Dokumen - Pub - Philosophy Politics Democracy Selected Essays 9780674271579
Dokumen - Pub - Philosophy Politics Democracy Selected Essays 9780674271579
Dokumen - Pub - Philosophy Politics Democracy Selected Essays 9780674271579
P H I L O S O P H Y,
POLITICS,
DEMOCRACY
Selected Essays
JOSHUA COHEN
H A R VA R D U N I V E R S I T Y P R E S S
Cambridge, Massachusetts, and London, England
2009
Copyright © 2009 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College
H61.15.C64 2009
321.8—dc22 2008052224
For Ellen
CONTENTS
Acknowledgments ix
Introduction 1
1 Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy 16
4 Freedom of Expression 98
5 Procedure and Substance in Deliberative Democracy 154
Index 387
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
have not tried to eliminate it. Nor have I updated the more empirical ma-
terials or the discussion of constitutional cases. Although reviewing them
has reminded me of their many flaws, I still hope that others will benefit
from reading them. The essays originally appeared in the following pub-
lications, and I thank the publishers for their permission to reprint:
Essay 1: “Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy,” in Alan Hamlin
and Phillip Petit, eds., The Good Polity (Oxford: Blackwell, 1989),
17–34.
Essay 2: “Moral Pluralism and Political Consensus,” in David Copp,
Jean Hampton, and John Roemer, eds., The Idea of Democracy
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 270–291. Copy-
right © 1993 Cambridge University Press. Reprinted with permis-
sion.
Essay 3: “Associations and Democracy” (with Joel Rogers), Social Phi-
losophy and Policy 10, 2 (Summer 1993): 282–312. Copyright © 1993
Social Philosophy and Policy Foundation. Reprinted with the per-
mission of Cambridge University Press.
Essay 4: “Freedom of Expression,” Philosophy & Public Affairs 22, 3
(Summer 1993): 207–263, by Blackwell Publishing Ltd.
Essay 5: “Procedure and Substance in Deliberative Democracy,” in
Seyla Benhabib, ed., Democracy and Difference: Changing Bound-
aries of the Political (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996),
95–119.
Essay 6: “Directly Deliberative Polyarchy” (with Charles Sabel), Eu-
ropean Law Journal 3, 4 (December 1997): 313–342, by Blackwell
Publishing Ltd.
Essay 7: “Democracy and Liberty,” in Jon Elster, ed., Deliberative De-
mocracy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), 185–231.
Copyright © 1998 Jon Elster. Reprinted with the permission of
Cambridge University Press.
Essay 8: “Money, Politics, Political Equality,” in Alex Byrne, Robert
Stalnaker, and Ralph Wedgwood, eds., Fact and Value (Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press, 2001), 47–80.
Essay 9: “Privacy, Pluralism, and Democracy,” in Joseph Keim Camp-
bell, Michael O’Rourke, and David Shier, eds., Law and Social Jus-
tice (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2005), 15–40.
Essay 10: “Reflections on Deliberative Democracy,” in Thomas
x
A C K N O W L E D G M E N T S
xi
P H I L O S O P H Y, P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
INTRODUCTION
1
We all have ideas that belong to political morality. We have some mix of
thoughts about rights and responsibilities, about the evil of slavery, cru-
elty, destitution, humiliation, and intolerance, about the fairness of social
inequality and the virtues of open discussion, about religious tolerance
and personal privacy, about whether the state is like a large family or
something fundamentally different, about the importance of a rule of law
and democracy, about when it is acceptable to fight a war and what we
owe to people in other places, and about whether justice is somehow
fixed by the nature of things or is a human construction.
Moreover, those thoughts, both more abstract and more concrete, play
a role in political life. That’s because politics is not only—though it is as-
suredly in (perhaps large) part—a struggle for power and a strategic pur-
suit of personal and group interests. Particularly in a democracy, politics
1
I N T R O D U C T I O N
1. See Jane Mayer, The Dark Side (New York: Doubleday, 2008), 219.
2
I N T R O D U C T I O N
not here arguing for a thesis, only expressing an outlook, the outlook ex-
pressed in these essays, which all are premised on a rejection of cynicism
about normative political discourse.
Normative political discourse is one thing, however; political philoso-
phy is something else. What do these observations about the place of nor-
mative thought in politics have to do with philosophy?
In his Prison Notebooks, Antonio Gramsci draws attention to the role
of normative ideas in our individual and collective conduct.2 Formu-
lating the point in striking terms, he says, “Everyone is a philosopher.”
That is because a “specific conception of the world” underlies our intel-
lectual activity. That conception, Gramsci says, is typically implicit, often
adapted from the “external environment,” passively internalized rather
than worked out “consciously and critically.” Gramsci probably over-
states the extent to which we each embrace a “specific conception of the
world,” a comprehensive doctrine with a significant degree of coherence
and stability, as distinct from a somewhat more inchoate family of convic-
tions. Still, his comment points to the role of a more or less connected set
of ideas in our ordinary understanding and conduct, a conception of the
world that comprises normative ideas, even if it is not confined to them.
More to the point, Gramsci’s invocation of philosophy suggests conti-
nuity between endorsing the conception of the world that shapes our
conduct—what he calls a spontaneous philosophy—and pursuing the
activity that we call political philosophy.3 Think of political philosophy as
a more reflective engagement with the political morality that shapes our
conduct and that we offer in argument to others, an engagement that
aims to bring greater coherence, comprehensiveness, and—most impor-
tantly—reasoned consideration to that morality. We suppose that our
convictions withstand scrutiny, and we think they are worthy of our alle-
giance—and suitable for political argument—because they do. Political
philosophy puts this thought to the test, aiming to judge, for example,
whether cruelty and torture are indeed morally on a par, each violating a
right to dignity; or whether treating people differently because of race or
gender is on a par with treating them differently because of differences in
2. Antonio Gramsci, Prison Notebooks, ed. and trans. Quintin Hoare and Geoffrey Nowell
Smith (New York: International, 1971), 323.
3. Gramsci distinguishes the possession of a conception of the world from a “second level,
which is that of awareness and criticism,” and he emphasizes the importance—sometimes the
necessity—of ordering “in a systematic, coherent and critical fashion one’s own intuitions of
life and the world.” Ibid., 323, 327.
3
I N T R O D U C T I O N
2
I attended graduate school in the mid-1970s, a period of great creativity in
political philosophy. John Rawls’s Theory of Justice had appeared in 1971,
followed soon by Robert Nozick’s Anarchy, State, and Utopia (1974).
This was also a period of political rethinking for people who, like me,
identified themselves as democrats and socialists and thought of their so-
cialism as principally a matter of political values—egalitarian, participa-
tory, and antiauthoritarian—rather than more specifically institutional
convictions about public ownership or a planned economy.
In 1975–76, I tried to write a PhD dissertation on socialism. The guid-
ing idea was that the socialism worth being concerned about—anyway,
the socialism that interested me normatively—had something to do with
democracy. The point was to create a more democratic society in many
5
I N T R O D U C T I O N
4. I eventually came to see that Rawls’s views were far more deeply shaped by a concep-
tion of democracy than I then understood. See Joshua Cohen, “For a Democratic Society,” in
Samuel Freeman, ed., Cambridge Companion to Rawls (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2002), 86–138.
6
I N T R O D U C T I O N
5. “Structure, Choice, and Legitimacy: Locke’s Theory of the State,” Philosophy and Public
Affairs 15, 4 (Fall 1986): 301–324.
6. “Reflections on Rousseau: Autonomy and Democracy,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 15,
3 (Summer 1986): 275–297.
7. “An Epistemic Conception of Democracy,” Ethics 97, 1 (October 1986): 26–38.
7
I N T R O D U C T I O N
of democracy). And I was working with the intuitive idea that democracy
might be thought of not only as a fair process or as an instrument for
achieving just ends but as a way to realize in actual political life an ideal
of justification through public reason-giving.
“Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy” (essay 1) was the result.
Originally written in 1986, it located deliberation—understood as a kind
of mutual reason-giving—as central to the democratic ideal in its most
attractive form. By making such reason-giving central, the deliberative
conception of democracy also showed how democracy was connected,
so I argued, with ideas of autonomy, equality, and the common good: de-
mocracy, understood deliberatively, was both a procedural and a substan-
tive ideal. And also, I thought, a specifically political ideal, not tied to
an encompassing moral outlook. The idea was not that people ought to
reason about everything, or guide their personal choices by reflective, au-
tonomous judgment, or that the unexamined life is not worth living, but
that the legitimacy that emerges from democratic collective choice re-
flects the role of reason-giving—of a kind of mutual justification—in the
process.
3
“Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy” proposed, then, that the de-
liberative conception, with its idea of reason-giving among equals, pro-
vides the most compelling account of settled elements of the democratic
ideal. And this suggested two lines of further evolution.
First, I wanted to see whether and how the idea of deliberative democ-
racy could serve as a unifying normative political ideal. Addressing that
issue required filling out its normative content, showing how it provided
argumentative traction in addressing disputed issues about liberty, equal-
ity, and the common good. I wrote several essays along these lines, which
aimed to show how deliberation, understood as a kind of reasoning, was
different from simply discussing and how the idea of deliberative democ-
racy could be used to organize an account of other political values. An es-
sential part of the argument, which I developed in “Moral Pluralism and
Political Consensus” (essay 2, originally written in 1990), was the idea of
reasonable pluralism.
Beginning in the mid-1980s, Rawls emphasized that societies that pro-
tect liberties are marked by what he called a “fact of pluralism,” a plural-
ism of distinct and incompatible comprehensive doctrines, religious and
8
I N T R O D U C T I O N
8. See the papers on “The Idea of an Overlapping Consensus,” “The Priority of Right and
Ideas of the Good,” and “The Domain of the Political and Overlapping Consensus,” all of
which emphasized the importance of the “fact of pluralism.” See John Rawls: Collected Papers,
ed. Samuel Freeman (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), chaps. 20, 21, 22.
9. Ibid., 479.
10. The paper presents a criticism of Rawls, but the point was to make a case about what he
really ought to have been saying in his account of political liberalism and overlapping consen-
sus. Rawls did shift focus to the fact of reasonable pluralism, though he also observes that both
facts are relevant. See Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996), 36–
37, 58–66.
9
I N T R O D U C T I O N
tions could play a larger regulatory role in advancing the common good
without ruining deliberative politics, and electoral finance (issues dis-
cussed in much greater detail in essays 3 and 8).
Because deliberative democracy has strong roots in a radical demo-
cratic tradition, emphasizing ideas of political autonomy, I was especially
concerned to show that and how it provided a way to think about the “lib-
erties of the moderns,” including religious and moral liberty. This, as I
mentioned earlier, was a gap in On Democracy. In “Deliberation and
Democratic Legitimacy,” I had tentatively suggested (in footnote 22) that
those liberties provided protections that bolster the confidence required
for independent participation. That thesis had the smell of the lamp.
Maybe confidence born of those protections emboldens people. Maybe
it privatizes. Who knows? And anyway, the argument assigned a kind
of unwanted privilege to political engagement. How could it be that
protections of liberties of conscience and of the person are simply a
shadow cast by the preconditions of participation? But wasn’t that conclu-
sion the natural consequence of an unnatural beginning? If you treat de-
mocracy—or, more abstractly still, politically autonomous lawgiving—as
basic, and are moved by convictions about the liberties of the moderns,
how can you avoid the suspicious result?
To address the issue, I focused initially on freedom of expression.
Though my concerns about freedom of expression grew partly out of an
interest in exploring the implications and plausibility of the conception
of deliberative democracy, I was also independently interested, as I men-
tioned earlier, in addressing a set of public debates about campus speech
codes, pornography, hate speech, and campaign finance. I was troubled
by the hate speech, could understand the concerns about pornography,
and saw that many people who shared an egalitarian sensibility thought
that concerns about regulation required a kind of abstract allegiance to
rights or liberty and that their egalitarianism put them on the side of a
less expression-friendly position.
After reading lots of constitutional cases and thinking about the differ-
ences between American and Western European protections of free ex-
pression, I was persuaded that no simple theory founded on a single
value or interest (autonomy, for example) would suffice to capture the
terrain. I proposed a view that had (to my mind) an attractive complexity,
founded on three basic interests—expressive, informational, and deliber-
ative—and a range of plausible judgments about the costs of regulation.
10
I N T R O D U C T I O N
In “Freedom of Expression” (essay 4), I did not present the theory as an il-
lustration of my account of deliberative democracy but as an indepen-
dently plausible view, which needed subsequently to be fit into the ac-
count of democracy, if it could be.11
“Procedure and Substance” pointed in the right direction, but I drew
out the connections most fully in “Democracy and Liberty” (essay 7),
which argues that religious, expressive, and moral liberties are essential
parts of democracy, not constraints upon it, that a political society is less
democratic to the extent that it fails to protect these liberties, and that
those liberties are not destructive of community, but integrative. Once
more, the argument turns on the reasons that can be used to defend regu-
lations in a society of equals, assuming the fact of reasonable pluralism.
Given the kinds of reasons that are expressed in religious conviction, for
example, and the need to justify to others on the basis of reasons that they
can reasonably accept, it will generally not be possible to justify regula-
tions of religious exercise. An essential part of the argument was to tie the
idea of finding such reasons to democracy itself, to the deliberative idea
that democracy is an arrangement of collective decision-making that
treats people as equals in part by offering reasons of a suitable kind. The
reason-giving among equals essential to deliberative democracy, along
with reasonable pluralism, brought the liberties inside the conception of
democracy. Deliberation and pluralism shape the content of what, in the
paper on “Privacy, Pluralism, and Democracy” (essay 9), I call “democ-
racy’s public reason.”
I also had been thinking for some time about political equality, which I
discussed briefly in “Procedure and Substance.” As a way to provide fo-
cus, I concentrated my attention on the troubled American system of
financing elections (essay 8). Once more—in part prompted by practical
engagement with the issue—I sketched an account of political equality
and campaign finance largely independent of the general conception of
deliberative democracy, drawing on arguments in American constitu-
tional law and empirical research on the role of money in elections. The
line of thinking adopted by the U.S. Supreme Court in Buckley v. Valeo
11. I also wrote a companion piece on pornography, “Freedom, Equality, and Pornography,”
in Austin Sarat and Thomas R. Kearns, eds., Justice and Injustice in Law and Legal Theory
(Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1996), 99–137, and in Jessica Spector, ed., Prostitu-
tion and Pornography: Philosophical Debate About the Sex Industry in the U.S. (Stanford: Stan-
ford University Press, 2006).
11
I N T R O D U C T I O N
12. Politics and Society 20, 4 (December 1992): 393–472. The essay was accompanied by re-
plies from Ellen Immergut, Andrew Levine, Jane Mansbridge, Philippe Schmitter, Wolfgang
Streeck, Andrew Szasz, and Iris Young.
13. “Sovereignty and Solidarity in the EU” (with Charles Sabel), in Jonathan Zeitlin and
David Trubek, eds., Governing Work and Welfare in a New Economy: European and American
Experiments (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003), 345–375; “Global Democracy?” (with
Charles Sabel), New York University Journal of International Law and Policy 37, 4 (2006): 763–
797.
13
I N T R O D U C T I O N
The penultimate essay (essay 10) aims at synthesis of some of the more
and the less philosophical arguments. I restate the idea of deliberative de-
mocracy, emphasizing the central role of reason-giving, explain why that
conception is not inattentive to the facts about political power, and dis-
cuss a range of considerations that might lead us to endorse the delibera-
tive view. I then explore some potential tensions between the deliberative
conception of democracy and the proposals to secure a more participa-
tory democracy. Deliberation and participation are arguably both impor-
tant elements of the democratic ideal, but it is easy to see how we might
be led to sacrifice the one for the other. The essay then concludes with a
discussion of some ways to remedy the tensions.
The concluding essay (“Truth and Public Reason”) is the most recent
and the most philosophical. Normative discourse, I said at the outset, is
part of politics. Moreover, it should be taken at face value, as concerned
with what we ought to do, not simply as a mask of attitude and interest. In
addition, it is continuous with the reflective, critical engagement with po-
litical values characteristic of political philosophy. In this essay, I argue
that the concept of truth has a role in public political discourse and pres-
ent a political conception of truth suited to that role. The kind of com-
mon ground that we might aim to occupy in political argument—a
ground of public reason—cannot make room for the whole truth. But be-
cause it is a form of reasoning about what we ought to do, it cannot dis-
avow a concern for truth. Preserving this concern does not turn practice
into theory but affirms the place of reflective normative thought in life.
4
I mentioned that essay 10 is concerned with accommodating the impor-
tance of deliberation and participation, which stand in uneasy tension.
This concern about reconciling tensions underscores a theme that runs
throughout the essays and is an especially important presence in the es-
says on political equality, procedure and substance, and associative de-
mocracy. Much work in political theory points in a very different direc-
tion: it draws our attention to the need to make hard choices. In the spirit
of Max Weber, Isaiah Berlin, and Bernard Williams, it reminds us that
all good things in life do not go together, and reminds us, too, that we
sometimes, in a cheerfully Panglossian or romantic spirit, gloss over these
tensions.
Such reminders are important. But the essays here are animated by a
14
I N T R O D U C T I O N
very different idea. My own experience is not that we are constantly yield-
ing to Panglossian temptations. Quite to the contrary, we are often too
quick to suppose that important values cannot be jointly realized, that
political life is filled with tragic conflicts between and among important
values. So we respond to political ideals with a knowing irony of the in-
tellect and a lassitude of the heart.
In his Gettysburg Address, Lincoln drew attention to the idea that the
United States was conceived in liberty and dedicated to a kind of equal-
ity. The question whether a country “so conceived and so dedicated”
could endure was very much open and not to be resolved through philo-
sophical argument. Still, Lincoln urged in effect that we not be too quick
to assume an intractable conflict. Perhaps conscientious and sustained
effort at improvement is not doomed to fail; perhaps we live in a perfect-
ible union. And here philosophy, too, has a role. It must not, of course,
deny the possibility of conflict between important values. But inspired by
hope, guided by reason, and focused on the political world as it might be,
philosophy can help us to see the possibility of more fully realizing our
largest political ideals.
15
1
D E L I B E R AT I O N A N D D E M O C R AT I C L E G I T I M A C Y
I have had countless discussions of the subject matter of this essay with Joel Rogers, and
wish to thank him for his unfailingly sound and generous advice. For our joint treatment of the
issues that I discuss here, see Joshua Cohen and Joel Rogers, On Democracy (Harmondsworth:
Penguin, 1983), ch. 6. The main differences between the treatment of issues here and the treat-
ment in the book lie in the explicit account of the ideal deliberative procedure, the fuller treat-
ment of the notions of autonomy and the common good, and the account of the connection of
those notions with the ideal procedure. An earlier draft of this essay was presented to the
Pacific Division Meetings of the American Philosophical Association. I would like to thank
Loren Lomasky, Alan Hamlin, and Philip Pettit for helpful comments on that draft.
1. I originally came across the term “deliberative democracy” in Cass Sunstein, “Interest
Groups in American Public Law,” Stanford Law Review 38 (1985): 29–87. He cites (n. 26) an ar-
ticle by Bessette, which I have not consulted.
16
D E L I B E R A T I O N A N D D E M O C R A T I C L E G I T I M A C Y
1
The idea of deliberative democracy is a familiar ideal. Aspects of it have
been highlighted in recent discussion of the role of republican concep-
tions of self-government in shaping the American constitutional tradition
and contemporary public law.2 It is represented as well in radical demo-
cratic and socialist criticisms of the politics of advanced industrial socie-
ties.3 And some of its central features are highlighted in Rawls’s account
of democratic politics in a just society, particularly in those parts of his
account that seek to incorporate the “liberty of the ancients” and to re-
spond to radical democrats and socialists who argue that “the basic liber-
ties may prove to be merely formal.” In the discussion that follows I shall
first say something about Rawls’s remarks on three such features, and
then consider his explanation of them.4
First, in a well-ordered democracy, political debate is organized
around alternative conceptions of the public good. So an ideal pluralist
2. For some representative examples, see Cass Sunstein, “Naked Preferences and the Con-
stitution,” Columbia Law Review 84 (1984): 1689–1732; idem, “Interest Groups in American
Public Law”; idem, “Legal Interference with Private Preferences,” University of Chicago Law
Review 53 (1986): 1129–1184. Frank Michelman, “The Supreme Court, 1985 Term—Foreword:
Traces of Self-government,” Harvard Law Review 100 (1986): 4–77. Bruce Ackerman, “The
Storrs Lectures: Discovering the Constitution,” Yale Law Journal 93 (1984): 1013–1072.
3. I have in mind, in particular, criticisms that focus on the ways in which material inequali-
ties and weak political parties restrict democracy by constraining public political debate or un-
dermining the equality of the participants in that debate. For discussion of these criticisms, and
of their connections with the ideal of democratic order, see Cohen and Rogers, On Democ-
racy, chs. 3, 6; Roberto Unger, False Necessity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987),
ch. 5.
4. In the discussion that follows, I draw on John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 1971), esp. sections 36, 37, 43, 54; John Rawls, “The Basic Liberties
and Their Priority,” Tanner Lectures on Human Values (Salt Lake City: University of Utah
Press, 1982). [The Tanner Lectures were reprinted as Lecture 8 in John Rawls, Political Liberal-
ism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996). I have kept the references to the original
here.]
17
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
5. Rawls, Theory of Justice, 360–361. [The page references to A Theory of Justice in essays 1–7
are to the 1971 edition. For a conversion table to page numbers in the revised, 1999 edition, see
John Rawls, A Theory of Justice, rev. ed. (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), 517–
519.] This rejection is not particularly idiosyncratic. Sunstein, for example, argues that ideal
pluralism has never been embraced as a political ideal in American public law. See his “Naked
Preferences” and “Interest Groups.”
6. Rawls, Theory, 360.
7. Ibid., 226, 472.
8. Ibid., 362.
9. Officially, the requirement of fair value is that “everyone has a fair opportunity to hold
public office and to influence the outcome of political decisions.” Rawls, “Basic Liberties,” 42.
10. Rawls, Theory, 225–226, 277–278; “Basic Liberties,” 42–43.
11. “Basic Liberties,” 43. Whatever their stringency, these distributional requirements take
priority over the difference principle, since the requirement of fair value is part of the principle
of liberty; that is, the first principle of justice. See ibid., 41–42.
18
D E L I B E R A T I O N A N D D E M O C R A T I C L E G I T I M A C Y
19
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
20
D E L I B E R A T I O N A N D D E M O C R A T I C L E G I T I M A C Y
people are looking for them. Even an ideal pluralist scheme, with equal
bargaining power and no barriers to entry, cannot reasonably be expected
to advance the common good as defined by the difference principle.18
But this is, I think, too indirect and instrumental an argument for the
three conditions. Like utilitarian defenses of liberty, it rests on a series of
highly speculative sociological and psychological judgments. I want to
suggest that the reason why the three are attractive is not that an order
with, for example, no explicit deliberation about the common good and
no manifest equality would be unfair (though of course it might be). In-
stead it is that they comprise elements of an independent and expressly
political ideal that is focused in the first instance19 on the appropriate
conduct of public affairs—on, that is, the appropriate ways of arriving at
collective decisions. And to understand that ideal we ought not to pro-
ceed by seeking to “mirror” ideal fairness in the fairness of political ar-
rangements, but instead to proceed by seeking to mirror a system of ideal
deliberation in social and political institutions. I want now to turn to this
alternative.
2
The notion of a deliberative democracy is rooted in the intuitive ideal of
a democratic association in which the justification of the terms and con-
ditions of association proceeds through public argument and reasoning
among equal citizens.20 Citizens in such an order share a commitment to
the resolution of problems of collective choice through public reasoning
and regard their basic institutions as legitimate insofar as they establish
the framework for free public deliberation. To elaborate this ideal, I be-
18. Rawls, Theory, 360.
19. The reasons for the phrase “in the first instance” are clarified below at 29.
20. Since writing the first draft of this section of the essay, I have read Jon Elster, “The Mar-
ket and the Forum: Three Varieties of Political Theory,” in Jon Elster and Aanund Hylland,
eds., Foundations of Social Choice Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986),
103–132; and Bernard Manin, “On Legitimacy and Political Deliberation,” Political Theory 15
(1987): 338–368, which both present parallel conceptions. This is especially so with Elster’s
treatment of the psychology of public deliberation (112–113). I am indebted to Alan Hamlin for
bringing the Elster article to my attention. The overlap is explained by the fact that Elster,
Manin, and I all draw on Jürgen Habermas. See Jürgen Habermas, Legitimation Crisis, trans.
Thomas McCarthy (Boston: Beacon Press, 1975); idem, Communication and the Evolution of
Society, trans. Thomas McCarthy (Boston: Beacon Press, 1979); and idem, The Theory of Com-
municative Action, vol. 1, trans. Thomas McCarthy (Boston: Beacon Press, 1984). I have also
found very helpful the discussion of the contractualist account of motivation in T. M. Scanlon,
“Contractualism and Utilitarianism,” in Amartya Sen and Bernard Williams, eds., Utilitarian-
ism and Beyond (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982), 103–128.
21
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
gin with a more explicit account of the ideal itself, presenting what I shall
call the “formal conception” of deliberative democracy. Proceeding from
this formal conception, I pursue a more substantive account of delibera-
tive democracy by presenting an account of an ideal deliberative proce-
dure that captures the notion of justification through public argument
and reasoning among equal citizens and serves in turn as a model for de-
liberative institutions.
The formal conception of a deliberative democracy has five main
features:
22
D E L I B E R A T I O N A N D D E M O C R A T I C L E G I T I M A C Y
ities, i.e., the capacities required for entering into a public ex-
change of reasons and for acting on the results of such public rea-
soning.
22. The distinction between the ideal procedure and an initial-choice situation will be im-
portant in the later discussion of motivation formation (see 26–27) and institutions (34–36).
23. There are of course norms and requirements on individuals that do not have deliberative
justification. The conception of deliberative democracy is, in Rawls’s term, a “political concep-
tion,” and not a comprehensive moral theory. On the distinction between political and com-
prehensive theories, see John Rawls, “The Idea of an Overlapping Consensus,” Oxford Journal
of Legal Studies 7 (1987): 1–25.
23
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
24
D E L I B E R A T I O N A N D D E M O C R A T I C L E G I T I M A C Y
25
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
26
D E L I B E R A T I O N A N D D E M O C R A T I C L E G I T I M A C Y
27. Jon Elster, “Sour Grapes,” in Sen and Williams, eds., Utilitarianism and Beyond, 219–
238. For an interesting discussion of autonomous preferences and political processes, see
Sunstein, “Legal Interference,” 1145–1158, and “Naked Preferences,” 1699–1700.
27
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
their desires, the Stoic slaves do not act autonomously when they seek to
be good slaves. The absence of alternatives and consequent denial of
scope for deliberative capacities that defines the condition of slaves sup-
ports the conclusion that their desires result from their circumstances,
even though those circumstances shape the desires of the Stoic slaves
through their deliberation.
There are then at least two dimensions of autonomy. The phenome-
non of adaptive preferences underlines the importance of conditions
that permit and encourage the deliberative formation of preferences; the
phenomenon of accommodationist preferences indicates the need for fa-
vorable conditions for the exercise of the deliberative capacities. Both
concerns are met when institutions for collective decision-making are
modeled on the ideal deliberative procedure. Relations of power and
subordination are neutralized (I1, I3, I4), and each is recognized as
having the deliberative capacities (D5), thus addressing the problem of
accommodationist preferences. Further, the requirement of reasonable-
ness discourages adaptive preferences (I2). While preferences are
“formed” by the deliberative procedure, this type of preferences forma-
tion is consistent with autonomy, since preferences that are shaped by
public deliberation are not simply given by external circumstances. In-
stead, they are the result of “the power of reason as applied through pub-
lic discussion.”28
Beginning, then, from the formal ideal of a deliberative democracy, we
arrive at the more substantive ideal of an association that is regulated by
deliberation aimed at the common good and that respects the autonomy
of the members. And so, in seeking to embody the ideal deliberative pro-
cedure in institutions, we seek, inter alia, to design institutions that focus
on political debates on the common good, that shape the identity and in-
terests of citizens in ways that contribute to an attachment to the com-
mon good, and that provide the favorable conditions for the exercise of
deliberative powers that are required for autonomy.
3
I want now to shift the focus. While I shall continue to pursue the rela-
tionship between the ideal procedure and more substantive issues about
deliberative democratic association, I want to do so by considering four
28
D E L I B E R A T I O N A N D D E M O C R A T I C L E G I T I M A C Y
29. See Cohen and Rogers, On Democracy, chs. 3, 6; Joshua Cohen, “The Economic Basis
of Deliberative Democracy,” Social Philosophy and Policy 6, 2 (1988): 25–50.
29
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
30. For contrasting views on sectarianism, see Rawls, “The Idea of an Overlapping Consen-
sus”; Ronald Dworkin, A Matter of Principle (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1985),
part 3; Alisdair MacIntyre, After Virtue (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1981);
Michael Sandel, Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1982).
30
D E L I B E R A T I O N A N D D E M O C R A T I C L E G I T I M A C Y
incoherence
Consider next the putative incoherence of the ideal. We find this charge
in an important tradition of argument, including Schumpeter’s Capital-
ism, Socialism, and Democracy and, more recently, William Riker’s work
on social choice and democracy. I want here to say a word about the lat-
ter, focusing on just one reason that Riker gives for thinking that the ideal
of popular self-government is incoherent.31
Institutionalizing a deliberative procedure requires a decision rule
short of consensus—for example, majority rule. But majority rule is glob-
ally unstable: as a general matter, there exists a majority-rule path leading
from any element in the set of alternatives to any other element in the
set. The majority, standing in for the people, wills everything and there-
fore wills nothing. Of course, while anything can be the result of the ma-
jority decision, it is not true that everything will be the result. But, be-
cause majority rule is so unstable, the actual decision of the majority will
not be determined by preferences themselves, since they do not constrain
the outcome. Instead decisions will reflect the particular institutional
constraints under which they are made. But these constraints are “exoge-
nous to the world of tastes and values.”32 So the ideal of popular self-gov-
ernment is incoherent because we are, so to speak, government by the in-
stitutions, and not by ourselves.
I want to suggest one difficulty with this argument that highlights the
structure of the deliberative conception. According to the argument I just
sketched, outcomes in majority-rule institutions reflect “exogenous” in-
stitutional constraints and not underlying preferences. This suggests that
we can identify the preferences and convictions that are relevant to
collective choices apart from the institutions through which they are
formed and expressed. But that is just what the deliberative conception
denies. On this conception, the relevant preferences and convictions are
those that could be expressed in free deliberation, and not those that are
prior to it. For this reason, popular self-government premises the exis-
tence of institutions that provide a framework for deliberation; these ar-
31. See William Riker, Liberalism Against Populism: A Confrontation between the Theory of
Democracy and the Theory of Social Choice (San Francisco: W. H. Freeman, 1982); for discus-
sion of Riker’s view see Jules Coleman and John Ferejohn, “Democracy and Social Choice,”
Ethics 97 (1986): 6–25; Joshua Cohen, “An Epistemic Conception of Democracy,” Ethics 97
(1986): 26–38.
32. Riker, Liberalism Against Populism, 190.
31
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
injust ice
The third problem concerns injustice. I have been treating the ideal of
democracy as the basic ideal for a political conception. But it might be
argued that the ideal of democracy is not suited to the role of funda-
mental political ideal because its treatment of basic liberties is mani-
festly unacceptable. It makes those liberties dependent on judgments
of majorities and thus endorses the democratic legitimacy of decisions
that restrict the basic liberties of individuals. In responding to this objec-
tion, I shall focus on the liberty of expression33 and shall begin by filling
out a version of the objection, which I put in the words of an imagined
critic.34
“You embrace the ideal of a democratic order. The aim of a demo-
cratic order is to maximize the power of the people to secure its wants. To
defend the liberty of expression you will argue that that power is dimin-
ished if the people lack the information required for exercising their will.
Since expression provides information, you will conclude that abridge-
ments of expression ought to be barred. The problem with your argu-
ment is that preventing restrictions on expression also restricts the power
33. For discussion of the connection between ideals of democracy and freedom of expres-
sion, see Alexander Meiklejohn, Free Speech and Its Relation of Self-Government (New York:
Harper and Row, 1948), and John Hart Ely, Democracy and Distrust (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 1980), 93–94, 105–116). Freedom of expression is a special case that can per-
haps be more straightforwardly accommodated by the democratic conception than liberties of
conscience, or the liberties associated with privacy and personhood. I do think, however, that
these other liberties can be given satisfactory treatment by the democratic conception, and
would reject it if I did not think so. The general idea would be to argue that other fundamental
liberties must be protected if citizens are to be able to engage in and have equal standing in po-
litical deliberation without fear that such engagement puts them at risk for their convictions or
personal choices. Whether this line of argument will work out on the details is a matter for
treatment elsewhere.
34. This objection is suggested by Dworkin, “The Forum of Principle,” in A Matter of Prin-
ciple, 61–63. He cites the following passage from a letter of Madison’s: “And a people who
mean to be their own Governors, must arm themselves with the power which knowledge gives”
(emphasis added).
32
D E L I B E R A T I O N A N D D E M O C R A T I C L E G I T I M A C Y
of the people, since the citizens may collectively prefer such restric-
tions. And so it is not at all clear as a general matter that the protection
of expression will maximize popular power. So while you will, of course,
not want to prevent everyone from speaking all the time, you cannot
defend the claim that there is even a presumption in favor of the protec-
tion of expression. And this disregard for fundamental liberties is unac-
ceptable.”
This objection has force against some conceptions in which democ-
racy is a fundamental ideal, particularly those in which the value of ex-
pression turns exclusively on its role as a source of information about
how best to advance popular ends. But it does not have any force against
the deliberative conception, since the latter does not make the case for
expression turn on its role in maximizing the power of the people to se-
cure its wants. That case rests instead on a conception of collective
choice, in particular on a view about how the “wants” that are relevant to
collective choice are formed and defined in the first place. The relevant
preferences and convictions are those that arise or are confirmed through
deliberation. And a framework of free expression is required for the rea-
soned consideration of alternatives that comprises deliberation. The de-
liberative conception holds that free expression is required for determin-
ing what advances the common good, because what is good is fixed by
public determination, and not prior to it. It is fixed by informed and au-
tonomous judgments, involving the exercise of the deliberative capaci-
ties. So the ideal of deliberative democracy is not hostile to free expres-
sion; rather, it presupposes such freedom.
But what about expression with no direct bearing on issues of public
policy? Is the conception of deliberative democracy committed to treat-
ing all “non-political expression” as second-class and as meriting lesser
protection? I do not think so. The deliberative conception construes poli-
tics as aiming in part at the formation of preferences and convictions, not
just at their articulation and aggregation. Because of this emphasis on
reasoning about preferences and convictions, and the bearing of expres-
sion with no political focus on such reasoning, the deliberative view
draws no bright line between political speech and other sorts of expres-
sion. Forms of expression that do not address issues of policy may well
bear on the formation of interests, aims, and ideals that citizens bring to
public deliberation. For this reason, the deliberative conception supports
protection for the full range of expression, regardless of the content of
33
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
that expression.35 It would violate the core of the ideal of free deliberation
among equals to fix preferences and convictions in advance by restricting
the content of expression, or by barring access to expression, or by pre-
venting the expression that is essential to having convictions at all. Thus
the injustice objection fails because the liberties are not simply among
the topics for deliberation; they help to provide the framework that
makes it possible.36
35. On the distinction between content-based and content-neutral abridgements, the com-
plexities of drawing the distinction in particular cases, and the special reasons for hostility to
content-based abridgements, see Laurence Tribe, American Constitutional Law (Mineola, NY:
Foundation Press, 1978), 584–682; Geoffrey Stone, “Content-neutral Restrictions,” University
of Chicago Law Review 54 (1987): 46–118.
36. I am not suggesting that the deliberative view provides the only sound justification for
the liberty of expression. My concern here is rather to show that the deliberative view is capa-
ble of accommodating it.
