Open navigation menu
Close suggestions
Search
Search
en
Change Language
Upload
Sign in
Sign in
Download free for days
0 ratings
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
471 views
160 pages
Set Theory and The Continuum Hypothesis
A good book on set theory
Uploaded by
Dibyendu Pramanik
AI-enhanced title
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content,
claim it here
.
Available Formats
Download as PDF or read online on Scribd
Download
Save
Save Set-theory-and-the-continuum-hypothesis For Later
Share
0%
0% found this document useful, undefined
0%
, undefined
Print
Embed
Report
0 ratings
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
471 views
160 pages
Set Theory and The Continuum Hypothesis
A good book on set theory
Uploaded by
Dibyendu Pramanik
AI-enhanced title
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content,
claim it here
.
Available Formats
Download as PDF or read online on Scribd
Carousel Previous
Carousel Next
Download
Save
Save Set-theory-and-the-continuum-hypothesis For Later
Share
0%
0% found this document useful, undefined
0%
, undefined
Print
Embed
Report
Download
Save Set-theory-and-the-continuum-hypothesis For Later
You are on page 1
/ 160
Search
Fullscreen
SET THEORY AND THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS Paul J. Cohen Stanford University W. A. BENJAMIN, INC. New York 1966 AmsterdamSET THEORY AND THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS Copyright © 1966 by W. A. Benjamin, Inc. Alll rights reserved Library of Congress Catalog Card Number 66-2866 4 Manufactured in the United States of America Final copy ready for camera was received from the author on July 21, 1966; this volume was published on September 16, 1966 W. A. Benjamin, Inc. New York, New York 10016‘PREFACE The notes that follow are based on a course given at Harvard Uni- versity, Spring 1965. ‘the main objective was to give the proof of the independence of the continuum hypothesis. To keep the course as self- contained as possible we included background material in logic and ax- jomatic set theory as well as an account of Gédel's proof of the con- sistency of the continuum hypothesis. Our review of logic is of neces- sity rather sketchy although we have tried to cover some of the funda- mental concepts such as formal systems, undecidable statements and re- cursive functions. Actually, with the exception of the Léwenheim-Skolem theorem, none of the results of the first chapter are used in the later work and the reader who has had an introductory course in logic may omit this chapter. Its primary purpose is to accustom mathematicians who are not specialists in logic to the strictly precise point of view which is necessary when dealing with questions in the foundations of mathematics. Also, it is intended to clarify certain common confusions such as that of the concept of an undecidable statement in a particular axiom system with the concept of an unsolvable problem, which concerns nethods of computation, Since our very sincere hope is to make these notes intelligible to the large body of non-specialists who are interested in the problem, we have not adopted the very formalistic style which is to be found in some textbooks on logic. Rather we have tried to emphasize the intuitive mo- tivations while at the same time giving as complete proofs as possible. No specific background is assumed, although we occasionally refer to ex- amples from other parts of mathematics, Of course, it would be helpful if the reader were familiar with the development of "naive" set theory as it is customarily taught in courses on real variables or point set topology.We would like to thank most heartily L. Corwin, D. Pincus, T. Scanlon, R. Walton, and J. Xenakis for taking notes for various sec- tions and Jon Barwise for helping in the preparation of the final version. To Azriel Lévy we are deeply indebted for corrceting many errors, for many improvements in presentation, and for helping to bring the entire stylistic level of these notes above their rather primitive original state. ‘thanks are also duc to the members of the course at large who consistently challenged all mistakes and who by their stimulating discussion made teaching the course a distinct pleasure. ‘the notes are certainly not in the polished form the sub- ject warrants, but since there is no reasonably complete account of these questions in the literature, we thought it best to publish them in the present informal manner rather than to procrastinate in- definitely. Lastly, our sincere thanks go to the typists who worked on the notes, principally Sue Golan and Mari Wilson, for their fine efforts.CHAPTER I. WON AU FW 10. ne CONTENTS GENERAL BACKGROUND IN LOGIC . Introduction ... Formal Languages Universally Valid Statements . Gddel Completeness Theorem .. The Léwenheim-Skolem Theorem . Examples of Formal Systems .. Primitive Recursive Functions General Recursive Functions .. Gédel Incompleteness Theorem . Generalized Incompleteness Theorem Further Results in Recursive Functions .... CHAPTER II. ZERMELO-FRAENKEL SET THEORY ...-..-+eseeeeeeeee OIA FWP AXLOME ceceseseeseceees . Discussion of the Axioms Ordinal Numbers .... Cardinal Numbers . The Axion of Regularity .... The System of Gédel-Bernays .. Higher Axioms and Models for Set Theory . Léwenheim-Skolem Theorem Revisited ... CHAPTER III. THE CONSISTENCY OF THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS Ou FUR AND THE AXIOM OF CHOICE Introduction . Proof of Theorem 1 . Absoluteness .... Proof of AC and GCH in L Relations with GB ‘The Minimal Model CHAPTER IV. ‘THE INDEPENDENCE OF THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS AND THE AXIOM OF CHOICE ...... Introduction .. Intuitive Motivation . The Forcing Concept ‘The Main Lemmas .. 