference relationships, by
means of which the speakers can classify reality. These relationships derive from the
process of learning, and the meaning of a word is identified in the denotative
conformity of a community of speakers. Schiappa, considering learning to be the result
of a process of persuasion in which a theory is imposed on the learner, describes
definition as a means of leading the interlocutor to accepting a specific theory. For this
reason definition is depicted as an argumentative act whose goal is to alter our
valuation of reality, an act imposing a different way of thinking. Schiappa applied this
theory to the study of the ‘‘definitional ruptures’’, or re-definitions. A re-definition is
always advanced to defend a particular viewpoint, such as in the case of the
redefinition of ‘‘death’’ as ‘‘brain death’’. This terminological change was done for the
purpose of extending the denotation of the term. On the other hand, a definitional
change can be performed for the purpose of changing a determinate perspective on a
fragment of reality. In sum, to fully grasp a definition we need to see it as dependent on
the goal of the definer in a talk exchange.
Schiappa distinguished between two main schemes relative to definition:
123
Reasoning from Classifications and Definitions 85
The second scheme, by definition, is based on the persuasive use of naming. Naming
a state of affairs X as Y is an argumentative strategy provoking an emotion (a
reaction R). For instance, a complex reality can be denoted by a ‘‘domestic term’’
(for instance, a missile can be named ‘‘Peacekeeper’’) or a ‘‘bureaucratic term’’,
incomprehensible for most of the interlocutors (for instance, neutron bombs are
called ‘‘radiation enhancement weapon’’). Names can enhance positive attitudes and
at the same time denote or conceal a fragment of reality commonly considered
negative. This characteristic of words is exploited in some descriptions. Defining
and naming for Schiappa always express an attitude, orientating the interlocutor
towards a certain conclusion. Describing reality is on his view never neutral either.
The same reality can be differently framed, in order for it to be differently
categorized. Some aspects of a situation or of an object can be emphasised while
others are concealed or ignored. For this reason, the same fragment of reality can be
differently described to defend specific points of view. Schiappa’s theory, we can
notice, is extremely interesting since it highlights the fundamental relation between
definition, reality, and attitude. However, the ‘‘definitional relativism’’ his theory is
grounded upon is problematic. His view that a definition is always aimed at altering
our valuation of reality seems not to distinguish between redefinitions, fallacious
definitions, and definitions shared by a community.
Schiappa and Stevenson point out the argumentative and persuasive use of
definition. Both stress the fundamental relation between emotions and predication,
and how a definition plays a crucial role in legitimating a predication of an emotive
word or of a term which is argumentatively relevant (for instance, legal terms). In
particular, whereas Schiappa focuses on the persuasive uses of definition, Stevenson
analyzes the structure of persuasion through definition distinguishing between the
descriptive and the emotive component of meaning.
123
86 D. Walton, F. Macagno
to the argumentation based on definition and classification, we can see how the
connection between a classification and the evaluation is simply a matter of
common knowledge. Concepts such as ‘‘beauty’’, ‘‘youth’’, ‘‘courage’’, ‘‘culture’’
are commonly considered to be positive in our culture (obviously this evaluation is
highly subjective and culturally bound). In other words, these concepts are positive
values and therefore desirable and reasons to act. The classification itself works in
these cases as an implicit argument as in the analysis of the following classification
of ‘‘the suppression of the opponents of Bolshevism’’:
These actions [the suppression of the opponents of the Bolshevism] are acts of
peace.
In the grey boxes (Fig. 1) the implicit premises are represented. We should
observe that in the argument represented by the classification of ‘‘suppression of the
opponents of Bolshevism’’ two crucial steps can be identified. The first step is the
process of characterizing the fragment of reality considered as ‘‘acts of peace’’ by
means of an implicit redefinition of ‘‘act of peace’’. The second step is the
evaluation of the suppression of the opponents, grounded on an endoxical premise
(peace is good) and a maxim, what leads to good results is itself good (Aristotle,
Rhetoric I, 6). This second implicit step leads to the conclusion that the suppression
of the opponents is good (desirable). This evaluation is an implicit commitment to
123
Reasoning from Classifications and Definitions 87
the rightfulness of the action. The argumentation process leading from values to an
evaluation, and therefore to a commitment, can be represented by the following
argumentation scheme from values (Walton et al., cap. 9):
123
88 D. Walton, F. Macagno
p. 98), in which Don Juan is trying to persuade his interlocutor, Sganarelle, of the
negativity of marriage and fidelity:
DON JUAN: What! Would you restrict a man to staying chained to the first
woman who takes his fancy, have him give up everything for her and never
look at any others again? The idea is ludicrous – making a bogus virtue out of
being faithful, being trapped forever in the same relationship and as good as
dead from youth onwards to the other pretty faces that might catch our eye! No
no: fidelity is for imbeciles. All beautiful women are entitled to our love, and
the accident of being the first on the scene shouldn’t deprive the rest of the
rightful claims they have on our affections.