37. For an especially sharp statement of the irrelevance objection, see Carl Schmitt, The
Crisis of Parliamentary Democracy, trans. Ellen Kennedy (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1985).
38. This view is sometimes associated with Rousseau, who is said to have conflated the no-
tion of democratic legitimacy with the institutional expression of that ideal in a direct democ-
racy. For criticism of this interpretation, see Joshua Cohen, “Autonomy and Democracy:
Reflections on Rousseau,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 15, 3 (Summer 1986): 275–297.
34
D E L I B E R A T I O N A N D D E M O C R A T I C L E G I T I M A C Y
39. Madison urges this point in the Federalist Papers. Objecting to a proposal advanced by
Jefferson, which would have regularly referred constitutional questions “to the decision of the
whole society,” Madison argues that this would increase “the danger of disturbing the public
tranquility by interesting too strongly the public passions.” And “it is the reason, alone, of the
public that ought to control and regulate the government . . . [while] the passions ought to be
controlled and regulated by the government.” I endorse the form of the objection, not its con-
tent. Federalist Papers, ed. Clinton Rossiter (New York: New American Library, 1961), 315–317.
35
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
40. Here I draw on Cohen and Rogers, On Democracy, 154–157. The idea that parties are re-
quired to organize political choice and to provide a focus for public deliberation is one strand
of arguments about “responsible parties” in American political-science literature. My under-
standing of this view has been greatly aided by Lee Perlman, “Parties, Democracy, and Con-
sent,” (unpublished PhD dissertation, MIT, 1987), and, more generally, by the work of Walter
Dean Burnham on the implications of party decline for democratic politics. See, for example,
Burnham, The Current Crisis in American Politics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1982).
36
D E L I B E R A T I O N A N D D E M O C R A T I C L E G I T I M A C Y
4
I have suggested that we take the notion of democratic association as a
fundamental political ideal and have elaborated that ideal by reference
to an ideal deliberative procedure and the requirements for institutional-
izing such a procedure. I have sketched a few of those requirements here.
To show that the democratic ideal can play the role of fundamental orga-
nizing ideal, I should need to pursue the account of fundamental liber-
ties and political organization in much greater detail and to address a
wide range of other issues as well. Of course, the richer the requirements
are for institutionalizing free public deliberation, the larger the range of
issues that may need to be removed from the political agenda; that is, the
larger the range of issues that forms the background framework of public
deliberation rather than its subject matter. And the larger that range, the
less there is to deliberate about. Whether that is good news or bad news,
it is, in any case, a suitable place to conclude.
37
2
M O R A L P LU R A L I S M A N D
POLITICAL CONSENSUS
This essay began as comments on an unpublished paper by John Rawls entitled “A Reason-
ably Realistic Idea of a Well-ordered Society.” I have rewritten it to address Rawls’s “The Do-
main of the Political and Overlapping Consensus,” which was originally published in New
York University Law Review 64, 2 (May 1989): 233–255, and reprinted in the book in which my
paper originally appeared. I thank Michael Hardimon, John Rawls, T. M. Scanlon, and Judith
Thomson for very helpful comments on earlier drafts of this essay.
1. John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), 263.
2. Rawls is concerned with forms of diversity that extend beyond the domain of morality, for
example, to religious and philosophical matters. Nothing turns on the limitation that I adopt
here.
3. The ideal of consensus may, of course, be unrealistic in other ways as well.
38
M O R A L P L U R A L I S M A N D P O L I T I C A L C O N S E N S U S
39
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
40
M O R A L P L U R A L I S M A N D P O L I T I C A L C O N S E N S U S
state the specific problem of pluralism and consensus that I will be con-
sidering here, I first need to fix some terminology. Following Rawls, then,
I will say that a “well-ordered society” is a society in which it is common
knowledge that the members share an understanding of justice and a
willingness to act on that understanding. A well-ordered society, that is,
features a restricted but important moral consensus. The moral consen-
sus is restricted in that it extends only to certain basic constitutional val-
ues and principles and norms of distributive justice, and not to all aspects
of the conduct of life. Despite this limitation, the consensus that defines
a well-ordered society is a genuinely moral consensus. For the norms and
ideals on which there is consensus play a reason-giving and an authorita-
tive role in the deliberation and choices of individual citizens.8
At the same time, a well-ordered society may be morally pluralistic in
that members may have conflicting views about the fundamental norms
and ideals that ought to guide conduct in life more generally. In a mor-
ally pluralistic society, the members hold different theories about what is
valuable and worth doing. Thus understood, moral pluralism is to be dis-
tinguished both from cultural pluralism—the existence of groups of peo-
ple within a single society who share distinct histories and ways of life
and who share a common identity as members of a group—and from or-
ganizational pluralism—the existence of a plurality of organized groups
pursuing distinctive interests or ideals. These forms of pluralism are dis-
tinct phenomena and less plausibly understood as a matter of people
holding different theories. So the discussion here of moral pluralism and
consensus is limited and does not naturally translate into an account of
consensus and either cultural or organizational pluralism.
Moving now from terminology to substance: a moral consensus on po-
litical fundamentals is a fundamental good for at least three reasons.
First, for any conception of justice, the likelihood that social order will
stably conform to the conception is increased by the existence of a moral
consensus on it.9
Second, the existence of a moral consensus supports a variety of spe-
cific values of considerable importance. It increases social trust and har-
8. I identify moral reasons by their functional role in individual deliberation and choice not
by their content. There may be content restrictions as well, but I think that the functional role
characterization captures a central aspect of ordinary usage and in any case suffices for my pur-
poses here.
9. See Rawls’s “third general fact,” 235.
43
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
10. See Jean-Jacques Rousseau, On the Social Contract, trans. Judith R. Masters (New York:
St. Martin’s, 1978), Book 1, chap. 6.
11. We also need to add that everyone believes with good reason that the decisions express
the values.
12. This is what Rawls calls the “first general fact.” See 234–235.
44
M O R A L P L U R A L I S M A N D P O L I T I C A L C O N S E N S U S
Historical Excursus
These concerns about the pluralistic consensus condition ought to have
a familiar ring. Earlier I mentioned the problem of reconciling self-
government with the chains of political connection. Rousseau identified
this problem and thought it could be solved if social order were regulated
by a consensual understanding of the common good—a “general will.”
Rousseau’s solution is commonly rejected on the ground that it is inat-
tentive to differences among people and to the diversity of human inter-
ests and ideals. In the face of that diversity, according to the objection,
consensus on the common good can be achieved only through the unat-
tractive combination of a sectarian conception of virtue and, for those
who do not share that conception, enforced subordination and homoge-
neity in the name of freedom.
Hegel’s response to Rousseau was more complex. He agreed that free-
dom could be reconciled with the chains of political connection and ap-
plauded the notion of a general will as the way to achieve that reconcilia-
tion.13 But he also appreciated the force of the critique of Rousseau that I
just sketched. His conclusion was that it was necessary to reformulate the
classical ideal of a political community organized around a moral con-
sensus in light of the modern distinction between the unity of political
society and the diversity of civil society. This distinction shapes Hegel’s
own political conception in three important ways:
1. He endorsed a fundamental distinction between civic diversity and
political unity, associating that distinction with the differentiation be-
tween two spheres of social life. While the civil sphere would feature a di-
versity of aims and ideals and a range of individual and group activities
organized around those aims and ideals, the political sphere would be or-
ganized around a set of values that both claimed authority over individ-
ual concerns and were alleged to lie within the diverse aspirations of civil
life and to provide their common ground.14
2. His distinction between political unity and civic diversity is associ-
13. Hegel’s discussion of Rousseau in the History of Philosophy is more balanced than his
critical remarks in the Philosophy of Right. Compare Lectures on the History of Philosophy, vol.
3, trans. Elizabeth Haldane (New York: Humanities Press, 1968) with Philosophy of Right,
trans. T. M. Knox (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1952), 156–157.
14. See Philosophy of Right, paragraph 261, where Hegel says that the state is both an “exter-
nal necessity,” with respect to the family and civil society, and “the end immanent within
them.”
45
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
15. Hegel did acknowledge the need to regulate property in the name of the general welfare
and to avoid certain extreme cases of poverty (see Philosophy of Right, paragraphs 234–248).
But his view does not appear to countenance the regulation of economic activity with an eye to
ensuring that the final distribution of resources is not determined by differences of social back-
ground and natural ability.
16. See his “On the Jewish Question,” in Marx-Engels Reader, 2d ed., ed. Robert Tucker
(New York: Norton, 1978), 26–46; Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right, trans. Joseph O’Mal-
ley (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970).
46
M O R A L P L U R A L I S M A N D P O L I T I C A L C O N S E N S U S
17. This impression was confirmed by conversations at the conference at which I presented
the first draft of these comments. See also the concerns about the “abstractions, vagueness, and
conservatism” of Rawls’s later work expressed in Thomas Pogge’s Realizing Rawls (Ithaca, NY:
Cornell University Press, 1989), 4.
18. See, for example, John Gray, “Contractarian Method, Private Property, and Market
Economy,” in John W. Chapman and J. Roland Pennock, eds., Markets and Justice, Nomos
XXIII (New York: New York University Press, 1989), 13–58; and William Galston, “Pluralism
and Social Unity,” Ethics 99, 4 (July 1989): 711.
47
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
48
M O R A L P L U R A L I S M A N D P O L I T I C A L C O N S E N S U S
common groun d
To see why the answer is no, it is important to note first that the bootstrap
argument for the egalitarian view is itself meant to proceed on common
ground shared by different moral conceptions in a well-ordered society
governed by it. That may seem puzzling, since the conception of potenti-
alities as morally fundamental may strike some as peculiarly Kantian. But
the contention of the argument (which I am not evaluating here) is that
those ideas will seem attractive for the purposes of political argument to
anyone who considers how best to defend the liberties, formal norms of
equal opportunity, and the requirement that public powers be exercised
for the common good.20
Noting this draws attention to a first feature of the notion of an overlap-
ping consensus that is important in assessing the objection. What lies in
the intersection of different moral conceptions is not simply a set of poli-
cies or a system of norms within which political conflict and competition
proceed.21 Nor is it simply a determinate set of moral principles. Instead,
the consensus extends to a view of persons, of the importance of fairness
and other political values, of what counts as an advantage, and of which
practices are paradigmatically evil (e.g., slavery, religious intolerance,
and racial discrimination). In short, what lies at the intersection of differ-
ent views is a (restricted) terrain on which moral and political argument
can be conducted, and not simply a fixed and determinate set of substan-
tive points of political agreement.
To show, then, that an egalitarian conception of justice meets the plu-
ralistic consensus test, one needs to show that the bootstrap argument
succeeds and that the terrain on which that argument proceeds could it-
self be the focus of an overlapping consensus in a society governed by it.
One need not deny the obvious fact of disagreement on egalitarian politi-
20. The attribution to Kant in particular of the idea that abstract human potentialities are
morally fundamental is also off the mark historically. That idea plays a central role in Rous-
seau’s view and is also suggested in Locke’s theory of natural law. The variations on this general
theme are complex, as is the evolution of the idea; fortunately, these details are not relevant
here.
21. Robert Dahl, for example, emphasizes the importance of “underlying consensus on pol-
icy” and on the basic rules of political competition in A Preface to Democratic Theory (Chi-
cago: University of Chicago Press, 1956), 75–84, 132.
49
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
cal ideals or the only slightly less obvious fact that such disagreement is
likely to persist even under favorable conditions.
22. See Theory of Justice, 582. For elaboration of this strategy, see my “Democratic Equality
and the Difference Principle,” Ethics 99, 4 (July 1989): 727–751.
23. See John Rawls, “The Priority of the Right and Ideas of the Good,” Philosophy and Pub-
lic Affairs 17, 4 (Fall 1988): 275–276.
50
M O R A L P L U R A L I S M A N D P O L I T I C A L C O N S E N S U S
51
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
With this last point, I have begun to tread on the issues of the next sec-
tion and so shall move directly to them.
24. One reason for referring to a fact of pluralism is to distinguish the view that we need to
accommodate the diversity of values that follows on the protection of the liberties from the
view that that diversity should be accommodated because it is a good thing in itself. Nothing
that I say is meant to challenge the propriety of this usage.
25. My discussion of reasonable pluralism is in agreement with Rawls’s account of the “bur-
dens of reason” (235–238). The point of the discussion is largely to indicate the special impor-
tance of those burdens, as distinct from the four other general facts that Rawls discusses (234–
235), in explaining the pluralistic consensus test and in responding to objections to it.
26. I take this formulation from conversations with Mark Johnston.
27. See, for example, W. V. O. Quine, Pursuit of Truth (Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univer-
sity Press, 1990), 98–101, from whom I take the phrase “irresoluble rivalry” and the term “sec-
tarian” as it is used in the next sentence.
52
M O R A L P L U R A L I S M A N D P O L I T I C A L C O N S E N S U S
tion is that it is permissible, even with full awareness of the fact of re-
flective divergence, to take the sectarian route of affirming one’s own
view; that is, believing it as a matter of faith. And since believing is believ-
ing true, a rationally permissible (though not mandatory) response to an
apparently irresoluble rivalry of evaluative conceptions is to affirm that
one’s own view contains the whole truth, while the truths in other views
are simply the subsets of those views that intersect with one’s own. This
being one of the options, and the option that creates the most trouble for
the pluralistic consensus test, I will frame the rest of my discussion so that
it is consistent with it.
These remarks about reasonable pluralism suggest two different ways
to understand the fact of pluralism:
The simple fact of pluralism: The protection of the deliberative liber-
ties will result in moral pluralism.
The fact of reasonable pluralism: The protection of the deliberative
liberties will result in moral pluralism, and some of the moral con-
ceptions will fall within the set of fully reasonable conceptions.
The reasonable pluralism interpretation does make a factual claim. The
asserted fact, however, is not simply that the protection of deliberative
liberties will result in a plurality of conceptions of value but, further, that
a number of those conceptions will be reasonable and permissibly taken
by their adherents to be true.
28. For elaboration of this point, see Thomas Nagel, “Moral Conflict and Political Legiti-
macy,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 16, 3 (Summer 1987): 215–240. Joseph Raz has criticized
Nagel’s point, suggesting that it rests on an untenable distinction between the position of the
speaker who advances a justification and the listener to whom it is addressed. See his “Facing
Diversity: The Case of Epistemic Abstinence,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 19, 1 (Winter
1990): 37–39. I am not persuaded by Raz’s contention. He is right that the positions of speaker
and listener are parallel. But taking up the point of view of the person to whom a justification is
addressed is simply a heuristic for understanding the limited force of an argument that appeals
to the whole truth. So, far from undermining Nagel’s point, the parallelism is essential to draw-
ing the right conclusions from the use of the heuristic.
54
M O R A L P L U R A L I S M A N D P O L I T I C A L C O N S E N S U S
good, and we understand that view to imply that choice is not an inde-
pendent final value. In the course of political argument, we affirm: “It is
true that welfare is the sole ultimate good.” Now others ought not to sup-
pose that what we mean is equally well captured by “We believe that wel-
fare is the sole ultimate good.” The indistinguishability at issue is not se-
mantical. The point, rather, is that if others accept the idea of reasonable
pluralism, then they notice what we also notice, namely, that what lies
between our taking our views to be reasonable (about which there may
be no disagreement) and our taking them to be true (about which there
is disagreement) is not a further reason, but simply our (rationally permis-
sible) belief in those views. Because there is nothing else that lies in be-
tween, an appeal to the whole truth will seem indistinguishable from an
appeal to what we believe.
t he simp l e-fa ct ex p l a na t i on
Following the reasonable pluralism interpretation, then, when we restrict
ourselves to common ground in the face of the fact of diversity, we are ac-
knowledging that reason does not mandate a single moral view and then
are refraining from imposing ourselves on others who are prepared to be
reasonable. This account of whom we need to accommodate turns on
our willingness to acknowledge that some people with whom we funda-
mentally disagree are not unreasonable. That is why we are not simply
accommodating principles to power when we are concerned, to ensure
that the conception of justice is acceptable to them as well. This explana-
tion of the pluralistic consensus test might be clarified by contrasting it
with another explanation, which is suggested by some of Rawls’s remarks
but which is not persuasive.
As I indicated at the outset, Rawls emphasizes the importance of real-
ism in the formulation of reasonable ideals. And he suggests that when
we confine ourselves to considerations that are reasons for others as well,
we are simply adjusting to certain general facts about the social world.
Here the emphasis is on the need to be realistic, to find common ground
because disagreement is a basic fact of life under free conditions.
To see why this explanation of the need to accommodate diversity is
not right, notice that it is a plausible general fact that there will always be
people with unreasonable views. But the fact that there are some people
with unreasonable views does not require that we adjust our conception
of justice so that it can be supported by an overlapping consensus that
55
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
will appeal to them. While we need to take the fact of disagreement into
account in some way in deciding what to do, the pluralistic consensus
condition is certainly not the only way to do that and is not mandated by
the recognition that there are and will always be such people. Further-
more, if we did embrace the requirement that a conception of justice be
able to bring everyone on board—that it restrict itself to reasons em-
braced by all understandings of value—then it is hard to see what the re-
sponse would be to the objection that the requirement of an overlapping
consensus simply forces an accommodation to power.
The problem with this explanation is that it makes too much of the de
facto diversity highlighted in the simple-fact interpretation. The first ex-
planation—which draws essentially on the idea of reasonable plural-
ism—does not deny the relevance of the fact that under conditions of de-
liberative liberty there will be diversity. But the response to that fact is not
undiscriminating and, in particular, is controlled by the distinction be-
tween reasonable and unreasonable understandings of value.
Ensuring that a conception of justice fits the fact of diversity under
conditions of deliberative liberty is not, then, an unacceptable accommo-
dation to power. But the reason that it is acceptable is not because diver-
sity is a fact of life, as the simple-fact interpretation of pluralism states,
and not because adjustment to general and unalterable facts of social life
is always to be distinguished from accommodation to power. Instead, that
adjustment is reasonable because some forms of diversity are the natural
consequence of the free exercise of practical reason. Once we agree that
they are, we will not be inclined to count moral diversity among the un-
favorable facts of human life nor to confuse a concern to find a concep-
tion of justice consistent with it with a willingness to compromise justice
in the face of the course of the world.
ex cl usion
Answering the charge of unwarranted accommodation, then, commits us
to the view that we need not accommodate the unreasonable. Indeed,
given the explanation for this view, if we did accommodate the unreason-
able in the formulation of fundamental principles, then we would be un-
acceptably adjusting principles to de facto power.
But this brings me to a different concern about power and political
consensus: that the promise of consensus is associated with the practice
of arbitrary exclusion. In view of the problem of securing general agree-
56
M O R A L P L U R A L I S M A N D P O L I T I C A L C O N S E N S U S
57
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
Conclusions
I noted earlier that Rawls’s problems—the reasonableness of the ideal of
a consensual order and of the pluralistic consensus condition—echo a set
30. It is an analog to “creation science,” operating in the domain of salvation. The proper re-
sponse is the same in both cases.
58
M O R A L P L U R A L I S M A N D P O L I T I C A L C O N S E N S U S
31. I am not confident that Hegel held the view I attribute to him in this paragraph. It does
fit with and make sense out of various pieces of his view, including his account of the relation-
ship between civil society and the state, his conception of the role of reason in history, and his
views about the rationality of modern social arrangements. But he does not state it anywhere in
the way that I put it here. If I am wrong in thinking that he held it, nothing else in the essay
would need to change.
32. See Philosophy of Right, paragraph 261.
59
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
about the operation and powers of practical reason. With this account of
diversity, we have a response to the contention that accommodating dif-
ferent understandings of value in the formulation of basic moral princi-
ples for the political domain is tantamount to supposing that justice com-
mands that we turn our money over to thieves. The response is that we
are accommodating basic principles not to the reality of power but,
rather, to the way that social reality reveals the powers of practical reason.
60
3
A S S O C I AT I O N S A N D D E M O C R A C Y
61
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
firmative state,2 have been far more sensitive to such issues than egalitar-
ian-democratic theorists, who simultaneously embrace classically liberal
concerns with choice, egalitarian concerns with the distribution of re-
sources, and a republican emphasis on the values of citizen participation
and public debate (we sketch such a conception below in Section 1). Ne-
glect of how such values might be implemented has deepened the vul-
nerability of egalitarian-democratic views to the charge of being unrealis-
tic: “Good in theory but not so good in practice.”
In this essay we address this vulnerability by examining the construc-
tive role that “secondary”3 associations—labor unions, employer associa-
tions, citizen lobbies and advocacy groups, private service organizations,
other private groups—can play in a democracy. Our central contention is
that, as a practical matter, implementing democratic norms requires a
high level of secondary group organization of a certain kind. Roughly
speaking, the “level” required is one in which all citizens, irrespective of
their initial endowment, enjoy the political benefits of organization; the
“kind” required is one which delivers those benefits in ways consistent
not only with political equality but also with other democratic norms.
The problem is that the required level and kind of group activity do not
arise naturally, and those groups that do arise often frustrate, rather than
advance, democratic aspirations. Our proposed solution to this problem
is to supplement nature with artifice: through politics, to alter the envi-
ronment, incidence, activity, and governing status of associations in ways
that strengthen democratic order. We call this deliberate politics of asso-
ciations “associative democracy.”4
We would recommend the pursuit of “associative democracy” for a
wide range of administrative and property regimes. Here, however, we as-
sume the context of modern capitalism, where markets are the primary
mechanism of resource allocation and private, individual decisions are
the central determinant of investment. Admitting the limits this context
62
A S S O C I A T I O N S A N D D E M O C R A C Y
64
A S S O C I A T I O N S A N D D E M O C R A C Y
8. Many saw this as irreversible. See, for example, Jürgen Habermas, The Legitimation Cri-
sis of Late Capitalism (Boston: Beacon Press, 1973).
9. On unions, see Jelle Visser, “Trends in Trade Union Membership,” OECD Employment
Outlook, July 1991, 97–134.
10. For the American case, see the classic characterization of the resulting “interest group
liberalism” offered by Theodore J. Lowi, The End of Liberalism: The Second Republic of the
United States, 2d ed. (New York: Norton, 1979).
65
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
11. Throughout, respect for the associational liberties of group members, recognition of the
resistance of many groups to change, and rejection of concessionist views of associations mean
that the strategy stops well short of legislating associative practice or its relation to the state. As-
sociative democracy is not a distinct form of order, but a strategy to reform aspects of current
practice.
66
A S S O C I A T I O N S A N D D E M O C R A C Y
answer to the question “Should the state take care of the problem, or
should it be left to the market?” is a double negative.
This seems to be so in three ideal-typical classes of regulatory prob-
lems. In the first, nonmarket public standards on behavior are needed,
and government has the competence to set them, but the objects of regu-
lation are so diverse or unstable that it is not possible for the government
to specify just how those standards should be met at particular regulated
sites. Much environmental regulation presents problems of this sort. In
the second, public standard-setting is needed, and government has the
competence to do it, but the objects of regulation are sufficiently numer-
ous or dispersed to preclude serious government monitoring of compli-
ance. Consider the problems of occupational safety and health enforce-
ment. In the third, uniform public standards are needed, but it lies
beyond the competence of either markets or governments to specify and
secure them, as doing either requires the simultaneous coordination of
private actors and their enlistment in specifying the behavior sought.
Here, consider the difficulties of getting private firms to agree on stan-
dards for vocational training and to increase their own training efforts.
Where these sorts of problems are encountered, associative governance
can provide a welcome alternative or complement to public regulatory
efforts because of the distinctive capacity of associations to gather local
information, monitor behavior, and promote cooperation among private
actors. In such cases, the associative strategy recommends attending to
the possibility of enlisting them explicitly in the performance of public
tasks.
In sum, the idea of the associative strategy is to encourage the use of
associations to address concerns about unequal representation, partic-
ularism, and excessive cost and inefficiency of egalitarian programs and,
through that address, to satisfy more fully egalitarian-democratic norms.
In the next two sections, we will explore in more detail the features of as-
sociations that provide foundations for the strategy and underlie our as-
sessment of its promise.
12. Alexis de Tocqueville, Democracy in America (New York: Vintage, 1945), vol. 2, p. 117.
69
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
13. See Philippe C. Schmitter, “Still the Century of Corporatism?,” Review of Politics 36
(1974): 85–131; Suzanne Berger, ed., Organizing Interests in Western Europe: Pluralism,
Corporatism, and the Transformation of Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1981); and John H. Goldthorpe, ed., Order and Conflict in Contemporary Capitalism (Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1984).
70
A S S O C I A T I O N S A N D D E M O C R A C Y
71
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
16. For examples of state policy, see Stuart A. Rosenfeld, Technology Innovation and Rural
Development: Lessons from Italy and Denmark (Washington: Aspen Institute, 1990). We em-
phasize that state policy is needed in all these cases. The appropriate infrastructure does not
emerge naturally from the interactions of economic actors or from favorable cultural tradition.
For further discussion, see Section 3 below.
17. For this and other examples of “flexible manufacturing networks,” see C. Richard Hatch,
Flexible Manufacturing Networks: Cooperation for Competitiveness in a Global Economy
(Washington: Corporation for Enterprise Development, 1988).
72
A S S O C I A T I O N S A N D D E M O C R A C Y
18. For a review of worker participation in safety regulation focusing on Europe, see the con-
tributions to Sebastiano Bagnara, Raffaello Misiti, and Helmut Wintersberger, eds., Work and
Health in the 1980s: Experiences of Direct Workers’ Participation in Occupational Health
(Berlin: Edition Sigma, 1985); for a particularly useful country study, see Bjørn Gustavsen and
Gerry Hunnius, New Patterns of Work Reform: The Case of Norway (Oslo: Universitetsforlaget,
1981); for the contrast with the United States, see Charles Noble, Liberalism at Work: The Rise
and Fall of OSHA (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1986); and Eugene Bardach and
Robert Kagan, Going by the Book (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1982).
73
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
19. For a close examination of the different public powers enjoyed by the “social partners” in
the German case, see Wolfgang Streeck, Joseph Hilbert, Karl-Heinz van Kevelaer, Frederike
Maier, and Hajo Weber, The Role of the Social Partners in Vocational Training and Further
Training in the Federal Republic of Germany (Berlin: European Center for the Development
of Vocational Training, 1987).
20. The phrase and the point come from Philippe C. Schmitter, “Interest Intermediation
and Regime Governability in Contemporary Western Europe and North America,” in Berger,
ed., Organizing Interests, 285–327.
74
A S S O C I A T I O N S A N D D E M O C R A C Y
imp ossibil it y
The argument for impossibility begins with the assumption that groups
are a product of nature or culture or some other unalterable substrate of a
country’s political life. Just as some countries are blessed with good top-
soil or a temperate climate, others are blessed with the “right” kinds of
groups, at the right level of organization. In countries that are so blessed,
group contributions of the sort we note are observed. But since patterns
of group organization and behavior lie beyond politics, the observation
provides no support at all for an associative strategy for addressing the
problems of egalitarianism. Indeed, precisely by highlighting the impor-
tance of a favorable social basis for egalitarian democracy, they explain
why equality does not travel well.
We think that this objection exaggerates the fixity of the associative en-
vironment. Groups are, after all, in important ways political artifacts.
Their incidence, character, and patterns of interaction are not merely the
result of natural tendencies to association among citizens with like prefer-
ences. They reflect structural features of the political economy in which
they form—from the distribution of wealth and income to the locus of
policy making in different areas. And they reflect variations across the
members of that society, along such dimensions as income, information,
and density of interaction. Existing political institutions and “culture”
may crystallize around certain structural features and patterns of varia-
tion along these dimensions. But those features and variations are in no
sense natural. They can be changed through public policy.
Public policy can, for example, make the background distribution of
wealth and income more or less uneven. It can shift the locus of public
decision making from regional to national levels or concentrate it in a
single department, in ways that encourage different sorts of group forma-
tion and discourage others. The availability of information can be wid-
ened or constricted. The density of interaction among similarly situated
citizens can be increased or decreased. The cost of administering joint ef-
forts, or navigating the negotiation antecedent to them, can be subsidized
75
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
undesira bil it y
Still, efforts to enlist associations in democratic governance may be unde-
sirable. While groups can contribute to democratic order, and while
their contribution can be secured through public policy, they can also
work to undermine democratic order. This threat of “faction” was evi-
dent in our own inventory, offered earlier, of the practical problems now
faced by democratic egalitarianism. Each problem suggested an impair-
ment of democracy produced by the existing system of secondary associa-
tion. If our associative strategy entails the further cultivation of groups,
76
A S S O C I A T I O N S A N D D E M O C R A C Y
and the ceding to them of further public powers, does it not risk making
faction truly ruinous?
Before addressing this question, we need to enter some background re-
marks aimed at clarifying the issues it raises.
The problem of faction has been a particular preoccupation of Ameri-
can politics and democratic theory ever since James Madison announced
it as the key issue of American constitutional design.21 But it must be
faced by any liberal order, by reason of one of the defining features of
such order: the protection of associative liberties. Once associative liber-
ties are protected, associations inevitably follow. And, inevitably, legiti-
mately, and without malfeasance, some of those associations will use
their powers in pursuit of their aims in ways that frustrate the satisfaction
of basic democratic norms. They will represent members in ways that un-
dermine political equality; they will capture areas of policy in ways that
undermine popular sovereignty and promotion of the general welfare; in
“doing their job” of advancing member interests, they will inevitably pro-
mote particularism in place of deliberative politics. The threat of faction
is, then, inescapable in any regime with associative liberties. Moreover,
since those liberties are fundamental, the issue is how to mitigate that
threat, not how to remove it.
The characteristic forms of faction were suggested earlier. There is,
first, a pathology of inequality. Given inequalities in organization arising
naturally from the background of market capitalism, group efforts to
represent the interests of members may simply compound political in-
equality rather than relieve it. Political inequality may then compound
material inequality, as groups use their political powers to improve their
material position, in a vicious cycle of privilege. Second, there is a pa-
thology of particularism. Groups are, by their very nature, to some degree
particularistic. Only some citizens are represented in them, group lead-
ers are (at best) accountable to their members and not others, and the in-
terests and ideals of groups are not shared by all citizens. Representing
their members faithfully, particular groups thus often seek policies that
impose costs to the society at large, even as they provide gains for their
own members, and promote a politics of narrow advantage and bar-
gaining that corrupts the ideal of public deliberation about the com-
mon good. Commonly, inequality and particularism both thrive, as over-
21. See James Madison, Federalist 10, in The Federalist (New York: G. P. Putnam’s Sons,
1907), 51–60. We are concerned here only with what Madison called “minority” faction.
77
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
represented interests bargain with one another, divide the political spoils,
and so preserve their privileges until the next round of bargaining begins.
The problem of faction is serious, then; it is also inevitable so long as
associative liberties are preserved. Since threats of faction are inevitable,
it would be a mistake to attribute them to the associative strategy or to ex-
pect that strategy to eliminate faction. But since those problems are seri-
ous, it would be objectionable if the associative strategy increased the
threat of faction. The question raised by the second objection, then, is
whether pursuit of associative strategy would make the problem of fac-
tion worse.
To address this question fully, we would need to consider the likely ef-
fects of the associative strategy on each of the defining norms of egalitar-
ian democracy: popular sovereignty, political equality, distributive equity,
deliberative politics, and the operation of society for the general welfare.
In the interests of space, we propose to focus here solely on the norm of
popular sovereignty, though our treatment of it will suggest the shape of
our more general response. Recall that that norm requires that the autho-
rization of state action be determined (within the limits set by fundamen-
tal civil and political liberties) by procedures in which citizens are repre-
sented as equals. Our question then becomes: Would the pursuit of our
associative strategy undermine the ultimate authority of the people in the
formation of policy?
In answering this question, we assume that all associations, includ-
ing those vested with quasi-public powers, will operate within a political
system with encompassing formal institutions organizing representation
along traditional territorial lines. We assume, then, a possibility of “exit”
from the group-based system of interest representation to the more tradi-
tionally organized system. Moreover, we assume that the group system is
itself regulated by the traditional system. Final formal authority resides
with traditional institutions. Associations will depend on them for autho-
rizations of certain of their powers and for material support in carrying
such authorizations out.
With these background assumptions in mind, we want first to indi-
cate four sorts of positive-sum relationships between associations and the
democratic state—four ways, that is, that the fuller and more explicit in-
corporation of groups into governance roles might actually enhance the
exercise of popular sovereignty through the traditional institutions and
practices of territorial representation.
78
A S S O C I A T I O N S A N D D E M O C R A C Y
First, groups provide the state with information, thus permitting better
definition of problems and greater precision in the selection of means for
addressing them. By thus sharpening policy instruments and enabling
them to be applied with greater precision, groups promote the capacity
of the people to achieve their aims. Second, groups provide additional
enforcement power, thus increasing the likelihood that decisions made
by the people will be implemented.22 Third, in mitigating enforcement
problems, groups remove one important constraint on political debate.
Instead of proposals being short-circuited with the claim that they are
unenforceable, a wider range of proposals can be seriously discussed.
Fourth, a more open politics of associations makes explicit a condition,
which is already a standing feature of even the most liberal of societies,
namely, that secondary associations do in fact perform a variety of func-
tions that affect the conditions of political order. The associative strategy
“exposes and brings out into the open, it institutionalizes a factor in law-
making that we have, eagerly in fact, attempted to obscure.”23 By bringing
the role of associations “into the open,” it would make the exercise of
power by associations more accountable. In combination, better and
more flexible means, better enforcement, less constrained debate about
ends and their achievement, and more openness and accountability in
the exercise of power all count as important gains for popular sovereignty.
These four contributions are, however, accompanied by three sources
of serious concern—of negative-sum relations between the powers of as-
sociations and the egalitarian-democratic order.
First, there are problems of disjunction of interest between the leader-
ships of groups and their members—the problem of the “iron law of oli-
garchy.” A dense world of association may make the government more in-
formed about, and more responsive to, the interests of group “oligarchs”
but not those of its members. Second, there is the problem of indepen-
dent powers—what might be called the “Frankenstein” issue. Endowed
with quasi-public status, and commonly subsidized by the state, groups
that at one point in time contribute to decent policy may continue to ex-
ercise power after outgrowing their usefulness, use that power to freeze
their position, and so work to distort future debate and choice. Third, in-
22. See, for example, the discussion of “fire alarm” enforcement in Mathew D. McCubbins
and Thomas Schwartz, “Congressional Oversight Overlooked: Police Patrols vs. Fire Alarms,”
American Journal of Political Science 28 (1984): 165–179.
23. Louis Jaffe, “Law-Making by Private Groups,” Harvard Law Review 51 (1937): 220–221.
79
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
which are in turn more democratic than the unions of West Germany,
which are intermediate in their level of centralization.24
If the union case is credited, internal responsiveness need not come at
the expense of external capacity. Moreover, internal responsiveness can
be designed into large organizations through their internal procedures.
In combination, these points suggest that oligarchy is more plastic than
the “iron law” suggests. More immediately, they suggest a natural re-
sponse to the problem of disjunction: require greater use of internal dem-
ocratic procedures among groups that are granted quasi-public status.
Operationally, the requirement should be that groups accorded this sta-
tus provide evidence that they in fact represent their members by show-
ing that they actually use some mechanism of responsiveness. Infinite
gradations in degree and differences in judgment are certainly imagina-
ble here, just as they are in ongoing disputes over the representativeness
of electoral systems. But as the case of electoral systems also suggests, it is
possible to articulate a general principle of legitimacy, in this case inter-
nal responsiveness, and to use that general principle to guide debate
about specific proposals.
Our second problem, the “Frankenstein” problem of independent pow-
ers, also carries a natural response, namely some variant of “sunset legis-
lation.” The quasi-public status of groups (and subsidies to them) should
be reviewed on a regular basis, with a rebuttable presumption that the
status (or subsidies) will be withdrawn or amended as group behavior, or
perceived social needs, warrants. The general requirements are reason-
ably clear, though their precise elaboration is not. On the one hand, the
threat of withdrawal must be sufficiently credible, and the gains associ-
ated with public status sufficiently great, to induce groups to meet ac-
countability requirements and other conditions on their conduct. On the
other hand, since continuity in bargaining relations is an important pre-
requisite of gains, the requirements must not be so exacting as to make
them impossible to satisfy.