85 85 92 95 99 107 1o7 109 113 8120 5. Definability of Forcing 6. The Model No .sssseeeveeseee wal 7. The General Forcing Concept . 127 8. The Continuum Hypothesis . 1e9 9. The Axiom of Choice ... 136 10. Changing Cardinalities . 143 11. Avoiding SM... 1k7 12. GCH Implies AC . 148 13. Conclusion .....4. 150 REVERENCES 0s .eseeseeeeeeeees Ron UUS nS ESEnocnaE an oe 153CHAPTER I GENERAL BACKGROUND IN LOGIC 1. IwwrROpUCTION It is now known that the truth or falsity of the continuum hypoth- esis and other related conjectures cannot be determined by set theory as we know it today. This state of affairs regarding a classical and presumably well-posed problem must certainly appear rather wsatisfac- tory to the average mathematician. One is tempted to look more closely and perhaps more critically at the foundations of mathematics. Although our present "Cantorian" mathematics is highly successful in its treat- ment of abstractions, one must not overlook the fact that from the vory beginning the use of infinite processes was regarded with suspicion by many people. In the 19th century, the objections regarding the use of convergent series and real numbers were met by Cauchy, Dedekind, Cantor and others, only to be followed by more profound criticisms from later mathematicians such as Brouwer, Poincaré and Weyl. The controversy which followed resulted in the formation of various schools of thought concerning the foundations. It is safe to say that no attitude has been completely successful in answering the fundamental questions, but rather that the difficulties seem to be inherent in the very nature of mathe- matics. Despite the fact that the continuum hypothesis is a very dra- matic example of what might be called an absolutely undecidable state- ment (in our present scheme of things), Gédel's incompleteness theorem still represents the greatest obstacle to a satisfactory philosophy of mathematics. These fundamental difficulties, often dismissed by mathe- maticians, make the independence of the continuum hypothesis less sur- prising.2 GENERAL BACKGROUND IN LOGIC ch. I Gauss seems to have been the first mathematician to have expressed doubts about too free a use of infinities. In 1831, he wrote, "I protest ..-egainst the use of an infinite magnitude as something completed, which is never permissible." Later, Kronecker expressed views which were crit- ical of definitions that required an infinite process to verify that an object satisfied them. Cantor's work on set theory was the subject of much criticism to the effect that it dealt with fictions. Nevertheless, infinite sets are accepted today with few reservations. The traditional attitude accepts the construction of the real number system from the ra- tionals as the last and final step in the long series of criticisms and re-examinations which have marked the history of mathematics. What pos- sible objections can be raised to the construction of the real numbers? Simply this: although the reals are based on the integers, the vague notion of an arbitrary set of integers (or, equivalently, an arbitrary sequence of integers) must be introduced. Mathematicians inclined to a finitist point of view might hold that only sets which have an explicit rule to determine which integers are in the set should be admitted. For example, the school of Brouwer (Intuitionism) would only admit finite sets as legitimate objects of study, and even a single integer would not be considered defined unless a very definite rule for computing it was given. (For instance, the set consisting of 5 if Fermat's Last Theorem is true and 7 if it is false is not well-defined, according to Brouwer.) The criticism of Weyl and Poincaré was directed against "impredicative" definitions. Although their objections were not as extreme as Brouwer's, the acceptance of these’ criticisms would mean the destruction of large portions of mathematics. Another source of objections was the paradoxes or antinomies of set theory. In Cantor's set theory a set was thought of as being defined by a property. Cantor himself pointed out that the set of all sets leads to an absurdity. Although this type of paradox (along with those of Russell, Burali-Forti and others), seems entirely remote from ordinary mathematical reasoning, the paradoxes did point out the necessity of cx- treme care when attempting to describe which properties describe sets. In 1908, Zermclo presented a formal set of axioms for set theory which encompassed all the present day reasonings in mathematics and yet which is presumably free from paradoxes, This axiouatization of set theory$2 FORMAL LANGUAGES 2 was in keoping with the spirit of the school of Formalism, led by David Hilbert. According to the Formalist point of view, mathematics should be regarded as a purcly formal game played with marks on paper, and the only requirement this game need fulfill is that it does not lead to an inconsistency. To completely describe the game required setting down the rules of mathematical logic with much greater precision than had ‘een previously done. This was done, and the Formalists