In this example, it is interesting to notice how the situation is described not only
using a not-shared definition of marriage, fidelity and love, but also a not-shared
evaluation of these concepts. In this argument, in fact, the speaker presupposes that
being committed to a relationship is not desirable (trapped), that the women look for
the kind of affection described as ‘‘love’’ and that the men have to fulfill the
appetitive desires of women. These premises are hardly accepted as true by the
interlocutor, a defendant of the faithfulness in the marriage and of the positive value
of the original concepts. This redefinition takes into consideration only some
accidental aspects of the concept defined, namely that a relationship can be a trap.
The manipulation of the concept defined leading to altering the values associated to
the definiendum can consist of narrowing or broadening a concept that sometimes is
vague (see Aberdein 2000), including positive (negative) accidental aspects or
excluding positive (negative) essential aspects of the concept. There is nothing
inherently fallacious in the speaker’s defining a particular way he is using a term.
The risk of fallacy can arise when he is presenting the particular word use as the
proper use of the word everybody agrees upon. The risk of sophistry lies in the fact
that the concept defined by the speaker is not the same as the hearer’s, but is
presented as such. By narrowing down a concept, it is possible to select only the
worst or best aspects of the reality it refers to. We can examine the following
example, in order to make this concept clearer (Goarke and Tindale 2004, p. 99):
Socialism is that form of government that steals wealth from energetic people
and divides it among the lazy poor.
Here the definition is of a commonly shared concept, socialism. The definition,
instead of referring to the whole reality of what is commonly intended to be
‘‘socialism’’, takes into consideration only a particular aspect of it, namely its
degeneration. The thing, the concept defined is another concept, namely the
degenerated socialism, or the worst effects of socialism, not ‘‘socialism’’ itself. The
definer, in other words, defines a new concept and make the negative emotive
inferences of ‘‘degenerate socialism’’ apply to ‘‘socialism’’ in its entirety.
The last case regards the relation between a shared definition and a not-shared
framing of the situation. In order for a state of affairs to fall into a definition, it
has to present the essential features stated in the definition. The speaker can use a
shared definition, but presuppose that the situation presents some inexistent
123
Reasoning from Classifications and Definitions 89
features, or suppress relevant evidence. For instance we can analyze the example
below4:
Reverend BARRY LYNN (Americans United): I just think it’s incredibly
inappropriate when you’ve got the head of an agency or a department of
government having a daily religious ritual that includes some people and of
course, by definition …
MATTHEWS: OK, ritual—loaded term.
Rev. LYNN: … excludes some.
MATTHEWS: Loaded term, ritual.
Rev. LYNN: Oh, sure. But it is—but it is a prayer session, a study section. It does
include a prayer as well and I think that the proof …
The word ‘‘ritual’’ presupposes a situation including not only prayers, but also some
ceremonials making the situation itself a ‘‘religious ceremony’’. Here the definition
is shared, but the situation is framed including facts that are not accepted by the
other party, such as the presence of prayers. In fact, in the last move, Rev. Lynn has
to prove that there are prayers as well. The classification can be based also on the
suppression of relevant evidence. For instance we can consider the following case5:
‘Once again Britain has been found sucking up to dictatorships.’ (Or
maintaining friendly relations with strong governments. Note how ‘found’
implies that we were discovered in a guilty secret.)
Here the classification is put forward referring to the relationships between Britain
and fascist countries. If we consider this statement, which can be used as an implicit
argument for drawing a value judgement on Britain, we can notice that the move
consisting of classifying dictatorships as ‘‘strong governments’’ is fallacious. The
definitions of ‘‘government’’ and ‘‘dictatorship’’ are shared, and in particular nobody
would think that ‘‘dictatorship’’ does not include in its definition the suppression of
political rights. The classification move presupposes that the countries mentioned do
not suppress political rights (otherwise they would be dictatorships, and not
governments), framing the situation in a fallacious way. The suppression of pieces
of information relevant to the making of a classification can be considered as a case
of suppression of evidence. This strategy is often used to depict a complex reality
under a single label (see Rigotti 2005; Lakoff 1996, p. 320; Goarke and Tindale
2004, pp. 86–87).
As seen in the section above, naming reality can be examined as having two
argumentative aspects: it is grounded on definitions and it often leads to evaluative
inferences. In this section the inference leading from a definition to a classification,
4
http://www.cwfpac.com/chairmans_corner_speeches_05_14_01.htm
5
http://www.adamsmith.org/logicalfallacies/000638.php
123
90 D. Walton, F. Macagno
2.1 Hastings
Hastings, in his Ph.D. thesis (1963), identified two schemes that can be treated under
the label of argument from classification. The first scheme, in fact, leads from a set
of characteristics to the attribution of a predicate to a subject, much like the process
of classification described above. In the second scheme, a subject, classified as X, is
predicated of the definition of X. In other words, first a predicate is attributed to a
subject (the subject is classified); then in virtue of the definition of the predicate
some fundamental characteristics are attributed to the subject.