Of course, the ultimate guard against independent powers is the vital-
24. See Peter Lange, Union Democracy and Liberal Corporatism: Exit, Voice, and Wage Reg-
ulation in Postwar Europe, Cornell Studies in International Affairs, Occasional Paper No. 16.
The measures include rules governing election to union councils, intermediate organizations,
and national office; incidences and support of informal caucuses; and procedures for debate
and vote on strikes, contracts, and other sorts of concerted action.
81
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
ity of the system dispensing the powers in the first place. This fact is pre-
cisely what gives normative force to our assumption, above, that systems
relying heavily on group-based representation still rest final authority in
encompassing territorial organizations. For evaluating associative democ-
racy, the narrow issue here is whether, ceteris paribus, that system is made
more or less vital by the increase in its democratic capacity that would
follow on its enlistment of the energies of representative groups. And to
ask that question is to answer it.
Finally, we offer two thoughts on the third problem noted above: the
problem of vague delegations of power and the attendant risks of abused
discretion. The first of these is simply a plea for realism and fairness in
evaluation. The threat of vague delegations of powers in our associative
scheme should be contrasted not with some ideal world but with the one
that exists and the alternative reform proposals for that world. When it is,
the contrast does not seem particularly damning. In the existing world,
there is already much vague delegation to and exercise of discretion by
administrative agencies. lf we consider a scheme of more limited govern-
ment as a means to cabin discretion, then we need to keep in mind that
such a scheme is unlikely to serve the egalitarian democratic aims at is-
sue here. If we consider a scheme with stronger legislative controls—less
vagueness in delegating and more sharpness in formulating legislative
standards—then we should consider familiar cautions that it may lead to
an unwelcome politicization of legislative instruction, reflected in unrea-
sonable goals, improbable deadlines on their achievement, or simple leg-
islative deadlock.25 Nor is there any reason to think that such reasonable
requirements as clarity in the statement of statutory goals will be incon-
sistent with the associative scheme.
Moving now to a more positive engagement with the issue, we pro-
pose to address the problem of delegation through performance crite-
ria. Where associations are involved in the enforcement and administra-
tion of policy, public institutions should formulate clear performance
standards for groups to enforce and administer, while avoiding detailed
specification of the means to be used in meeting those standards. For ex-
ample, in the area of workplace health, there might be performance stan-
25. These effects are noted in Cass Sunstein, “Constitutionalism after the New Deal,” Har-
vard Law Review 101 (1987): 480–481: “The movement toward increased congressional control
is not without risks of its own [since] . . . undue specificity may produce regulation riddled by
factional tradeoffs.”
82
A S S O C I A T I O N S A N D D E M O C R A C Y
26. For an instructive discussion of the role of nonprofit organizations in welfare-state ser-
vice delivery, emphasizing the increased dependence of many of these agencies on their ties to
government, see Steven Rathgeb Smith and Michael Lipsky, Nonprofits for Hire: The Welfare
State in the Age of Contracting (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1995).
27. A useful (though not impartial) survey of local economic development strategies is pro-
vided in R. Scott Fosler, Local Economic Development (Washington: International City Man-
agement Association, 1991).
28. For an enthusiastic review of some of the emerging linkages between schools and private
business associations, see Anthony Carnevale, Leila Gainer, Janice Villet, and Shari Holland,
Training Partnerships: Linking Employers and Providers (Alexandria: American Society for
Training and Development, 1990).
84
A S S O C I A T I O N S A N D D E M O C R A C Y
ing, the largest single training program in the United States, the Job
Training Partnership Act (JTPA), is almost wholly administered through
“private industry councils” dominated, by statute, by local business inter-
ests.29 In environmental regulation, from the deliberate promotion of bar-
gaining among industry and environmental groups as a prelude to stan-
dard setting at the federal level, to the promotion of bargaining between
business and community organizations over the appropriate implementa-
tion of environmental standards in local neighborhoods and regions, pol-
icy is rife with secondary associations exercising de facto public powers.30
Some of these efforts display the great strengths of associative gover-
nance; others display its many dangers. Our point here is simply that
such governance in fact goes on, widely, even in this liberal culture. And
its incidence provides a natural basis for more deliberate, and demo-
cratic, associative strategies.
Moreover, while we acknowledge the weakness of the American state,
we think that at least some sorts of associative reforms can make it stron-
ger. Particularly given a weak state, it is important that group empower-
ment proceed in a way that is reliably positive-sum with state power. But
this merely requires judgment in the choice of associative strategies. It
does not generally bar pursuit of them. And while we acknowledge,
finally, the overwhelming business dominance of the American polity,
we think this again simply constrains choice in the groups that are advan-
taged through the associative strategy. If business is too powerful, then as-
sociative resources should be provided to labor or other nonbusiness-
dominated groups; the current imbalance is not an argument for aban-
doning the general idea.
Most generally, we agree that the United States has high levels of in-
equality, a less-than-competent government, and weak cooperative insti-
tutions—that, in brief, it does not work well as a democracy. This, in fact,
29. JTPA has been widely criticized as insufficiently accountable to public needs. Among
others, see John D. Donahue, Shortchanging the Workforce: The Job Training Partnership Act
and the Overselling of Privatized Training (Washington: Economic Policy Institute, 1989);
United States General Accounting Office (GAO), Job Training Partnership Act: Inadequate
Oversight Leaves Program Vulnerable to Waste, Abuse, and Mismanagement, GAO/HRD-91–
97 (Washington: General Accounting Office, 1991).
30. Some of the federal experience is reviewed in Charles W. Powers, The Role of NGOs in
Improving the Employment of Science and Technology in Environmental Management (New
York: Carnegie Commission on Science, Technology, and Government, May 1991); the experi-
ence of local communities in fostering such environmental bargaining among organized
groups is reviewed in Valjean McLenighan, Sustainable Manufacturing: Saving Jobs, Saving
the Environment (Chicago: Center for Neighborhood Technology, 1990).
85
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
is the very problem that provides our point of departure. We move, then,
to some examples of how an associative strategy might proceed from this
point of departure in this distinctive polity. We offer two illustrations of
the general look and feel of the associative project: the reform of worker
representation and industrial relations in the United States, and the re-
form of vocational training. In each case we sketch some problems that
need to be addressed, indicate the ways that a richer associational setting
might help in addressing them, and discuss some measures that might
now be taken to promote that setting.
86
A S S O C I A T I O N S A N D D E M O C R A C Y
87
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
33. There are many such statements of possible labor-law reform. A good guide to the issues
involved, containing both more and less ambitious recommendations for reform, is provided
by Paul Weller, Governing the Workplace: The Future of Labor and Employment Law (Cam-
bridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990).
88
A S S O C I A T I O N S A N D D E M O C R A C Y
v oca t iona l t ra in i ng
Our second example of constructive group artifice comes from the area
of vocational training. In the United States, as in most other rich coun-
tries, intensified international competition and rapid technological
change have underscored the need for improvements in workforce skills.
To preserve living standards in the face of low-wage competition from
abroad, labor must be made substantially more productive, and firms
must become increasingly adept at such “nonprice” aspects of product
competition as quality, variety, customization, and service. Success here
will require, inter alia, that “frontline” production and nonsupervisory
workers be equipped with substantially higher and broader skills than
they presently possess.
The vocational training problem in the United States consists in the
fact that such skills are being provided in insufficient quality and quantity
by schools and firms, and insofar as they are provided, they are directed
to college-bound youths and managers. In the public school system, very
little occupational training is provided for the “forgotten half” of each
high school cohort that does not go on to college or the “forgotten three-
quarters” of each cohort that does not complete it. And U.S. employers
provide their frontline workforce with far less training than do leading
foreign competitors. Moreover, the training they do provide is generally
narrower than is desirable—for the economy as a whole, for innovative
firms drawing from the external labor market, and for individual workers,
who typically change employers several times in their working lifetimes.34
With skills more essential than ever to compensation, the failures of U.S.
training have powerfully contributed to the decline in production and
34. For general reviews of U.S. training problems, making all these points, see U.S. Con-
gress, Office of Technology Assessment, Worker Training: Competing in the International
Economy, OTA ITE-457 (Washington: Government Printing Office, 1990); and Commission
on the Skills of the American Workforce, America’s Choice: High Skills or Low Wages! (Roches-
ter: National Center on Education and the Economy, 1990).
90
A S S O C I A T I O N S A N D D E M O C R A C Y
91
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
United States, operate with relatively open external labor markets and
high rates of inter-firm worker mobility.
As the second European strategy makes clear, the presence of com-
petent, encompassing employer and labor associations immensely aids
both in addressing the problem of linkage between the worlds of school
and work and in increasing the level and quality of employer-sponsored
training.
Facilitating linkage, associations provide the state with timely informa-
tion on emerging industry trends and practices, new technologies, skill
needs, and access to the insides of firms. They permit industries to speak
with a unified voice to public training providers, to negotiate authorita-
tively with the state over training curricula, access to firms, require-
ments on skills certification, rules on the use of equipment, and the like.
They permit the state to get closure and enforcement on decisions once
made—“If you don’t like it, talk to your association” being a far more ef-
fective retort to second-guessing firms than, “Well, that’s just what we de-
cided to do”—while providing monitoring and enforcement capacities to
supplement any public training effort. And being broad in their represen-
tation, and accountable to members, associations are natural vehicles for
developing general standards, of wide applicability, of the sort that pro-
tect the training investment made by employees themselves.
Facilitating employer training efforts, industry associations help in part
by setting general standards on skills—something no single firm can do.
The identification of commonly desired competencies assures workers
that acquiring those competencies will improve their position on the ex-
ternal labor market. This leads to increased take-up rates on training, as-
suring employers of a large pool of workers with high and common skills.
And this assurance encourages more proactive industry strategies of up-
grading and inter-firm cooperation in implementing those strategies.
But associations also act to facilitate employer training efforts by miti-
gating the externality problem that discourages those efforts. They re-
quire training as a condition of membership, or of receipt of its benefits.
They monitor the training that goes on, relieving fears of “suckering.”
They ease the flow of information about new technology and work prac-
tices among members, providing a natural vehicle for voluntary industry
benchmarking that creates upward pressures on existing standards. They
share training facilities and curricula among themselves, reducing per
capita training costs. More elusive, but not less important, they help de-
93
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
38. The Department of Labor’s Office of Work-Based Learning is already making qualified
moves in this direction—“qualified” in that outside more heavily unionized industries, it re-
mains unclear what, if any, organized voice workers in the industry will have.
39. Following current practice for joint research and development activities.
40. Recommendations on how to do this are made in Margaret Hilton, “Shared Training:
Learning from Germany,” Monthly Labor Review 114, 3 (March 1991): 33–37.
41. An experiment along these lines is under way in Milwaukee, where several firms (non-
union and unionized), unions, and public training providers have come together around a
Wisconsin Manufacturing Training Consortium designed to do just these things. See Joel Rog-
ers and Wolfgang Streeck, Recommendations for Action (Madison: Center on Wisconsin Strat-
egy, 1991).
95
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
Conclusion
The examples just given provide no more than a couple of illustrations of
the directions an associative democratic strategy might take in the United
States. But they suffice to underscore the sorts of concerns that define
that strategy and the considerations relevant to its execution. What we
have argued in this essay, and what is displayed in the examples just
given, is straightforward enough. To proceed, egalitarian politics must
once again be shown to work. To work, it requires associative supports.
Those supports can be developed. And developing them, and realizing
their contribution to democratic governance, requires neither a naive
view of associations as free from the threat of faction nor a dangerous
view on the surrender of encompassing public authority. Faction can be
mitigated through the same artifice that enlists associative contributions,
and the strength and the competence of public authorities can be en-
hanced by this enlistment.
More broadly, by assuring greater equality in organized representation
96
A S S O C I A T I O N S A N D D E M O C R A C Y
97
4
FREEDOM OF EXPRESSION
Introduction
In April 1989, students at the University of Michigan walked into a class
and were faced with a blackboard that read: “A mind is a terrible thing
to waste—especially on a nigger.” This message followed closely on the
appearance of a flier at the University declaring “open season on Blacks.”
A month later, an African student at Smith College found a message
slipped under her door, which read: “African nigger do you want some
bananas? Go back to the jungle.”1
Responding to a pattern of such incidents and the longstanding Ameri-
can traditions of racial hatred and violence reflected in them, a substan-
tial number of colleges and universities have adopted codes regulating
racist and other forms of hate speech. These regulations have been the
object of intense controversy. Denounced by some as the work of “ten-
ured radicals,”2 they have also been the target of more serious criticism.
I have presented talks based on earlier drafts of this essay at Haverford College, the Univer-
sity of California (Davis), the John F. Kennedy School of Government, Wellesley College, the
University of Illinois (Chicago), Northwestern University, the Jerusalem Philosophical En-
counter, Amherst College, New York University, the Inter-Africa Group Symposium “On the
Making of the New Ethiopian Constitution,” and the Society for Ethical and Legal Philoso-
phy. I am grateful to audiences at these talks for their criticisms and suggestions. I would also
like to thank C. Edwin Baker, Randall Forsberg, John Rawls, John Simmons, and Cass
Sunstein for comments on previous versions, Sunstein for making available successive drafts of
his Democracy and the Problem of Free Speech (New York: Free Press, 1994), and Archon Fung
for his research assistance. More generally, I am very much indebted to Tim Scanlon’s papers
on freedom of expression, in particular his “Freedom of Expression and Categories of Expres-
sion,” University of Pittsburgh Law Review 40 (1979): 519–550.
1. See Charles Lawrence, “If He Hollers Let Him Go: Regulating Racist Speech on Cam-
pus,” Duke Law Journal (1990): 431–483; Mari Matsuda, “Public Response to Racist Speech:
Considering the Victim’s Story,” Michigan Law Review 87 (1989): 2320–2381; Richard Delgado,
“Campus Antiracism Rules: Constitutional Narratives in Collision,” Northwestern University
Law Review 85 (1991): 343–387.
2. See for example George Will, “Curdled Politics on Campus,” Newsweek, 6 May 1991, 72;
Chester E. Finn, “The Campus: ‘An Island of Repression in a Sea of Freedom,’” Commentary,
September 1989, 17–23.
98
F R E E D O M O F E X P R E S S I O N
99
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
100
F R E E D O M O F E X P R E S S I O N
strategies for defending such stringency. The first, which I will call “mini-
malist,” holds that expression deserves stringent protection, not because it
is so valuable but because it is costless (“just speech”), or because the
costs it imposes cannot permissibly be taken into consideration by the
state, or because government is especially untrustworthy when it comes
to regulating expression: the common thread running through the sev-
eral variants of minimalism is that the defense is to proceed without re-
course to the thesis that expression has substantial value. “Maximalist”
views, by contrast, concede the costs of stringent protections but argue
that the transcendent value of expression guarantees that it trumps the
costs (except when they are of equally transcendent value).
Minimalism and maximalism are not formal theories about freedom of
expression. Still, each represents an important tendency of thought in
this area.9 Moreover, their attractive simplicity encourages the assump-
tion that they exhaust the field of justifications. Because neither is com-
pelling, nihilism about freedom of expression lives parasitically off their
defects—the nihilism urged, for example, in Stanley Fish’s claim that
“there’s no such thing as free speech and it’s a good thing, too.”10 Put less
colorfully, the nihilist claims that all there really is—all there could be—
when it comes to decisions about restricting or permitting speech is an ad
hoc weighing of costs and benefits in particular cases using the scales pro-
vided by “some particular partisan vision.”11 No general presumption in
favor of protection can withstand inspection.
But minimalism and maximalism do not exhaust the strategies of ar-
gument for stringent protections.12 The central burden of my argument
(in Sections 3 and 4) is to present an alternative to maximalist and mini-
malist outlooks and, thereby, to defuse some of the temptations to nihil-
ism. Less simple than the alternatives, this view proposes that stringent
protections emerge as the product of three distinct considerations:
101
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
13. See, for example, Vincent Blasi, “The Pathological Perspective and the First Amend-
ment,” Columbia Law Review 85 (1985): 449–514.
14. For an argument based more fundamentally on mistrust, see Richard Epstein, “Property,
Speech, and the Politics of Distrust,” University of Chicago Law Review 59 (1992): 41–90. For
criticisms, see Frank Michelman, “Liberties, Fair Values, and Constitutional Method,” Univer-
sity of Chicago Law Review 59 (1992): 91–114.
15. Cass Sunstein criticizes my view along these lines. He suggests that the legal principles
that emerge from it might be “simply too complex, ad hoc, and unruly.” See Democracy and
the Problem of Free Speech, 146. I try to address this concern in my discussion of specific issues
in Sections 4 and 5.
16. For the suggestion that it does so depend, see Ronald Dworkin, “Two Concepts of Lib-
erty,” in Edna Ullman-Margalit and Avishai Margalit, eds., Isaiah Berlin: A Celebration (Lon-
don: Hogarth Press, 1991), 100–109.
102
F R E E D O M O F E X P R E S S I O N
1. Stringent Protections
I will begin by explaining what I mean by “stringent protections of ex-
pressive liberties.” My explanation proceeds by setting out four familiar
themes suggested by the free-speech tradition. Nothing I say about these
17. In this connection I wish to thank C. Edwin Baker for pointing out a number of blun-
ders that marred the penultimate draft of the paper.
103
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
ca t egoriz a t ion
Despite this general presumption, some kinds of content regulation seem
intuitively less troubling—as with regulations of express, direct incite-
ment, truth in advertising, private libel, fighting words, bribery, espio-
nage, and nonobscene child pornography.19 Because content regulation
is in general objectionable, it is important to confine these exceptions.
So a second main theme recommends a special approach to handling
18. The classic statement of the general concern is Justice Marshall’s in Police Department
of Chicago v. Mosley, 408 U.S. 92, 95–96 (1972): “Above all else, the First Amendment means
that government has no power to restrict expression because of its message, its ideas, its subject
matter, or its content.” On viewpoint discrimination, see Texas v. Johnson, 491 U.S. 397, 414
(1989). For discussion, see John Hart Ely, “Flag Desecration: A Case Study in the Roles of Cat-
egorization and Balancing in First Amendment Decisions,” Harvard Law Review (1975): 1482–
1508; Geoffrey Stone, “Restrictions of Speech Because of its Content: The Peculiar Case of
Subject-Matter Restrictions,” University of Chicago Law Review 46 (1978): 81–115, and “Con-
tent-Neutral Restrictions,” University of Chicago Law Review 54 (1987): 46–120; and T. M.
Scanlon, Jr., “Content-Regulation Reconsidered,” in Judith Lichtenberg, ed., Democracy and
the Mass Media (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), 331–354.
19. For example, on incitement, see Brandenburg v. Ohio, 395 U.S. 444 (1968); on commer-
cial speech, Virginia State Board of Pharmacy v. Virginia Citizens Consumer Council, 425
U.S. 748 (1976); Central Hudson Gas and Electric v. Public Service Commission of New York,
447 U.S. 557 (1980); Posadas de Puerto Rico Associates v. Tourism Company of Puerto Rico,
106 S. Ct. 2968 (1986); on fighting words, Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U.S. 568 (1942);
on child pornography, Ferber v. New York, 458 U.S. 747 (1982).
104
F R E E D O M O F E X P R E S S I O N
20. I emphasize that I am using this protean term exclusively as a label for the approach to
content regulation described here.
21. For doubts about the virtues of categorization, and corresponding skepticism about cate-
gorically formulated prohibitions on content regulation, see John Paul Stevens, “The Freedom
of Speech,” Yale Law Journal 102 (1993): 1293–1313.
22. For a subtle discussion of the structure of argument about content-neutral regulations,
and of the extent to which the thumb gets put in the balance for different sorts of regulations,
see Stone, “Content-Neutral Restrictions.”
23. By “costs,” I mean, quite generically, conditions that it is reasonable to want to avoid.
24. See Schneider v. State, 308 U.S. 147 (1939) (on cleanup costs); New York Times v.
Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254 (1964) (on reputational injury); Cohen v. California, 403 U.S. 15 (1971)
(on offense); Hustler v. Falwell, 485 U.S. 46 (1988) (on intentional infliction of emotional dis-
tress).
25. Say, a fine for leaving a pile of leaflets sitting on a bench for people to pick up.
105
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
fa ir a ccess
A system of stringent protections of expressive liberties must assure fair
opportunities for expression: that is, that the value of expressive liberties
must not be determined by a citizen’s economic or social position.28
Taking the unequal command of resources as a fact, a system of stringent
protections must include measures aimed expressly at ensuring fair ac-
cess to expressive opportunities. Such measures might include keeping
traditional public forums (parks and streets) open and easily accessible;
expanding the conception of a public forum to include airports, train
stations, privately owned shopping centers, and other places of dense
public interaction; affirming the importance of diverse broadcast mes-
sages and the role of fair access in contributing to such diversity; financ-
ing political campaigns through public resources; and regulating private
political contributions and expenditures. The requirement of fair access
supports a strong, general presumption against content-neutral regula-
tions that have substantially disparate distributive implications—when, as
with regulations on the distribution of handbills, or on the use of parks
and sidewalks, they work to disproportionately burden those who other-
wise lack the resources to get their messages out.
Several preliminary comments on this inclusion of fair access in the
account of stringent protections are in order.
106
F R E E D O M O F E X P R E S S I O N
First, the measures I listed for ensuring fair access are all content-
neutral, and all are addressed to remedying problems of unfair access
that reflect inequalities of material resources. But it is a serious and open
question whether, and to what extent, fair access can be assured through
content-neutral remedies. For a lack of fair access—social and political
exclusion—is sometimes said to result precisely from what others say
and not from the distribution of resources.29 This tension between de-
mands of content-neutrality and fair access lies at the heart of Catharine
MacKinnon’s argument for the regulation of pornography on grounds
that its content silences women and so prevents fair access.30 Here I want
simply to call attention to this concern. Later, I will suggest some ways to
address it and so broaden the range of cases in which values of fair access
and content-neutrality can be reconciled (135–140).
Second, it might be objected that the inclusion of requirements of fair
access abuses the phrase “stringent protection”—that ensuring fair access
is really a matter of “positively” expanding expressive opportunities rather
than “negatively” protecting expressive liberties. I have a more formal
and a more substantive response to this objection.
The formal response is that my four points define “stringent protec-
tion” for the purposes of this essay. So the terminological issue does not
interest me very much. More substantively, I disagree that this represents
an abuse or stretching of the term “protection.” When owners of shop-
ping malls wish to prevent people from leafleting on the premises, and
the state bars them from doing so, the state is protecting at least some
expression from efforts (by the owners) to silence it. It is tendentious to
describe this as an effort by the state to expand opportunities for the
leafleteers (rather than as an effort to protect their liberty from intrusion),
because that description imports a presumptive right of owners to ex-
clude into the distinction between protection and expansion.31 The real
29. See Frank Michelman, “Universities, Racist Speech, and Democracy in America,” Har-
vard Civil Rights-Civil Liberties Law Review 27 (1992): 352.
30. See, for example, Catharine MacKinnon, “Francis Biddle’s Sister,” in her Feminism
Unmodified (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1987), 163–197; for discussion of the si-
lencing argument, see Frank Michelman, “Conceptions of Democracy in American Constitu-
tional Argument: The Case of Pornography,” Tennessee Law Review 56 (1989): 291–319; and the
critical appraisal in Ronald Dworkin, “Liberty and Pornography,” New York Review of Books 38,
14 (1991): 12–15.
31. For an extended elaboration of the importance of this point for free-speech doctrine, see
Cass Sunstein’s discussion of a New Deal for speech in “Free Speech Now,” The University of
Chicago Law Review 59 (1992): 255–316, esp. 263–277, 316.
107
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
minima l ism
Generically described, minimalism aims to defend stringent protections
without attaching any elevated importance to expression, instead con-
centrating, so to speak, on the magnitude of the evil those protections
prevent rather than on the magnitude of the good they protect. One fa-
miliar minimalist strategy—I will call it “no-cost minimalism”—rests on
a distinction between expression and action. Relying on that distinction,
the minimalist argues that expression—as distinct from action—is not in
itself costly or harmful and that the harms that may flow from it in con-
junction with its surrounding conditions can always be addressed without
abridging expression. The no-cost case does not rest on attaching an es-
pecially significant value to expression itself: the harm principle suffices
to generate the protections.
Other minimalists emphasize as well the remedial side of stringent
protections, arguing that they are required by the pervasive tendency of
people generally (or, in some versions, of political officials) to silence ex-
pression for insubstantial or impermissible reasons: for example, to pro-
tect officials from criticism or for reasons that are moralistic or in other
108
F R E E D O M O F E X P R E S S I O N
32. “Do We Have A Right to Pornography?” in A Matter of Principle (Cambridge, MA: Har-
vard University Press, 1985): 335–372. For an excellent discussion of the limits of this argument,
see Rae Langton, “Whose Right? Ronald Dworkin, Women, and Pornographers,” Philosophy
and Public Affairs 19 (1990): 311–359. Dworkin’s recent discussions of expressive liberty seem
less minimalist. In “What is Equality? Part 3: The Place of Liberty,” he ties the value of expres-
sive liberties to the formation of “authentic preferences.” See Iowa Law Review 72 (1987): 34–
36. And in “The Coming Battles over Free Speech,” he notes the importance of an active side
to personal responsibility. See New York Review of Books, 11 June 1992, 57.
33. For criticism of the project of founding an account of freedom of expression on a prior
expression-action distinction, see Scanlon, “A Theory of Freedom of Expression,” Philosophy
and Public Affairs 1 (1972): 205–208.
109
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
ma x ima l ism
Maximalism inverts the minimalist strategy. Generically described, the
maximalist proposes that expression merits stringent protection because
34. Indeed, as Scanlon emphasizes, the central task for a theory of freedom of expression is
to explain why this should be so. See ibid., 204.
35. See Schneider v. State, 308 U.S. 147, 161 (1939).
36. To put the point in a constitutional slogan: you cannot derive the First Amendment
from the equal protection clause of the Fourteenth Amendment.
110
F R E E D O M O F E X P R E S S I O N
its great value guarantees that the benefits of protection trump the costs.37
The maximalist might, for example, argue that the dignity of human be-
ings as autonomous and responsible agents is so immediately at stake in
any act of expression and/or so immediately threatened by any regulation
of expression—or at least any regulation of expression on grounds of its
communicative impact—that abridgements of it represent intolerable vi-
olations of human dignity.38
The maximalist view has something right, and I will say what it is when
(in Section 3) I discuss fundamental expressive and deliberative interests.
Still, maximalism is too simple to capture the contours of freedom of ex-
pression. In its simplicity, it either exaggerates the stakes in particular
cases of the regulation of expression or else manipulates the notion of au-
tonomy to make it fit the complexity of the terrain.39
For example, maximalism does not help us to understand why there
are cases in which considerations of costs do seem relevant to the jus-
tification of regulations: why regulations of group libel might be more
problematic than restrictions on individual libel, why it might make
sense to distinguish the treatment of reputational injury to public and
nonpublic figures, or why autonomy does not simply trump reputational
injury altogether. Similarly, maximalism does not seem to be a promising
route to understanding why false or misleading advertising seems less
worthy of protection than false or misleading claims offered in the course
of political or religious argument.40 In each of these cases, maximalism
37. The maximalist need not hold that the value is intrinsic, nor that there is just a single
value associated with expression. I am indebted to Connie Rosati for urging this clarification.
38. See, for example, Scanlon’s listener-autonomy theory in “A Theory of Freedom of Ex-
pression,” 204–226; and his criticisms of that theory in “Freedom of Expression and Categories
of Expression,” 534–35. In “Persuasion, Autonomy, and Expression,” Columbia Law Review 91
(1991): 334–371, David Strauss aims to rescue a version of Scanlon’s theory from these criti-
cisms. Strauss condemns restrictions of speech justified by reference to the harmful results of
the speech’s persuasive power as inconsistent with listener autonomy.
39. This complaint is registered in Scanlon, “Freedom of Expression and Categories of Ex-
pression”; Steven H. Shiffrin, The First Amendment, Democracy, and Romance (Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press, 1990), chap. 4. On the contrast between the complexity of the
terrain and the simplicity of familiar theories, see Harry Kalven, A Worthy Tradition: Freedom
of Speech in America, ed. Jamie Kalven (New York: Harper and Row, 1988), 23.
40. In “Persuasion, Autonomy, and Expression,” Strauss argues that persuasion is “a process
of appealing, in some sense, to reason” (335), and that we ought not to regulate expression
when its harmful effects come from its power to persuade. Thus false advertising gets reduced
protection because it does not work by persuasion (as though we were in no danger of being
persuaded by liars); nonobscene pornography is protected because it does work by persuasion
(as though the scenes of the Washington Monument and the American flag featured at the
start of some triple-X movies were representative). Here I lose hold of his conception of persua-
sion and so of the argument about commercial speech.
111
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
has troubles with an intuitive idea, or distinction. Perhaps there is, in the
end, nothing more to these “intuitions” than second nature masquerad-
ing as first. But they do have some presumptive weight and so raise trou-
bles for maximalism.
Furthermore, if considerations about the transcendent value of expres-
sion are understood to provide only reasons for rejecting regulations on
grounds of communicative impact, then they will provide no limit at all
on content-neutral regulations—no weighted balancing—and no basis
for a concern with fair access. On the other hand, if considerations of au-
tonomy are understood to ground a uniform presumption against all reg-
ulation of expression because of the uniform connection of expression
with the value of autonomy, then either the uniform presumption will be
very low and the protections will be weak, or the uniform presumption
will be very high, and we will all have lots of listening to do.
More fundamentally, the main idea behind the variant of maximalism
I have focused on here is that expression always trumps other values be-
cause of its connection with autonomy. And this suggests that a commit-
ment to freedom of expression turns on embracing the supreme value of
autonomy. But this threatens to turn freedom of expression into a sectar-
ian political position. Is a strong commitment to expressive liberties re-
ally available only to those who endorse the idea that autonomy is the
fundamental human good—an idea about which there is much reason-
able controversy? I am not doubting that such a strong commitment is
available to those whose ethical views are of this kind, but I reject the
claim that such views are really necessary. The force of this concern
about sectarianism will become clearer as I describe an alternative to
minimalism and maximalism. Suffice it to say for now that it would be
desirable to frame an account of the values at stake that is capable of re-
ceiving wider support, an account that would free the doctrine both from
the insulting idea that expression is costless and from the sectarian idea
that it is priceless.
int erest s
Freedom of expression is commonly associated with such values as
the discovery of the truth, the self-expression of individuals, a well-
functioning democracy, and a balance of social stability and social
change.41 I do not wish to dispute these associations but rather to connect
more transparently the importance of expression with certain fundamen-
tal interests.
In particular, I distinguish three interests that are protected by stringent
assurances of expressive liberty and whose importance makes the de-
mand for substantial protection reasonable. I will call them the expres-
sive, the deliberative, and the informational interests. Before describing
those interests, however, I want to highlight the background of my ac-
count of them.
Earlier I accused maximalism of sectarianism. Because I want to steer
clear of that sectarianism, my presentation of these interests, and of their
importance, is framed to accommodate what I will call “the idea of rea-
sonable pluralism.”42 In brief, the idea of reasonable pluralism is that
41. See, in general, Thomas Emerson, The System of Freedom of Expression (New York: Vin-
tage, 1971). Lee C. Bollinger emphasizes as well the importance of encouraging tolerance in
The Tolerant Society (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986); and Vincent Blasi examines the
role of freedom of expression as a check on official misconduct in “The Checking Value in
First Amendment Theory,” American Bar Foundation Research Journal 3 (1977): 521–649.
42. For fuller discussion, see my “Moral Pluralism and Political Consensus,” in The Idea of
Democracy, ed. David Copp, Jean Hampton, and John Roemer (Cambridge: Cambridge Uni-
versity Press, 1993), 281–287 [essay 2 in this volume]; also see John Rawls, Political Liberalism,
35–38.
113
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
114
F R E E D O M O F E X P R E S S I O N
45. I say “perhaps” because expression often has nothing to do with communication. See C.
Edwin Baker, Human Liberty and Freedom of Speech (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989),
51–54. I am grateful to Randall Forsberg for her helpful comments on an earlier draft in which
I characterized the expressive interest much too narrowly.
46. My emphasis on reasons in the description of the expressive interest distinguishes my
treatment from conventional discussion of the value of self-expression and self-fulfillment.
When someone fulfils what they take to be an obligation (as specified by their moral views, for
example), it is wrong to treat this as a matter of self-expression or self-fulfillment.
47. Here I follow a suggestion advanced in Rawls’s discussion of liberty of conscience: that
the rationale for liberty of conscience lies in obligations that religious and moral views assign
to those who hold them, and that this rationale can, in some measure, be extended to other lib-
erties. See Rawls, Theory of Justice, 206.
115
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
48. Whitney v. California, 274 U.S. 357, 375 (1927) (Brandeis concurring).
49. See, for example, Barnes v. Glen Theatre, Inc., 111 S. Ct. 2456 (1991) (White dissenting).
50. See Kathy Acker, “Devoured by Myths: An Interview with Sylvère Lotringer,” in
Hannibal Lecter, My Father (New York: Semiotext(e), 1991); and the interview of Acker in An-
gry Women, ed. Andrea Juno and V. Vale (San Francisco: Re/Search, 1991), 184–185.
51. Cited in Edward de Grazia, Girls Lean Back Everywhere: The Law of Obscenity and the
Assault on Genius (New York: Random House, 1992), 459–460.
116
F R E E D O M O F E X P R E S S I O N
ing things of beauty. But the three I have mentioned are central cases of
the expressive interest and suffice to underscore the basis of its impor-
tance. They work outward from the case of fully conscientious expres-
sion, the paradigm of expression supported by substantial reasons from
the agent’s point of view. To be sure, diverse evaluative conceptions carry
different implications about what is reasonable to say and do. But com-
mon ground is that they assign to those who hold them substantial rea-
sons for expression, quite apart from the value of the expression to the au-
dience, even if there is no audience at all.
One alternative line of argument about freedom of expression focuses
entirely on public discussion and locates the contribution of expression
to public debate at the core of the ideal of freedom of expression. Such
views miss the parallels between expressive liberty and liberty of con-
science. As a result, they are insufficiently attentive to the weight of the
expressive interest and are likely to be too narrow in the scope of their
protections.
Cass Sunstein, for example, has recently restated the case for a two-tier
conception of freedom of expression, in which political speech occupies
the upper, stringently protected tier.52 Although Sunstein’s immediate fo-
cus is the proper interpretation of the First Amendment, his case rests in
part on general political values and so intersects with my concerns here.53
Sunstein defines speech as political when “it is both intended and re-
ceived as a contribution to public deliberation about some issue.”54 This
conception of political speech is very broad and is understood to encom-
pass “much art and literature,” because much “has the characteristics of
social commentary.”55 It is not boundless, however, in that it excludes
from highest level protection commercial speech, bribery, private libel,
and obscenity.
Because of the breadth of this conception of political speech, the prac-
tical differences between Sunstein’s approach and mine may, in the end,
turn out to be rather subtle. Still, it strikes me as a mistake to make core
protection contingent on the role of expression in contributing to public
52. See his “Free Speech Now” and his Democracy and the Problem of Free Speech.
53. See in particular his four reasons for special protection for political speech, only the first
of which is concerned specifically with constitutional interpretation, Democracy and the Prob-
lem of Free Speech, 132–137. Of course, his view is also controversial as constitutional interpre-
tation.
54. Ibid., 130.
55. Sunstein, “Free Speech Now,” 308.
117
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
56. Just for the record, I think it is neither instructive nor raving.
57. Expression that falls outside the upper tier is not for that reason without protection.
Thus the formulation in terms of “level of protection.”