turned their attention to showing that various systems were consistent. As is well known, this hope was destroyed by Gédel's discovery of the incomplete- ness theorem, which implies that the consistency of a mathematical sys- tem cannot be proved except by methods more powerful than those of the system itself. Despite this failure, the Formalist program contributed greatly to the development of logic by establishing a systematic study of mathe- matical systems. In these notes, our first object will be to describe how a mathematical system can be completely reduced to a purely formal game involving the manipulation of symbols on paper. By a formal system we shall mean a finite collection of symbols and perfectly precise rules for manipulating these symbols to form certain combinations called "the- orems". Of course, these rules must be given in informal mathematical language. However, we shall demand that they be completely explicit rules requiring no infinite processes to check and that in principle they can be coded into computing machine. In this way questions con- cerning infinite sets are replaced by questions concerning the combina- torial possibilities of a certain formal game. Then we will be able to say that certain statements are not decidable within given formal sys- tems. 2. FORMAL LANGUAGES If we examine Peano's axioms for the integers, we find that they are not capable of being transcribed in a form acceptable to a computing ma- chine. This is because the crucial axiom of induction speaks about "sets" of integers but the axioms do not give rules for forming sets nor other basic properties of sets, Here is an example of the difficulty in satis- fying the stringent requirements for a formal system outlined above. When4 GENERAL BACKGROUND IN LOGIC ch. L we do construct a formal system corresponding to Peano's axions we shall find that the result can not quite live up to all our expectations. This difficulty is associated with any attempt at formalization. ‘two types of symbols will appear in our formal language. First, there are those symbols common to all mathematical systems. Then there are those used to denote particular concepts in special branches of math- ematics, such as the symbols for addition, group multiplication, adjoint of a matrix, etc. The general symbols we shall use are the following: & v 4 o not and, or implies if and only if v = G) ee for all there exists equals parentheses variable symbols Thc words beneath the symbols have, in principle, nothing to do with our “Qo! as formally formal language. Rather, we are thinking of the symbol representing the words "if and only if". The ordinary meanings of these words will suggest certain rules concerning the symbols, but the formal game must be played by the rules without recourse to any meanings which may have suggested then. The first five symbols are known as propositional connectives. The symbols which formally represent "for all" and "there exist” are know as universal and existential quantifiers respectively. Parentheses are used in the formation of expressions to insure their unique readability. In any given discussion one may need arbitrarily many variables so that we shall use x, x', x",..-, as symbols for variables. In practice we will use the letters x,, xp) x)+-- or x, y, 2 although in theory these should be replaced by x, x', x",... . In this way we need only a finite set of symbols. Our list of symbols is in no sense the most economical for our purposes since (as will follow from the rules for our formal system) some of the symbols can be avoided by combinations of others. For example, it will follow from rules A and G below that V could be replaced by ~~ . We shall sometimes omit parentheses or employ other abbreviations in our formulas if there is no danger of confusion.$2 FORMAL LANGUAGES 5 To express interesting statements we need special symbols which will be used to formally represent particular relations under consider- ation. For this purpose we admit a finite set of relation symbols R,, Royer + To each R, is assigned an integer ny 21, ny intuitively indicating that the relation represented by R, is a relation between Ry objects. For example, if me 2, then R, is a binary relation (such as < between real numbers), and in our rules for forming formal expressions we will require that R, be folloved by two variables or constants as in Rj (x,y) and Ry (c)2)- We will say that R, is an n,- ary predicate symbol, and sometimes write Ry (x 9+0%,)) to indicate n, explicitly. We shall also use particular symbols to represent con- stants which play special role in the system. For example, in group theory it is convenient to have a symbol for the identity element. We use the letter "c" together with "' " to generate the symbols c, c', c", ete. to represent constants. In practice, we write more simply ey oy ete. Before we give the precise rules for forming the formal expressions of our formal language we give some examples. Instead of thinking of "addition" an an operation on pairs of numbers, we can think of it as a relation between triples of numbers, namely the relation rt+s=t. Thus if we are considering » formal language in which R, is a ternary relation symbol, we could let R represent this relation. Then the uniqueness of addition would be insured by Vx Vy VzVu ((R, (x,y,z) & R, (x,y5u)) ~z=u If we let multiplication (r+ s = +) be represented by R,(x,y,z), then the