We can notice that the second scheme is the mirror image of the first. The
definition used to classify a subject is in the latter scheme applied to the classified
subject. We can represent the two argument schemes as follows (see Hastings 1963,
pp. 36–52):
Argument from Criteria to Verbal Classification
Event or object X has characteristics A, B, C…
If x has characteristics A, B, C… then x is Q
Therefore, event or object X is Q.
For example, Hastings gives the following example (p. 36):
In Voluntary health insurance you generally get a poor return for your money
because overhead and profits of the insurance company eat up huge chunks of
the premiums you pay. On individual policies these companies spend for
overhead and profits an average of about 60% of what you pay them and only
about 40 cents of your premium dollar goes for benefits to policyholders.
Obviously such insurance is a mighty poor buy (Fig. 2).
Hastings highlights the fact that the classification proceeds from the evidence that
is presented. This is an extremely interesting observation, since we can notice that
it is connected to the ancient studies on issues (stasis). According to this ancient
theory (see Cicero and Hermagoras), the process of classification follows two
other stages, in which evidence is collected and the definition of the terms is
established.
123
Reasoning from Classifications and Definitions 91
123
92 D. Walton, F. Macagno
123
Reasoning from Classifications and Definitions 93
2.2 Kienpointner
Descriptive What is predicated of the definition is also predicated of the definiendum and vice versa
X is predicated of the definition
Therefore X is predicated of the definiendum
What the definiendum is predicated of, also the definition is predicated of
The definiendum is predicated of X
Therefore the definition is predicated of X
Normative If X is defined by means of definition Y, valuation Z relative to X is justified
X is defined by means of definition Y
Therefore valuation Z relative to X is justified
If X is defined by means of definition Y, action Z is advisable
X is defined by means of definition Y
Therefore action Z is advisable
In these schemes, the definition can be substituted by the interpretation of the name
(p. 259). The last two schemes are frequently used in persuasive definitions. In
commercials, a product is described as having a certain number of qualities, leading
to the conclusion that it should be bought. The scheme can be presented as follows:
If product X is defined by means of Y, it is advisable to buy X
Product X is defined by means of Y
It is advisable to buy X
123
94 D. Walton, F. Macagno
The purpose of this subsection is to show how the argument schemes from
classification presented in the last section are somehow inadequate to describe the
semantics of the inferential structure of the argument. By taking into consideration
the weaknesses of the schemes we can develop a new formulation of the
argumentation from classification.
In Walton (2006, p. 129), the following scheme from verbal classification is
advanced, maintaining the structure of the scheme presented in Hastings (1963):
We should notice that in this scheme, such as in Hastings’ argument schemes, the
relation between F and G is not specified. If the structure of the inference
represented is logically valid, the reasonableness of the inference itself does not
seem to be considered in the classification scheme. The conclusion ‘a is blue’
follows logically from the classification premise ‘for all x, if x is red then x is blue’
and from the premise ‘a is red’, but is unreasonable. In Walton et al. (2008), the
nature of the classification was made clearer by developing the classification
premise into the following one:
CLASSIFICATION PREMISE (Walton et al. 2008): For all x, if a fits definition D,
then x can be classified as having property G.
123
Reasoning from Classifications and Definitions 95
Walton’s (2006) scheme can be therefore refined and made more useful for
describing the inferential structure by making the nature of the relation between F
and G explicit. However, even in this scheme, the relation between D and G is not
clear. A better formulation of the inferential passage can be found in Keinpointner.
If we take into consideration Kienpointner’s scheme from definition and apply it
to a case, the following argument will follow:
However, we can notice, the endoxical premise ‘rational animal is the definition of
man’ is lacking here.6 The only possible inference that can be drawn from the
premises is the following:
For this reason, we can represent the structure of the inference as follows (see
Rigotti and Greco 2006):
MAXIM ENDOXON
What the definiendum is predicated of, also the definition is
predicated of
Rational animal is the definition of
man
PRELIMINARY CONCLUSION
Following the connection between the endoxon and the maxim, the argumentation
scheme from criteria to verbal classification can be formulated as follows, merging
together the schemes advanced in (Walton et al. 2008) and (Walton 2008), in which:
6
We would like to thank Eddo Rigotti for his advice and observation on this aspect of Kienpointner’s
argument schemes.