58. See Sunstein, Democracy and the Problem of Free Speech, 136.
59. Absent a precise delineation of the category of political speech, the empirical issue is
hard to adjudicate. But some reasons for doubting the case for special vulnerability are sug-
gested in de Grazia, Girls Lean Back Everywhere; and in William Noble, Bookbanning in
America (Middlebury: Erikson, 1990).
60. On the issue of American constitutional tradition: Sunstein associates his own concep-
tion of freedom of expression with Brandeis’s focus on deliberation rather than Holmes’s mar-
ketplace of ideas. See Democracy and the Problem of Free Speech, 23–28. But Brandeis’s con-
currence in Whitney v. California, 274 U.S. 357, 373–378 (1927), is perhaps the classic
statement of the very great constitutional weight of the interests protected by the right to free-
dom of expression; it is not about the special vulnerability of political speech to government re-
striction.
118
F R E E D O M O F E X P R E S S I O N
Let us proceed, then, to the second basic interest: the deliberative in-
terest. This interest has two principal aspects. The first is rooted in the ab-
stract idea—shared by different evaluative conceptions—that it is impor-
tant to do what is best (or at least what is genuinely worthwhile) not
simply what one now believes best (or what one now believes to be
worthwhile). For this reason, we have an interest in circumstances favor-
able to finding what is best, or at least what is worthwhile: that is, to find-
ing out which ways of life are supported by the strongest reasons.
The second aspect of the deliberative interest is rooted in the idea that
it is important that one’s evaluative views not be affirmed out of igno-
rance or out of a lack of awareness of alternatives. So alongside the inter-
est in doing what is in fact supported by the strongest reasons, there is
also an interest in understanding what those reasons are and the nature of
the support they give. This, too, leads to an interest in circumstances fa-
vorable to such understanding.
The connection between these two aspects of the deliberative interest
and expression lies in the familiar fact that reflection on matters of hu-
man concern typically cannot be pursued in isolation. As Mill empha-
sized, it characteristically proceeds against the background of an articula-
tion of alternative views by other people.61 So here, again, there is an
interest in circumstances suited to understanding what is worth doing
and what the reasons are that support it—e.g., circumstances featuring a
diversity of messages, forcefully articulated.62
Finally, and most straightforwardly, I assume a fundamental informa-
tional interest in securing reliable information about the conditions re-
quired for pursuing one’s aims and aspirations.
Having described these three interests, I want to return to the com-
61. This is the force of Mill’s contention that censorship robs the human race, and that for
this reason, it does not matter whether all censor one or one censors all. Mill does not focus on
the harm or robbery to the person who is censored. See On Liberty (Indianapolis: Hackett,
1978), 16 (chap. 2, par. 1).
62. Robert Post has suggested a tension among various conditions required for satisfying the
deliberative interest in a diverse community. In particular, deliberation depends on civility, but
requiring civility puts the community in danger of making one particular understanding of ci-
vility authoritative for the community. I am not sure how deep this tension goes. To be sure, ci-
vility has its place in public deliberation. But so do anger, disgust, bitter criticism, and open ex-
pressions of hostility. Post’s immediate concern is with a parody of Reverend Jerry Falwell in
Larry Flynt’s Hustler magazine. Suffice it to say here that the parody of Falwell was, in my
view, a contribution to public debate, even if it was not civil and was not an invitation to
Falwell to have a conversation with Larry Flynt. See Robert Post, “The Constitutional Concept
of Public Discourse: Outrageous Opinion, Democratic Deliberation, and Hustler Magazine v.
Falwell,” Harvard Law Review 103 (1990): 601–686.
119
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
120
F R E E D O M O F E X P R E S S I O N
cost s
What then of the costs of expression? Commentators since Justice
Holmes have noted that protection for expression cannot be premised on
faith in its impotence.64 As Harry Kalven put it, “Speech has a price. It is
a liberal weakness to discount so heavily the price. [It] is not always cor-
rect to win [the protection of speech] by showing danger [it threatens]
has been exaggerated.”65 Underscoring Kalven’s point about the price of
speech and the weakness of characteristic arguments for protection, re-
cent “outsider” jurisprudence has portrayed the injuries that hate speech
imposes on its targets by narratively recounting those injuries.66 If we ab-
jure both the minimalist denial of the price and the sectarian route of
maximalism, then the idea of stringent protections may seem just inde-
fensible, and the skeptical response—“there’s no such thing”—may seem
a natural alternative.
What then are some of the kinds of costs that expression imposes? In
answering this question, I want to organize costs along just one axis, dis-
tinguishing three types by the pattern of their etiology.
First, there are direct costs. Here I have in mind cases in which, intu-
itively, nothing intervenes in between the expression and its price, where
“the very utterance inflicts injury”:67 I shriek at a neurasthenic with a
weak heart; disrupt the peace and quiet with loud shouting; falsely tell an
elderly parent that her child has just died; spread defamatory falsehoods
about a colleague; use offensive language in a public setting; offer a raise
or a higher grade in return for sex. When I have said my piece, the dam-
age is done, and it is done by what I said—and in the latter four cases, by
its content.
A second category of costs are “environmental.” Thus expression may
help to constitute a degraded, sickening, embarrassing, humiliating, ob-
trusively moralistic, hypercommercialized, hostile, or demeaning envi-
ronment. It might, for example, combine with other expressive actions to
64. Abrams v. U.S., 250 U.S. 616, 629 (1918) (Holmes dissenting).
65. Cited from Kalven’s notes in the “Editor’s Introduction” to A Worthy Tradition, xxii.
66. See in particular Matsuda, “Public Response to Racist Speech”; Charles Lawrence, “If
He Hollers Let Him Go”; Delgado, “Campus Antiracism Rules.”
67. Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U.S. 568, 571–572 (1942). Or, where the “evil” is “cre-
ated by the medium of expression itself,” as in the case of signs posted on utility poles, as dis-
tinct from leaflets handed to individuals. See City Council v. Taxpayers for Vincent, 466 U.S.
789, 810 (1984).
121
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
ba ckground fa c t s
To complete the picture of the bases of stringent protections, I now come
to the background facts.69 These facts are the set of sociological and an-
thropological claims that plays a central role in arguments about freedom
of expression, though often only as an implicit, half-articulated, and so
easily manipulable background.70 Whatever their common treatment,
their importance will eventually become clear. My aim here is simply to
make them explicit.
I will group the facts into three broad categories, which I label the
Facts of Reasonableness, the Bare Facts of Life, and the Unhappy Facts of
68. A work environment, for example, may be actionably hostile under Title VII of the Civil
Rights Act because of either the severity or the pervasiveness of conduct. See Meritor Savings
Bank v. Vinson, 477 U.S. 57, 67 (1986). For discussion of severity and pervasiveness, see Ellison
v. Brady, 924 F.2d 872 (9th Circuit, 1991).
69. Scanlon discusses the importance of “linking empirical beliefs” in arguments about
right to expressive liberty. His discussion overstates, I believe, the importance of beliefs spe-
cifically about the role of government in suppressing expression. See “Freedom of Expression
and Categories of Expression,” 534.
70. For a general discussion of the tendency of legal-doctrinal argument to suppress refer-
ence to background factual assumptions, see Roberto Unger, The Critical Legal Studies Move-
ment (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1982). In the case of freedom of expression,
Bollinger claims that the “fortress model” of speech protection presumes a set of irrational ten-
dencies to suppress speech that conflicts with the assumption of rational competence that
drives the ideal of an open market of ideas. So the conjunction of these two doctrines in a jus-
tification of free expression is untenable because it requires inconsistent background beliefs.
See The Tolerant Society, 92–93.
122
F R E E D O M O F E X P R E S S I O N
Life. Intuitively, the difference among the three categories is that the
facts of reasonableness are considerations that would favor the protection
of speech even under fully ideal conditions; the bare facts favor protec-
tion and are unalterable; the unhappy facts of life are considerations that
now favor protection but that we might hope are alterable features of our
circumstances.
Among the Facts of Reasonableness are:
123
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
124
F R E E D O M O F E X P R E S S I O N
78. Alexander Meiklejohn, Political Freedom (New York: Harper & Brothers, 1960), 27.
125
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
ca t egoriz a t ion
We come next to categorization as an approach to handling content regu-
lations. Recall that the idea of categorization is to confine exceptions to a
general presumption against content regulation by singling out a small
set of categories of expression—for example, child pornography, com-
mercial speech, obscenity, fighting words, and express incitement—for
lesser protection, specifying conditions for permissible regulation of ex-
pression in each category. The rationale for this strategy divides naturally
into two parts.
126
F R E E D O M O F E X P R E S S I O N
We need first to account for the distinctions between more and less im-
portant kinds of expression. Judgments of importance proceed princi-
pally by considering the connection of the expression to the fundamental
interests and secondarily by considering the prospects of addressing the
harms through more expression and the fragility of expression given the
Bare and the Unhappy Facts of Life.
Political expression, for example, is especially important because it is
so closely connected to each of the basic interests and because of its fra-
gility in light of the Fact of Power. Because it is commonly a form of po-
litical speech, expression that libels a group is more strongly connected
to expressive and deliberative interests than expression that threatens in-
dividual libel is; the injuries are also more easily remedied with group li-
bel than with individual libel. For these reasons it is important to confine
reduced protection to a category of individual libel, even though people
may be harmed by libeling groups to which they belong or with which
they identify. The idea that group libel ought to be more strongly pro-
tected than individual libel is not contingent on a liberal individualist
failure to acknowledge the possibility of harm through group libel, any
more than the protection of the libel of public figures requires a denial of
its harm.80
Commercial speech can be a source of information. But it is less im-
portant than political expression, because it is not so closely connected to
the expressive or the deliberative interests.81 Moreover, the Cold Facts
and the Fact of Limited Understanding have much less force in the case
of commercial speech.82 The economic interests that fuel commercial
speech ensure that it is less susceptible to a regulatory chill, while the fact
that commercial advertisers are best situated to know the accuracy of
80. Here I disagree with the defense of group libel laws in Note, “A Communitarian De-
fense of Group Libel Laws,” Harvard Law Review 101 (1988): 682–701. The main reason for re-
jecting regulations of group libel is not that such libel is harmless. See, for example, Justice
Black’s dissent in Beauharnais v. Illinois, 343 U.S. 250 (1952). Black does not deny the costs but
emphasizes the extensive “inroads” on expression that would result from accepting regulations
of group libel.
81. C. Edwin Baker proposes that commercial speech ought to have no First Amendment
protection, in part because such speech reflects the coercive logic of profit-maximization
rather than the choice of the speaker. This explanation strikes me as a strained defense of the
idea that regulations of commercial speech are less burdensome, not least because it suggests
that advertising by price-setting monopolists, which is less subject to the coercive demands of
profit-maximization, ought to be more protected. See Baker, Human Liberty and Freedom of
Speech, chap. 9.
82. See Virginia State Board of Pharmacy v. Virginia Citizens Consumer Council, 425 U.S.
748, 771 (n. 24) (1976), and 777–781 (Stewart concurring).
127
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
their claims reduces concern about the chilling effects of requiring accu-
racy in commercial speech.
But—and here we come to the second part of the case—even if we can
provide an account of relative importance, why filter judgments of rela-
tive importance by categorization rather than proceed case by case?83
Here the main burden is carried by the Chilling Facts and the Unhappy
Facts of Power, Bias, and Disadvantage. Together they induce an expec-
tation that ad hoc regulation will err on the side of excessive interference,
on the side of underprotection of what should be protected. Moreover,
ad hoc judgments are likely to raise greater concerns about chilling ex-
pression. Categories, then, serve as a protective device—a device of self-
binding—against excessive interference in a context in which a very sub-
stantial value is at stake.
To elaborate: unless expression falls into a less protected category, we
impose very high barriers to regulating it. And before we can consider
more substantial regulation of some act of expression, we need to find a
general category into which it falls such that we are prepared to reduce
the protection for all expression in that general category. The result may
be greater protection for some expression than we are inclined to think
suitable.84 But—if the facts are right—then the alternative would be in-
sufficient protection to some expression. Of course, the claim that cate-
gorization plays this role premises that the categories are—whether for
semantical or psychological reasons—not so utterly manipulable and in-
determinate that they serve no channeling function at all. If they are not,
if the facts are as stipulated, and if the choice of regulatory form does
have the proposed consequences, then it is reasonable to pursue the strat-
egy of protection through categorization.
128
F R E E D O M O F E X P R E S S I O N
85. Stanley Fish, “There’s No Such Thing as Free Speech and It’s a Good Thing Too,”
Boston Review 17, 1 (1992): 3–4, 23–26.
86. See ibid., 26. I am indebted to Duncan Kennedy for discussion of this point.
87. Ibid.
129
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
88. Black, “The Bill of Rights,” New York University Law Review 35 (1960): 879.
89. Fish, “There’s No Such Thing,” 26.
90. Ibid.
130
F R E E D O M O F E X P R E S S I O N
91. I take this example from “Moral Pluralism and Political Consensus,” 286.
92. It is an analog to “creation science,” operating in the domain of salvation. The proper re-
sponse is the same in both cases.
93. Most fundamentalists are not rationalist fundamentalists, and would I think agree with
this response.
94. I offer the rationalist fundamentalist simply as one illustration. The case of the
nonrationalist fundamentalist—who affirms that the basis of religious conviction lies in faith—
is more complicated. The latter may wish to distinguish truths delivered by faith from the bases
of political justification, and so may be prepared to acknowledge expressive and deliberative
interests, at least in the context of political argument.
131
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
and deliberative interests—is much greater than the weight of the interest
in not being offended, so those restrictions would be intolerable. More-
over, it will not help to confine efforts to regulate to the “grossly offen-
sive”—then we will run into troubles because of the chilling effects of
vagueness. The likely vagueness in regulations of the “grossly offensive,”
that is, threatens to chill acceptable expression.95
I do not deny that there is a cost or “price” to offensive expression; in-
deed the cost is direct. Instead, I claim that the costs of avoiding offense
are to be borne by those subject to it—they must, for example, “avert
their eyes.”96
Offensive expression is, as I said, a special case. Moving beyond it,
then, the general strategy in deciding whether to protect expression de-
spite its price is to consider the importance of the expression (with atten-
tion to the role of categories), the directness and seriousness of the harm,
and the vulnerability of the expression to underprotection, given the
background facts. Let me illustrate with three kinds of case.
In cases of the first type, expression belongs to an important category, it
is vulnerable, and the costs are either environmental or indirect. Then
the reasons against restriction are especially strong, even if the cost is sub-
stantial.
Consider, for example, the pornography ordinances adopted in Min-
neapolis and Indianapolis in the 1980s. According to the Indianapolis or-
dinance, pornography is the “graphic, sexually explicit subordination of
women, whether in pictures or in words,” which also meets one of the
following conditions:
132
F R E E D O M O F E X P R E S S I O N
133
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
100. I take the proposal from Duncan Kennedy, “Sexual Abuse, Sexy Dressing and the
Eroticization of Domination,” New England Law Review 26 (1992), 1318.
101. For a more general discussion of associative approaches to reconciling egalitarian and
liberal commitment, see Joshua Cohen and Joel Rogers, “Secondary Associations and Demo-
cratic Governance,” Politics and Society 20 (1992): 393–472.
102. See, for example, Cass Sunstein’s proposal in “Pornography and the First Amendment,”
Duke Law Journal 4 (1986): 589–627. He sharply narrows the class of pornographic expression,
defining the class in a way that aims to make it low value. It amounts, more or less (and implic-
itly), to substituting “erotizes violence and subordination” for “offensive” in the definition of
obscenity.
134
F R E E D O M O F E X P R E S S I O N
fa ir a ccess
Finally, we come to the requirement of ensuring fair access to expres-
sive opportunities. Three main lines of argument converge on this con-
clusion.
The first begins by underscoring the central role played in the ac-
103. There was, for example, no suggestion that Falwell was really responsible for the distress
because of a hypersensitivity to accusations of sin.
135
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
136
F R E E D O M O F E X P R E S S I O N
106. As, for example, in Rawls’s argument that reflection on the ideal of natural liberty leads
to the ideal of democratic equality. See Theory of Justice, 65–74; and my discussion of the boot-
strapping strategy in “Moral Pluralism and Political Consensus,” 278–279.
107. Reasoning of broadly this kind can be found in Metro Broadcasting, Inc. v. FCC, 100 S.
Ct. 2997 (1990), where the Court upholds an FCC program aimed at increasing broadcast di-
versity, by increasing the number of minorities with broadcast licenses. For criticisms, see
Charles Fried, “Metro Broadcasting, Inc. v. FCC: Two Concepts of Equality,” Harvard Law Re-
view 104 (1990): 107–127.
108. See Owen Fiss, “Silence on the Street Corner,” Suffolk University Law Review 26 1
(1992): 13–14.
137
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
109. Current tendencies in doctrine are, more or less, opposite to the suggestion here. See
U.S. v. Kokinda, 110 S. Ct. 3115 (1990); and the discussion in Fiss, “Silence on the Street Cor-
ner.”
110. For an argument—close to the perspective in this essay—that the current private
scheme of campaign financing violates requirements of equal protection, and a sketch of alter-
native directions of reform, see Jamin Raskin and John Bonifaz, “Equal Protection and the
Wealth Primary,” Yale Law and Policy Review 11 (Winter 1993): 273–332. For an instructive dis-
cussion of campaign finance that focuses more or less exclusively on the deliberative interest,
see Charles Beitz, Political Equality (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1989), chap. 9.
111. 424 U.S. 1 (1976). It is consistent with Buckley to move to a system of voluntary public
financing, with matching funds for candidates whose opponents opt to spend private contribu-
tions, or to spend their own money. For a sketch of such a system, see Ellen S. Miller, “Money,
Politics, and Democracy,” Boston Review 18 (March/April 1993): 5–8.
112. 424 U.S. 1, 48–49 (1976).
113. Ibid.
138
F R E E D O M O F E X P R E S S I O N
I agree with the last claim about the implications of a serious commit-
ment to freedom of expression, and later I will present a style of pornog-
raphy regulation that is less encompassing than MacKinnon’s proposals
but consistent with the perspective I have advanced in this essay. I do
wish, however, to resist jumping too quickly to the conclusion that con-
114. MacKinnon, “Francis Biddle’s Sister,” 193.
139
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
tent regulation is the only way to ensure fair access. Other measures of
empowerment that are more affirmative than regulations of expression
may show real promise in addressing silencing and exclusion—at least as
much promise as restricting pornography. In particular, alongside efforts
to address the general unjust inequalities of men and women—to over-
come the division of household labor and the labor-market segregation of
women115—alternative ways to meet the problems of silencing directly
should be explored. Earlier, for example, I mentioned a tort of domestic
sexual harassment, regular public hearings on sexual abuse, perhaps sub-
sidies for women’s organizations to hold such hearings, or easier access of
women to broadcast licenses.
Indeed, it is not clear that MacKinnon would disagree with the plausi-
bility of these remedies. Responding to the Brandeisian idea of address-
ing the harms of speech with more speech, she asks: “Would more
speech remedy the harm [of pornography]?” Her response is instruc-
tive: “In the end, the answer may be yes, but not under the abstract
system [my emphasis] of free speech, which only enhances the power of
pornographers while doing nothing to guarantee the free speech of
women, for which we need civil equality.”116 MacKinnon is right in say-
ing that a serious commitment to freedom of expression cannot be
sharply distinguished from a program of civil equality. For that reason,
the proposals I have mentioned are not exclusively about “the abstract
system of free speech”; they aim directly to enhance the speech of wo-
men and are part of a program of “civil equality.” So it is unclear why
they should not be expected to do as well as a more restrictive strategy for
addressing the harms at issue.
115. For discussion, see Susan Moller Okin, Justice, Gender, and the Family (New York: Ba-
sic Books, 1989).
116. “Francis Biddle’s Sister,” 193.
117. I take the term from R. A. V. v. St. Paul, 112 S. Ct. 2538, 2546 (1992).
140
F R E E D O M O F E X P R E S S I O N
ba ckground
The facts in R. A. V. v. St. Paul are straightforward and uncontested.
R. A. V. (Robert A. Viktora, a juvenile at the time of prosecution) and his
friends burned a cross in the yard of a black family; he was arrested, and
charged under a St. Paul Bias-Motivated Crime Ordinance. The ordi-
nance provides that:
Whoever places on public or private property a symbol, object,
appellation, characterization or graffiti, including, but not lim-
ited to, a burning cross or Nazi swastika, which one knows or
has reasonable grounds to know arouses anger, alarm or resent-
ment in others on the basis of race, color, creed, religion or
gender commits disorderly conduct and shall be guilty of a mis-
demeanor.118
141
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
119. 315 U.S. 568, 571–572 (1942). For doubts about the fighting words doctrine, see Note,
“The Demise of the Chaplinsky Fighting Words Doctrine: An Argument for its Interment,”
Harvard Law Review 106 (1993): 1129–1146.
120. This is the basis of the reasoning by the Minnesota Court. Scalia’s opinion emphati-
cally rejects this claim. See R. A. V., 112 S. Ct. 2543.
121. The Minnesota Court said it was restricted to fighting words. But the concurrences re-
jected that Court’s construal of the fighting words test. Ibid., 2558–2560.
142
F R E E D O M O F E X P R E S S I O N
Proscribable Expression Is Not without Protection. From the fact that the
government could proscribe a whole category of expression—say, child
pornography—it does not follow that every less inclusive regulation pro-
scribing a subclass and permitting the rest is also acceptable: think of a
child pornography statute restricted to kiddie porn in which at least one
actor wears an “I like Dan Quayle” button, or a regulation of obscenity
produced after supper. Regulations targeted on those subcategories are
unacceptable. So the argument for restricting hateful fighting words can-
not count among its premises the claim that every subcategory of a
proscribable category can be targeted permissibly.
143
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
144
F R E E D O M O F E X P R E S S I O N
126. Thus Scalia’s firm distinction between “no part” of the exposition of ideas and “no es-
sential part” of that exposition, ibid., 2544. Implicit in these remarks is the suggestion that the
concurrences endorse the tempting but implausible view that I note in the text.
127. There is certainly no “prohibition of public discussion of an entire topic.” Boos v. Barry,
485 U.S. 312, 319 (1988).
145
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
the reasons for expression in the form of fighting words do not seem espe-
cially substantial. Taking these points together, it seems much less plausi-
ble that a regulation targeted on hateful fighting words would severely
suppress ideas or would be motivated by a desire to suppress them than
that a regulation targeted on hate speech generally would have that unac-
ceptable effect or illegitimate motivation. So there does appear to be a
substantial difference in the fears about suppression that would reason-
ably be triggered by a general regulation of hate speech and a regulation
targeted specifically on the hateful subset of fighting words.
Of course, given the Facts of Power, Easy Offense, and Abuse, con-
cerns about suppression could be revived if a regulation were focused on
a relatively insignificant harm. But racial subordination, for example,128 is
a serious evil; and it is at least plausible that racist fighting words play
some role—plausibly a significant role—in maintaining racial inequality.
They contribute to an environment of fear, suspicion, hostility, and mis-
trust that makes racial division so resistant to remedy. So the regulation
picks out not an arbitrary class of fighting words but a class that is espe-
cially damaging to fundamental political values, for example the value of
racial equality. Finally, it seems especially implausible that the injuries
produced by hateful fighting words can be remedied with more speech.
The anger, the fear, and the suspicion that they produce are not kinds
that can be easily addressed by verbal reassurances.
The regulation, then, is targeted on a category with only a minimal
connection with the fundamental deliberative and expressive interests;
and within that category it focuses on a subcategory that is plausibly more
injurious than other elements of the category and whose effects are plau-
sibly more recalcitrant to expressive cure.
There are three responses to this argument, each of which aims to rein-
state suspicions about the suppression of ideas in a hateful fighting words
regulation.
The first is that there is a straightforward basis for the suspicion: it is
agreed, as I indicated earlier, that a general hate-speech regulation would
128. I say “for example” because the St. Paul ordinance was not simply addressed to racial
hate speech nor, more particularly, to racial hate speech targeted on African Americans or
other groups subordinated on the basis of race. For the suggestion that such a narrow and
“openly asymmetric regulation” might have been less constitutionally suspect—in light of the
Thirteenth Amendment ban on badges of servitude—see Akhil Reed Amar, “Comment: The
Case of the Missing Amendments: R. A. V. v. City of St. Paul,” Harvard Law Review 106 (1992):
155–161. See also my discussion of the asymmetry in the Stanford regulation, 152–153 below.
146
F R E E D O M O F E X P R E S S I O N
129. See R. A. V., 112 S. Ct. 2545: “When the basis for the content discrimination consists en-
tirely of the very reason the entire class of speech is proscribable, no significant danger of idea
or viewpoint discrimination exists.”
147
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
130. This appears to be the force of Scalia’s remark that “what makes the anger, fear, sense of
dishonor, etc. produced by violation of this ordinance distinct from the honor fear, sense of dis-
honor, etc. produced by other fighting words is nothing other than the fact that it is conveyed
by a distinctive idea, conveyed by a distinctive message.” Ibid., 2548.
131. Here I agree with Amar that a cleaner focus on the nature of the harms and a more dis-
criminating discussion of the differences among the categories mentioned in the ordinance—
“race, color, creed, religion, or gender”—would have sharpened both the regulation and the
Court’s assessment of it. See Amar, “The Case of the Missing Amendments,” 155–160.
132. Miller v. California, 413 U.S. 15 (1973).
133. See Roth v. United States, 354 U.S. 476, 512 (Douglas dissenting), and Harry Kalven,
“The Metaphysics of the Law of Obscenity,” The Supreme Court Review: 1960, ed. Philip B.
Kurland (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1960), 18–19.
148
F R E E D O M O F E X P R E S S I O N
149
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
135. Indeed, I suspect that many who hold this second view would be more inclined to regu-
late the pornographically obscene than the grossly obscene. But I will put this matter to the
side.
150
F R E E D O M O F E X P R E S S I O N
152
F R E E D O M O F E X P R E S S I O N
137. I say “not now” because I was frequently called “kike,” “bagel-bender,” and the like
when I was growing up.
153
5
P R O C E D U R E A N D S U B S TA N C E
I N D E L I B E R AT I V E D E M O C R A C Y
I would like to thank John Rawls, Charles Sabel, T. M. Scanlon, Cass Sunstein, and Iris
Marion Young for illuminating comments on earlier drafts of this essay. The “Deliberative De-
mocracy” section draws on my “Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy,” in Alan Hamlin
and Phillip Petit, eds. The Good Polity (Oxford Blackwell, 1989), 17–34 [reprinted as essay 1 in
this volume]. The “Three Principles” section draws on my review of Robert Dahl’s Democracy
and Its Critics (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1989) in Journal of Politics 53, 1 (1991): 221–
225; and on my “Pluralism and Proceduralism,” Chicago-Kent Law Review 69, 3 (1994): 589–
618. The “Realizing Democracy” section draws on Joshua Cohen and Joel Rogers, Democracy
and Association (London: Verso, 1995).
1. “Governed by” rather than “affected by.” Democracy is about justifying authority not
about justifying influence. See Michael Walzer, Spheres of Justice (New York: Basic Books,
1983); and Christopher McMahon, Authority and Democracy (Princeton: Princeton University
Press, 1994). Alternatively stated, authorization must come from the popular will, where “pop-
ular will” is understood as indicating the ultimate authority and responsibility of citizens as a
body not as implying a collective ranking of alternatives that preexists institutions and seeks au-
thentic expressions through them. See William Riker, Liberalism Against Populism (San Fran-
cisco: W. H. Freeman, 1992).
2. On the notion of a comprehensive doctrine, see John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New
York: Columbia University Press, 1996 [1993]), 13.
154
P R O C E D U R E A N D S U B S T A N C E
155
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
about the relative merits of contemplative and practical lives and the im-
portance of personal and political engagement; and disagreements about
the religious and philosophical backgrounds of these evaluative views.
Apart from the sheer fact of disagreement, there is, moreover, no appar-
ent tendency to convergence generated by the exercise of practical rea-
son; furthermore, we have no theory of the operations of practical reason
that would lead us to predict convergence on comprehensive moralities,
nor can I think of any marginally attractive social or political mecha-
nisms that might generate such agreement.
This fact of reasonable pluralism gives shape to the conception of citi-
zens as free and equal that constitutes part of the conception of democ-
racy I want to explore here. To say that citizens are free is to say, inter alia,
that no comprehensive moral or religious view provides a defining condi-
tion of membership or the foundation of the authorization to exercise po-
litical power. To say that they are equal is to say that each is recognized as
having the capacities required for participating in discussion aimed at au-
thorizing the exercise of power.
What, then, are the implications of reasonable pluralism for a concep-
tion of democracy? It is natural to suppose that by excluding a compre-
hensive consensus on values, the fact of reasonable pluralism leads to a
procedural conception of democracy. According to such a conception,
the democratic pedigree that lies at the source of legitimacy can be set-
tled by looking exclusively to the processes through which collective de-
cisions are made and to the values associated with fair processes: for ex-
ample, values of openness, equal chances to present alternatives, and full
and impartial consideration of those alternatives. The fact of reasonable
pluralism appears to require a procedural conception because it deprives
us of a background of shared moral or religious premises that could give
determinate content to the idea of popular authorization or constrain the
substance of genuinely collective choices. Without that background, we
are left, it may seem, with no basis for agreement on anything more than
fair procedures—and perhaps not even that.
I think this conclusion is not right and will sketch a view that combines
an assumption of reasonable pluralism with a more substantive concep-
tion of democracy. Moreover, I will argue that this combination is a natu-
ral result of a particular way of thinking about democracy—a “delibera-
tive” understanding of the collective decisions that constitute democratic
governance. Before discussing the deliberative conception, though, I
156
P R O C E D U R E A N D S U B S T A N C E
need first to fix the concerns about procedure and substance more pre-
cisely, distinguish a deliberative from an aggregative conception of de-
mocracy, and show how aggregative conceptions lead to proceduralism.
157
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
7. See Dahl’s concerns about judicial review in Democracy and Its Critics, 183.
8. It is, of course, open to a democratic pluralist to hold that such infringements are unjust
and that the people ought to reject them.
9. On the distinction between aggregative and deliberative views, and its bearing on the pos-
sibility of reconciling commitments to values of liberty and equality within a conception of de-
mocracy, see my review of Dahl’s Democracy and Its Critics. For discussion of the related dis-
tinction between strategic and deliberative conceptions, see David Estlund, “Who’s Afraid of
Deliberative Democracy? On the Strategic/Deliberative Dichotomy in Recent Constitutional
Jurisprudence,” Texas Law Review 7, 7 (June 1993): 1437–1477. Estlund identifies strategic theo-
ries with views that make use of the idea of utility-maximization. I think that the crucial issue is
whether a conception of democracy emphasizes the idea of providing reasons acceptable to
others.
10. In Democracy and Its Critics, chaps. 6–8, Dahl derives conditions on democratic proce-
dure from a principle of equal consideration and a presumption of personal autonomy.
158
P R O C E D U R E A N D S U B S T A N C E
159
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
Deliberative Democracy
The deliberative conception of democracy is organized around an ideal
of political justification. According to this ideal, justification of the exer-
cise of collective political power is to proceed on the basis of a free public
reasoning among equals. A deliberative democracy institutionalizes this
ideal. Not simply a form of politics, democracy, on the deliberative view,
is a framework of social and institutional conditions that facilitates free
discussion among equal citizens—by providing favorable conditions for
participation, association, and expression—and ties the authorization to
exercise public power (and the exercise itself) to such discussion—by es-
tablishing a framework ensuring the responsiveness and accountability of
political power to it through regular competitive elections, conditions of
publicity, legislative oversight, and so on.13
I will come back later to the conditions for institutionalizing delibera-
tion in greater detail. First, though, I want to say more about the idea of
deliberative justification itself.
A deliberative conception puts public reasoning at the center of politi-
cal justification. I say “public reasoning” rather than “public discussion”
because a deliberative view cannot be distinguished simply by its empha-
sis on discussion rather than on bargaining or voting. Any view of democ-
13. On the role of the idea of democracy as more than a political idea, see Gordon Wood,
The Radicalism of the American Revolution (New York: Knopf, 1992), esp. 232.
160
P R O C E D U R E A N D S U B S T A N C E
161
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
16. T. M. Scanlon, “Contractualism and Utilitarianism,” in Amartya Sen and Bernard Wil-
liams, eds., Utilitarianism and Beyond (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982). The
point of contrast in the text is prompted by Scanlon’s discussion of the role of maximin reason-
ing in moral contractualism in What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, MA: Harvard Uni-
versity Press, 1997), 223–229.
162
P R O C E D U R E A N D S U B S T A N C E
others. And these constraints on reasons will limit the substantive out-
comes of the process; they supplement the limits set by the generic idea
of a fair procedure of reason giving.
I am not here raising an objection to Scanlon’s view. He has a different
topic—morality generally, as distinct from democratic legitimacy. In-
stead, I am urging that this difference in background makes a difference
to the kinds of reasons that are suited to the two cases.
To conclude these general remarks about the deliberative view, I want
to emphasize that its virtues are allied closely with its conception of bind-
ing collective choice, in particular with the role in that conception of the
idea of reasons acceptable to others who are governed by those choices
and who, themselves, have reasonable views. By requiring reasons ac-
ceptable to others, the deliberative view suggests an especially compel-
ling picture of the possible relations among people within a democratic
order.
To see the character of those relations, notice first that the deliberative
conception offers a more forceful rendering than the aggregative view of
the fundamental democratic idea—the idea that decisions about the ex-
ercise of state power are collective. It requires that we offer consider-
ations that others (whose conduct will be governed by the decisions) can
accept, not simply that we count their interests in deciding what to do,
while keeping our fingers crossed that those interests are outweighed.
Thus the idea of popular authorization is reflected not only in the pro-
cesses of decision making but also in the form—and, we will see later,
the content—of political reason itself.
This point about the force of the deliberative view and its conception
of collective decisions can be stated in terms of the idea of political com-
munity. If political community depends on sharing a comprehensive
moral or religious view, or a substantive national identity defined in
terms of such a view, then reasonable pluralism ruins the possibility of
political community. But an alternative conception of political commu-
nity connects the deliberative view to the value of community. In particu-
lar, by requiring justification on terms acceptable to others, deliberative
democracy provides for a form of political autonomy: that all who are
governed by collective decisions—who are expected to govern their own
conduct by those decisions—must find the bases of those decisions ac-
ceptable. And in this assurance of political autonomy, deliberative de-
mocracy achieves one important element of the ideal of community.
163
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
Three Principles
The aggregative conception of democracy promises the protections re-
quired for a fair process of binding collective choice, including pro-
tections against discrimination that would undermine the claim of the
process to ensure equal consideration. I said earlier that the deliberative
view will provide a basis for wider guarantees of basic liberties. It is time
to make good on that claim. The main idea is that the deliberative con-
ception requires more than that the interests of others be given equal
consideration; it demands, too, that we find politically acceptable rea-
sons—reasons that are acceptable to others, given a background of differ-
ences of conscientious conviction. I will call this requirement the “prin-
ciple of deliberative inclusion.”
Consider, for example, the case of religious liberty. Religious views
set demands of an especially high order—perhaps transcendent obli-
gations—on their adherents; moreover, if we see these requirements
from the believer’s point of view, then we cannot think of them as self-
imposed. Instead, the requirements are fixed by the content of the con-
victions, which the agent takes to be true. Reasonable adherents, then,
cannot accept as sufficient, reasons in support of a law or a system of pol-
icy, considerations that would preclude their compliance with those de-
164
P R O C E D U R E A N D S U B S T A N C E
mands. What, then, about people who do not share those views? (I will
describe the issue from the point of view of citizens who have fundamen-
tal moral convictions but no religious convictions. Broadly parallel re-
marks could be made from the standpoint of citizens with different reli-
gious convictions.) They might regard all religious views that impose
such stringent demands, whatever their content and foundation, as un-
reasonable. I see no rationale for this view. Or they might treat the reli-
gious demands as intense preferences, to be given equal consideration
along with other preferences of equal intensity. This reductive response
indicates an unwillingness to see the special role of religious convictions
from the point of view of the person who has them, an unwillingness to
see how the religious view, in virtue of its content, states or implies that
the requirements provide especially compelling reasons.