associativity of multiplication becomes Va Wy We St, St, 3t,(,(oy,t,) @R(ty »2/t)) &R,(¥,2,t3) OR, (20t, 5tp)) ‘The existence of an additive identity can be stated as Ax Wy (R,(x,y,y)) tut this would be inconvenient in many cases. For, whenever an argument used this additive identity we would have to restate its existence. It is simpler to use a constant symbol "0" and introduce as an axiom6 GENERAL BACKGROUND IN LOGIC Ch. I Vx (x + 0+ x). In general the use of abbreviations is indispensable for making mathematics comprehensible and we shall not hesitate to use them when their meaning is clear and when it is also clear how to re- place them by the strict formal language. Let us examine further our formal system using only the special relation symbols R, end R, representing addition and miltiplication. It is not hard to see that we can express all the axioms of Field Theory within the system. (Observe that we are not yet discussing proofs or “true” statements, merely what can be expressed.) More complicated as- sertions such as the fact that a quadratic equation has at most two roots can be written as follows? Neyo du dv Wx (x? + ax + b= 0) 4 (x=uvx=v))- We leave as an exercise to show how the forma x° +2x+b=0 can be transcribed in the formal system. One encounters difficulty if one tries to say that an equation of degree n has at most n roots. This is because we have no notation (within the formal system) for an inte- ger to denote the degree of an arbitrary polynomial nor an induction procedure to define the notion of a polynomial of arbitrary degree. Thus we cannot handle properties which involve the notion of an arbitrary in- teger. Nevertheless, one could formulate the theorems of Galois theory for quadratic, cubic, etc. extensions by speaking only of root perm tations. Gelois theory in its customary formation speaks about sets, such as sub-fields, sub-groups, etc. and so cannot be expressed directly in our system. We now give the precise rules for forming grammatically correct statements. These are called well-formed formilas (wff). Recall that our formal language consists of the general symbols given above includ- ing variable symbols and constant symbols, as well as a finite number of relation symbols each associated with an integer. Rules for well-formed formulas 1. x=yx=c,c=c! are wff's where x and y are variable sym- pols and c and c' are any constant symbols. 2. If R is an n-ary relation symbol and each of t,,...,t, is either s& variable or constant symbol, then R(t) y++.5t,) is a wef.§2 FORMAL LANGUAGE 7 3. If A and Bare wff's so are ~(A), (A) & (B), (A) v (B), (A) (8), and (A) <> (B). 4, If A isa wf, then soare AxA and Vxa. Observe that our wff's may have loose constant and variable symbols dangling about. Also Rule 4 allows an expression such as Vxy=z as avwff. This is to be interpreted intuitively as meaning that if Wx or Hx occurs before a wff A which does not involve x then the ef- fect of the quantifiers is nil, and they can be omitted. This brings us to the precise distinction between bound and free variables. Definition. Fach occurrence of a variable symbol in a wff is defined as free or bounded as follows: 1. Every variable occurring in a formula of the form mentioned in Rules land 2 is free, 2. The free and bound occurrences of variables in the wff's mentioned in Rule 3 are precisely the samc as those for A and B separately. 3. the free and bound occurrences of a variable in a formula JxA or VxA are the same as those of A except that every free occurrence of x is now considered bound. ‘The reader may object that we have been too carcless in Rule 4 by allowing bound variables to be bound again. Actually, no confusion is possible if we agree that such quantification has no effect, but to be more specific we can make the following definition: Definition. A wff is called "good" if in the application of Rule 3, A and B have only free variables in common, and in the application of Rule 4, x occurs as a free variable in A. The conventions concerning the use of parentheses are such that no ambiguity can arise, This would actually require a simple coubinatorial argument, which we omit, Definition. A statement is a formula with no free variables.8 GENERAL BACKGROUND IN LOGIC ch. I 3. UNIVERSALLY VALID STATEMENTS The object of mathematics is to discover “true” theorems. We shall use the term "valid" to describe statements formed according to certain rules and then shall discuss how this notion compares with the intuitive idea of "true". When we write down a statement involving certain con- stant and relation symbols, we have not indicated any specific interpre- tation of these symbols. If such a statement is to be intuitively con- sidered as "true" it must be true independently of how these symbols are interpreted. For example, (f A 1s the conjunction of the usual axioms for field theory and B is the statement that a quadratic equation has at most two roots, then A+B isa true statement, because in any sys- tem where the axioms hold with regard to two ternary relations (which we may call addition and multaplication), a quadratic equation may have at most two roots. We shall introduce the concept of a model for a for- mal system and a fundamental result will be the identification of the valid statements with those that are true in overy model. The rulcs for forming valid statements arc known as the Predicate Calculus. A certain simple sub-system of these rules, whose importance was realized before the other rules, is known as the Propositional Cal- culus, ‘These are the rules concerning the manipulation of the symbols ~s&,v, 4,4. For the moment, let Ay, 4 be variable let- pee ters, not to be confused with the variables uscd in the formal ianguage. These variables will eventually be replaced by wff's. Definition. A propositional function is a formal string of symbols de- fined as follows: l. If A isa variable letter then A is a propositional function. 