123
96 D. Walton, F. Macagno
The analysis of the argument schemes from verbal classification shows how the link
between the premises and conclusion is grounded on a semantic link which was called
by the tradition the maxim, and on an endoxical, or commonly shared premise, namely
the definition itself. In the section above, in fact, we took into account the structure of
the inference, showing how the conclusion depends on two conditions:
r the object x must fit the definition D
r D must be the (shared) definition of G
However, we can notice, there might be different types of definition of the same
concept. For instance, a concept such as ‘‘man’’ can be defined as ‘‘the rational
animal’’, ‘‘the animal that can pity the Gods’’ ‘‘the biped animal’’, ‘‘the being
composed of two legs, a head, two arms…’’, ‘‘the being Homo sapiens sapiens and
Homo sapiens idaltu belong to’’…There might be many types of definition, different
for the semantic content (for instance ‘‘man is the rational animal’’ and ‘‘man is the
7
We would like to thank the anonymous referee for his comments on this point.
123
Reasoning from Classifications and Definitions 97
laughing animal’’) or for their structure (for instance ‘‘man is the rational animal’’
and ‘‘man is the being composed of two legs, a head, two arms…’’.
In the first case, we can notice, the acceptability of the conclusion of a reasoning
from definition depends only on the acceptability of the definitional premise. For
instance, we can consider the two different inferences drawn from two different
definitions of ‘‘monopoly’’:
1. Pop Cola is controlling the soft drinks market. A monopoly is a company that exclusively
Therefore it is a monopoly controls the market
2. Pop Cola is the biggest soft drinks company. A monopoly is the biggest industry in a field
Therefore it is a monopoly of activity
3. There is a building that serves as living quarters for one House is a building that serves as living
or a few families. Therefore there is a house quarters for one or a few families
4. There are four walls, a roof, the foundation. Therefore House is four walls, a roof, the foundation
there is a house
Whereas in (3) the conclusion reasonably follows from the premise, in (4) the
conclusion is not supported in the same fashion from the premise. If there is a
building that serves as living quarters for one or a few families, there must be a
house, but even if there are four walls, a roof, the foundation, it can be reasonably
concluded that there is no house.
Moreover, if we consider other types of definitions, we can notice that they can
be used for different purposes. We can introduce the topic by taking into
consideration the two following inferences:
1. Man is the being who can pity the Gods. Therefore man is a good being To pity the Gods is good
2. Man is the being who can despise the Gods. Therefore man is a bad being To despise the Gods is
bad
In these two examples, different types of evaluative inferences are drawn from the
two definitions. In both cases, we can notice, the definition can be acceptable, and it
is convertible with the definiendum (man is the only being who can pity or despise
the Gods). However, according to the definition used, different conclusions can be
supported.
From these examples, we can notice how definitions differ not only because of
their different status as shared premises, namely whether they are commonly
accepted or they are not, but also because of their nature. The question we want to
123
98 D. Walton, F. Macagno
address in this section regards the possibility of evaluating definitions. Our claim is
that the existence of many different types of definitions does not lead to a
definitional relativism, but, on the contrary, to argumentative discussions on what is
the best definition. In order to have a discussion on definition, however, it is
necessary first to establish what the best, or the ‘‘real’’ definition is. The starting
point for our analysis is Aristotle’s dialectical work, namely the Topics, in which the
concept of dialectical definition is introduced.
Aristotle in his Topics laid the fundamentals of his dialectical studies of classification.
In this work, Aristotle distinguishes between the four predicables, that are four classes
of semantic–logical relations of predication. These relations are formulated in the
form of intrinsic topics, namely instruments of discovery and inference warrants
directly connected to the subject of discussion. Aristotle distinguished four
predicables: genus (for instance ‘‘house is a building’’), definition (for instance
‘‘house is a building that serves as living quarters for one or a few families’’), property
(for instance ‘‘do up a house’’, which is said of ‘‘house’’ only), and accident (for
instance ‘‘red’’ or ‘‘nice’’ said of ‘‘house’’). All the predicables can be predicated of the
species, which, in these examples, is for instance ‘‘house’’. The species, conceived by
Aristotle as a thing, can be interpreted as a categorization of a fragment of reality that
we can describe as the meaning of a word.8 The species (or concept) is that which can
be predicated of more individuals different in number (for instance ‘‘house’’ can be
predicated of my house, or my neighbor’s house ….), and falls outside the domain of
dialectic. Dialectic is concerned about relations between concepts, not about reasoning
relative to the particular objects (Crowley and Hawhee 1999, p. 54; Green-Pedersen
1984, p. 119).9
The predicables are divided into two groups according to their semantic
properties. The first class incorporates the predicables that can reveal the essence of
the thing, that is (see Rigotti and Greco 2006), what the concept is or, rather, its
fundamental characteristics (see Stebbing 1933, p. 429). In this group falls genus
and definition. The second class is characterized by not expressing the essence of
the thing and it incorporates property and accident. On the other hand, a second
division of the predicables is advanced in the Topics, and is relative to the logical
properties. While definition and property are convertible with the species they are
predicated of, genus and accident are not. From this broad division it is possible to
understand the definition of the predicables.