Alternatively, they might take seriously that the demands impose what
the adherent reasonably regards as fundamental obligations, accept the
requirement of finding reasons that might override these obligations, and
acknowledge that such reasons cannot normally be found. The result is
religious liberty, understood to include freedom of conscience and wor-
ship. It emerges as the product of the demanding character of religious
requirements—which are seen, from the point of view of those who are
subject to them, as matters of fundamental obligation—together with the
requirement of finding reasons that those who are subject to those re-
quirements can reasonably be expected to acknowledge, and the fact that
citizens who are not religious have fundamental convictions that they
take to impose especially compelling obligations.
Suppose, then, that we prevent others from fulfilling such demands for
reasons that they are compelled—by the lights of a view that commands
their conviction—to regard as insufficient. This is to deny them standing
as equal citizens—full membership in the people whose collective ac-
tions authorize the exercise of power. And that, according to the delibera-
tive conception, is a failure of democracy. We have failed to provide a
justification for the exercise of power by reference to considerations that
all who are subject to that power, and prepared to cooperate on reason-
able terms, can accept. There are many ways to exclude individuals and
groups from the people, and this surely is one.
These points about religious liberty—essentially about its free exer-
cise—do not say anything about how to handle claims for religious ex-
emption from general obligations with a strong secular justification (in-
165
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
17. On this last point: the key to the case for religious liberty is that the content of a view as-
signs stringent obligations to a person who holds it. But specifically religious content is not es-
sential.
18. This account of religious liberty may seem to rest on the idea of a natural right to reli-
gious liberty: to say, in effect, that reasons will count as acceptable in a deliberative process
only if they accept this right. If the idea of a natural right to religious liberty simply comes to
the claim that there is a right that can be abridged only on pain of illegitimacy, then the delib-
erative view includes natural rights. But natural rights views have claimed more than this: they
offer an explanation of the basis of fundamental rights in human nature, in natural law, or in a
prepolitical normative order to which political society must conform. The idea of democratic
legitimacy does not depend on that explanation, though it asserts nothing inconsistent with it.
It suffices that religious liberties have an explanation tied to the idea of democratic legitimacy.
For the purpose of political argument, nothing more needs to be said, positively or negatively.
19. Roberto Unger argues that a system of immunity rights is one component of a demo-
cratic order, because “freedom as participation presupposes freedom as immunity.” Rejecting
the view of “critics of traditional democratic theory,” who hold that “participatory opportunities
[are] a more than satisfactory substitute for immunity guarantees,” Unger sees immunity rights
as necessary if a citizen is to have the “safety that encourages him to participate actively and in-
dependently in collective decision-making.” In False Necessity (Cambridge: Cambridge Uni-
versity Press, 1987), 525. I agree with Unger’s observations, but I think that a conception of de-
mocracy can make a less instrumental place for certain liberties, even when those liberties are
not procedural.
20. This discussion draws on my “Freedom of Expression,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 22,
3 (Summer 1993): 207–263 [reprinted as essay 4 in this collection].
166
P R O C E D U R E A N D S U B S T A N C E
trasts with a more familiar strand of free speech theory that traces the
foundations of stringent guarantees of expressive liberty to the need to as-
sure a democratic framework of collective choice but guarantees strin-
gent protection only for political speech.21 This limit is in tension with
the requirement of deliberative inclusion.
Confining stringent protection to political speech seems natural, once
one has decided to base rights to free expression on the importance of re-
quiring government accountability and responsiveness to citizens as a
body. But as my remarks on the religion case suggest, a deliberative con-
ception of democracy cannot accept such a limit. To be sure, the idea of
discussion aimed at reaching reasonable agreement is fundamental to
the deliberative view. But it does not follow that the protection of expres-
sion is to be confined to speech that contributes to such discussion.
Consider expression that is not part of any process of discussion or per-
suasion—that is not “intended and received as a contribution to public
deliberation about some issue”22—but that, nevertheless, reflects what a
citizen takes, for quite understandable reasons, to be compelling reasons
for expression.23 This might be so in cases of bearing witness, with no ex-
pectation or intention of persuading others, or giving professional advice,
with no expectation or intention of shaping broader processes of collec-
tive decision making. The deliberative view extends stringent protection
to such expression, as a way to acknowledge the weight of those reasons.
Given the background of reasonable pluralism, the failure to do so—to
give due weight to an expressive interest that does not serve as input to
political discussion—will constitute a denial of equal standing, and de-
cisions that fail to ensure those stringent protections are not suitably col-
lective.
The tradition that traces protections of expressive liberty to democratic
ideals and then restricts stringent protection to contributions to debate in
the public forum conflates the general strategy of providing a case for
freedom of expression rooted in the idea of democracy with one ele-
21. See Alexander Meiklejohn, Free Speech and Its Relation to Self-Government (New York:
Harper and Row, 1948); and Cass R. Sunstein, Democracy and the Problem of Free Speech
(New York: Free Press, 1993). Also, Robert Bork, “Neutral Principles and Some First Amend-
ment Problems,” Indiana Law Journal 47, 1 (Fall 1971): 1–35; Ely, Democracy and Distrust; and
Owen Fiss, “Why the State?” Harvard Law Review 100 (1987): 781–794.
22. This is Sunstein’s account of political speech, in Democracy and the Problem of Free
Speech, 130.
23. I do not mean to suggest that stringent protection ought to be confined to expression ani-
mated by such compelling reasons. The conventional democratic defense of rights of expres-
sion also provides a basis for stringent protection. My aim is to supplement that rationale.
167
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
168
P R O C E D U R E A N D S U B S T A N C E
lations, or policies that are not attentive to the interests of some citi-
zens may be justifiable as part of an overall package of laws and policies
that is.)26 This minimal constraint—of advancing the interests of each—
comes out of the generic conception of a deliberative process and suf-
fices to establish a pareto-efficiency requirement, as one element of a
conception of democracy.
But as I have emphasized, the deliberation that plays a role in the con-
ception of deliberative democracy is not simply a matter of reason giving,
generically understood. The background conception of citizens as equals
sets limits on permissible reasons that can figure within the deliberative
process. For suppose one accepts the democratic process of binding col-
lective choice, agreeing that adults are, more or less without exception, to
have access to it. One can then reject, as a reason within that process,
that some are worth less than others or that the interests of one group are
to count for less than the interests of other groups. That constraint on rea-
sons will, in turn, limit the outcomes of the process, adding to the condi-
tions set by the generic idea of deliberation. In particular, it provides a
case for a public understanding about the distribution of resources that
severs the fates of citizens from the differences of social position, natural
endowment, and good fortune that distinguish citizens.
John Rawls’s difference principle provides one illustration of such an
understanding.27 Treating equality as a baseline, it requires that inequali-
ties established or sanctioned by state action must work to the maximal
advantage of the least advantaged. That baseline is a natural expression
of the constraints on reasons that emerge from the background equal
standing of citizens: it will not count as a reason for a system of policy
that that system benefits the members of a particular group singled out by
social class or native talent or any other feature that distinguishes among
equal citizens. I do not wish to suggest here that Rawls’s difference princi-
ple is the uniquely acceptable conception of the common good. But
there is an especially strong case for it, both because it accepts the pre-
26. The vices of a sales tax, for example, depend on the nature and level of exemptions, the
presence (or not) of tax credits, and the nature of the policies that the revenue pays for.
27. See John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971),
513. For discussion of the connections between the difference principle and an ideal of democ-
racy, see my “Democratic Equality,” Ethics 99, 4 (July 1989): 736–743. Another view that might
be used to illustrate the points in the text is Dworkin’s equality of resources. See Ronald
Dworkin, “What Is Equality? Part 2: Equality of Resources,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 10, 4
(Autumn 1981): 283–345.
169
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
170
P R O C E D U R E A N D S U B S T A N C E
elites, thus enabling people to make informed choices among them and
the views they represent, without any special provision for more substan-
tive political equality, understood as requiring equally weighted votes and
equal opportunities for effective influence.32 How, then, does the deliber-
ative view connect to concerns about participation and political equality?
Three considerations are important.
First, given the principles of deliberative inclusion and of the common
good, the deliberative view can avail itself of conventional instrumental
reasons in support of equal political rights. Such rights provide the means
for protecting other basic rights and for advancing interests in ways that
might plausibly promote the common good. Moreover, absent assur-
ances of effective influence, such promotion seems an unlikely result.
And it would be especially unlikely if inequalities in effectiveness corre-
sponded to underlying social or economic inequalities in the society.33
In making this instrumental case, I may appear to be shifting to a bar-
gaining conception of politics, with assurances of equal power working to
ensure a political equilibrium with fair outcomes. But that gets the in-
strumental rationale and the mechanism wrong. The idea instead is that
ensuring that all citizens have effective political rights serves as a re-
minder that citizens are to be treated as equals in political deliberation
and, by reducing inequalities of power, reduces the incentives to shift
from deliberative politics to a politics of bargaining.
A second consideration is that many of the conventional, historical jus-
tifications for exclusions from or inequalities of political rights—justifica-
tions based on race and gender, for example—will not provide accept-
able reasons in public deliberation. This consideration will not exclude
all reasons for inequality—for example, if votes are of unequal weight be-
cause the political system relies, as in the case of the U.S. Senate, on a
32. Thus Beitz’s account of political equality connects the interests in recognition and equi-
table treatment with assurances of equally weighted votes and fair access. What he calls the
“deliberative interest,” by contrast, simply requires well-conducted political debate. See Politi-
cal Equality (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1989).
33. See the discussion of the interest in equitable treatment in Beitz, Political Equality, 110–
114. This interest plays an important role in the apportionment cases decided by the Supreme
Court in the early 1960s. “No right is more precious in a free country than that of having a
voice in the election of those who make the laws under which, as good citizens, we must live.
Other rights, even the most basic, are illusory if the right to vote is undermined.” Wesberry v.
Sanders, 376 U.S. 1 (1964), cited in Reynolds v. Sims, 377 U.S. 533, 558 (1964). Or again: “Espe-
cially since the right to exercise the franchise in a free and unimpaired manner is preservative
of other basic civil and political rights, any alleged infringement of the right of citizens to vote
must be carefully and meticulously scrutinized.” Reynolds v. Sims, 562.
171
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
Realizing Democracy
The deliberative conception of democracy captures the role of “undemo-
cratic” as a term of criticism applying to results as well as processes: it
provides common roots for the “by the people” and “for the people” as-
pects of the ideal of democracy. But this incorporation of important sub-
stantive requirements into the conception of democracy gives rise to a
problem of its own. The concern is that if we offer an interpretation of
democracy that treats all good things as ingredient in the idea of democ-
racy—requirements of political equality, considerations of common
good, and liberties of the moderns—then we may appear to integrate pro-
cedural and substantive values at the cost of practical guidance. What are
we to do when the many elements of deliberative democracy come into
conflict? Common foundations in deliberative democracy do not pro-
vide any insurance against conflict in practice. For example, the liberties
mandated by the requirement of deliberative inclusion may conflict with
the equal political liberties that fall under the requirement of participa-
tion. Why does it help to have all these elements ingredient within the
ideal of democracy, given conflicts among them?
172
P R O C E D U R E A N D S U B S T A N C E
34. This may seem puzzling. Making the safe assumption that incumbents have advantages
in raising funds, it might seem clear that challengers would fare better under a system of spend-
ing restrictions. But, according to one influential line of argument, background incumbency
advantages make challengers more dependent on money. Thus a challenger is better off run-
ning with $300,000 against an incumbent with $500,000 than running with $250,000 against
an incumbent with $250,000. See Gary Jacobson, “Enough Is Too Much: Money and Compe-
tition in House Elections,” in Kay Lehman Schlozman, ed., Elections in America (Boston: Al-
len and Unwin, 1987), 173–195. For criticisms of Jacobson’s view, see Donald Philip Green and
Jonathan S. Krasno, “Salvation for the Spendthrift Incumbent: Reestimating the Effects of
Campaign Spending in House Elections,” American Journal of Political Science 32, 4 (Novem-
ber 1988): 884–907.
35. I say a “regime” of unrestricted expenditures because the choice among systems of
financing is a choice among alternative schemes of permissions and restrictions, not a choice
between regulation and nonregulation.
173
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
174
P R O C E D U R E A N D S U B S T A N C E
175
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
45. This section of the essay draws on Joshua Cohen and Joel Rogers, “Solidarity, Democ-
racy, Association,” in Wolfgang Streeck, ed., Staat und Verbaende, special issue of Politischen
Vierteljahresschrift (Wiesbaden: Westdeutscher Verlag, 1994), 136–159.
176
P R O C E D U R E A N D S U B S T A N C E
46. This concern emerges naturally from criticisms of modern pluralism. See, for example,
Theodore Lowi, The End of Liberalism: The Second Republic of the United States, 2d ed. (New
York: Norton, 1979). For discussion of associative democracy as a response to the problem of
faction, see Joshua Cohen and Joel Rogers, “Secondary Associations in Democratic Gover-
nance,” Politics and Society 20, 4 (December 1992): 393–472.
47. Or it can set them only in very abstract terms, for example, as requirements of “reason-
ableness” or “due care.”
177
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
178
P R O C E D U R E A N D S U B S T A N C E
49. Though to the extent that they receive public support, they are to be subject to constitu-
tional constraints, in particular to guarantees of equal protection.
50. This claim depends, of course, on the background assumption of a democratic state pro-
tecting basic liberties and ensuring equal protection.
179
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
Conclusion
The fact of reasonable pluralism does not, I have argued, mandate a pro-
cedural account of democracy and collective choice. Conjoined with a
deliberative conception of justification, it is compatible with a substan-
tive account of democracy whose substance—captured in principles of
deliberative inclusion, the common good, and participation—includes
values of equality and liberty. Moreover, such a deliberative conception
offers an attractive rendering of the idea of collective choice, tying that
idea to a view of political community. Finally, we are not without re-
sources for addressing possible tensions between and among the values
of liberty, equality, and community built into the deliberative concep-
tion. But whether those resources are exploited is, of course, a matter of
politics.
180
6
D I R E C T LY D E L I B E R AT I V E P O LYA R C H Y
1. Introduction
In this essay we defend a form of democracy that we will call “directly de-
liberative polyarchy.” We argue that it is an attractive kind of radical,
participatory democracy with problem-solving capacities useful under
current conditions and unavailable to representative systems. In directly
deliberative polyarchy, collective decisions are made through public de-
liberation in arenas open to citizens who use public services or who are
otherwise regulated by public decisions. But in deciding, those citizens
must examine their own choices in the light of the relevant delibera-
tions and experiences of others facing similar problems in comparable
jurisdictions or subdivisions of government. Ideally, then, directly delib-
erative polyarchy combines the advantages of local learning and self-
government with the advantages (and discipline) of wider social learning
and heightened political accountability that result when the outcomes of
many concurrent experiments are pooled to permit public scrutiny of the
effectiveness of strategies and leaders.
One starting point for our argument is a commonplace of contempo-
rary political debate: that current economic and political institutions are
not solving problems they are supposed to solve, in areas of employment,
economic growth, income security, education, training, environmental
regulation, poverty, housing, social service delivery, or even basic per-
sonal safety. A second point of departure is the intrinsic appeal of collec-
We presented earlier versions of this essay at the University of Lausanne, the European Uni-
versity Institute, and the University of Chicago. We thank participants for instructive com-
ments. We also wish to thank Frank Michelman, Norman Daniels, Michael Dorf, Mark
Barenberg, and Sam Bowles for helpful criticisms and suggestions.
181
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
1. For background on diagnosis and remedies, see Joshua Cohen and Joel Rogers, Associa-
tions and Democracy (London: Verso, 1995), especially the concluding chapter; Joshua Cohen,
“Procedure and Substance in Deliberative Democracy,” Seyla Benhabib, ed., Democracy and
Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
1996), 95–119 [reprinted as essay 5 of this volume]; and Charles Sabel, “Learning by Moni-
toring: The Institutions of Economic Development,” in Neil Smelser and Richard Swedberg,
eds., Handbook of Economic Sociology (New York and Princeton: Russell Sage and Princeton
University Press, 1995). For a companion essay on the constitutional and institutional implica-
tions of directly deliberative polyarchy, see Michael Dorf and Charles Sabel, “A Constitution
of Democratic Experimentalism,” Columbia Law Review 98, 2 (1998): 267–473.
182
D I R E C T L Y D E L I B E R A T I V E P O L Y A R C H Y
2. See Friedrich Hayek, The Constitution of Liberty (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1960); James Buchanan, The Limits of Liberty (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1975);
Antonin Scalia, “The Rule of Law Is a Law of Rules,” University of Chicago Law Review 56, 4
(Fall 1989): 1175–1188; William Riker, Liberalism Against Populism (San Francisco: Freeman,
1982); William Riker and Barry Weingast, “Constitutional Regulation of Legislative Choice:
The Political Consequences of Judicial Deference to Legislatures,” Virginia Law Review 72, 2
(1988): 373–401.
3. See Robert Kuttner, Everything for Sale: The Virtues and Limits of Markets (New York:
Knopf, 1997).
4. See Robert Putnam, Democracy and the Civic Community: Tradition and Change in
an Italian Experiment (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1992); idem, “Bowling Alone:
Democracy in America at the End of the Twentieth Century,” Journal of Democracy 1 (1995):
35–50. Michael Sandel’s remarks on a new public philosophy mix the sociological anxiety
characteristic of much communitarianism with the concerns about the political economy of
citizenship that are closer to our own focus on new arrangements of democratic governance:
see Michael Sandel, Democracy’s Discontent: America in Search of a Public Philosophy (Cam-
bridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1995), 324–328.
183
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
184
D I R E C T L Y D E L I B E R A T I V E P O L Y A R C H Y
and that may include public research, technical assistance, or training fa-
cilities as well.6
These new arrangements suggest troubles for the standard categories of
analysis and remedy. The arrangements are not conventionally public
because, in solving problems, they operate autonomously from the dic-
tates of legislatures or public agencies; they are not conventionally pri-
vate in that they do exercise problem-solving powers and their gover-
nance works through discussion among citizens rather than assignment
of ownership rights. At the same time, they do not presuppose a success-
ful, densely organized, trust-inspiring network of associations. Indeed,
they often emerge precisely against a background of associative distress.
Nor are these new arrangements mere intellectual curiosities. They are
attractive because they appear to foster two fundamental democratic val-
ues—deliberation and direct citizen participation—while potentially of-
fering advantages as problem-solvers that programs conceived within the
limits of conventional representative democracies do not. Indeed, if the
same properties made them both democratically and pragmatically at-
tractive, we would have a compelling case for the novel form of public
governance that we call directly deliberative polyarchy.
Because these new governance arrangements resonate so strongly with
the (often implicit) programmatic suggestions associated with radical
democratic criticisms of the modern state, a straightforward and appeal-
ing generalization of them seems at hand. Congenitally hostile to the
market inequalities and economic subordination, but always suspicious
of an overweening state as the best defense against them, radical democ-
racy emphasized the deficiencies of centralized power, the virtues of de-
centralization, the expressive and instrumental values of participation,
and the values of citizen discussion both as an intrinsically attractive form
of politics and as a good method of problem-solving.7
But evoking the core features of the radical democratic tradition—its
emphasis on direct participation and deliberation—immediately suggests
three lines of criticism. First, that in a large-scale political system, wide-
6. For discussion, see Charles Sabel, Local Development in Ireland: Partnership, Innovation,
and Social Justice (OECD, 1996); idem, “Milwaukee Jobs Initiative Consortia Employment
Project Description,” (unpublished, on file with author, 1996).
7. See, for example, Hannah Arendt, On Revolution (New York: Penguin, 1973); Jürgen
Habermas, Between Facts and Norms, trans. William Rehg (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press,
1996); we discuss our differences with Habermas and Arendt in section 5.
185
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
186
D I R E C T L Y D E L I B E R A T I V E P O L Y A R C H Y
187
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
188
D I R E C T L Y D E L I B E R A T I V E P O L Y A R C H Y
12. A common rationale for democracy is that it treats people as equals by giving equal con-
sideration to their interests. Dahl, Democracy and Its Critics; Thomas Christiano, The Rule of
the Many (Denver: Westview, 1996). We avoid this rationale because the idea of equal consid-
eration of interests is normatively implausible in as much as it may conflict with the equal con-
sideration owed to persons.
13. Rousseau, Social Contract, trans. Victor Gourevitch (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1997), Book 3, chap. 14.
14. In the case of the U.S. Senate, for example, votes are of unequal weight because the po-
litical system relies on a scheme of territorial representation in which districts (in this case
states) correspond to political subdivisions: in this case, the inequality seems less objectionable
because it can be provided with a rationale that does not offend against the requirement of
treating members as equals.
189
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
fined by the ends and projects with which they identify. Thus, democra-
cies provide mechanisms for regular, popular authorization of exercises
of public power: in a representative democracy that means (at a mini-
mum) regular elections of legislators; in a direct democracy it means reg-
ular opportunities to review past decisions and evaluate the performance
of officials responsible for implementing those decisions. Such regular
renewal serves to make the exercise of collective power accountable to
the governed in the formal sense that the governed can impose sanctions
of removal from office on government. More fundamentally, an account-
able system for the exercise of collective power, in which citizens are
treated as equals, arguably helps ensure peaceful transitions of power, re-
strain the exercise of power by protecting majorities from minority rule,
avoid at least some egregious violations of minority rights, and foster
greater responsiveness of government to the governed.15
Both arguments—intrinsic and instrumental—are strengthened when
we consider, third, the educative aspects of democracy. Thus, by estab-
lishing the position of equal citizen, with associated entitlements to
participate in determining the terms of association, democratic arrange-
ments not only respect but also provide instruction in fundamental polit-
ical values—in particular, the value of equality itself and the conception
of citizens as free and equal. By participating, citizens acquire political
ideas in the light of which democracy itself is justified. Furthermore,
by opening debate to all and addressing problems through public dis-
cussion—rather than through market exchange or bureaucratic com-
mand—democracy not only assumes adequate information but also
helps ensure it. Democracy provides a way to pool dispersed information
relevant to problem-solving and to explore the range of possible solu-
tions to practical problems: in short, a framework for collective learning.
As Rawls puts it, within a democracy: “Discussion is a way of combin-
ing information and enlarging the range of arguments. At least in the
15. Such instrumental considerations played an important role in the U.S. Supreme Court’s
classic apportionment decisions, which urged that the same instrumental reasons that support
universal political rights also support equally weighted votes. Thus, in Wesberry v. Sanders: “No
right is more precious in a free country than that of having a voice in the election of those who
make the laws under which, as good citizens, we must live. Other rights, even the most basic,
are illusory if the right to vote is undermined.” Cited in Reynolds v. Sims, 377 U.S. 533, 558. Or
in Reynolds v. Sims itself: “Especially since the right to exercise the franchise in a free and
unimpaired manner is preservative of other basic civil and political rights, any alleged infringe-
ment of the right of citizens to vote must be carefully and meticulously scrutinized.” Reynolds,
562.
190
D I R E C T L Y D E L I B E R A T I V E P O L Y A R C H Y
t wo dimensions of de moc ra c y
We said that political institutions are democratic just in case they link the
authorization to exercise public power—and that exercise itself—to col-
lective decisions of citizens, understood as free and equal. There are, of
course, very different ways to interpret this abstract ideal of democracy,
corresponding to different interpretations of the notions of collective and
authorization.
Democratic collective decision-making can be either aggregative or
deliberative, depending on how we interpret the requirement that collec-
tive decisions treat citizens as equals. Understood aggregatively, a demo-
cratic decision is collective just in case the procedure gives equal consid-
eration to the interests of each person: it treats people as equals by giving
their interests equal weight in making a binding decision. Conventional
rationales for majority-rule as a method of collective decision rest on the
idea that it gives direct expression to this requirement of equal consider-
ation.17
Understood deliberatively, democratic decisions are collective just in
case they proceed on the basis of free public reasoning among equals: in-
terests unsupported by considerations that convince others carry no
weight. Put otherwise, in deliberative decision-making, decisions are to
be supported by reasons acceptable to others in the polity of decision-
makers; the mere fact that decisions are supported by a majority of citi-
zens, deciding on the basis of their interests, does not suffice to show that
the decisions are democratically authorized. On the deliberative inter-
pretation, then, democracy is a framework of social and institutional con-
ditions that both facilitates free discussion among equal citizens by pro-
viding favorable conditions for expression, association, and discussion
and ties the authorization to exercise public power—and the exercise it-
self—to such discussion, by establishing a framework ensuring the re-
sponsiveness and accountability of political power to it.
To be sure, discussion may not—and often does not—issue in agree-
ment. So even in a deliberative democracy, collective decisions must of-
16. John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), 359.
17. According to an epistemic conception of majority rule, the rationale is that decisions
supported by a majority are more likely to be right, not simply that the process visibly assigns
equal weight to the interests of each.
191
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
ten be made through voting, under some form of majority rule. But it
may be argued that if collective decision-making concludes in a vote,
then participants—anticipating that final stage—will not have any incen-
tive to deliberate earlier on and instead will simply seek allies for their
position. Though we cannot resolve the issue here, this outcome hardly
seems necessary. Even if all parties know that, at the end of the day, heads
may be counted, they still may accept the importance of finding consid-
erations that others acknowledge as reasons: they only need accept that
something other than a resolution that advances their antecedent inter-
ests matters to them. They may, for example, believe that reason-giving is
an important expression of respect or that deliberation sometimes yields
solutions that could not have been achieved if discussion were purely
strategic. If they do, they will be willing to deliberate in the stages leading
up to the vote. In short, the objection supposes that, once voting is in
prospect, interaction must turn strategic. But this view is no more plausi-
ble than the claim that moral advantages and possible mutual gains from
deliberation eliminate all strategic maneuvering.
As to authorization to make collective decisions, we have again two dis-
tinct understandings: in representative democracy, popular authorization
proceeds through a choice by citizens of representatives who decide on
content of public decisions. Citizens vote as individuals for persons who
will participate in making binding collective choices in an aggregative or
a deliberative legislature. In direct democracy, citizens authorize public
action by deciding on the substance of public policy. Again, those direct
decisions can be made either aggregatively, as some argue is true in refer-
enda, because of their yes/no structure,18 or deliberatively, as in an ideal-
ized town meeting, in which decisions on policy take place after debate
on the merits. The essential distinction between direct and representative
is not the level of participation but the topic on the agenda: direct de-
mocracy requires decisions on substance, whereas representative democ-
racy involves choices on legislators, who decide on substance.19
18. See Max Weber, “Parliament and Government in a Reconstructed Germany,” in Econ-
omy and Society, vol. 3, ed. Guenther Roth and Claus Wittich (New York: Bedminster, 1968),
p. 1455; Derek Bell, “The Referendum: Democracy’s Barrier to Racial Equality,” Washington
Law Review 54, 1 (1978): 1–29; Yannis Papadopolous, “A Framework for Analysis of Functions
and Dysfunctions of Direct Democracy: Top-Down and Bottom-Up Perspectives,” Politics and
Society 23, 4 (1995): 421–448.
19. Complexities arise when we think of systems with strong parties with well-defined policy
positions and ways of disciplining members who depart from those positions. Such systems
have a direct aspect. But we abstract from these subtleties here.
192
D I R E C T L Y D E L I B E R A T I V E P O L Y A R C H Y
193
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
vested in a body that all citizens may attend. In the case of the Athenian
ecclesia, that often meant meetings of five thousand (with women and
slaves excluded from participation). In the polis, the unit of collective
decision-making was small, and the members were homogeneous in gen-
eral outlook and sufficiently disconnected from banausic activities (be-
cause sufficiently secure in their social and economic positions) to de-
vote their passions and energies to common affairs. If the combination of
directness and deliberativeness can be achieved only under these condi-
tions, then the conventional criticisms of radical democracy are individu-
ally damaging and collectively overwhelming.
To vindicate the virtues of deliberativeness and directness, then, we
must distinguish these values themselves from familiar ways of institu-
tionalizing them—for example, citizen assemblies, or such modern anal-
ogies as workers’ councils or economic parliaments—and then describe a
modern set of arrangements of collective decision-making suited to these
values and to modern conditions of scale and heterogeneity. To guide
this elaboration of a workable direct and deliberative alternative to assem-
bly democracy, we need first to establish criteria for “workable” demo-
cratic solutions by characterizing the problems democracies now face
and the limits of representative, aggregative arrangements in addressing
them.
the problems of modern democracy arise quite apart from the clash of
antagonistic interests or any guileful exploitation by individuals of block-
ages created by constitutional arrangements: they are (in the game-theo-
retic sense) problems of failed coordination, in which mutual gains are
available but different parties are unable to come to terms in a way that
captures those gains. If the right arrangements of collective choice were
in place, the parties could come to terms on one of the available alterna-
tives. In contrast, recognition of the mismatch between solutions and
available structures of decision-making leads, by itself, to paralysis, as it
reasonably suggests that it is better to do nothing than to do something
that will almost certainly fail.
Put another way, we assume that for some substantial range of current
problems, citizens agree sufficiently about the urgency of the problems
and the broad desiderata on solutions that, had they the means to trans-
late this general agreement into a more concrete, practical program,
would improve their common situation and would possibly result in the
discovery of further arenas of cooperation. This is not to make the fool-
ish claim that everyone endorses the same ranking of solutions, only that
everyone prefers a wide range of alternatives to the status quo. No sur-
prise, then, that the new problem-solving institutions have begun to
emerge just in those areas—public safety, public education, economic
restructuring—where established institutions have most conspicuously
broken down and the problems are agreed to be urgent. For breakdown
opens space for new initiatives, and where, as we are assuming, actors are
urgently motivated to look for a solution and prefer many alternatives to
the status quo, that space is likely to be occupied.
But even in thus qualifying the extent of agreement, we may still be ac-
cused of an extravagant confidence in consensus. In its stronger form,
this accusation rejects the idea of deliberative problem-solving altogether
by criticizing the assumptions about consensus on which it depends. It
asserts that the fundamental problem of politics is the pervasiveness of
deep disagreement, the consequent fragility of political order, and the
immanence of its disintegration into violence. So any assumptions about
agreement—and not simply the set just noted—miss the point.21 The
criticism is right in recognizing disastrous possibilities but wrong in the
21. See, for example, Carl Schmitt, The Concept of the Political (Chicago: University of Chi-
cago Press, 1995); Adam Przeworski, “Minimalist Conception of Democracy: A Defense,” in
Democracy’s Value, ed. Ian Shapiro and Casiano Hacker-Cordón (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1999), 23–55.
195
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
22. On the idea of consolidation, see Alfred Stepan and Juan Linz, “Toward Consolidated
Democracies,” Journal of Democracy 7, 2 (1996): 14–33. For doubts about the importance of
consolidation, see Adam Przeworski, “What Makes Democracies Endure?,” Journal of Democ-
racy 7, 1 (1996): 39–55. But note that Przeworski and others do not consider the importance of
consolidation, as characterized in the text.
196
D I R E C T L Y D E L I B E R A T I V E P O L Y A R C H Y
allow the powerful to favor themselves by writing laws that accord them
benefits directly? It might be thought, too, to imply a requirement of
precision or a lack of ambiguity in those regulations. For why prevent
directly self-serving regulations, but then permit indirect self-service
through exploiting vagueness at the stage of interpretation and applica-
tion of laws?
Other, related devices of constitutional democracy have the same ef-
fects. Thus, a basic institutional expression of the requirement of the rule
of law—in particular, of the ban on self-serving interpretation—is the
separation of powers, understood as the requirement that rule-making au-
thority be vested in a body that includes representatives of diverse partic-
ular interests but that does not itself apply the rules it makes to individual
cases. The conventional rationale for this separation of rule-making and
rule-applying is that it permits diverse interests to be incorporated into
rules, even as it decreases incentives for rule-makers to design rules that
favor themselves (either as representatives or as officials). But in obstruct-
ing corruption, the separation of powers so understood reinforces the
substantive uniformity requirement and thereby tightens the constraint
on tailoring solutions to special circumstances.
Hence a familiar and inconclusive tug of war: when problems need to
be solved, pressure mounts to violate the constitutional constraints of the
rule of law and the separation of powers—to overturn the Tudor polity—
precisely because of the restrictions these impose on problem-solving.
Then, as the dangers of violations mount, as politics threatens to de-
generate into a patchwork of particularistic deals and local privileges, as
constitutional democracy approximates pre-Tudor feudalism—pressure
mounts to reimpose a system of strict rules. Thus, in the United States,
the standard criticism leveled against administrative agencies—created
precisely to adopt law to particular circumstances—is that they pave the
road back to serfdom. And standard proposals for reform—ranging from
Lowi’s juridical democracy and Sunstein’s post-New Deal constitu-
tionalism to Hayek’s neo-liberal constitutionalism—would redeploy rule-
making authority to legislatures in order to ensure such substantive uni-
formity, thus reimposing the very constraints that had prompted earlier
constitutional reform.23
This to and fro cannot be resolved simply by cutting the Gordian
23. For discussion of these three views, see Cohen and Rogers, Associations and Democracy.
197
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
198
D I R E C T L Y D E L I B E R A T I V E P O L Y A R C H Y
Deliberative Process Within and Among Units. At the heart of the delib-
erative conception of democracy is the view that collective decision-mak-
ing is to proceed deliberatively—by citizens advancing proposals and de-
fending them with considerations that others, who are themselves free
and equal, can acknowledge as reasons. The shared commitment of citi-
zens in a deliberative democracy is that the exercise of collective power
should be confined to cases in which such justification is presented. Citi-
zens contemplating the exercise of collective power owe one another rea-
sons and owe attention to one another’s reasons.
But not all reasons are on a par. So the kind of attention owed must be
calibrated to the kind of consideration offered. Thus, constitutional rea-
sons are considerations that command substantial weight in decision-
making. In deciding which considerations are to be assigned such
weight, we look for a close connection to the standing of citizens as free
and equal members of the political society: considerations affirming that
201
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
standing have substantial weight, whereas those that deny it are weight-
less. Thus, citizens must have fundamental political and civil rights be-
cause those rights are backed by reasons that affirm the standing of citi-
zens as free and equal, whereas the denial of those rights requires appeal
to considerations that throw such standing into question perhaps by de-
nying that members meet all the qualifications for citizenship. But deni-
als of qualification—assertions that some member is not to be regarded as
a free and equal citizen—do not count as reasons at all because they are
not considerations that command respect from those whose standing is
denied. So effective participation rights cannot, except perhaps in very
special circumstances (perhaps cases of extreme emergency), permissibly
be denied. Similarly, proposals backed by reasons rooted in interests fun-
damental to the standing of members as free and equal can be rejected
only upon offering alternative, more plausible projects for advancing
those interests. Thus, a requirement of ensuring a basic educational
threshold—a threshold defined relative to participation as a citizen, and
more generally, as a cooperating member of society—would be a consti-
tutional reason, and a proposal that would ensure such a threshold would
be rejected in a well-ordered deliberative body only in favor of an alterna-
tive, better designed scheme.25
The first and most fundamental requirement of a directly deliberative
polyarchy is, therefore, that it affirm its character as democratically delib-
erative by giving stringent protection to claims backed by constitutional
reasons.
Of course, not all acceptable reasons for public choices are of constitu-
tional magnitude. The class of policy reasons comprises those consider-
ations whose endorsement is neither required by nor incompatible with
a conception of citizens as free and equal and which are relevant to an
issue under consideration. A proposal framed by such considerations
may reasonably be rejected by a counter-argument that articulates an al-
ternative balancing of the reasons generally understood as relevant to al-
locating the resource in question. Consider again the case of education.
In deciding how to allocate resources, some relevant and potentially
25. Amy Gutmann argues for a democratic threshold principle in her account of the distri-
bution of primary schooling in Democratic Education (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
1987), 136ff. But she confines the threshold to “effective participation in the democratic pro-
cess”—as though there were not an equally good claim to effective participation in labor mar-
kets.