2. If P and Q are propositional functions so arc ~ (P), (P) & (Q), (P) v (Q), (P) +(@), and (P) (a). If P is a propositional function of the variables Apr A, (that is, P only involves variable letters among the A,,...,A,, and not nec- essarily all of these), we wish lo indicate how the truth or falsity of P depends on that of A,. To this end we associate wth P a function defined on the set of all n-tuples of O and 1 (i.e., (epee), where is either 0 or 1) taking the values 0 and 1. This is done as follows: 4§3 FORMAL LANGUAGE 9 1, The propositional function A, corresponds to the projection func- tion (eys--4¢,) +e. 2. If f is the function corresponding to P and g that for Q, the functions corresponding to ~ (P), (P) & (Q), (P) v (a), (P) +(@), (P) 4 (Q) are respectively, 9,(f), 9,(f,8)) 93(f 6), 9,(f8), 9,(f8) where the 9, are given by the “truth tables": fe oe eee ee oO 1 oO ae oO = oO x x x x x 1 Ol of o/o] +s ofof}1z} 4 of2fal ¢ oO lio 1[ 0 1 1jl 1 ae - 1) 0 1 930409) 9, (59) ~ & v > o The reader will casily check that this corresponds to the usual usage of the propositional connectives, with the understanding that 1 represents truth and 0 falsity. We define a propositional function as identically true if the corresponding function takes only the value 1. This means intuitively that the propositional function is "true" no matter what statements are substituted for the variables. We can now state the basic rule of the Propositional Calculus Rule A (Rule of the Propositional Calculus) If P is a propositional function of the variable letters A,,...,4, wnich is identically true, then the result of replacing each A, by any statement is a valid statement. Recall that our intended meaning of the term "valid statement" will be a statement which is intuitively true in any interpretation of the re- lation and constant symbols used to form it. There is another rule of the predicate calculus related to A which allows us to form new valid statements from old ones. It has often been illustrated by statements concerning the mortality of Socrates. Rule B (Rule of Inference) If A and (A) +(B) are valid statements so is B. We next give the rules for manipulating the sign of equality.30 GENERAL BACKGROUND IN LOGIC ch. I Rule C (Rules of Equality) lL. cee, (ce =e') 3(e' =e), and ((c =c') & (ec = c")) a(e = 0") are valid statements where c, c', c" are any three constant symbols. 2, If A isa statement, c and c' constant symbols, and if A’ re- presents A with every occurrence of c replaced by c', then (ec = ¢')—+((A) +(A')) is a valid statement. Rule D (Change of Variables) If A is any statement and A' results from A by replacing cach occurrence of the symbol x with the symbol x', where x and x' are any two variable symbols, then the statement (A) «+(A') is a valid statement. Both of these rules are obvious and require no discussion. It is a simple exercise to show that for every statement A, there is a "good" statement A' obtained by replacing the variable symbols in A by other variable symbols, and such that (A) ¢+(A') is a valid statement. For the next rule, let A(x) represent a formula with one free variable x and in which every occurrence of x is free and let A(c) represent the result of replacing every occurrence of x by the constant symbol c. Rule E (Rule of Specialization) (Vx A(x)) +(A(c)) is a valid statement where c is any constant symbol. The next rule is a bit misleading and requires some explanation. Often in arguments we say "let c be an arbitrary but fixed integer”. We then proceed to reason about ¢ and come to @ certain conclusion A(c). We can then deduce that Vx A(x) since we used no special prop- erties of c. In reality, we have treated ¢ as a variable, even though we called it a constant, This is because our valid statements will be true in every interpretation of the constant and relation symbols. We could express this by: if A(c) is a valid statement sois Vx A(x). However, rule F is in a form more convenient for our purposes and yields the above, as we shall see. Rule F Let B be a statement not involving c or x. Then if A(c) 9B is valid, so is HxA(x) +B.gh GODEL COMPLETENESS THEOREM ul The next rule will allow us to bring every formula involving quanti- fiers into a form in which it begins with a quantifier. Rule G Let A(x) have x as the only free variable and let every occur- rence of x be free, Let B be a statement which does not contain x. Then the following are valid statements. (~ (Wea(x))) > (Ax ~ (A(x))) ((MeA(x)) & (B)) > (eC (A(x)) & (B))) (Ca xA(x)) & (B)) > (Bx(A(x)) & (B)) Definition. Let S be a collection of statements. We say that A is derivable from 8, if for some B,,...,B, in S, the statement ((B) ieee & (B,)) (A) is valid. Fact: If S and §' are collections of statements such that every statement in S' is derivable from 8, then every statement derivable from $' is derivable from S. Proof. Exercise. In the course of a proof we often reason by con- tradiction or assume certain hypotheses temporarily. Such steps are all justified by the propositional caleuJus, although we shall not give all the formal details in applications. Assume for example we know that A(c) is a valid statement. We shall show that V(x) A(x) is valid. (This is not the same as saying A(c) + Vx) A(x) is valid, which it is not in gen- eral.) It is sufficient to show that ~ W(x) A(x) leads to a contra- diction (i.e., B&~B for any B). Equivalently by Rule G we show that Hx~ A(x) leads ta a contradiction. But ~A(c) does lead to a con- tradiction since A(c) is valid and hence by Rule F so does Sx ~ A(x). 