8
This interpretation is coherent with Aristotle’s perspective of dialectic. Dialectic does not deal with
objects and individuals (what we can call ‘‘things’’), but with species, namely linguistic organization of
reality. He is not interested in the matter, but in the form, that is in the relevant semantic properties of the
concepts.
9
Aristotle (Topics, I, 10), considers a dialectical proposition to be a proposition held by everybody, or
the majority, or the wise. Dialectic (Topics, I, 14) is about science, and science is not concerned with
particulars. In the Middle Ages, the account of the predicables is different. Medieval tradition stems, in
fact, from Prophyry’s Isagoges, in which the species is considered to be a predicable, along with property,
difference, genus and accident. This distinction is extremely helpful in the process of stasis.
123
Reasoning from Classifications and Definitions 99
The genus answers the question ‘‘What is it?’’ and reveals the essence of the
thing, without being convertible with the species it is predicated of. It is predicated
of several species. For instance, the genus (or, rather, the proximate genus) of man is
‘‘animal’’: in fact, it would be meaningless to say: ‘‘This is a man, but he is not an
animate being’’. The definition is that which is convertible with the species it is
predicated of and reveals the essence of it. It is constituted by the proximate genus
and the specific difference.10 For instance, the definition of man that was agreed
upon in the Middle Ages was ‘‘animal, mortal, rational’’. The property is what is
convertible with the subject it is predicated of, without expressing the essence of the
thing. In other words, the property is absolutely or relatively predicable of only one
thing. In order to explain this concept, it is useful to use some examples. The word
‘‘pitch’’, used as an adjective, can only be predicated of the term ‘‘black’’.
‘‘Grammaticus’’, in the Aristotelian and medieval tradition, was considered the
property of man, since it cannot be predicated of any other being. This property
differentiates the concept from everything else. It is, in other words, absolute.
However, the property might be relative. If nearby a stable there are horses, dogs,
cows, and a kangaroo, the kangaroo can be identified as the ‘‘two-legged animal’’.
Two-leggedness is in this case a property of kangaroo relatively to the other four-
legged animals. Last in the Aristotelian semantic system comes the accident.
Accident is defined as ‘‘something which can belong or not belong to some one
particular thing’’ (Topics 102b, 6–7). For instance, a person can be sitting or not be
sitting,11 or a house can be red or white, nice or tiny, big or small.
From this distinction between the different relations of predication, it is possible
to understand the Aristotelian treatment of the types of classification. It is possible
to classify a concept (a thing) indicating its genus. For instance, a man is an animal.
It is possible to identify a thing by using its definition. For instance, a man is a
rational animal. Finally, it is possible to describe a concept by using a property,
absolute or relative. For instance, a man is a being that is able to learn grammar, or
is a two-legged being, or the animal at the top of the food chain. The Aristotelian
semantic system allows one to understand what the definition is and how it can be
explained as a method for the semantic analysis of a concept.
10
A good example of this procedure is found in Cicero’s Topics (Topica, XXVIII): Hereditas est
pecunia. Commune adhuc; multa enim genera pecuniae. Adde quod sequitur: quae morte alicuius ad
quempiam pervenit. Nondum est definitio; multis enim modis sine hereditate teneri pecuniae mortuorum
possunt. Unum adde verbum: iure; iam a communitate res diiuncta videbitur, ut sit explicata definitio sic:
Hereditas est pecunia quae morte alicuius ad quempiam pervenit iure. Nondum est satis; adde: nec ea aut
legata testamento aut possessione retenta; confectum est.
11
It is interesting to notice (Rigotti 1997) that a man can be sitting or standing, or he can be stretched
out, but he must be in a position. Similarly, a stone can be green or grey, but cannot jump. Accident is
related to the possibility of predication, to the semantic genera of the predicates, the ten categories.
123
100 D. Walton, F. Macagno
Victorinus, De Definitione), in this section we will discuss the one type recognized
by Aristotle, the definition by genus and differentia.
An awareness of this type of definition is fundamental to communication and
argumentation. According to Aristotle, there must be only one definition of a thing,
that is, of a concept (Topics, VI, 4, 141a 32–34; 143a 1). His interest is focused on
the different possible uses of a word (Topics, 106a 9–10), namely, the different
essences a word can be used to represent. This approach can be named, using the
modern classification, as ‘‘terminological’’ (see De Besse 1988). Making distinc-
tions between the different senses of a word (a semantic analysis) is a necessary
preliminary step to any discussion, in order to avoid equivocations. In other words,
only if the interlocutors speak about the same concepts it is possible for them to
understand each other and avoid fallacies. The method to achieve this result is to
share the same definitions of the concepts.