202
D I R E C T L Y D E L I B E R A T I V E P O L Y A R C H Y
competing policy reasons are: helping each student to fully achieve po-
tential; ensuring that students who are performing least well are given
special attention; ensuring common educational experience for students
of diverse backgrounds. In the case of health care, the reasons include:
helping those who are worst off; helping those who would benefit most
from medical resources; assisting larger numbers of people; ensuring that
people have fair chances at receiving help, regardless of the urgency of
their situation and of expected benefits from treatment.26
As these examples suggest, the policy reasons relevant to particular do-
mains are complex and varied, and there often will be no clear, princi-
pled basis for ranking them: different, equally reasonable participants in
deliberative process (and, a fortiori, different deliberative bodies) will
weigh them differently. Reasonable people and reasonable collective de-
cision-makers reasonably disagree and recognize the results of a delibera-
tive process in which such reasons are aired as legitimate.
This distinction between constitutional and policy reasons brings us to
the second broad condition, a requirement of substantive due process on
the operation of directly deliberative polyarchy: the process is to give due
consideration to reasons of both types, suitably weighted (and allowing
for reasonable differences of weight).
Moreover, we require, third, that this consideration be explicit. It is
not sufficient to require that outcomes be rationalizable—that the delib-
erative process issues in decisions for which appropriate reasons could
be cited—and to leave it to another institution, say, a court, to deter-
mine whether that condition is met. Outcomes in directly deliberative
polyarchy are to be arrived at through discussion in which reasons of the
appropriate kind are given by participants. Five considerations lead to
this conclusion:
1. Though deliberative justifiability itself is important, it must be aimed
at being achieved; that is, it will not in general be true that results
achieved through a process of exchange or bargaining, or outcomes that
reflect a balance of power, will be defensible by reasons of an appropriate
kind. So requiring actual deliberation helps establish a presumption that
results can be defended through reasons, and thus a presumption that the
outcomes of collective decision-making are legitimate.
26. See Norman Daniels and James Sabin, “Limits to Health Care: Fair Procedures, Demo-
cratic Deliberation, and the Legitimacy Problem for Insurers,” Philosophy and Public Affairs
26, 4 (1997): 303–350.
203
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
27. See Iris Young, “Communication and the Other: Beyond Deliberative Democracy,” in
Benhabib, ed., Democracy and Difference, 120–135; Sidney Verba, Kay Lehman Schlozman,
Henry E. Brady, Voice and Equality: Civic Voluntarism and American Politics (Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press, 1995), 500–508.
204
D I R E C T L Y D E L I B E R A T I V E P O L Y A R C H Y
ular discursive style, with all the conventional indicia of the rational: for-
mal, deductive, and unemotional. By insisting on abstraction from the
personal and particular, deliberation excludes both people and informa-
tion. People, because it silences citizens whose discursive style is de-
tailed, narrative, and passionate; information, because it invites only con-
tributions cast in general terms. As a result, deliberation is unfair and
ineffective. Urging more of it is a reform strategy, but not an especially in-
viting one.
This objection makes two assumptions, both unwarranted. First, that
requiring an explicit statement of reasons implies that nothing other than
reasons can be stated—as though a conception of deliberative justifica-
tion supported a ban on undeliberative humor. Second, that the canoni-
cal form of deliberation is the justification of a regulation from first prin-
ciples: the argument for progressivity in the tax system on grounds of a
conception of political fairness. Deliberation may take this form, but
nothing in the concept of reason-giving requires that it do so. Nor, more
immediately, is the reason-giving that occupies us here naturally ex-
pressed in the form of deductions from general political axioms. On the
contrary, deliberative problem-solving is by its nature focused on address-
ing specific problems in local settings. Giving reasons under these condi-
tions is, generally speaking, a matter of offering considerations recog-
nized by others as pertinent to solving the problem at hand. It is simply
impossible to limit in advance the kinds of considerations that might be
relevant or the form in which those considerations are to be stated. In-
deed, deliberation will characteristically involve debating the implications
of general principles (standard operating procedures, rules of thumb) in
the light of the particulars of local experience and inviting discussion
of such experience in whatever terms suit participants—including the
ironic “yeah, yeah” that condemns the latest implausible suggestion.
Still, it might be said that requirements of deliberation unfairly bias de-
cision-making in favor of the verbal, that we may end up with a pluralis-
tic logocracy, in which the many forms of verbosity are all on display, but
the shy, the quiet, and the reserved are left out. We agree that there is a
difficulty here, but why isn’t it remediable? In settings of deliberative
problem-solving, everyone has something to contribute, so the first task
in improving the operation of deliberative arrangements is to ensure that
all participants understand that and are encouraged to contribute. The
potential for deliberative failure is no argument against efforts at such im-
provement.
205
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
28. Susan Sturm, “A Normative Theory of Public Law Remedies,” Georgetown Law Journal
79, 5 (1991): 1357–1446. Also, Rebecca Abers discusses the requirement that citizen-budgeters
incorporate considerations of fair distribution in the deliberations in the Porto Alegre system:
“Learning from Democratic Practice,” in Cities for Citizens: Planning and the Rise of Civil So-
ciety in a Global Age, ed. Mike Douglass and John Friedmann (Chichester: John Wiley, 1998),
39–65.
207
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
29. Bargaining and command are ways of making collective decisions without mutual rea-
son-giving; confession is the practice of giving reasons to others for individual decisions.
30. The paragraph that follows presents an account of public goods suited to the special set-
ting of a conception of deliberative democracy.
208
D I R E C T L Y D E L I B E R A T I V E P O L Y A R C H Y
ers and about which it is relatively easy (either for consumers or for a cen-
tralized monitor) to acquire accurate information. Assume, then, that the
good is best supplied by a restricted range of providers, and that there are
high costs to switching among those providers: there can, then, be no
presumption of voluntarism in the choice of provider. Add, now, that in-
formation about the good is difficult to acquire or summarize because a
large number of dimensions are important to its evaluation, people dis-
agree about the relevant dimensions and their relative weights, and the
conditions of its production and allocation are volatile. Under these con-
ditions, we want goods to be provided through mechanisms in which de-
cisions are backed by reasons and based on pooled information. In short,
we have reason to favor directly deliberative polyarchy over market.
ef f ect iv eness
Why expect that such problem-solving will have concrete benefits? How
might it be able to overcome the problems of limited information and
diversity of sites that vex state action? Five considerations are important.
First, the parties to the discussion are presumed to have relevant local
knowledge; moreover, they can put that information to good use because
they understand the terrain better and have a more immediate stake in
the solution.
Second, assuming a shared concern to address a problem, and an ex-
pectation that the results of deliberation will regulate subsequent action,
the participants would tend to be more other-regarding in their politi-
cal practice than they would otherwise tend to be. The structure of dis-
cussion—the requirement of finding a solution that others can agree to
rather than pressuring the state for a solution—would push the debate
in directions that respect and advance more general interests. Other-
regardingness would encourage a more complete revelation of private in-
formation. And this information would permit sharper definition of prob-
lems and solutions.
Third, pursuing discussion in the context of enduring differences among
participants would incline parties to be more reflective in their definition
of problems and proposed strategies for solution; it would tend to free dis-
cussion from the preconceptions that commonly limit the consideration
of options within more narrowly defined groups, thus enabling a more
complete definition and imaginative exploration of problems and solu-
tions. The same is true for the federalism of problem-solvers that emerges
from requirements of discussion across units—here, too, comparisons of
solutions at different sites, and benchmarking of local solutions by refer-
ence to practice elsewhere, suggest a basis for improving local practice.
Here, notice that directly deliberative polyarchy—understood as a
form of problem-solving—is not thwarted by, but instead benefits from,
heterogeneity of participants. Of course, the participants must—as our
discussion of deliberation indicates—share a view about relevant rea-
sons. But this is, we think, a rather weak constraint that does not demand
substantial homogeneity—certainly not homogeneity of comprehensive
moral outlook.
210
D I R E C T L Y D E L I B E R A T I V E P O L Y A R C H Y
inst it ut ions
We conclude with a brief discussion of the implications of directly delib-
erative polyarchy for the design of and expectations on basic political in-
stitutions.
First, directly deliberative polyarchy is, as we have indicated, a form of
polyarchy. So we assume the continued presence of the legislatures,
courts, executives, and administrative agencies, controlled by officials
chosen through free and fair elections, in which virtually all adults have
rights to suffrage, office-holding, association, and expression, and face al-
ternative, legally protected sources of information.31 Though the opera-
tion of these institutions and arrangements changes, the institutions re-
main and continue to serve some of the political values with which they
are conventionally associated: peaceful transitions of power, restraints on
unbridled power, fair chances for effective influence over authoritative
collective decisions, opportunities to develop informed preferences, and
so forth.
But with the shift in the locus of problem-solving, the operations and
expectations of basic institutions change markedly.
Consider first the role of legislatures. Directly deliberative polyarchy is
animated by a recognition of the limits on the capacity of legislatures to
solve problems—either on their own or by delegating tasks to administra-
tive agencies—despite the importance of solutions. Rejecting the Neo-
Liberal Constitutionalist idea that the problems are essentially recalci-
trant to collective address, and the modern Civic Republican idea that
their address requires only a more vigilant exclusion of private interests
from national policy-making (and a correspondingly more acute inter-
vention by technically adept guardians of the common good), the legisla-
ture in a directly deliberative polyarchy takes on a new role: to empower
211
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
32. For related discussions of federalism, see Stephen Gardbaum, “Rethinking Constitu-
tional Federalism,” Texas Law Review 74 (1996): 795–838; and the account of the “comman-
deering problem” in Dorf and Sabel, “Constitution of Democratic Experimentalism.”
212
D I R E C T L Y D E L I B E R A T I V E P O L Y A R C H Y
214
D I R E C T L Y D E L I B E R A T I V E P O L Y A R C H Y
34. Habermas says that he has “no illusions about the problems that our situation poses and
the moods it invokes. But moods—and philosophies in a melancholic ‘mood’—do not justify
the defeatist surrender of the radical content of democratic ideals.” Between Facts and Norms,
xlii–xliii. We agree with the observation about moods and their unfortunate consequences,
but—as will emerge—think Habermas has surrendered too much.
217
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
218
D I R E C T L Y D E L I B E R A T I V E P O L Y A R C H Y
But the capacity of the public’s critical contributions to steer the state
must remain, given Habermas’s fundamental partition of human action,
an open question. The freer the communication within the public—the
greater the immunities from state interference with the formation of
opinion, the more accessible the newspapers, the less venal the televi-
sion, the richer the associational life on which public discussion rests—
the greater clarification it can attain. Indeed, the call for democratization
of the public sphere, which follows naturally from Habermas’s emphasis
on the role of communicative action in social integration, is exactly the
aspect of his general theory that classes it as a type of radical democracy.37
The basic dualism of understanding and success-oriented action, how-
ever, suggests as well that even the most radical extension of the public
sphere would be of limited consequence precisely because the technical
demands, to which administration, parliament, and party must in turn
respond, set limits—but which ones?—to the direction that might is-
sue from a more encompassing, unrestricted discussion among citizens:
“Communicative power cannot supply a substitute for the systematic in-
ner logic of public bureaucracies. Rather, it achieves an impact on this
logic ‘in a siege-like manner.’”38 At its most paradoxically self-defeating,
Habermas’s view seems to be that the democratic public cannot be just
and effective, because to be just, it must be informal in the sense of con-
stituted freedom of institutions, while to be effective, it must be institu-
tionalized in forms that constrain discussion and hinder the pursuit of
justice. In the end, radical democracy serves as a series of reminders—
that human communication need not be narrowly technical, that un-
solved problems remain outside the purview of conventional institu-
tions—rather than as a program to redirect the ensemble of institutions to
ensure a controlling role for communicative power.39
As a second illustration of the self-limitation of radical democracy, con-
sider the position of Hannah Arendt. Whereas Habermas sets his account
37. Ibid, 371. Though note the immediately subsequent discussion of the “self-limiting”
quality of radical-democratic practice—in particular, the need for a communicatively gener-
ated public opinion to work its effects through conventional political institutions.
38. Habermas, “Further Reflections on the Public Sphere,” in Craig Calhoun, ed.,
Habermas and the Public Sphere (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992), 452.
39. See especially Habermas’s striking discussion of the “surprisingly active and momentous
role” that actors in civil society can play in a “perceived crisis situation.” Between Facts and
Norms, 7, 380–382. This discussion suggests that Habermas is operating with a distinction be-
tween crisis situations, in which radical democratic impulses play a central role, and normal
politics, in which they do not. For an instructive comparison, see Bruce Ackerman, We, The
People: Foundations (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1991).
219
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
40. Hannah Arendt, The Human Condition (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1950),
177.
41. Ibid., 176.
42. Seyla Benhabib emphasizes that “appearing” is to be taken fully literally: “When Arendt
links the public space with the space of appearances she primarily has in mind a model of face-
to-face human interactions,” within a relatively homogeneous community whose shared ethos
makes the meaning of individual action more or less transparent. The Reluctant Modernism of
Hannah Arendt (New York: Sage, 1996), 201.
43. These remarks, made by Mary McCarthy at a conference on Arendt’s work, are reported
in ibid., 155; also see 156 for Arendt’s reply and a convincing assessment of its plausibility.
220
D I R E C T L Y D E L I B E R A T I V E P O L Y A R C H Y
221
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
222
7
DEMOCRACY AND LIBERTY
1. Main Ideas
The fundamental idea of democratic, political legitimacy is that the au-
thorization to exercise state power must arise from the collective decisions
of the equal members of a society who are governed by that power.1 That
is a very abstract statement of the concept of democracy—as abstract as it
should be. Democracy comes in many forms, and more determinate
conceptions of it depend on an account of membership in the people
and, correspondingly, what it takes for a decision to be collective—autho-
rized by citizens as a body.
Consider two conceptions of democracy, distinguished by their inter-
pretations of the fundamental idea of collective decision: I will call them
aggregative and deliberative. Both views apply in the first instance to insti-
tutions of binding collective decision making,2 and each interprets the
fundamental ideal that such institutions are to treat people bound by
I have presented parts of this essay to the Eastern Division Meetings of the American Philo-
sophical Association, the University of Chicago Workshop on Deliberative Democracy, the
Instituto Universitário de Pesquisas do Rio de Janeiro, the North Carolina Philosophy Collo-
quium, and a seminar with the Graduate Fellows in the Harvard Program in Ethics and the
Professions; in my Wesson Lectures entitled “Liberty, Equality, and Democracy” at Stanford
University, the University of Nebraska-Lincoln, and Princeton University; and as the Wade
Memorial Lecture at St. Louis University. I also discussed these issues in my Fall 1995 political
philosophy seminar at MIT. I am grateful for all the comments and suggestions I have received
and want especially to thank David Austen-Smith, Zairo Cheibub, Alasdair MacIntyre, Carole
Pateman, Adam Przeworski, John Rawls, Elisa Reis, Charles Sabel, T. M. Scanlon, Cass
Sunstein, Iris Marion Young, and Judith Jarvis Thomson. Some of the main ideas are pre-
sented in “Procedure and Substance in Deliberative Democracy,” in Seyla Benhabib, ed., De-
mocracy and Difference: Changing Boundaries of the Political (Princeton: Princeton University
Press, 1996), 95–119 [reprinted as essay 5 in this collection].
1. “Governed by” rather than “affected by.” Democracy is about justifying authority, not
about justifying influence. See Michael Walzer, Spheres of Justice (New York: Basic Books,
1983); Christopher McMahon, Authority and Democracy (Princeton: Princeton University
Press, 1995).
2. I am grateful to T. M. Scanlon for emphasizing the importance of this parallel.
223
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
224
D E M O C R A C Y A N D L I B E R T Y
2. Reasonable Pluralism
I begin with the fact of reasonable pluralism:6 the fact that there are dis-
tinct, incompatible philosophies of life to which reasonable people are
drawn under favorable conditions for the exercise of practical reason. By
a “philosophy of life”—what Rawls has called a “comprehensive doc-
4. Jürgen Habermas, “Further Reflections on the Public Sphere,” in Craig Calhoun, ed.,
Habermas and the Public Sphere (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992), 446.
5. Ibid., 452.
6. For discussion of this fact, see Joshua Cohen, “Moral Pluralism and Political Consensus,”
in David Copp, Jean Hampton, and John Roemer, eds., The Idea of Democracy (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1993), 270–291; John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Co-
lumbia University Press, 1996); and Joshua Cohen, “A More Democratic Liberalism,” Michi-
gan Law Review 92, 6 (May 1994): 1502–1546.
225
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
7. On the importance of moral diversity as a source of pressures toward relativism and nihil-
ism, see Gilbert Harman, “Moral Relativism,” in Gilbert Harman and Judith Jarvis Thomson,
Moral Relativism and Moral Objectivity (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1996), 8–14.
226
D E M O C R A C Y A N D L I B E R T Y
8. See Rawls’s discussion of the burdens of judgment in Political Liberalism, 54–58. Leif
Wenar argues that these burdens are not widely acknowledged, that, for example, “a religious
doctrine characteristically presents itself as universally accessible to clear minds and open
hearts,” and he cites the Vatican II statement on Divine Revelation in support. See Leif Wenar,
“Political Liberalism: An Internal Critique,” Ethics 106 (October 1995): 32–62. But to say that
certain religious truths require revelation is to acknowledge that they, unlike truths of natural
religion, are not simply available to clear minds and open hearts.
227
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
228
D E M O C R A C Y A N D L I B E R T Y
12. Consider, for example, the changes in the Catholic doctrine on toleration that emerge
in Vatican II. The idea of human dignity, always a central element in Catholic moral and so-
cial thought, is developed along new lines as the basis for an account of political legitimacy
with principled limits on the state’s authority in matters of religious faith and practice. See The
Revised Documents of Vatican II, “Declaration on Religious Freedom,” 1.2, ed. Austin Flannery
(Northport: Costello, 1976), 800–801. Dignity imposes an obligation to seek the truth and em-
brace it. But though the “one true religion subsists in the Catholic and apostolic Church,” the
pursuit and embrace of truth must comport with our nature as free beings “endowed with rea-
son” and the dignity owing to that nature. And this requires immunity from “external coercion”
as well as from “psychological freedom.” The introduction to the Declaration ties the force of
the sense of dignity and an understanding of its implications to modern experience (the “con-
sciousness of contemporary man”). In an interesting essay on modern Confucian humanism
and human rights, Tu Wei-ming suggests a way to reinterpret Confucian doctrine as incorpo-
rating a conception of dignity, tied to obligations in social relationships, that could serve in
turn as a basis for a conception of human rights. Here, too, the conception of dignity is tied to
central Confucian notions, but its formulation is prompted by modern political sensibilities, as
articulated through international institutions. See Tu Wei-ming, “A Confucian Perspective on
Human Rights,” unpublished, 1995.
229
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
13. For critical discussion of the idea of the “exclusive rights of truth,” see John Courtney
Murray, “The Problem of Religious Freedom,” in J. Leon Hooper, S.J., ed., Religious Liberty:
Catholic Struggles with Pluralism (Louisville: Westminster John Knox Press, 1993), ch. 2.
230
D E M O C R A C Y A N D L I B E R T Y
dence for the thesis that practical reason generates a more general moral
convergence among people working within different moral and religious
traditions; rather, they are important cases of agreement on political val-
ues among people who have fundamental moral disagreements.
Moreover, let us suppose that comprehensive agreement has impor-
tant virtues. Still, if the exercise of practical reason does not generate
convergence among people who begin with very different outlooks, asso-
ciated with different traditions of moral, religious, and philosophical
thought and practice, then how is comprehensive moral agreement to be
achieved? Perhaps through some form of common moral education in a
comprehensive view. But how is such education—as distinct from educa-
tion about requirements of civic responsibility and decency—to proceed
in the face of different and competing forms of moral thought, each with
its own associational life? Perhaps through the state’s coercive means. But
it is not so clear that the state can produce genuine moral agreement, as
opposed to public spectacles of conformity; and if it could, the price
seems unacceptable, despite the values associated with agreement.
I assume the fact of reasonable pluralism, then. And this fact gives
shape to the conception of citizens as free and equal that constitutes part
of the deliberative conception of democracy I want to explore here. To
say that citizens are free is to say, inter alia, that no comprehensive moral
or religious view provides a defining condition of membership or the
foundation of the authorization to exercise political power. Not that reli-
gious or moral views are, religiously, morally, or metaphysically speaking,
matters of choice. To someone who has a religious view, for example, be-
lieving the view is a matter of believing what is true, and acting on it, a
matter of fulfilling obligations that are not self-legislated and are perhaps
more fundamental than political obligations.14 But politically speaking,
citizens are free in that it is open to them to accept or reject such views
without loss of status. To say citizens are equal is to say that each is recog-
nized as having the capacities required for participating in discussion
aimed at authorizing the exercise of power.
What, more particularly then, can we say about a conception of de-
14. Michael McConnell says, “It would come as some surprise to a devout Jew to find that
he has ‘selected the day of the week in which to refrain from labor’ since the Jewish people
have been under the impression from some 3,000 years that this choice was made by God.”
“Religious Freedom at a Crossroads,” University of Chicago Law Review 59 (1992): 115. The
source of the quotation to which McConnell is responding is Estate of Thornton v. Caldor,
Inc., 472 U.S. 703, 711 (1985) (O’Connor, J., concurring).
231
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
3. Public Reasoning
A deliberative conception of democracy puts public reasoning at the cen-
ter of political justification. I say public reasoning rather than public dis-
cussion because a deliberative view cannot be distinguished simply by its
emphasis on discussion rather than bargaining or voting as methods of
collective decision making. On any view of democracy—indeed any
view of intelligent political decision making—discussion is important, if
only because of its essential role in pooling private information, against a
background of asymmetries in its distribution.
According to the deliberative interpretation of democracy, then, de-
mocracy is a system of social and political arrangements that institution-
ally ties the exercise of power to free reasoning among equals. This con-
ception of justification through public reasoning can be represented in
an idealized procedure of political deliberation, constructed to capture
the notions of free, equal, and reason that figure in the deliberative ideal.
The point of the idealized procedure is to provide a model characteriza-
tion of free reasoning among equals, which can, in turn, serve as a model
for arrangements of collective decision making—arrangements that es-
tablish a framework of free reasoning among equals. Using the model, we
can work out the content of the deliberative democratic ideal and its con-
232
D E M O C R A C Y A N D L I B E R T Y
233
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
16. Pope John Paul II, Evangelium Vitae (New York: Times Books, 1995), §§29, 62. For criti-
cal discussion of these claims and the argument based on them, see Judith Jarvis Thomson,
“Abortion,” Boston Review 20, 3 (Summer 1995): 11–15.
235
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
17. I say “arguably” because it might be said that reasons are essentially public and capable
of being shared. If that is right, then the fact stated in the text would not constitute a reason.
18. See Adam Przeworski, Democracy and the Market (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1991), 17.
236
D E M O C R A C Y A N D L I B E R T Y
19. Ibid.
237
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
238
D E M O C R A C Y A N D L I B E R T Y
21. For discussion, see Christine Korsgaard, “Skepticism about Practical Reason,” Journal of
Philosophy 83, 1 (January 1986): 5–25; Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other, ch. 1. For illumi-
nating criticism of instrumental rationality, see Robert Nozick, The Nature of Rationality
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993), ch. 5. Particularly important for purposes here
are the remarks on the symbolic utility of acting on principles.
22. Using Nozick’s terminology (see note 21), when I see that a proposal cannot be defended
with acceptable reasons, its symbolic utility declines. Assuming that symbolic utility is
motivationally important, the motivation for advancing the proposal declines.
23. I am not worrying here about distinctions between “desire” and “prefer,” in particular
that the latter is a polyadic relation.
239
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
24. On the distinction between primitive and induced preferences, and a case for the view
that deliberation-induced preference change is a matter of changes in induced preferences as a
result of new information, see John Ferejohn, “Must Preferences Be Respected in a Democ-
racy?,” in Copp, et al., eds., The Idea of Democracy, 236–237.
240
D E M O C R A C Y A N D L I B E R T Y
5. Religious Liberty
I have focused thus far on the structure of the deliberative view. I turn
now to its substance, in particular to the thesis that democracy—on the
deliberative interpretation of collective choice—must ensure religious,
expressive, and moral liberties. This proposal departs from conventional
understandings of the relationship between democracy and these liber-
ties. To illustrate that understanding, I want to present a familiar di-
lemma associated with the idea of democratic legitimacy.
On the one hand, the value of democracy seems too procedural to pro-
vide a basis for an account of legitimacy; some democratic collective
choices are too repulsive to be legitimate, however attractive the proce-
dures that generate them. On the other hand, the idea of democracy ap-
pears to be the authoritative, sovereign requirement of collective deci-
sions. That is because democracy appears to be the form of collective
choice mandated by the fundamental political idea that citizens are to be
treated as equals. Because the ideal of treating people as equals is so fun-
damental, and so intimately linked to democratic procedures of binding
collective decision making, democracy is naturally identified not simply
as one political value to be combined with others but also as the way we
must settle the ordering of other political values—the way to ensure
equal standing in settling the common environment. To put issues off
the democratic agenda appears, by contrast, to establish objectionable
spheres of privilege. Thus, Robert Dahl says:
It seems to me highly reasonable to argue that no interests
should be inviolable beyond those integral or essential to the
democratic process. . . . [O]utside this broad domain [which in-
cludes rights of political expression, participation, and associa-
tion] a democratic people could freely choose the policies its
members feel best; they could decide how best to balance free-
25. For suggestive discussion of the role nonstrategic reasons can play in constraining discus-
sion and in improving its effectiveness, see James Johnson, “Is Talk Really Cheap? Prompting
Conversation Between Critical Theory and Rational Choice,” American Political Science Re-
view 87, 1 (1993): 74–86.
241
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
dom and control, how best to settle conflicts between the inter-
ests of some and the interests of others, how best to organize
and control their economy and so on. In short, outside the invi-
olable interests of democratic people in the preservation of the
democratic process [inviolable because of the roots of that pro-
cess in an ideal of equal intrinsic worth] would lie the proper
sphere for political decisions.26
Dahl immediately indicates some qualms about this view and explores
ways to ensure that conventional democratic process might better protect
fundamental interests that are not integral or essential to it.27 But he has
identified a genuine problem, whose most familiar expression arises in
connection with what Benjamin Constant called the “liberties of the
moderns”—religious liberty, liberty of conscience more generally, liberty
of thought and expression, rights of person and personal property. These
liberties lack any evident connection to conditions of democratic proce-
dure: to borrow Dahl’s words, they are neither integral nor essential to it.
So their protection is commonly understood as constraining democratic
process—limiting its appropriate scope. In that respect they differ from
political liberties, including rights of association, of speech on political
questions, and of participation. If a constitution disables a majority from
restricting political participation or regulating the content of political
speech, that constitution can be interpreted as safeguarding the essen-
tials of democratic process. Assurances of such political liberties help
to ensure a connection between popular authorization and political
outcome—to preserve the continuing authority of the people, and not
simply the majority of them.28 Those liberties—the liberties of the an-
cients—are constitutive elements of democratic process.
The liberties of the moderns appear, then, to be based on independent
26. Dahl, Democracy and Its Critics, 182.
27. Dahl has long been skeptical about the role of courts with powers of judicial review in
providing such protection. See his remarkable essay, “Decision-Making in a Democracy: The
Supreme Court as a National Policy-Maker,” Journal of Public Law 6 (Fall 1957): 279–295; and
Democracy and Its Critics, chs. 12, 13.
28. See John Hart Ely, Democracy and Distrust (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,
1980); Dahl, Democracy and Its Critics; and, more generally, on constitutional requirements
as enabling democracy, Stephen Holmes, “Precommitment and the Paradox of Democracy,”
in Jon Elster and Rune Slagstad, eds., Constitutionalism and Democracy (Cambridge: Cam-
bridge University Press, 1988), esp. 195–240; and Samuel Freeman, “Original Meaning, Demo-
cratic Interpretation, and the Constitution,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 21 (Winter 1992):
3–42.
242
D E M O C R A C Y A N D L I B E R T Y
243
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
31. Michael Sandel, Democracy’s Discontent (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,
1996), 322.
244
D E M O C R A C Y A N D L I B E R T Y
245
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
246
D E M O C R A C Y A N D L I B E R T Y
ligious liberty. First, my remarks are limited. I have not said anything di-
rectly about how to handle claims for religious exemption from general
obligations with a strong secular justification (including obligations to
educate children); or whether special provision is to be made for spe-
cifically religious convictions, as distinct from conscientious ethical con-
victions with no religious roots;35 or about tolerating the intolerant. My
aim here is not to resolve, or even to address, these issues: any view recog-
nizing rights of free exercise will need to face those hard questions. I am
interested only in making the more restricted point that a deliberative
conception of democracy is not barred—by its emphasis on an ideal of
democracy—from acknowledging a fundamental role for rights of reli-
gious liberty: indeed, that it must provide a place for such rights. The ba-
sis of such rights, on the deliberative view, lies deeper than contingent
popular consensus. Like rights of political expression, they are founded
on the idea of democracy itself.
Second, I emphasize that the rationale for the guarantees of religious
liberty that fall under the requirement of deliberative inclusion is neither
narrowly political nor antipolitical. It is not narrowly political, because
those guarantees are not simply about enabling people to participate in
normal politics (or to participate without fear), nor simply about im-
proving public discussion by adding more diverse voices to it. It is not
antipolitical, because they are not simply about ensuring the strength of
organized associations (churches among them) that help to protect indi-
viduals from the state’s power.36 The argument does not deny the links
between religious liberty and associational liberty. The idea instead is
that abridgments of such liberties would constitute denials to citizens of
standing as equal members of the sovereign people, by imposing in ways
that deny the force of reasons that are, by the lights of their own views,
compelling. The reasons for abridgment are unacceptably exclusionary,
because they are unsuited to the ideal of guiding the exercise of power by
a process of reason-giving suited to a system of free and equal citizens.
The view I am presenting might, then, be contrasted with an approach
35. On this last point: the key to the case for religious liberty is that the content of a view as-
signs stringent obligations to a person who holds it. But specifically religious content is not es-
sential.
36. See the discussion of this rationale in Stephen Carter, The Culture of Disbelief (New
York: Basic Books, 1993), 17–18, 35–39. As a general matter, Carter’s defense of religious liberty
seems too exclusively focused on the parallels between religious and associational liberty and,
correspondingly, too dismissive of the continuities between freedom of conscience and free-
dom of public worship. On those continuities, see Murray, “The Problem of Religious Free-
dom,” 148–151.
247
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
6. Expressive Liberty
The principle of deliberative inclusion extends naturally from religious
liberty to a wide guarantee of expressive liberty. By a “wide guarantee,” I
mean a guarantee not confined to political speech, even on very capa-
cious understandings of political speech. Cass Sunstein, for example, de-
fines political speech as speech that is “intended and received as a con-
tribution to public deliberation about some issue.”38 I believe that a
deliberative view supports stringent protections of expressive liberty, even
when the expression falls outside the political, thus understood.
The deliberative view thus extends a more familiar democracy-based
strand of free-speech theory, which defends stringent protections of spe-
cifically political speech as one prerequisite for a democratic framework
of collective choice.39 Alexander Meiklejohn’s version of this theory lo-
cates the roots of a strong free-speech guarantee in the U.S. constitu-
tional design of popular self-government. Because popular sovereignty re-
37. Unger, False Necessity, 525, emphases added; Joshua Cohen, “Deliberation and Demo-
cratic Legitimacy,” in Alan Hamlin and Phillip Petit, eds., The Good Polity (Oxford: Blackwell,
1989), 17–34 [reprinted as essay 1 in this collection].
38. See Cass Sunstein, Democracy and the Problem of Free Speech (New York: Free Press,
1993), 130.
39. See Alexander Meiklejohn, Political Freedom (New York: Harper & Brothers, 1960);
Sunstein, Democracy and the Problem of Free Speech; Robert Bork, “Neutral Principles and
Some First Amendment Problems,” Indiana Law Journal 47, 1 (Fall 1971): 1–35; Ely, Democ-
racy and Distrust; Owen Fiss, Liberalism Divided (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1996).
248
D E M O C R A C Y A N D L I B E R T Y
249
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
41. Whitney v. California, 274 U.S. 357, 375 (1927) (Brandeis, J., concurring).
250
D E M O C R A C Y A N D L I B E R T Y
42. The discussion that follows is taken from Joshua Cohen, “Freedom, Equality, Pornogra-
phy,” in Austin Sarat and Thomas Kearns, eds., Justice and Injustice in Law and Legal Theory
(Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1996), 99–139.
251
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
252
D E M O C R A C Y A N D L I B E R T Y
46. See Judith Butler, Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of Identity (New York:
Routledge, 1990); Susan Keller, “Viewing and Doing: Complicating Pornography’s Meaning,”
Georgetown Law Review 81 (1993): 2195–2228; Duncan Kennedy, Sexy Dressing: Essays on the
Power and Politics of Cultural Identity (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993), 126–
213.
253
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
pornography and not simply advance the speculative arguments that are
commonly proposed.
7. Moral Liberty
I want now to discuss the implications of the principle of deliberative in-
clusion in the area of moral liberty, what John Stuart Mill called the “lib-
erty of tastes and pursuits.”47 I propose to concentrate, in particular, on
the enforcement of morality.
My principal focus here will be on the permissibility of imposing crim-
inal punishment on citizens for violating the ethical code shared by the
majority in a society, even when that conduct is neither injurious nor of-
fensive to others: Is it permissible for a political society to use its criminal
law to force members to lead lives that are not, by the lights of the major-
ity, immoral or perverse?48 Criminalization is, of course, a special case,
and problems of moral liberty extend well beyond it. Mill’s defense of
moral liberty was as much a criticism of intrusive collective opinion as of
state regulation. And, confining attention to state action, we need to ad-
dress the codification of morality through regulations that are not backed
by criminal sanction: for example, bans on same-sex marriage. But be-
cause the issues have important affinities, and can be seen more sharply
in the area of criminalization, I will focus on it here.
In two important cases in the 1980s and 1990s—Bowers v. Hardwick
and Barnes v. Glen Theatre—the U.S. Supreme Court affirmed the con-
stitutional permissibility of criminalizing immoral conduct. In the first,
“the presumed belief of a majority of the electorate in Georgia that ho-
mosexual sodomy is immoral and unacceptable” was offered as a suitable
rationale for a law imposing criminal sanctions on consensual homosex-
ual sodomy.49 To be more precise, the Georgia law itself imposed crimi-
nal sanctions on consensual sodomy quite generally, but it was upheld by
the Court only as applied to homosexual sodomy. In the second, the
Court upheld an Indiana public indecency law requiring dancers to
wear pasties and G-strings. As rationale for the law, Justice Rehnquist of-
fers the public’s “moral disapproval of people appearing in the nude
among strangers in public places.” Moreover, he notes traditional com-
mon law restrictions on public nudity and the view underlying those re-
254
D E M O C R A C Y A N D L I B E R T Y
strictions: that public nudity was an act malum in se. Writing in concur-
rence, Justice Scalia emphasizes that the conduct is prohibited because it
is “immoral”—in conflict with “traditional moral belief”—not because it
is offensive: “The purpose of Indiana’s nudity law would be violated, I
think, if 60,000 fully consenting adults crowded into the Hoosier Dome
to display their genitals to one another, even if there was not an offended
innocent in the crowd.” Rejecting Mill’s harm principle—which requires
a showing of harm to others as a necessary condition for criminal sanc-
tion—Scalia says, “Our society prohibits, and all human societies have
prohibited, certain activities not because they harm others, but because
they are considered, in the traditional phrase, contra bonos mores, i.e.,
immoral”—and he goes on to mention “sadomasochism, cockfighting,
bestiality, suicide, drug use, prostitution, and sodomy” as areas in which
legal regulation of conduct is constitutionally permitted, though the ra-
tionale for the regulations is rooted in “traditional moral belief.”
As Scalia’s examples indicate, the debate about the enforcement of
morals is not confined to issues of sexual morality. Still, that has been a
central historical focus—as in Bowers and Barnes, as well as in disagree-
ments about generic anti-sodomy laws and in disagreements about regu-
lations of prostitution and pornography. I will maintain that focus here.