4, GODEL, COMPLETENESS THEOREM Having now given rules for forming valid statements we come to the problem of identifying these statements with the intuitively "true" statements. This discussion will be carried out in the spirit of tradition12 GENERAL BACKGROUND IN LOGIC ch. I mathematics, that is to say, outside of any formal language. We shall use some elementary notions of set theory. After we have formalized set theory itself, then of course this discussion can be expressed in that formal system. In our original discussion, we had a finite number of symbols. This was important for foundational purposes, in order to re- duce mathematics to a formal game playable by a computing machine. How- ever, for some purposes it is of interest to allow arbitrarily many con- stant and relation symbols. We write the proofs of Sections 4 and 5 for this more general case. Assume now that we are dealing with a collection S of statements involving constants ¢,, @¢ I, and relation symbols R,, B ¢ J, vhere each R, has a fixed number of variables. Let M be @ non-empty set and le Cy fq be a map from the constant symbols to elements of M, not nec- essarily distinct, and R, +R, @ map which associates to @ k-ary relatio symbol, a subset of the k-fold direct product, MXMx +++ XM, We shall then say that we have an interpretation of the constants fy and the re- lation symbols R, in the set M. To every statement using only these constant symbols and relation symbols, we shall associate its “truth value" under this interpretation. Intuitively, of course, we merely mean whether or not the statement is true in M under the given interpreta- tion of the constant and relation symbols. However, a precise definition is easy to give if we proceed by induction on the iength of formulas. Definition. Let A be a formula with free variables among Rp Xs n> 0, and let Ryo er ok pe elements of M. We define the truth value of A (in M) at xy. 1, If A is of the form x, in mm Ky se ___——s~_—=™=TE at Ky.ok if Xk, =x,, % = c, or =6 a t 7 pF 1 = Sy respectively. eeceeeeeeraeeee eae R(t» ++ yt,) where R is an m-ary relation symbol and each t, is a constant symbol or one of the x,,...,x,, then A is true at X),..+,%, if the m-tuple By ot) isin R (the sub- set of M™ associated with R under the given interpretation). 3. If A is a propositional function of formulas, we evaluate the truth of A at x a ok, by means of the propostional calculus.gh GODEL COMPLETENESS THEOREM 13 4, If A is of the form V(y)B(y,x,,.+.5x,)[resp. AyB(y,x,,.-+5%,)] then A is true at york, if, forall y in M [resp. for some y in M] BY, x1 9+++9%,) is true at J, X.-+o%,+ To avoid any ambiguity over substitution of variables we may assume that all the formulas are good wff's as defined in Section 3. We note that if A is a statement we can take n = 0, and our definition is just truth in M under the given interpretation. Definition. oe S isa set statements containing Ly and Ry Ma set and ey +6, and R, +R, are maps as above, ve say that M isa model for § (under the interpretation) if all the statements of $ are true in M. Strictly speaking a model is a set M together with an interpreta- tion of some (possibly none) constant and relation symbols. Unless it is necessary for clarity, we shall suppress any mention of the explicit interpretation. Definition. A set of statements is said to be consistent if the state- ment A&~A cannot be derived from S$ for any A. The point of these definitions is the following obvious fact: THEORFM 1. If A is a valid statement, it is true in every model. If a set of statements § has a model then it is consistent. We omit the tedious proof, which is merely a verification that the rules of the predicate calculus correspond to correct methods of deduc- tion. A much more interesting question is whether the rules we have given exhaust all possible deductions. With out notion of models we can phrase this quite precisely. THEOREM 2, Godel Completeness Theorem. Let S be any consistent set of statements, ‘Then there exists a model for §$ whose cardinality does not exceed the cardinality of the number of statements in S if S is infinite, and is countable if S is finite. The proof uses the axiom of choice (unless the set S is already well-ordered). Given S we shall explicitly show how to construct awy GENERAL BACKGROUND IN LOGIC ch. I model for S. The proof however is non-constructive in the sense that the construction of the model for S may depend upon examining an in- finite number of possibilities. Neverthcless, if S is finite, the model can be taken as the set of integers and the resulting rclations will be arithmetically definable (i.e, definable by formulas using only addition and multiplication). This will follow from the form of the proof although we shall not go into the matter. The first step