The methodology of definition given in the Topics is based on two main
characteristics: the correctness of the definition, and the ability of the definition to
express the essence of the thing. For a definition to be correct, two requisites must
be respected (Topics. IV, 3):
a) Avoiding obscurity and unclear expressions;
b) Avoiding unnecessarily long descriptions.
Aristotle lists a series of topics, which can be understood as rules for the assessment
of a definition. For instance we can analyze the topics below:
Obscurity
a. The definition contains equivocal words a. A house is a place where a family lives
b. The definition does not distinguish between the b. A house is a building with a roof (Dwelling?
different meanings of the definiendum Shelter?)
c. The definition contains words used in a c. A house it the heart of a family
metaphorical sense
c. The definition contains words whose use is d. A man is a being able to vent his emotions
unusual (not very well established and known)
e. The definition contains terms whose proper e. A boat is a vehicle with a jetty
meaning does not describe the thing and that are
not metaphors. The sense of these words cannot be
recovered
Length
a. The definition contains attributes universally a. A house is a building that has the foundation
applicable (attributes that are not the proximate
genus or that apply to all the things under the same
genus)
b. The definition contains an attribute that is useless, b. A house a dwelling, sometimes very nice, that
that is not necessary to distinguish the thing from serves as living quarters for big or small
all the other concepts families
c. The definition is not peculiar of the species c. A house is a big dwelling that serves as living
defined, since it does not belong to all the quarters for families
individuals falling under the same species
d. In the definition the same attributes are predicated d. A house is a dwelling built by humans that
more than once of the same thing serves as living quarters for families
123
Reasoning from Classifications and Definitions 101
Definition must express the essential property of a thing, in other words, its
fundamental semantic features. The notion of essential property, or ‘‘semantically
fundamental characteristic’’ depends upon the concepts of intelligibility and
differentiation (Topics, VI, 4). The definition must make known the meaning of the
concept, by describing it using the prior and more intelligible concepts,12 that is, the
genus and the differentia. The genus is more intelligible than the species, since the
species is more complex, being constituted by the genus and the difference. The
same applies to the difference.
First, the semantic characteristic expressed in a definition must be prior:
An opposite cannot be defined by means of its opposite Good is what is not bad
(when it is possible to avoid this circular definition)
A definition cannot contain the term defined A house is a building that is a house
for a family
A thing cannot be defined by its opposite belonging A man is a being that is not a beast
to the same division
A thing cannot be defined by using its species A boat is a vehicle a ferry belongs to
Second, for a definition to express an essence, the genus must be attributed and
attributed correctly. The concept of genus can be clarified by the most important
topics it is characterized by (Topics, IV, 120b 12- 123a 27):
The genus must include all the members Good is the genus of pleasure: therefore, this kind
of the species it is predicated of of pleasure is good
The genus is predicated in the category White is not the genus of the snow, since it does not
of essence. Genus and species must fall tell what snow is
in the same category White is a quality; snow is a substance
The species can be predicated of the definition Man is an animal. Therefore, man is an animate body
of the genus, not vice versa
The genus is predicated of what the species Knowable is the genus of conjectural. Therefore,
is predicated of a not-existing thing is knowable
It is impossible for something to be predicated Pleasure is not a motion, since it is neither locomotion,
of the genus if it is not predicated of one nor alteration nor any other kinds of movement
of its species
What is placed in the genus cannot be predicated The soul is life; but, since the number does not live,
of the definition of anything contrary to the soul is not a number
the genus
A definition therefore must show the genus, and the right proximate genus of the
definiendum. Aristotle expresses this rule in the following topics:
12
See, for the notion of basic elements of meaning, Mel’cuk’s Sense—Text theory (Mel’cuk 1997).
123
102 D. Walton, F. Macagno
In a definition the genus must be specified A house serves as living quarters for families
The genus must be attributed appropriately. A house is an instrument that serves as living
It is possible to apply the topics from the quarters for families (an instrument is a device
genus in order to see if they hold that requires skill for proper use. Therefore
a house is a device)
The genus attributed must be the nearest. A house is an artifact that serves as living quarters
The nearest genus presupposes the highest for families
ones, but not the contrary
Third, in the definition the genus must be specified by means of the specific
difference.