The debate about enforcing morality implicates in especially profound
ways the value of democracy. Indeed, the debate about the permissibility
of enforcing conventional ethics is commonly presented as a conflict be-
tween democracy, which is said to support the enforcement of morals,
and some other value—say, personal liberty or autonomy—which is seen
to be compromised by and to condemn that enforcement. Ronald
Dworkin, for example, says that the argument from democracy is “politi-
cally the most powerful argument against liberal tolerance.”50 And in his
classical critique of Lord Devlin’s defense of the enforcement of morals,
H. L. A. Hart says, “It seems fatally easy to believe that loyalty to demo-
cratic principles entails acceptance of what may be termed moral popu-
lism: the view that the majority have a moral right to dictate how all
should live.”51
To state the views of the moral populist in more generous terms: on
moral issues, the values of the majority ought to be decisive because no
255
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
52. Lord Devlin, “Democracy and Morality,” in The Enforcement of Morals (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1965).
53. See Ely, Democracy and Distrust, 256. See also John Hart Ely, “Professor Dworkin’s Ex-
ternal/Personal Preference Distinction,” Duke Law Review (1983): 985.
256
D E M O C R A C Y A N D L I B E R T Y
257
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
258
D E M O C R A C Y A N D L I B E R T Y
choice under favorable conditions for considering how best to live (e.g.,
conditions in which people pursue different “experiments in living,” to
borrow Mill’s phrase).
This argument has considerable force. The premise about autonomy
serves as an axiom in a family of reasonable comprehensive moralities;
and for the sake of discussion, I assume that the conclusions are well sup-
ported by the premises. But as political argument, it has an important
shortcoming: it depends on a comprehensive philosophy of life, and the
deliberative view requires that, under conditions of reasonable pluralism,
we free political argument from such dependence, particularly when
such argument bears on the fundamentals of conduct.
Thus, the autonomy theory is a form of comprehensive moral liberal-
ism, rejected by citizens who think, not unreasonably, that human lives
are made good at least in part by their compliance with divine law, or
their conformity to the order of the universe, or the quality of their im-
pact on the world, or the extent to which they realize human powers. To
be sure, citizens who endorse such views may themselves reject the en-
forcement of morality because they judge it worse or inappropriate to
force lives to be as good as they can be. But just as the belief in religious
toleration is not and should not be presented as contingent on a religious
view about the sufficiency of inner faith to salvation, acceptance of moral
toleration is not and should not be presented as contingent on the view
that personal autonomy is the supreme moral value and the comprehen-
sive guide to conduct. I mentioned earlier that the autonomy argument
for moral toleration generalizes a Lockean argument for religious tolera-
tion; whereas the latter rejects enforcement of a religious code because
inner faith is required for salvation, the former, more abstractly, treats re-
flective endorsement as constitutive of the goodness of a life for the per-
son who lives it. I think there is something right in this use of religious
toleration as a model, but as I explain in some detail below, the delibera-
tive view presents the parallel in a different way: it emphasizes, in partic-
ular, the weight of the reasons that lie behind the regulated conduct and
the unacceptability for the purposes of political argument of the consid-
erations that would justify the regulations.
The failure of this argument might suggest that majority rule ought, af-
ter all, to extend to moral issues. Precisely by underscoring moral dis-
agreement—indeed, reasonable moral disagreement—the limits of the
autonomy argument might suggest that treating citizens as equals re-
259
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
quires that the majority be left free to fix the shared moral landscape.
Lord Devlin makes just this point. Agreeing that moral differences often
cannot be resolved through a good faith exercise of practical reason—
that “after centuries of debate, men of undoubted reasoning power and
honesty of purpose have shown themselves unable to agree on what the
moral law should be”61—he concludes that the arbiter of social morality
cannot be reason but must instead be the people—“the ordinary man,
the man in the jury box, who might also be called the reasonable man or
the right-minded man.”62
But the deliberative account of democracy rejects that conclusion. To
see why, notice first that controversies about the enforcement of moral-
ity characteristically track moral controversies: when enforcement is con-
troversial, so, too, is the moral question itself. The issue, then, is not
whether conduct, assumed not to be injurious to others, can permissibly
be regulated for moral reasons on which there is general agreement. In-
stead, the issue is whether conduct can permissibly be regulated for
moral reasons, despite deep and apparently unresolvable disagreement
about the morality of the conduct and the grounds for regulating it.
This point seems easy to miss. In his criticisms of Devlin, for example,
Hart asks “why we should not summon all the resources of our reason,
sympathetic understanding, as well as critical intelligence, and insist that
before general moral feeling is turned into criminal law it is submitted to
scrutiny of a different kind from Sir Patrick’s. Surely the legislator should
ask whether the general morality is based on ignorance, superstition, or
misunderstanding. . . .”63 Such questions are certainly in order. But in
controversial cases of enforcement, the assumption that regulations en-
force “general morality” or “general moral feeling” is typically not, unless
by “general” we mean “majority,” in which case a very large step needs to
be filled in—the step that authorizes the majority to speak in the name of
the community.
Take the case of homosexuality. It would be preposterous to say that
the moral consensus of the community condemns homosexuality, but
some people want nevertheless to practice it despite its accepted immo-
rality. Instead, some citizens, for religious or perhaps other reasons, con-
demn it and perhaps wish to regulate it (though not all who condemn
260
D E M O C R A C Y A N D L I B E R T Y
64. A third argument, advanced by Roger Scruton, claims that homosexuality exhibits an
objectionable form of narcissism and obscene perception, that instead of “mov[ing] out from
my body towards the other, whose flesh is unknown to me . . . I remain locked within my body,
narcissistically contemplating in the other an excitement that is the mirror of my own.” Sexual
Desire (New York: Free Press, 1986), 310. Though Scruton presents the antinarcissism argu-
ment as an alternative to arguments from the natural end of sexuality and complementarity, it
is not clear that it stands independently of the latter.
65. For a crisp statement, see C. H. Peschke, Christian Ethics, vol. 2 (London: C. Goodliffe
Neale, 1978), 379.
66. For discussion of the idea of complementarity, see Scruton, Sexual Desire, 309; Andrew
Sullivan, Virtually Normal: An Argument About Homosexuality (New York: Knopf, 1995); and
especially Gareth Moore, The Body in Context: Sex and Catholicism (London: SCM Press,
1992), ch. 7. Moore rightly points out that, on natural interpretations, the idea of comple-
mentarity depends on the procreation-as-natural-end doctrine. The passage on com-
plementarity comes from the Letter on the Pastoral Care of Homosexual Persons of the Catho-
lic Church’s Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith.
67. See, e.g., Sullivan, Virtually Normal; and Moore, The Body in Context.
261
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
262
D E M O C R A C Y A N D L I B E R T Y
70. I borrow the example of security policy from the discussion of toleration in Thomas
Nagel, Equality and Partiality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991), 164–165. The general
point—that the case for majority rule weakens when a collective policy is not necessary and
that such policy is not required when it comes to moral issues—can be found in both Nagel
and Joel Feinberg, Harmless Wrongdoing (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990), 51.
263
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
265
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
267
8
M O N E Y, P O L I T I C S , P O L I T I C A L E Q U A L I T Y
1. Introduction
In this paper, I discuss and criticize the current system of electoral
finance in the United States and the constraints on the reform of that sys-
tem imposed by the Supreme Court.
1. I begin by stating and discussing a three-part principle of political
equality (section 2), which I present as a partial statement of a normative
ideal of democracy.
2. I argue that the current system of campaign finance conflicts with
the principle of political equality, in particular its requirement of equal
opportunity for political influence. Current arrangements establish, in
effect, a framework of inequalities of opportunity (sections 3, 4).
3. I discuss the constitutional limits on reform initially set down by the
Supreme Court in the 1976 case of Buckley v. Valeo and reinforced in a
number of cases decided since then. These decisions substantially limit
the role that the value of political equality can play in shaping our system
of campaign finance. A regulatory scheme that gave weight to that value
by aiming to equalize opportunities for political influence would (barring
This essay originally appeared in a volume dedicated to Judith Jarvis Thomson. In it, as in
everything I write, I aspire to meet her high standards of clarity. I am sure that I have not suc-
ceeded but am deeply indebted to Judy for demonstrating in all her work that it is possible to
say important things without sacrificing clarity. The essay started as a talk to a meeting of the
Northeast Citizen Action Resource Center. I have presented subsequent and expanded ver-
sions to the MIT Club in Washington, D.C., the Tufts University philosophy colloquium,
McGill University departments of philosophy and political science, and a Brown University
Conference on political equality. I also presented a draft at a meeting of the September Group
and earlier versions of the main ideas to political philosophy seminars (in fall 1995 and spring
1998). I am grateful for the comments I received and wish particularly to thank Philippe van
Parijs, Erik Olin Wright, and David Estlund for suggestions. I am indebted to Stephen
Ansolabehere and James Snyder for discussions of the current system of election finance and
to Leonardo Avritzer for discussions of the persisting importance of the Schumpeterian view of
democracy in contemporary democratic thought. As always, my debt to John Rawls runs
throughout.
268
M O N E Y, P O L I T I C S , P O L I T I C A L E Q U A L I T Y
1. See Joseph Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy (New York: Harper and
Row, 1942), chaps. 21, 22. Not that Schumpeter himself was especially concerned about ensur-
ing more informed electoral judgments. What comes from him is the thesis that we should
think of democracy as a particular way of organizing competition for political leadership—that
instead of using “birth, lot, wealth, violence, co-optation, learning, appointment, or examina-
tion” to resolve the contest for political power, democracies resolve it through voting in regular
elections—and think of the role of citizens as analogous to that of consumers in the product
market.
2. See Daggett v. Webster, U.S. District Court, District of Maine, slip op. (November 5,
1999 and January 7, 2000).
269
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
tary spending limits, incentives to accept the limits as condition for re-
ceiving the subsidy (therefore incentives to reduce the overall quantity of
speech), some constraints (in the form of reasonably low contribution
limits) on private money nonparticipants, and additional support for pub-
lic money candidates who face large private spending by opponents or
large independent expenditures.3
One final prefatory note: as I was adding final touches to this paper (in
January 2000), the Supreme Court announced its decision in Nixon v.
Shrink, in which it upheld Missouri’s statutory limits on campaign con-
tributions. Were I rewriting the paper now, I would make two changes in
light of the opinions in Nixon. First, I would change the discussion in
section 6 to take notice of the fact that Nixon v. Shrink rejects the idea
that restrictions on the size of campaign contributions should be sub-
jected to the most demanding level of scrutiny. Second, and more impor-
tant, I would underscore that the vast majority of the Court now seems
willing to uphold campaign finance regulations enacted to ensure a
more fair democratic process. This willingness is explicitly stated in Jus-
tice Breyer’s concurrence and is suggested as well by Justice Souter (writ-
ing for the Court), who indicates that corruption of democratic process is
not confined to the financial quid pro quo. The implications of this shift
remain to be seen. But the apparent departure in constitutional philoso-
phy is cause for hope.
270
M O N E Y, P O L I T I C S , P O L I T I C A L E Q U A L I T Y
271
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
272
M O N E Y, P O L I T I C S , P O L I T I C A L E Q U A L I T Y
ing that position. We now agree that economic position is not a relevant
formal qualification. But if economic position is not a relevant formal
qualification for voting and other forms of political influence, how could
it be acceptable to organize the highest-level system for exercising politi-
cal influence in a way that makes the opportunity for such influence de-
pendent on economic position? How could it be acceptable to organize
the framework so that greater opportunity comes with greater resources?
I do not propose here to defend this principle (though see 292–302 for
some relevant considerations) but will confine myself to four comments
on the idea of equal opportunity for political influence. Three of the com-
ments bear on the content of the principle—why equal opportunity for
political influence, why equal opportunity for political influence, and
why equal opportunity for political influence—and one bears on its sta-
tus as “autonomous” or independent.
First, then, political equality demands equal opportunity for effective
political influence rather than equality of effective influence itself. In-
equalities of effective influence are sometimes acceptable, on any rea-
sonable view of political equality. Some citizens may be more influential
because, for example, they care more about politics. Differences of influ-
ence that trace to such differences in values and choices seem unobjec-
tionable. Similarly, if a person is more influential because her views are
widely shared, or her judgment widely trusted, and others are therefore
likely to be swayed by her position on the issue at hand: the differences of
influence trace to the distribution of political values and commitments in
the population, not to the organization of the structure of collective
choice. The requirement of equal opportunity for effective influence
condemns certain kinds of effective exclusion or dilution, but it does not
support charges of objectionable exclusion or dilution merely because I
am unwilling to make reasonable efforts to persuade others, or because
others regard my views as ridiculous, or because they lack confidence in
my judgment.
What about inequalities due to differences in persuasiveness, or in
physical attractiveness? In neither case are the greater opportunities for
influence due to aspects of the design of arrangements for making collec-
tive decisions that we can permissibly control. To be sure, we could make
collective efforts to reduce the importance of differential persuasiveness,
for example, by investing more in civic education. But the legitimacy
and importance of making such investment do not imply that it would
273
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
10. Here, I disagree with Dworkin’s account of political equality in “What Is Equality? Part
4: Political Equality,” University of San Francisco Law Review (Fall 1987). Dworkin there re-
jects the idea that political equality has autonomous importance.
274
M O N E Y, P O L I T I C S , P O L I T I C A L E Q U A L I T Y
11. In discussions of equal opportunity in the context of education, the focus is often on ade-
quacy, in part because a number of state constitutions in the United States guarantee an ade-
quate level of education.
12. David Estlund explores these concerns in his excellent paper, “Political Quality,” Social
Philosophy and Policy 17, 1 (Winter 2000): 127–160.
275
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
13. Rawls, Theory of Justice, 477. I trace this idea to Rousseau, in Joshua Cohen, “The Natu-
ral Goodness of Humanity,” in Christine Korsgaard, Barbara Herman, and Andrews Reath,
eds., Learning from the History of Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 102–
139.
276
M O N E Y, P O L I T I C S , P O L I T I C A L E Q U A L I T Y
14. Bruce Cain and Kathleen Sullivan both accept equal voting influence but reject equal
opportunity for electoral influence. See Cain, “Moralism and Realism in Campaign Finance
Reform,” University of Chicago Legal Forum (1995). At p. 136, Cain indicates that equalizing
electoral influence through restrictions on political expenditures threatens excessive respon-
siveness to “ill-formed majoritarian preferences.” The basis for that presumption is unclear but
appears to derive from the idea that spending limits restrict the flow of information, and thus
give too much sway to uniformed preferences. Sullivan’s case is far more plausible. See
Kathleen M. Sullivan, “Political Money and Freedom of Speech,” University of California Da-
vis Law Review 30, 31 (Spring 1997): esp. 674–675. She points out, rightly, that the equalizing
opportunities for electoral influence will require some regulations of election-related expres-
sion, but that no such regulations are required by equally weighted votes, however broadly we
interpret the range of unacceptable gerrymanders. So we will need to draw some lines between
electoral and political speech that occurs in informal political discussion. The result may be ei-
ther unacceptable restrictions of political speech in the informal public sphere, if the bound-
aries around electoral speech are loosely drawn, or only minimal corrections for unequal
chances for influence, if those boundaries are drawn more crisply. For if we know one thing
from our experience with regulation in this field, it is that every regulation represents an invita-
tion to invest in political strategies that are equally effective but that circumvent the regulation.
One might have thought that these “practical difficulties,” as Sullivan calls them, would
prompt efforts at legal invention. Sullivan puzzlingly treats them as insuperable hurdles.
15. To be sure, the boundaries are vague, as is amply demonstrated by the problem of regu-
lating issue advertising.
277
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
suppose that a case for ensuring equal chances for political influence
would support equal chances for public influence as well.
I think, however, that we should resist this conclusion and reject the
wide interpretation of the principle of political equality.
First, the content of the requirement of equal opportunity for public
influence is obscure. The informal process of opinion-formation is not at
all well defined, bounded, or understood: it extends throughout life and
spreads through all its spheres. So it is not clear what the requirement de-
mands: not clear, that is, when opportunities for influence are suitably
equal—when individuals who are equally motivated and equally able
have equal chances to influence the formation of public opinion. To
be sure, effective chances to persuade others and to discuss cultural
and political issues are important, but those chances are ensured both by
the protections of expressive and associative liberties that fall under the
first part of the principle of political equality and by a fair distribution
of resources. Here, I am asking whether there is a further, independent
requirement of equal opportunities for public influence. To be more
precise, I am asking whether such a requirement ought to be included
in a principle of political equality, as a fundamental political value to
be accommodated along with equal rights of participation and equally
weighted votes. If it is not included, it may still be legitimate to reduce
inequalities of opportunity for public influence by subsidizing opportuni-
ties for people with limited resources: through ensuring more traditional
public fora and expanding access to the new fora by, for example, sub-
sidizing internet access (addressing the so-called digital divide) and op-
portunities for content provision. But the obscurity of the norm speaks
against including it in a first principle of political equality, for such inclu-
sion might lead to excessive restrictions on expression.
Second, part of the reason for requiring equal chances for political in-
fluence is that the state speaks in the name of citizens, claiming authori-
zation for its binding collective decisions from its equal members; more-
over, its decisions are enforceable. So we want to be sure that that claim
is founded on arrangements that manifestly treat citizens as equals. But
in the wider public sphere, we have no such authoritative statement of
results. Although citizens have fundamental interests in chances for pub-
lic influence, the equality requirement is less compelling.
Third, part of the reason for ensuring equal opportunities for political
influence is to establish, in a visible, public way, the respect for citizens
278
M O N E Y, P O L I T I C S , P O L I T I C A L E Q U A L I T Y
Increasing costs: In the 1996 election cycle, $2.4 billion was raised, and
$2.2 billion was spent on candidate campaigns.16 In addition, another
$175 million was spent on independent expenditures and issue advocacy.
Independent expenditures are funds—roughly $25 million for the 1996
elections—that are used expressly to advocate the election of one candi-
date or the defeat of another but that are not spent in explicit coordina-
tion with a candidate’s campaign. In issue advocacy, money—roughly
$150 million for the 1996 elections—is spent supporting or opposing the
stand of an elected official or a challenger on some issue, but without ex-
pressly advocating the election or defeat of the candidate. These aggre-
gates nearly doubled the previous record.
16. I use the 1996 numbers because the essay was originally written in 1999. The $2.4 billion
comprises public money for the presidential campaign ($211m), small donors contributing less
than $200 ($734m), larger donors contributing more than $200 ($597m), PACs ($234m), “soft
money,” which is contributed to the parties but not to be spent in connection with federal elec-
tions ($262m), and candidates themselves ($262m, led by Steve Forbes’s $37m).
279
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
dates, business gave nine times as much money as organized labor, and
fifteen times as much as ideological donors.”17
In Voice and Equality, Verba, Schlozman, and Brady provide two find-
ings that bear on our understanding of this relatively small pool of citi-
zens who participate in American politics by making financial contribu-
tions and who are responsible for a large share of contributions and
spending. First, willingness to contribute money is largely explained by
income—by the capacity to contribute—and not by political interest.
Whereas every other political-participatory act—voting, talking, giving
time to a campaign—is substantially explained by the participant’s gen-
eral interest in politics, contributing is explained very little by general po-
litical interest and very strongly by income.18 Second, the pool of contrib-
utors is unrepresentative of the citizenry: for example, contributors tend
to be more conservative on economic issues.19
• Soft money: Soft money given to political parties for activities alleg-
edly unrelated to federal elections—for example, get-out-the-vote
campaigns by a state Democratic or Republican Party—is entirely
unrestricted by federal law.20 Such soft money contributions grew by
17. From an online publication by Center for Responsive Politics, http://www.opensecrets
.org/pubs/bigpicture/overview/bpoverview.htm.
18. Level of political interest is measured by responses to survey questions that ask about the
respondent’s interest in local and national affairs. See Sidney Verba, Kay Lehman Schlozman,
and Henry E. Brady, Voice and Equality (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1995),
553. The finding is striking, but not surprising. Someone with little political interest, thus mea-
sured, might be highly motivated to give to a candidate because of a concern about some par-
ticular issue, and assuming a declining marginal utility of money, the cost to the contributor is
very small. Moreover, people with high capacity but low interest are more likely to give than
people with low capacity and comparably low interest, because the former are more likely to
be asked for money. My guess is that the finding that financial contributions (unlike other
forms of activity) are largely explained by capacity rather than by interest is probably true for a
wide range of activities and is almost certainly true of any activity in which professional fund-
raisers are involved, because they target capacity, not motivation. Perhaps contributions to reli-
gious organizations are an exception.
19. Voice and Equality, 303, 358, 361–364, 477, 512, 516.
20. Federal candidates are, however, permitted to solicit soft money. For discussion of the
complexities of soft money, see Note, “Soft Money: The Current Rules and the Case for Re-
form,” Harvard Law Review 111 (1998).
280
M O N E Y, P O L I T I C S , P O L I T I C A L E Q U A L I T Y
206 percent between 1992 and 1996, to $262 million. Whereas cor-
porations and unions are prohibited from contributing money from
their treasury to a candidate, they can contribute soft money, with
no restrictions on amounts.
• Issue ads: Spending on issue ads is also unregulated by federal
law, because such advocacy is not explicit in its endorsement of
candidates. So corporations and unions can spend as they wish
on issue advocacy, with no disclosure requirements. Absent such
requirements, the estimate of $150 million in 1996 is inevitably
speculative, but everyone agrees that issue ads are growing in im-
portance.
• Candidate spending: Out-of-pocket spending by candidates is unreg-
ulated: the cases of Ross Perot, Steve Forbes, and Michael
Huffington are the most famously large doses of such spending.
• Independent expenditures: Whereas contributions to organizations
that engage in independent expenditures are regulated, the extent of
such expenditures cannot be regulated. The importance of such
spending has grown—fourfold between 1994 and 1996, to $22 mil-
lion—because the Supreme Court decided that spending by parties
on candidate elections cannot be regulated unless that spending is
expressly coordinated with the candidate. But contribution limits for
donations to parties are much higher than limits on giving to indi-
vidual campaigns: individuals can give $40,000 to a party in an elec-
tion cycle (half during the primary season, and half for the general
election), but only $2000 to a candidate. So I can give $20,000 to
the Democratic Party to spend on vote-for-Kennedy ads promoting
Ted Kennedy over other Democratic hopefuls for senator and then
another $20,000 to support Kennedy in the general election. So
long as the Democrats don’t ask Kennedy how to spend the money,
there is no problem.
Money matters. In 1996, the candidate who outspent his or her oppo-
nent won 92 percent of the House races and 88 percent of the Senate
races. These high correlations of spending and winning are typical. But
they leave open questions of fact and interpretation about the political
difference that money makes, even in the relatively well-defined arena of
candidate elections, much less in the wider arena of political influence.
For three things are true:
281
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
282
M O N E Y, P O L I T I C S , P O L I T I C A L E Q U A L I T Y
Putting the complexities to the side, what seems undeniable is that the
success of candidates depends on their fund-raising success, that the ca-
pacity to raise money depends on their performance, that the ability to at-
tract support from the groups that give depends on their conduct; contrib-
utors, by providing such support, gain some measure of influence over
electoral outcomes.
To summarize these four observations, then: formal politics is get-
ting more expensive, just as the flow of money unregulated by sum or
by source is increasing. Because of these increasing costs, and because
money is important to electoral success, candidates must be especially—
arguably increasingly—attentive to the interests and the concerns of the
relatively small and unrepresentative group of citizens who spend money
on politics and thus provide essential resources for running a modern
campaign.
283
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
284
M O N E Y, P O L I T I C S , P O L I T I C A L E Q U A L I T Y
5. Constitutional Landscape
What might be done to remedy this situation? To answer this question, I
start with the constitutional landscape.
In the 1976 case of Buckley v. Valeo, the Supreme Court heard a chal-
lenge to the Federal Election Campaign Act (FECA) of 1971, as
amended in 1974.25 The Court’s assessment was mixed: some parts were
upheld, some not. But the details of the decision matter less than the
framework of analysis and the argument announced in it. That analytic
framework comprises two key elements.
First, the Buckley Court held that “money is speech”: meaning that
spending money on politics—both contributions to campaigns and ex-
penditures (by candidates or individual citizens or organizations)—has
First Amendment protection. Indeed, as political speech, it lies at the
core of the First Amendment. For the First Amendment is centrally
(though not exclusively) about protecting political speech from regula-
tion, as a necessary condition for assuring popular sovereignty—rather
than governmental sovereignty—that defines the American constitu-
tional system.
The argument that spending is, for constitutional purposes, protected
political speech proceeds as follows: “Contribution and spending limita-
tions impose direct quantity restrictions [emphasis added] on political
communication and association. . . . A restriction on the amount of
money a person or group can spend on political communication during
a campaign necessarily reduces the quantity of expression by restrict-
ing the number of issues discussed, the depth of their exploration, and
the size of the audience reached. This is because virtually every means
of communicating in today’s mass society requires the expenditure of
money. . . . The electorate’s increasing dependence on television, radio,
and other mass media for news and information has made these expen-
sive modes of communication indispensable instruments of effective po-
litical speech.”26
So sending messages requires money, and restrictions on money there-
fore restrict such sending: they limit the “quantity” of speech. The quan-
25. Buckley v. Valeo, 424 U.S. 1 (1976).
26. Ibid., 19.
285
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
286
M O N E Y, P O L I T I C S , P O L I T I C A L E Q U A L I T Y
28. Burdick v. Takushi, 504 U.S. 428, 445 (1992); see also Timmons v. Twin Cities Area New
Party, 117 S. Ct. 1364, 1377 (1997) (Stevens, J., joined by Ginsburg and Souter, JJ., dissenting),
where the dissent attributes this view to the majority.
29. Samuel L. Popkin, The Reasoning Voter: Communication and Persuasion in Presidential
Campaigns (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1991); Arthur Lupia and Matthew
McCubbins, The Democratic Dilemma: Can Citizens Learn What They Need to Know? (Cam-
bridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998).
287
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
Returning to Buckley: The second main idea is that the state has a
compelling interest in avoiding the appearance and the reality of quid
pro quo—dollars for votes—corruption. “Corruption,” the Court said in
1985, “is a subversion of the political process,” and the “hallmark of cor-
ruption is the financial quid pro quo: dollars for political favors.”30 The
essential point is that the corruption rationale is narrowly understood—in
effect, as a generalization of bribery law.
The Court allows that there may be other compelling rationales for
regulating spending but insists that none has yet been identified. In
particular, the state is said not to have a compelling interest in “leveling
the playing field”—ensuring equal opportunity for political influence.
FECA, the Court says, was “aimed in part at equalizing the relative abil-
ity of all voters to affect electoral outcomes by placing a ceiling on expen-
ditures for political expression by citizens and groups.” But the majority
opinion rejects this rationale: “The concept that government may restrict
the speech of some elements of our society in order to enhance the rela-
tive voice of others is wholly foreign to the First Amendment.”31 In this
important remark, the Court does not dispute that restricting the voice
of some may enhance the relative voice of others—indeed, that it might
be necessary to enhancing their voice. Nor does it deny that such en-
hancement would be a very good thing, a legitimate and perhaps sub-
stantial governmental objective. Instead, the majority asserts that the
First Amendment bars the door to achieving equalization through restric-
tion on First Amendment liberties.
With those two elements in place, the rest of the system follows pretty
straightforwardly. Because contributions merit lesser First Amendment
protection, and because restrictions on “large contributions” are well de-
signed to avoid the appearance and reality of political quid pro quo,
restrictions on such contributions are permissible, though only if they
are addressed to quid pro quo corruption, and that means only if the reg-
ulated contributions are sufficiently large to pose a genuine threat of
such corruption. Because expenditures merit especially stringent protec-
tion, and because restrictions on expenditures do not advance the one
concededly compelling interest in the arena of electoral finance—the in-
terest in avoiding the appearance or reality of quid pro quo corruption—
expenditure restrictions are impermissible, unless they are voluntary, as
30. FEC v. NCPAC, 470 U.S. 480, 497 (1985).
31. Buckley v. Valeo, 424 U.S. 1, 48–49 (1976).
288
M O N E Y, P O L I T I C S , P O L I T I C A L E Q U A L I T Y
under the public financing scheme for presidential elections that was
part of FECA.
6. Persisting Constraints
In the period since Buckley, the two fundamentals of this framework
have been restated and reinforced, but they have not been changed.
Thus, the Court continues to hold that the First Amendment protects
both contributions and expenditures and has continued to emphasize
the importance of spending in contributing to the quantity of speech,
and thus to the interest of the audience, even more than it has empha-
sized the importance of protecting the interests of speakers. Because of
this emphasis on quantity of speech, the Court has held that the iden-
tity of the speaker is not especially relevant to the permissibility of regula-
tion. Particularly important and revealing in this connection is the 1978
Bellotti decision, in which the Court held that states could not regulate
corporate spending on ballot initiatives. The fact that the speakers were
not individual citizens but corporations did not matter because the pro-
tected value was not the corporation’s interest in speaking but the audi-
ence’s interest in a full airing of views.32 This is “the type of speech indis-
pensable to decision making in a democracy,” and its value “in terms of
its capacity for informing the public does not depend upon the identity
of its source, whether corporation, association, union, or individual.”33
“The Constitution,” according to the Court majority, “often protects in-
terests broader than those of the party seeking their vindication. The First
Amendment, in particular, serves significant societal interests,” in partic-
ular the interest in the “free discussion of governmental affairs.” So the
Court vindicated the expressive liberty of the corporation (in this case,
the bank) not because of any special concern for the corporation’s inter-
ests, or because of a judgment that the regulation was especially burden-
some to those interests, but because of a concern for the wider public in-
terest in informed decision making. The essential idea is captured in a
paraphrase of Mill’s reason for thinking that it is as bad to silence one as
to silence all: “Were an opinion a personal possession of no value except
to the owner; if to be obstructed in the enjoyment of it were simply a pri-
vate injury, it would make some difference who the injury was inflicted
upon. But the peculiar evil of silencing the expression of an opinion is,
32. First National Bank v. Bellotti, 435 U.S. 765, 767 (1978).
33. Ibid., 777.
289
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
290
M O N E Y, P O L I T I C S , P O L I T I C A L E Q U A L I T Y
37. Citizens Against Rent Control v. City of Berkeley, 454 U.S. 290 (1981).
38. Colorado Republican Federal Campaign Committee v. FEC.
39. FEC v. NCPAC, 470 U.S. 480 (1985) (overturning limits on independent expenditures
on behalf of Presidential candidates who have accepted public funding).
291
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
40. Day v. Holahan, 34 F.3d 1356 (8th Cir. 1994), cert. denied, 513 U.S. 1127 (1995).
41. Rosensteil v. Rodriguez, 101 F.3d 1544 (8th Cir. 1996), cert. denied, 520 U.S. 1229 (1997).
Also, Gable v. Patton, 142 F.3d 940 (6th Cir. 1998).
42. Daggett v. Webster, 74 F. Supp. 2d 53 (D. Me. 1999).
292
M O N E Y, P O L I T I C S , P O L I T I C A L E Q U A L I T Y
43. Deborah Goldberg, ed., Writing Reform: A Guide to Drafting State and Local Cam-
paign Finance Laws (New York: Brennan Center for Justice, 1998), 1–7. The only evidence
cited for the proposition quoted in the text is the infamous line in Buckley about the im-
permissibility of “restricting the speech of some elements of our society in order to enhance
the relative voice of others.” But the passage is specifically about restricting speech, not about
the legitimacy of the interest in ensuring equal opportunity for political influence.
44. Bruce Ackerman’s voucher scheme is so accompanied: it excludes real money and per-
mits only voucher-based expenditures. See Bruce Ackerman, “The Patriot Option,” in Joshua
Cohen and Joel Rogers, eds., Money and Politics: Financing Elections Democratically (Boston:
Beacon Press, 1999).
293
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
294
M O N E Y, P O L I T I C S , P O L I T I C A L E Q U A L I T Y
295
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
296
M O N E Y, P O L I T I C S , P O L I T I C A L E Q U A L I T Y
297
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
functioning democracy.”49 The critic I have described here turns that ar-
gument around. This critic accepts the overriding interest in a well-func-
tioning democracy but argues that a “well-functioning democracy,” prop-
erly conceived, does not permit regulation of speech in the name of
equal opportunity for political influence. The critic who endorses the in-
trinsic argument does not say: “Yes, the current regime of campaign
finance injures democracy, but this injury is justified by the need to en-
sure that citizens can freely use their private property” (though, of course,
some critics may say that). Instead, the argument is that the value of de-
mocracy itself condemns regulation, because of the conception of re-
sponsibility ingredient in the best conception of democracy. The dis-
sent in Nixon v. Shrink suggests just this point: “The right to free speech
is a right held by each American, not by Americans en masse. The Court
in Buckley provided no basis for suppressing the speech of an individ-
ual candidate simply because other candidates (or candidates in the ag-
gregate) may succeed in reaching the voting public. Any such reasoning
would fly in the face of the premise of our political system—liberty
vested in individual hands safeguards the functioning of our democ-
racy.”50
Observing the earlier discussion of equal opportunity for influence, the
critic argues that a plausible principle of political equality, suited to a po-
litical society of free and equal persons, needs to include some account of
individual political responsibility. So the argument might be put this
way: the principle of political equality includes a right of free political
speech and an associated idea of political responsibility, implicit in its
hostility to content and viewpoint regulation and the distinction between
equalizing opportunity for influence and equalizing influence itself.
That’s part of what is involved in treating democratic citizens as free. But
once we embrace this notion of political responsibility, we must accept,
too, that collective regulation of the quantity of speech is incompatible
with democracy.
Though forceful, this argument is doubly deficient. First, it miscon-
ceives the case for regulation by representing it as dependent on a judg-
ment about who is entitled to decide whether the quantity and the kind
of information are sufficient. The argument for regulation based on the
principle of equal opportunity for influence is not of this kind. Though it
49. Kathleen M. Sullivan, “Political Money and Freedom of Speech,” 671.
50. Slip op., 17.
298
M O N E Y, P O L I T I C S , P O L I T I C A L E Q U A L I T Y
51. For a parallel discussion, see Ronald Dworkin, “The Curse of American Politics,” New
York Review of Books 17 (October 1996): 19–24. Dworkin emphasizes the dual role of citizens, as
judges of electoral contests and as participants in those contests.
52. See Samuel Popkin’s The Reasoning Voter, on the acquisition of information through in-
formal discussion.
53. See my discussion of the deliberative and expressive interests, in “Freedom of Expres-
sion,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 22, 3 (summer 1993), 224–229 [reprinted as essay 4 in this
collection].
299
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
300
M O N E Y, P O L I T I C S , P O L I T I C A L E Q U A L I T Y
301
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
8. Conclusion
A fundamental proposition of democratic thought is that our collective
decisions should reflect our judgments (the judgments of individual citi-
zens), formed through open processes of communication, unconstrained
by collective judgments about what and how much we should hear. But
this important principle must not lead to the undemocratic proposition
that citizens are equals only when we sit in the audience, listening to
what others say, and unequals when we take to the political stage. The
principle of political equality requires that we accommodate the interests
of citizens as audience and actor. We need to preserve a system of open
political communication that enables citizens to exercise their delibera-
tive responsibilities by forming their views against a background of ade-
quate information and rich debate and also that ensures equal access to
the public arena: we should not organize the political arena as a system
of unequal opportunities. Designing a regulatory scheme that promises
both will be hard: we need some experimentation. But we do not solve
the conundrum by throwing out half the democratic ideal.
56. I should add that it is very much consonant with the view suggested in the concurrence
by Justice Breyer in Nixon v. Shrink, which states that contribution limits are based on the
“need for democratization” and not simply on the concerns about quid pro quo corruption.
Slip op., 10.