is an examination of the special case in which S does not contain any quantifiers. THEOREM 3. (Completeness of the Propositional Calculus). If S contains no quantifiers and is consistent, then there is a model M for § in which every element of M is of the form , for some ¢, appear- ing in 8. We need one lemma. LEMMA. If T is a consistent set of statements, A an arbitrary statement, either Tu (A) or TU (~A) is consistent. Proof. If TU (A) is inconsistent, then for some B, in 1, A&B, & +++ &B »C&~C for some C, is valid. If TU (~A) is in consistent, then for some By in T, (~A)& BL Bee & BL ~C&-Cis valid, The propositional calculus now implies that B, & ++: &B. & BY Bere & BL 3C&~C is valid, so that T must be inconsistent. Now to prove Theorem 3. Let § be well-ordered. This induces a well-ordering on all the constant and relation symbols which appear in 8, This in turn induces a well-ordering of all possible statements of the forn c, = ‘, and Ba(eys+--2e,) where c, and RB are constant and relation symbols occurring in 8. Call these statements F,. We now define statements G, by induction on a. If F, is consistent with Su (c,|B
a, € oO This motivates the following definition; Definition. x is an integer if 1) Wealycx&zexsy=zvyezviey) 2) Wiz (yex&zey +z x) One easily sees that in our intuitive model M, the sets o, are pre- cisely the sets satisfying this definition. Namely, first observe that in M every non-empty set x contains a member y such that if ze x then ~zey. That is, y is "minimal" with respect to the e-relation. Now if x is an integer in M, a "minimal" element of x must be $ by 2). If y is the minimal element of x - $ , then clearly by 1) and 2) y must be (g]. By repeating this operation, one can show that x must be equal to some o:. Thus our definition of integer is a reasonable one. Definition. If x is an integer, let x +1 denote x U (x). We show that x +1 is an integer. If y and z belong to x+l, either both belong to (x}, both belong to x, or one belongs to x and the other to (x}. Ifa set belongs to {x} it must equal x, so that in the first case y = 2, in the second since both belong to x and x is an integer 1) holds, and in the third we trivially have either ye z or zey. Thus 1) holds. If ye x+1 and zey, then if y =x, wehave zex so zex+l. If yex we again have 2 x, since x isan integer so zex+l. We can now state the induction axiom, Again AL (x, tyy rth) range over all formulas with at least one free variable. We write © in place of § and Int x as an abbreviation for the definition that x is an integer. : Ntpese ke [A(t s+ sty) & Wy (Int y &A (yt ot) > Ayly Ly ty ++sst))) 9 VeUInt x 9 AL(x,ty,---5t,))] Om$6 EXAMPLES OF FORMAL SYSTEMS Ea) This axiom scheme is essentially identical to the one given for zy. Again, we have not intuitively captured the complete strength of the in- formal induction principle since not every possible set of integers, is described by a property A, for suitable t,. Since as has been al- ready remarked, no set of axioms for the integers can be categorical, this is not an overpovering objection to our system. We now show how to develop conventional number theory in our system Z,. First, we define a function as a set of ordered pairs such that a set occurs as a left member at most once. The domain of the function is the set of left mem- bers. Now, whenever a function is defined in elementary number theory it usually is defined as follows: there is a certain condition B(x) which says that x is a set of ordered pairs defining a function on the integers
y as well as constants Axtons for Real-Closed Fields 1. Field Axioms These are the well-known axioms for a field which we do not bother to repeat here. 2. Order Axioms: i) Vay (xs yvx
O&y>O>xty>O&x+y>O) 3,° Completeness Axioms. Let f(x) denote age + total. The axion states Va +28 eXpy( f(x) >O& ty)
x(d,i) >M & x(d,j) >M & (x(a,4) and x(d,Jj) are relatively prime)]. Proof. In words, ii) says that forall n and M, we can find a a, such that x(d,i) for i
y is an abbreviation for 3z(z/0 & x=y+z). Also "x and y are relatively prime" can be written as Vavelkeu-schyev-zazell. We now define B(dji,x) as x=1+(i+1)d. If n and M are given, we can take d = (max(n,M))!, so that clearly x(d,i) >M. Also,30 GENERAL BACKGROUND OF LOGIC ch. I if 1
iii) for each N, there is a number (in the proof taken as N!) which is divisible by all n
You might also like
Paul Cohen - Set Theory and The Continuum Hypothesis
PDF
No ratings yet
Paul Cohen - Set Theory and The Continuum Hypothesis
160 pages
Set Theory, Logic, and Their Limitations - Machover, Moshé - 1996 - Cambridge New York - Cambridge University Press - 0521479983 - Anna's Archive
PDF
No ratings yet
Set Theory, Logic, and Their Limitations - Machover, Moshé - 1996 - Cambridge New York - Cambridge University Press - 0521479983 - Anna's Archive
312 pages
Paul J. Cohen - Set Theory and The Continuum Hypothesis - W. A. Benjamin (1966)
PDF
No ratings yet
Paul J. Cohen - Set Theory and The Continuum Hypothesis - W. A. Benjamin (1966)
160 pages
Kleene - Introduction To Metamathematics (1971) PDF
PDF
100% (6)
Kleene - Introduction To Metamathematics (1971) PDF
560 pages
Introduction To Axiomatic Set Theory
PDF
100% (1)
Introduction To Axiomatic Set Theory
255 pages
A Course in Mathematical Logic
PDF
No ratings yet
A Course in Mathematical Logic
617 pages
Stilwell Roads To Infinity PDF
PDF
No ratings yet
Stilwell Roads To Infinity PDF
193 pages