The definition must divide the species by means A house is a dwelling with a roof (no dwelling
of the difference from something else. There must without a roof); A man is a biped featherless animal
be an opposite of the species in the division. The (no featherless animals with four feet).
difference must be a difference of the genus A man is a rational body (difference of ‘‘animal’’,
considered not of ‘‘body’’)
The genus cannot be divided by negation A house is a building which is not dedicated
to any business activity
The difference must not be a species of the genus A house is building which is a dwelling
or the genus of the one stated
The difference must signify an essential (not A man is an animal that pities the Gods
accidental) quality of the subject. It cannot signify
affections, special or temporal indications
The genus is predicated of the species; the A man is a rational that is an animal
difference is predicated of the species. The genus
cannot be predicated of the difference or vice versa.
The species cannot be predicated of the difference
The difference of relatives must be relative and A boat is a vehicle designed for
relative to the primary relation of the term. In case transportation (not the natural purpose)
of an artifact, the difference must be relative to its
natural purpose
The difference must not be an affection of the genus A man is a reading animal (if there are no books,
there won’t be men)
The definition, in addition to being convertible with the subject13 must express its
fundamental characteristics. In other words, the definition must not be merely wider
or narrower than the definiendum, but also respect semantic and logical conditions.
The argumentative power of essential definition is based on its being hardly
questionable. Semantics can be conceived as the deepest level of endoxa (or shared
commitments): to refuse to accept the most basic semantic characteristics may result
in refusing to accept a fragment of the shared semantic system. Moreover, the
essential definition is always convertible with the definiendum, and it can be used to
develop inferences based on the genus. For instance, if we consider the definition of
‘‘free speech’’ as ‘‘the human right regarding the freedom of expression’’, by
13
For the use of the topics in rhetorical speech, see Weaver (1953). Analyzing the definition of ‘‘human
referred to the black slaves’’, for instance, he notices that the category of ‘‘not human’’ applies only in
certain circumstances to the slaves and not to all the black people.
123
Reasoning from Classifications and Definitions 103
showing that ‘‘free speech’’ has been forbidden we can support the conclusion that a
human right has been violated (‘‘what is said of the species is said of the genus as
well’’). These observations can be useful to understand the difference between the
essential definition and the other kinds of definitions.
3.3 Other Methods of Classification
Definitions Inferences
X is A and B A house is walls, the foundation, There are walls, the foundation, a roof.
a roof Therefore there is a house
(there might be not)
X is made of A and B A house is made of walls, A house is destroyed. Therefore walls,
the foundation, a roof the foundation, a roof are destroyed
(they might be not destroyed)
X is A plus B A house is walls plus foundation,
plus a roof.
(plus means and or made of)
In all these schemes, we should notice that the subject is not identical with the single
part. In the first scheme, the whole is not identical to the compound of the parts. In
other terms, the subject is not convertible with the definiens. In the second scheme,
the subject and the definiens are not convertible since they cannot be subject to the
same predications. For instance, if a house is destroyed, the parts it was made of can
still be intact. The definition must indicate the specific composition of the parts, in
order to indicate the essence of the compound. Finally, the third scheme can be
reduced to the other two. The ‘‘definition’’ by integral parts is better explained as
description by permanent property. The definition by integral parts is weaker than
the definition by genus and species. It is useful, however, for destructive purposes
(see Cicero, Topica 9). If one of the parts is missing, the whole cannot be the case.
The definition by definite description is analyzed in the section of the Topics
relative to the property (Topics, V). Property can be used in fact as a description
123
104 D. Walton, F. Macagno
(132a): for instance, man can be described as the animal able to laugh. Aristotle
distinguishes between four kinds of property (128b 34- 129a6): absolute (per se),
relative, permanent, and temporary (see also Rigotti and Greco 2006). For instance,
we can show the different types of description as follows:
There is no space for us to try to build our own theory for evaluation of definitions
and classifications here, but one thing we can do is sketch out some elements of a
prior theory, Aristotle’s theory, that offers an idea of how the task needs to be
14
This example can be translated as «Rich (pecuniosum) from abundance of sheep (pecorum)».
15
The argument can be interpreted as «According to the law, the patrician must help the patrician;
therefore the rich must help the rich. In fact the patrician (assiduous) is who gives money (as do), and the
rich gives money. Therefore the rich is the same as the patrician».
123
Reasoning from Classifications and Definitions 105
4 Conclusion
References
Aberdein, Andrew. 2000. Persuasive definition. In Argumentation at the Century’s turn, ed. C. W.
Tindale, H. V. Hansen and E. Sveda. CD ROM, OSSA (Ontario Society for the Study of
Argumentation) Proceedings.
123
106 D. Walton, F. Macagno
Aristotle. 1969. Topica. In The works of Aristotle, ed. W. D. Ross. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Boethii, Anicii Manlii Severini. 1988. In Ciceronis Topica. Translated, with notes and introduction by
Eleanore Stump. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Cicero, Marcus Tullius. 1949. De Inventione, De optimo genere oraturum, Topica (trans: Hubbell, H.).
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Crowley, Sharon, and Debra Hawhee. 1999. Ancient rhetorics for contemporary students. Boston: Allyn
and Bacon.
De Besse, Bruno. 1988. La Définition terminologique. In La De´finition, ed. Jacques Chaurand and
Francine Mazière. Paris: Actes du Colloque de Définition, 18th and 19th November.
Codevilla, Giovanni. 2003. Military language in the constitutional laws of Soviet Russia. Studies in
Communication Sciences 1: 55–76.
Goarke, Leo, and Christopher Tindale. 2004. Good reasoning matters!. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Green-Pedersen, Niels J. 1984. The tradition of topics in the middle age. Munich, Germany: Philosophia
Verlag.
Hallden, Sören. 1960. True love, true humour and true religion: A semantic study. Lund: Gleerlup.
Hastings, Arthur C. 1963. A reformulation of the modes of reasoning in argumentation. Evanston, Illinois:
Ph.D. Dissertation, Northwestern University.
Kienpointner, Manfred. 1992. Alltagslogik: Struktur und Funktion von Argumentationsmustern. Stuttgart,
Germany: Fromman-Holzboog.
Lakoff, George. 1996. Moral politics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Mel’cuk, Igor A. 1997. Vers une linguistique Sens-Texte. Leçon inaugurale, Collège de France, Chaire
internationale, 43 pp. http://www.fas.umontreal.ca/LING/olst/FrEng/melcukColldeFr.pdf.
Molière, Jean-Baptiste. 2000. Don Juan. In Molière. The Miser and other plays, trans: J. Wood and
D. Coward. Toronto: Penguin Books.
Perelman, Chaim and Lucie Olbrechts-Tyteca. 1969. The new rhetoric: A treatise on argumentation
(trans. J. Wilkinson and P. Weaver). Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press.
Quintilian, Maximus Fabius. 1996. Institutio Oratoria (trans: Butler, H. E.). Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard
University Press.
Rigotti, Eddo. 1997. Lezioni di Linguistica Generale. Milano: CUSL.
Rigotti, Eddo. 2005. Towards a typology of manipulative processes. In New perspectives on manipulative
and ideological discourse in pragmatics and discourse analysis. ‘‘Discourse Approaches to Politics,
Society and Culture’’, ed. Louis de Saussure and Peter Schulz, 61–83. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Rigotti, Eddo, and Sara Greco. 2006. Topics: The argument generator. Argumentum eLearning Module.
Disponibile presso www.argumentum.ch. (URL consultato il 14 dicembre 2007).
Robinson, Daniel. 1947. The principles of reasoning. New York: D. Appleton – Century Company.
Robinson, Richard. 1950. Definition. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Rößler, Jürgen L. 1998. Die operationale definition. Berlin: Peter Lang.
Schiappa, Edward. 1998. Constructing reality through definitions: The politics of meaning. A lecture
presented for the Center for Interdisciplinary Studies of Writing and the Composition, Literacy, and
Rhetorical Studies Minor. Speakers Series, 11, 1998, pp. 1–55.
Schiappa, Edward. 2003. Defining reality. Carbondale and Edwardsville: Southern Illinois University
Press.
Stebbing, Susan. 1933. A modern introduction to logic. New York: The Humanities Press.
Stevenson, Charles L. 1944. Ethics and language. New Haven: Yale University Press.
van Rees, Agnes. 2005. Indicators of dissociation. In Argumentation in practice, ed. F. Van Eemeren and
P. Houtlosser, 53–67. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Victorini, C. Marii. 1997. Liber de Definitionibus, mit Einleitung, Übersetzung und Kommentar von
Andreas Pronay, Peter Lang, Frankfurt.
Walton, Douglas. 2005. Deceptive arguments containing persuasive language and definitions. Argumen-
tation 19: 159–186.
Walton, Douglas. 2006. Fundamentals of critical argumentation. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Walton, Douglas. 2008. Arguing from definition to verbal classification: The case of redefining ‘planet’ to
exclude pluto. Informal Logic 28(2): 129–154.
Walton, Douglas, Chris Reed, and Fabrizio Macagno. 2008. Argumentation schemes. New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Weaver, Richard. 1953. The ethics of rhetoric. Chicago: Henry Regnery Company
Windes, Russell and Arthur Hastings. 1965. Argumentation and advocacy. New York: Random House
123
Reasoning from Classifications and Definitions 107
Zarefsky, David. 1997. Definitions. In Argument in a time of change, ed. J. Klumpp. Proceeding of the
Tenth NCA/AFA Conference on Argumentation, Utah, August 1997, National Communication
Association, Annandale.
Zarefsky, David. 2006. Strategic maneuvering through persuasive definitions: Implications for dialectic
and rhetoric. Argumentation 20: 399–416.
123
View publication stats