Set Theory and The Continuum Hypothesis
PDF
No ratings yet
Set Theory and The Continuum Hypothesis
160 pages
GTM001.Introduction - To.axiomatic - Set.theory (1ed, 1971) (ISBN.0387053026) (K) .Takeuti.G.,Zaring.W.M. (600dpi) (T) (259s) MAa .Djvu
PDF
No ratings yet
GTM001.Introduction - To.axiomatic - Set.theory (1ed, 1971) (ISBN.0387053026) (K) .Takeuti.G.,Zaring.W.M. (600dpi) (T) (259s) MAa .Djvu
259 pages
Roads To Infinity - The Mathematics of Truth and Proof - Stillwell
PDF
100% (9)
Roads To Infinity - The Mathematics of Truth and Proof - Stillwell
200 pages
The Continuum Hypothesis Is An Open Problem
PDF
100% (1)
The Continuum Hypothesis Is An Open Problem
4 pages
Monk J.D. Introduction To Set Theory (MGH, 1969) (ISBN 0070427151) (T) (O) (204s) - MAa
PDF
No ratings yet
Monk J.D. Introduction To Set Theory (MGH, 1969) (ISBN 0070427151) (T) (O) (204s) - MAa
204 pages
14 Jerome - Malitz - (Auth.) - Introduction - To - Mathematic PDF
PDF
No ratings yet
14 Jerome - Malitz - (Auth.) - Introduction - To - Mathematic PDF
208 pages
A Set Theory Workbook
PDF
No ratings yet
A Set Theory Workbook
162 pages
Gaisi Introduction To Axiomatic Set Theory
PDF
100% (1)
Gaisi Introduction To Axiomatic Set Theory
258 pages
Feferman - Infinity in Mathematics - Is Cantor Necessary
PDF
No ratings yet
Feferman - Infinity in Mathematics - Is Cantor Necessary
66 pages
Paul Cohen Set Theory and The Continuum Hypothesis PDF
PDF
No ratings yet
Paul Cohen Set Theory and The Continuum Hypothesis PDF
160 pages
Andrzej Grzegorczyk - An Outline of Mathematical Logic - Fundamental Results and Notions Explained With All Details (2011)
PDF
No ratings yet
Andrzej Grzegorczyk - An Outline of Mathematical Logic - Fundamental Results and Notions Explained With All Details (2011)
605 pages
Set Theory Notes 4
PDF
No ratings yet
Set Theory Notes 4
112 pages
Dixon, P.G. - Set Theory
PDF
No ratings yet
Dixon, P.G. - Set Theory
45 pages
A New Reading and Comparative Interpretation of Gödel's Completeness (1930) and Incompleteness (1931) Theorems
PDF
No ratings yet
A New Reading and Comparative Interpretation of Gödel's Completeness (1930) and Incompleteness (1931) Theorems
2 pages
Guide To Options at Part C - 1
PDF
No ratings yet
Guide To Options at Part C - 1
34 pages
Godel Proof
PDF
100% (1)
Godel Proof
31 pages
Georg Cantor (1845-1918) :: The Man Who Tamed Infinity
PDF
No ratings yet
Georg Cantor (1845-1918) :: The Man Who Tamed Infinity
33 pages
Set Theory
PDF
100% (2)
Set Theory
126 pages
Barnaby Sheppard-The Logic of Infinity-Cambridge University Press (2014)
PDF
100% (2)
Barnaby Sheppard-The Logic of Infinity-Cambridge University Press (2014)
498 pages
Elementary Set Theory
PDF
100% (2)
Elementary Set Theory
240 pages
Mathematics of Infinity
PDF
No ratings yet
Mathematics of Infinity
52 pages
Set Theory (Not Finish)
PDF
No ratings yet
Set Theory (Not Finish)
34 pages
Cantor and Gödel Refuted
PDF
No ratings yet
Cantor and Gödel Refuted
68 pages
Topic 22 Proof and Paradox
PDF
No ratings yet
Topic 22 Proof and Paradox
9 pages
300 Textfa 22
PDF
No ratings yet
300 Textfa 22
95 pages
Set Theory
PDF
No ratings yet
Set Theory
170 pages
Abstract 0
PDF
No ratings yet
Abstract 0
4 pages
Hintikka J. (Ed) - The Philosophy of Mathematics
PDF
No ratings yet
Hintikka J. (Ed) - The Philosophy of Mathematics
96 pages
Set Theory Notes 2
PDF
No ratings yet
Set Theory Notes 2
100 pages
Moerdijk-VanOosten2018 Book SetsModelsAndProofs
PDF
100% (2)
Moerdijk-VanOosten2018 Book SetsModelsAndProofs
151 pages
Lectures in Logic and Set Theory
PDF
No ratings yet
Lectures in Logic and Set Theory
20 pages
An Introduction To Set Theory
PDF
No ratings yet
An Introduction To Set Theory
119 pages
An Introduction To Highed Mathematics
PDF
No ratings yet
An Introduction To Highed Mathematics
138 pages
Fea Feferman
PDF
No ratings yet
Fea Feferman
6 pages
International Journal of Soft Computing, Mathematics and Control (IJSCMC)
PDF
No ratings yet
International Journal of Soft Computing, Mathematics and Control (IJSCMC)
17 pages
Philippeter AxiomaticSetTheory
PDF
No ratings yet
Philippeter AxiomaticSetTheory
54 pages
MATH 421 Practice
PDF
No ratings yet
MATH 421 Practice
86 pages
Yu. L. Ershov, E. A. Palyutin - Mathematical Logic-Mir Publishers (1984)
PDF
No ratings yet
Yu. L. Ershov, E. A. Palyutin - Mathematical Logic-Mir Publishers (1984)
303 pages
Logic Induction and Sets - Forster
PDF
100% (1)
Logic Induction and Sets - Forster
245 pages
Models Set Theory
PDF
No ratings yet
Models Set Theory
47 pages
Set Theory Oxford
PDF
No ratings yet
Set Theory Oxford
47 pages
Goodstein, Constructive Formalism
PDF
No ratings yet
Goodstein, Constructive Formalism
42 pages
Setth
PDF
No ratings yet
Setth
602 pages
Gödel's Completeness (1930) ND Incompleteness (1931) Theorems: A New Reading and Comparative Interpretation
PDF
No ratings yet
Gödel's Completeness (1930) ND Incompleteness (1931) Theorems: A New Reading and Comparative Interpretation
61 pages
The Continuum Hypothesis,: W. Hugh Woodin
PDF
No ratings yet
The Continuum Hypothesis,: W. Hugh Woodin
10 pages
The Continuum Hypothesis Part I
PDF
100% (1)
The Continuum Hypothesis Part I
10 pages
CBCS M.SC Syllabus
PDF
No ratings yet
CBCS M.SC Syllabus
123 pages
Grad Schedule
PDF
No ratings yet
Grad Schedule
1 page
Band Ler 1986
PDF
No ratings yet
Band Ler 1986
21 pages
Maths STD El
PDF
No ratings yet
Maths STD El
4 pages
Math CBCS B.SC - Syllabus Final
PDF
No ratings yet
Math CBCS B.SC - Syllabus Final
72 pages