302
9
P R I VA C Y, P L U R A L I S M , A N D D E M O C R A C Y
I presented earlier versions of this essay at a meeting of the Eastern Division of the Ameri-
can Philosophical Association, at the Universidad Torcuato di Tella, at the University of Geor-
gia, at the Graduate Center, City University, at the Inland Northwest Philosophy Conference,
and as a Donald Kalish Memorial Lecture at UCLA. I am indebted to Martha Nussbaum, Ju-
dith Thomson, Frances Kamm, David Estlund, Eduardo Rivera-López, Andrew Sabl, Seana
Shiffrin, and Erik Olin Wright for their helpful comments on earlier versions. I would like to
think that my friend Don Kalish would have endorsed the combination of privacy rights and
cultural democracy that I endorse here.
1. John Rawls, “The Idea of Public Reason Revisited,” University of Chicago Law Review 64
(1997): 791, 769.
303
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
2. Cited in Seyla Benhabib, “The Personal is not the Political,” Boston Review 24 (1999): 45.
3. Thomas Nagel, “Concealment and Exposure,” in Concealment and Exposure and Other
Essays (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002), 3.
304
P R I V A C Y, P L U R A L I S M , A N D D E M O C R A C Y
Deliberative Democracy
1. The deliberative-democratic idea is that authoritative collective deci-
sions should issue from public reasoning among equals.4 Three ideas
play a central role in this conception:
1. The fact of reasonable pluralism, according to which citizens en-
dorse a plurality of politically reasonable philosophies of life;
2. The requirement of deliberation, which states that the justification
4. The discussion that follows draws on Joshua Cohen, “Democracy and Liberty,” in Jon
Elster, ed., Deliberative Democracy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998) [reprinted
as essay 7 in this collection].
305
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
of human beings in the world: it does not say that the truth in these mat-
ters is unknowable, or that there is no truth, or that the truth varies across
persons, or cultures, or places; nor does it deny any of these views. Cer-
tainly, people who hold different outlooks think of their views as true:
they believe them, and believing is believing true. The fact of reasonable
pluralism does not conflict with what they believe but says that the truth
in such matters, if there be such, transcends the exercise of practical rea-
son that we can appropriately expect of others, as equals in the political so-
ciety. So it affirms a kind of toleration of reasonable differences in ulti-
mate outlook. As the italicized formulation indicates, when we assert the
fact of reasonable pluralism, we are already operating within the domain
of political argument. We are not relying on a philosophical theory about
the scope and competence of reason that provides common ground for
different outlooks: the nature and competence of reason, both theoretical
and practical, is one matter on which such outlooks disagree. Instead, we
are making a point about what we can appropriately expect of others, as
free and equal.
A crucial point for the issue of privacy is that liberalism itself is both a
political outlook and a philosophy of life.5 As a philosophy of life, liberal-
ism emphasizes the importance of autonomous choice—of reflective
self-direction—as a guide to conduct. As a political outlook, liberalism is
committed, inter alia, to securing basic personal and political liberties
through a system of rights, whose precise content is a matter of contro-
versy. One such controversy is about the scope and content of privacy
rights, and about whether such rights depend on a liberal philosophy of
life. I believe that they do not, for reasons I will discuss later.
Second, the deliberative conception of democracy puts public reason-
ing at the center of political justification, which I understand as the jus-
tification of coercively enforced regulations. To clarify, let’s distinguish
two conceptions of democracy, aggregative and deliberative. The basic
distinction lies in their interpretations of the fundamental idea of a dem-
ocratic society as a society of equals, and thus of a collective decision
made or authorized by citizens as equals. Both views apply in the first in-
5. A central point of Rawls’s political liberalism is to show that liberalism as a political con-
ception does not depend on liberalism as a broader philosophy of life, with a distinctive moral,
metaphysical, and epistemological outlook. See John Rawls, Justice as Fairness: A Restatement,
ed. Erin Kelly (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2001). For the alternative view, see
Roberto Unger, Knowledge and Politics (New York: Free Press, 1974); and Michael Sandel,
Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982).
307
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
6. See, for example, the discussion of intrinsic equality and equal consideration in Thomas
Christiano, The Rule of the Many (Boulder: Westview, 1996); and Robert Dahl, Democracy
and Its Critics (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1989), 85, 87. Also, conditions imposed on
social choice functions—in particular, anonymity and independence—are sometimes moti-
vated in ways that suggest an identification of the requirement that people be treated as equals
with the requirement that interests be given equal consideration. See William Riker, Liberal-
ism Against Populism: A Confrontation Between the Theory of Democracy and the Theory of So-
cial Choice (San Francisco: W.H. Freeman, 1982).
7. Rawls suggests that we model the political relation by thinking of it as a relation in a
“structure we enter only by birth and exit only by death.” See Rawls, “The Idea of Public Rea-
son Revisited,” 769. To be sure, this modeling assumption is not literally true, but it captures
the idea that political decisions are binding on citizens, and that they cannot be made compati-
ble with the freedom of citizens simply by establishing a right to emigrate.
308
P R I V A C Y, P L U R A L I S M , A N D D E M O C R A C Y
Privacy Rights
1. Thus far I have sketched a general framework of ideas about democ-
racy and indicated how at least some personal liberties might be under-
stood to have a constitutive place in democracy’s public reason. Under
conditions of moral pluralism, the collective authorization that lies at the
heart of democracy has limited scope.
What, then, about the right of privacy—in particular, a right to per-
sonal independence in areas of life, death, and sex? Can it be defended
without appealing to a liberal philosophy of life? Skepticism in American
constitutional argument about a capacious right to privacy derives in part
from the concern that such a right does depend on a liberal philosophy of
life. In particular, constitutional theorists who interpret the constitution
as fundamentally a design of democracy, whether aggregative or deliber-
ative, have typically been skeptical about a constitutional privacy right, in
311
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
8. See John Ely, Democracy and Distrust (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1980);
and Cass Sunstein, One Case at a Time (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), esp.
250–252.
9. Roe v. Whalen, 429 U.S. 589, 599–600 (1977).
10. If having an abortion, for example, meant that your name appeared in the newspaper,
then the decision about whether to have one would to that extent be less independent.
11. See the quote from Rawls about the public-private distinction at the start of the essay.
312
P R I V A C Y, P L U R A L I S M , A N D D E M O C R A C Y
constitutional privacy right and that have been at the center of the debate
about that right in the United States. I will be very brief on these extraor-
dinarily complex issues, because I mean to be illustrating the framework
rather than saying anything very distinctive about the issues themselves.
Thus, in the case of abortion, three considerations suggest the conclu-
sion that restrictive regulations are especially burdensome. First, there is
the burden on women’s equality if women are required to carry un-
wanted pregnancies to term. This point is acknowledged in the Supreme
Court’s 1992 Casey decision, with reference to the consequences of a
twenty-year adjustment to the Roe regime—“The ability of women to
participate equally in the economic and social life of the nation has been
facilitated by their ability to control their reproductive lives”12—but the
same point could have been made without the reference to issues of ad-
justment to Roe v. Wade.
Second, restrictive regulations burden women’s liberty, by restricting
choices of a deeply personal kind, thus impinging on a woman’s exercise
of personal responsibility about the course of her life. They represent a
substantial denial of judgment about the conduct of elementary aspects
of life. There is of course an equality aspect to the issue here, inasmuch
as no comparable denial is contemplated for men. But the relevant bur-
den would not be alleviated by generalizing it.
A third burden—the burden on judgment—results from the kinds of
reasons that commonly support decisions about continuing life and is es-
pecially pertinent here. In its Casey decision, the U.S. Supreme Court
says that “at the heart of liberty is the right to define one’s own concept of
existence, of meaning, of the universe, and of the mystery of human
life,”13 and it supposes that women take guidance from such judgments
314
P R I V A C Y, P L U R A L I S M , A N D D E M O C R A C Y
associated. But it is not clear why the effort to draw such distinctions is bound to undermine
the rule of law, except of course if the rule of law means a law of rigid rules. See Antonin
Scalia, “The Rule of Law as a Law of Rules,” University of Chicago Law Review 56 (1989): 1175–
1188.
14. Ronald Dworkin, Life’s Dominion (New York: Knopf, 1993), 91.
15. See Pope John Paul II, The Gospel of Life [Evangelium Vitae] (New York: Random
House, 1995).
315
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
strictively regulated, the side that favors restrictive regulation wins. If they
are not, then the side that has a liberal view wins. So yes, some people do
reject the justification for regulation: and let’s say that they are politically
reasonable. But why should their objections carry the day? After all, some
people reject the current settlement, which permits abortion. Why do
their objections to a permissive regulatory regime not carry as much
weight as the objections to a restrictive regime?
This alleged symmetry is illusory. The restrictive regime imposes un-
deniably substantial burdens on women’s liberty, equality, and indepen-
dence of judgment; in a society of equals, those burdens need to be justi-
fied, and the terms of that justification must carry some weight with those
whose liberty and equality are impaired. Otherwise, we fail to respect
them as equals. The restrictive regime cannot stand, then, because no
such acceptable justification is available.
The case for a right to die, understood as comprising a right to assisted
suicide, is importantly different. To be sure, there is a compelling case for
the conclusion that regulations of assisted suicide are burdensome: like
restrictive abortion regulations, they regulate conduct governed by judg-
ments about when we have compelling reason to ensure the continua-
tion of life. The considerations that support regulations in this area are,
however, of a different kind. In particular, the defense of such regulation
should appeal not to a conception of when life ends or what makes a
whole life (or parts of it) worth living but to concerns about when we
have a conclusive showing of a person’s willing decision to end her own
life, and worries about pressures to make that decision as a way to reduce
burdens on family and friends. A compelling case for the conclusion that
these decisions about death should be treated as private matters would
need to address these concerns. Absent such address, it is not unreason-
able for a democratic process to regulate, and thus to hold that the inter-
est in independent judgment, although present and substantial, is over-
ridden (though it would also be reasonable to have a more permissive
regime).
In the case of sexual intimacy, there is a strong case for concluding
that democracy’s public reason must treat it as a private matter—an arena
to be regulated by the independent and diverse judgments of individu-
als. On the one hand the reasons for regulation—a religiously founded
moral outlook—are arguably weightless because they are objectionably
316
P R I V A C Y, P L U R A L I S M , A N D D E M O C R A C Y
Conventions
1. I turn now to the second privacy issue: the social conventions that mark
the boundaries between the public and the private. This is a sprawling
territory, and to narrow it I will focus here on a discussion of these issues
by Thomas Nagel. According to Nagel, we ought to embrace strong
16. The majority opinion in Lawrence v. Texas notes that the moral reasons that support reg-
ulation have, among other things, a religious background (they are “shaped by religious be-
liefs, conceptions of right and acceptable behavior, and respect for the traditional family”), and
asserts their weightlessness, though the weightlessness does not turn on their provenance in re-
ligious morality.
17. Bowers v. Hardwick, 478 U.S. 186 (1986).
18. The majority in Lawrence v. Texas cites Casey’s “sweet-mystery-of-life” passage in ex-
plaining the importance of the conduct regulated by restrictions on sexual intimacy. Auton-
omy in intimate conduct is important because such conduct is tied to independent self-defini-
tion.
19. The issue of gay and lesbian marriage raises questions that extend beyond my concerns
here, though the considerations I have presented bear on the issue in three ways, which I
will simply mention. First, the regulated conduct is supported by important reasons. Second,
some of the considerations appealed to in arguments against legal status are weightless: for
example, the argument in the Vatican’s “Considerations Regarding Proposals to Give Legal
Recognition to Unions Between Homosexual Persons” that “marriage is holy, while homo-
sexual acts go against the natural moral law.” Third, although arguments about the “best inter-
ests of the child” (also in the Vatican statement) are certainly not weightless, they need to be
made in a sufficiently compelling way, given the importance of the regulated conduct. The
statement is available at http://www.vatican.va/roman_curia/congregations/cfaith/documents/
rc_con_cfaith_doc_20030731_homosexual-unions_en.html.
317
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
318
P R I V A C Y, P L U R A L I S M , A N D D E M O C R A C Y
320
P R I V A C Y, P L U R A L I S M , A N D D E M O C R A C Y
26. On the duty of civility, see John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia Uni-
versity Press, 1996), 216; and John Rawls, “The Idea of Public Reason Revisited,” 768–769.
27. Rawls, “The Idea of Public Reason Revisited,” 793.
321
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
sions that are made in the name of all: the majority is the tribune of the
people. But the fact that laws are made in the name of all, in the name of
citizens as equals, naturally suggests that they ought to be justifiable—
and be shown to be justifiable—by reference to values that all can rea-
sonably accept, and that they should provide for everyone a secure place
in the debate: this, as I indicated earlier, is the deliberative interpretation
of the idea that democratic decisions should be suitably collective. When
the supreme political authority speaks in a democracy, it ought to be
manifest that it speaks in the name of equal citizens. In the informal pub-
lic culture, we find no such corresponding authoritative statement of a
conclusion: “cultural democracy” names a social practice of argument
among equals, not a form of authority. With no agent authorized to speak
for all, there is no corresponding case for restraint in the terms of debate.
Second, collective decisions apply to all and are backed by the collec-
tive power of the state. If we wish to reconcile this coercive imposition of
regulation with the recognition of citizens as politically autonomous self-
legislators, then the best we can hope for is that the justification of basic
laws and policies rests on political values that can be shared. But, once
more, there is no comparable coercive imposition in the case of the pub-
lic culture, and so no comparable requirement of restraint.
I have said that cultural democracy is not a form of authority, and that
it does not involve a coercive imposition of constraints comparable to the
formal political system. I do not, however, wish to deny that cultural de-
mocracy is a form of power or to deny that cultural norms constrain con-
duct. To the contrary. Equal standing in the system of cultural democ-
racy is important in part because of the importance of the common
environment of cultural norms and standards of taste and value: we do
not want to leave these matters in the hands of others, even if we can
count on an exercise of collective political authority that is governed by
democracy’s public reason. For we may still find the public culture and
the constraints it fosters deeply uncongenial. Thus Scanlon says: “I have
no desire to dictate what others, individually, in couples or in groups, do
in their bedrooms, but I would prefer to live in a society in which sexual-
ity and sexual attractiveness, of whatever kind, was given less importance
than it is in our society today.” Or again, “What I fear is not merely the le-
gal enforcement of religion but its social predominance.”28 In both cases,
28. Thomas Scanlon, “The Difficulty of Tolerance” in David Heyd, ed., Toleration: An Elu-
sive Virtue (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996), 30.
322
P R I V A C Y, P L U R A L I S M , A N D D E M O C R A C Y
29. On this point, see my discussion of the distinction between equal opportunity for elec-
toral, political, and public influence in “Money, Politics, Political Equality,” in Fact and Value,
ed. Alex Byrne, Robert Stalnaker, and Ralph Wedgwood (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2001),
153–157.
323
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
the complaint, even if presented not with the aim of enlightenment but
simply as a way of expressing a hostile attitude toward a social practice,
perhaps with the suggestion that the speaker’s finding the practice to be
objectionable suffices to condemn it. The speaker need not expect a col-
lective response nor act in the hope of prompting agreement, but instead
may be seen as providing information about how a feature of the culture
is not universally appreciated.
By fundamental criticism, I mean an explicit attack on the moral, reli-
gious, or philosophical foundations of someone’s political outlook—pre-
cisely the kind of thing that violates the duty of civility when it happens
in political discourse. But there are three reasons for pursuing fundamen-
tal criticism rather than adopting a general policy of reticence as a re-
sponse to fundamental disagreements.
The first reason is, once more, simply informational: I may want to let
my opponents know that others who share the public culture with them
find their public displays of religiosity creepy, or find their views false or
childish.
Second, I may entertain the more ambitious thought that an awareness
of deeper and persisting disagreements will result in some modification
of opposing views, particularly if fundamental criticism is coupled with
the political respect reflected in the duty of civility. This point has partic-
ular force when there are political disagreements that we think are proba-
bly rooted in deeper religious or moral disagreements: certainly true in
issues about sexuality, life, and death that provided the focus of my dis-
cussion of privacy rights. If a duty of civility restrains us from pursuing
these disagreements in the political arena, it will be important that there
be a setting in which they can be openly aired. Here I offer a speculation
about the cultural basis of political democracy: namely, that we are more
inclined to keep political deliberation within the confines of democracy’s
public reason and to respect the duty of civility if we think that opponents
have been subjected to more open-ended pressure elsewhere. A vibrant
cultural democracy may be both supportive of a liberal political democ-
racy and philosophically consistent with it.
Third and finally, I may think that the public culture itself is now one-
sided: that it is far easier to express conventional religious sentiment or
to deploy conventional religious symbols than to express skeptical or hos-
tile views about religion, or to embrace unconventional religious views.
Think again of Scanlon’s examples. Believing that the public culture is
324
P R I V A C Y, P L U R A L I S M , A N D D E M O C R A C Y
325
10
R E F L E C T I O N S O N D E L I B E R AT I V E D E M O C R A C Y
1. Introduction
For more than two decades, egalitarian-democrats have sought to de-
scribe a “post-socialist” political project. The socialist project, including
its social democratic variant, comprised a set of political values and an in-
stitutional and political strategy for advancing those values. The values
were egalitarian and participatory. The institutional models and the po-
litical strategy focused on the state.
Contemporary debate among egalitarian-democrats begins in the con-
viction that this approach is misguided and moves along two paths.
The first, growing out of appreciation of the state’s limits as an eco-
nomic manager is sometimes called “asset-egalitarianism.” The idea is to
shift the distribution of income by changing the distribution of income-
generating assets. It is an important idea, particularly with pressures from
globalization on income security, but not my topic here.1
A second—and this will provide my focus here—is more political.
Building on what I will describe as “radical-democratic” ideas, it seeks to
construct models of political decision in which “local” players can be in-
volved more directly in regulation and in collective problem solving,
with a center that coordinates local efforts, rather than dictating the terms
of those efforts. Thus, local—or, more exactly, lower-level actors (nation-
states or national peak organizations of various kinds; regions, provinces,
I presented earlier versions of this essay at the University of Southern California Law School
and as a keynote address at a Princeton University conference on deliberative democracy. I am
grateful to the audiences on both occasions for their comments and criticisms.
1. For representative ideas, see John Roemer, Equal Shares: Making Market Socialism Work
(New York: Verso, 1996); Samuel Bowles and Herbert Gintis, Recasting Egalitarianism: New
Rules for Communities, States and Markets (New York: Verso, 1999); Stuart White, The Civic
Minimum (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003); Bruce Ackerman and Anne Alstott, The
Stakeholder Society (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2000); Richard Freeman, The New In-
equality (Boston: Beacon Press, 1998).
326
R E F L E C T I O N S O N D E L I B E R A T I V E D E M O C R A C Y
2. I have written elsewhere on this radical-democratic project: with Joel Rogers (on associa-
tive democracy), Chuck Sabel (on deliberative polyarchy), and Archon Fung (on participation
and deliberation). In writing this essay, I have drawn freely on this joint work, and I am very
grateful to my co-authors for the collaborations that produced it. See Joshua Cohen and Joel
Rogers, Associations and Democracy (London: Verso, 1995); Joshua Cohen and Charles Sabel,
“Directly-Deliberative Polyarchy,” European Law Journal, vol. 3, no. 4 (December 1997): 313–
342 [reprinted as essay 6 in this collection]; Joshua Cohen and Joel Rogers, “Power and Rea-
son,” in Archon Fung and Erik Olin Wright, eds., Deepening Democracy: Institutional Innova-
tions in Empowered Participatory Governance (New York: Verso, 2003); Joshua Cohen and
Charles Sabel, “Global Democracy?,” New York University Journal of International Law and
Policy 37, 4 (2006): 763–797; Joshua Cohen and Archon Fung, “Radical Democracy,” Swiss
Journal of Political Science 10, 4 (2004).
3. Rousseau himself explored other forms of democratic participation, particularly in his
Constitution of Poland, where considerations of size precluded direct citizen participation in
lawmaking.
327
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
engage with the substance of law and policy and not simply delegate re-
sponsibility for such substantive engagement to representatives.
Along with participation, radical democrats emphasize deliberation. In-
stead of a politics of power and interest, radical democrats favor a deliber-
ative democracy in which citizens address public problems by reasoning
together about how best to solve them—in which, at the limit, no force is
at work, as Jürgen Habermas said, “except that of the better argument.”4
According to the deliberative interpretation, democracy is a political ar-
rangement that ties the exercise of collective power to reason-giving
among those subject to collective decisions. Once more, we see substan-
tial differences among different formulations of the deliberative-demo-
cratic ideal. Some see deliberative democracy as a matter of forming a
public opinion through dispersed and open public discussion and trans-
lating such opinion into legitimate law; others as a way to ensure that
elections—or legislative debates, or perhaps discussions within courts or
agencies—are themselves infused with information and reasoning; others
as a way to bring reasoning by citizens directly to bear on addressing regu-
latory issues. But in all cases, the large aim of a deliberative democracy is
to shift from bargaining, interest aggregation, and power to the common
reason of equal citizens—democracy’s public reason—as a guiding force
in democratic life.5
In this essay, I will explore these two distinct strands of the radical-dem-
ocratic project—participatory and deliberative—though I will focus on
the deliberative because that is the topic here. My central point is that
participation and deliberation are both important, but different, and they
are important for different reasons. Moreover, it is hard to achieve both,
but the project of advancing both is coherent, attractive, and worth our
attention. I begin by presenting an idea of deliberative democracy. Sec-
4. Jürgen Habermas, Legitimation Crisis, trans. Thomas McCarthy (Boston: Beacon Press,
1973), 108. In this passage, Habermas is not describing an idealized democracy but a hypotheti-
cal situation suited to the justification of norms.
5. We now have many statements of the deliberative conception. For my own, which I draw
on here, see Joshua Cohen, “Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy,” Alan Hamlin and
Phillip Petit, eds., The Good Polity (Oxford: Blackwell, 1989); “Procedure and Substance in
Deliberative Democracy,” in Democracy and Difference: Changing Boundaries of the Political,
ed. Seyla Benhabib (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996); “Democracy and Liberty,”
in Jon Elster, ed., Deliberative Democracy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998);
and “Privacy, Pluralism, and Democracy,” Law and Social Justice, eds. Joseph Keim Camp-
bell, Michael O’Rourke, and David Shier. (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2005). [All these es-
says are reprinted here.]
328
R E F L E C T I O N S O N D E L I B E R A T I V E D E M O C R A C Y
2. Deliberation
Carl Schmitt said that deliberation belongs to the world of the par-
liament, where legislators reason together about how to address public
problems. It does not belong to the world of mass democracy, where
ethno-culturally homogeneous peoples find leaders who pick the peo-
ple’s friends and enemies. According to Schmitt, “The development of
modern mass democracy has made argumentative public discussion an
empty formality.”6 Rejecting Schmitt’s view, as well as its more benign
contemporary progeny, deliberative democrats explore possibilities of
combining deliberation with mass democracy. And not just explore: we
are hopeful about the possibilities of fostering a more deliberative de-
mocracy.
Deliberation, generically understood, is about weighing the reasons
relevant to a decision with a view to making a decision on the basis of
that weighing. So an individual can make decisions deliberatively, a jury
has a responsibility to deliberate, and a committee of oligarchs can delib-
erate: deliberation, in short, is not intrinsically democratic. The “democ-
racy” in “deliberative democracy” is not pleonastic.
Democracy is a way of making collective decisions that connects deci-
sions to the interests and the judgments of those whose conduct is to be
regulated by the decisions. The essential idea is that those governed by
the decisions are treated as equals by the processes of making the deci-
sions. Democracy, as Tocqueville emphasized, is also a kind of society—a
society of equals—but I will be confining myself as a general matter to
the more specifically political understanding of democracy. Of course,
even if we think of democracy politically, as a way to make binding col-
lective decisions, constructing a more deliberative democracy is not a
narrowly political project: deliberative democracy requires attention to
encouraging deliberative capacities, which is, inter alia, a matter of edu-
6. Carl Schmitt, The Crisis of Parliamentary Democracy, trans. Ellen Kennedy (Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press, 1985), 6.
329
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
7. In Is Democracy Possible Here? (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2006), Ron-
ald Dworkin emphasizes the importance of education in a well-functioning, deliberative de-
mocracy, and he asserts that “the most daunting but also most urgent requirement is to make a
Contemporary Politics course part of every high school curriculum” (148). The idea of such a
course is sensible enough, but it hardly seems the most urgent issue about the reform of our
educational system, for the purposes of fostering the partnership in argument that is so central
to democracy.
330
R E F L E C T I O N S O N D E L I B E R A T I V E D E M O C R A C Y
331
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
counted, they may still accept the idea of arriving at a collective judg-
ment based on considerations that others acknowledge as reasons. They
may, for example, believe that reason-giving is an important expression of
respect or that it is the right way to acknowledge the collective nature of
the decision. If they do, they will be willing to deliberate in the stages
leading up to the vote, even when they know a vote is coming.
Deliberative democracy, thus understood, is a distinctive interpretation
of democracy: democracy, no matter how fair, no matter how informed,
no matter how participatory, is not deliberative unless reasoning is central
to the process of collective decision-making. Nor is democracy delibera-
tive simply because the process and its results are reasonable: capable of
being given a rational defense, even a rational defense that would be rec-
ognized as such on reflection by those subject to the decisions. The con-
cern for reasonableness must play a role in the process. Thus the contrast
between deliberative and aggregative democracy. In an aggregative de-
mocracy, citizens aim to advance their individual and group interests. If
the process is fair, the results may well be reasonable. But unless the rea-
sonableness is aimed at by participants in the process, we do not have de-
liberation.
Of course, it might be argued that reasonable results must be aimed at
to be achieved and that democracy must therefore be deliberative to be
reasonable. So, for example, if we have a hypothetical test for the right-
ness of decisions, where the hypothetical process involves reasoning un-
der idealized conditions about what is best to do, then it might be said
that the actual process must look something like the hypothetical to pro-
vide a basis for confidence in the rightness of results.10 Still, it is best to
see this connection between reasonableness and deliberation as a broadly
empirical claim and to keep deliberation as a way of deciding—a way
that comprises both the nature of the process and the content of the rea-
sons—distinct from reasonableness as a property of decisions.
Aggregative and deliberative democracy do not exhaust the space of in-
terpretations of democracy. Consider a community of politically princi-
pled citizens, each of whom endorses a conception of justice. The con-
ceptions they endorse differ, but each person accepts some conception as
setting bounds on acceptable policy and decent institutions. Assume fur-
ther that they do not see much point in arguing about what justice re-
10. See, for example, Jürgen Habermas, Between Facts and Norms, trans. William Rehg
(Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996), 296, 304.
332
R E F L E C T I O N S O N D E L I B E R A T I V E D E M O C R A C Y
333
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
334
R E F L E C T I O N S O N D E L I B E R A T I V E D E M O C R A C Y
17. I believe that Lynn Sanders was the first to raise this objection, in “Against Delibera-
tion,” Political Theory (1997): 347–376.
18. Archon Fung, Empowered Participation: Reinventing Urban Democracy (Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 2004), chap. 4.
336
R E F L E C T I O N S O N D E L I B E R A T I V E D E M O C R A C Y
ing in Porto Alegre, Abers and Baiocchi find high rates of involvement by
poorer, less-educated citizens and discover substantial rates of participa-
tion by women and Afro-Brazilians.19 The thread running through these
and related cases is that participation is not exogenously given. Delibera-
tive bodies can undertake affirmative measures to address participatory
biases. In particular, they can help to train participants in the issues de-
cided by the body and in how to frame arguments about the relevant pol-
icies.
Now it might be argued that in the favorable cases just noted, the de-
liberative bodies aim to solve relatively concrete problems—to improve
policy in relatively well-defined areas (say, pertaining to the provision
of local public goods)—not to have an open-ended public debate. In-
equalities of argumentative skills on broader matters may resist remedy.20
But evidence from deliberative polling suggests otherwise: deliberative
capacities seem reasonably widely shared, even when issues are more ab-
stract and less locally focused. Critics of deliberation, it seems, were too
quick to conclude that deliberative decision-making empowers the ver-
bally agile.
2. A second objection is about effectiveness. Thus it might be said that
a deliberative process does not mitigate the effects of power on outcomes
of collective decisions. In addressing this issue, we face a large method-
ological problem. As a general matter, and putting aside the issue of de-
liberative democracy, it is hard to make an empirically compelling case
that process changes produce outcome changes, because changes in pro-
cess and in result may well both be produced by some third factor: as, for
example, when a party with a redistributive project empowers the less ad-
vantaged and promotes a shift in economic resources as well, thus sug-
gesting (incorrectly) that the change in process produced the change in
result.
A few studies, though not of deliberative democracy, have forcefully
addressed these problems of spuriousness. Ansolabehere, Gerber, and
Snyder have shown that court-ordered reapportionment in the 1960s
19. See Rebecca Abers, “Reflections on What Makes Empowered Participatory Governance
Happen,” in Fung and Wright, Deepening Democracy, 206, and more generally her Inventing
Local Democracy (Boulder, CO: Lynne Riener, 2000); Gianpaolo Baiocchi, Militants and Cit-
izens: The Politics of Participatory Democracy in Porto Alegre (Stanford: Stanford University
Press, 2005).
20. In his critique of deliberative democracy, Richard Posner is less hostile to locally focused
discussion about the provision of public goods, perhaps for reasons of the kind noted in the
text. See Law, Pragmatism, and Democracy (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003).
337
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
338
R E F L E C T I O N S O N D E L I B E R A T I V E D E M O C R A C Y
25. Cass Sunstein, “Group Judgments: Statistical Means, Deliberation, and Information
Markets,” NYU Law Review 80 (June 2005): 962–1049; and Tali Mendelberg’s very instructive
discussion of deliberation and small-group decision-making, in “The Deliberative Citizen:
Theory and Evidence,” in Political Decision-Making, Deliberation, and Participation: Research
in Micropolitics, vol. 6, ed. Michael X. Delli Carpini, Leonie Huddy, and Robert Shapiro
(Greenwich, CT: JAI Press, 2002), pp. 151–193.
26. See Cohen and Rogers, “Power and Reason.”
339
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
ations that are arguably reasons. For example, they may make appeals to
ideas of the common advantage but press a conception of the common
advantage that assigns great weight to a deeply unequal status quo. Or if
they fail in this, the advantaged will simply refuse to accept the discipline
of deliberation.
If this objection is right, then proposals for deliberative democracy that
are inattentive to background relations of power will waste the time of
those who can least afford its loss: those now subordinate in power. The
time and energy they spend in argument, laboring under the illusion that
sweet reason will constrain the power that suppresses them, could have
been spent in self-organization, instrumental efforts to increase their own
power, or like efforts to impose costs on opponents.
The complaint that deliberative democracy is touchingly naïve about
power betrays vertiginously boundless confusion.
First, the importance of background differences in power is not a criti-
cism of the deliberative ideal per se, but a concern about its application.
Deliberative democracy is a normative model of collective decision-
making, not a universal political strategy. And commitment to the nor-
mative ideal does not require commitment to the belief that collective
decision-making through mutual reason-giving is always possible. So it
may indeed be the case that some rough background balance of power is
required before parties will listen to reason. But observing that does not
importantly lessen the attraction of the deliberative ideal; it simply states
a condition of its reasonable pursuit.
Thus, in Habermas’s account of the ideal speech situation, or in my
own account of an ideal deliberative procedure, inequalities in power
are stipulated away for the sake of presenting an idealized model of delib-
eration.27 These idealizations are intended to characterize the nature of
reasoned collective decision-making and, in turn, to provide models for
actual arrangements of collective decision-making. But actual arrange-
ments must provide some basis for confidence that joint reasoning will
actually prevail in shaping the exercise of collective power, and gross in-
equalities of power surely undermine any such confidence. So discussion
that expresses the deliberative ideal must, for example, operate against a
background of free expression and association, thus providing minimal
conditions for the availability of relevant information. Equally, if parties
27. See Cohen, “Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy,” and Habermas, Between Facts
and Norms, chap. 7.
340
R E F L E C T I O N S O N D E L I B E R A T I V E D E M O C R A C Y
28. Diana Mutz explores a different tension between deliberation and participation in her
important book, Hearing the Other Side: Deliberative Versus Participatory Democracy (Cam-
bridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006). Mutz argues that deliberation among the diverse
encourages greater toleration but dampens participation because of a desire to avoid conflict
with the people to whom one talks. Participation, in turn, is animated by a sense of passion that
is dampened by deliberation. I am not sure that Mutz’s results extend outside participation in
highly competitive political settings. But the challenge she raises is deep and needs to be ad-
dressed.
29. See, for example, Derek Bell, “The Referendum: Democracy’s Barrier to Racial Equal-
ity,” Washington Law Review 54, 1 (1978): 1–29; Yannis Papadopolous, “A Framework for Analy-
sis of Functions and Dysfunctions of Direct Democracy: Top-Down and Bottom-Up Perspec-
tives,” Politics and Society 23 (1995): 421–448.
342
R E F L E C T I O N S O N D E L I B E R A T I V E D E M O C R A C Y
relatively small, and so the quality of deliberation will decline with the
scope of participation. Of course, knowledge and interest are not fixed,
and deliberation may improve both. Still, time and resource constraints
make it undesirable for any particular area of public governance to be
both fully deliberative and inclusively participatory.
6. And So?
These three tensions notwithstanding, public decision-making in liberal
democracies could become both more participatory and deliberative.
The challenge is to devise practical projects that can incorporate both.
Radical democrats have two broad strategies for achieving that aim,
which I will sketch in very broad strokes.
The first aims to join deliberation with mass democracy by promot-
ing citizen deliberation on political matters, in what Habermas calls the
“informal public sphere,” constituted by networks of associations in civil
society.30 Because such informal discussion does not aim at a practical
decision but—insofar as it has an aim—at an informed public opinion, it
can pursue an unencumbered discussion about political values and pub-
lic goals. Moreover, these dispersed discussions—one element of a politi-
cal society’s process of collective decision-making—are potentially very
broadly participatory, for they take place through structures of numerous,
open secondary associations and social movements. For this mix of mass
democracy and deliberation, the essential ingredients, apart from ensur-
ing basic liberties, are diverse and independent media; vibrant, indepen-
dent civil associations; and political parties that operate independently
from concentrated wealth and help to focus public debate. All of this ar-
guably helps to foster deliberative capacities—a point I mentioned earlier
and promised to return to. The marriage of open communication in the
informal public sphere with a translation—through elections and legisla-
tive debate—of opinion formed there into law provides, on this view, the
best hope for achieving a greater mix of participation and deliberation
under conditions of mass democracy and a rule of law.
Much of the attractiveness of this view, then, hinges first upon the
deliberativeness of discourse in the public sphere and then upon the
strength of the links between such deliberation and the decisions of legis-
lative bodies and administrative agencies. But because dispersed, infor-
30. Habermas, Between Facts and Norms, chap. 8; John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New
York: Columbia University Press, 1996), 14, 382–383.
343
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
mal public deliberation and public policy are only loosely linked, a more
participatory and deliberative informal public sphere may have little im-
pact on decisions by formal institutions. Citizen participation in the in-
formal public sphere, then, may be of limited political relevance, and the
marriage of reason with mass democracy may proceed in splendid isola-
tion from the exercise of power. To be clear: I am not here objecting to
this first approach, only pointing to a concern and a possible limitation.
A second radical-democratic approach builds on the distinctive practi-
cal competence that citizens possess as users of public services, as sub-
jects of public policy and regulation, or as residents with contextual
knowledge of their circumstances. The idea is to draw on these compe-
tencies by bringing ordinary citizens into relatively focused deliberations
over public issues. Typically, such strategies create opportunities for lim-
ited numbers of citizens to deliberate with one another or with officials to
improve the quality of some public decision, perhaps by injecting local
knowledge, new perspectives, and excluded interests or by enhancing
public accountability.
One approach randomly selects small groups of citizens to deliberate
on general political issues, such as laws and public policies. Citizen ju-
ries in the United States and planning cells in Germany, for example,
empanel small groups (12–40) of randomly selected citizens to discuss
issues such as agriculture, health policy, and local development con-
cerns.31 Fishkin and his colleagues have sponsored larger gatherings of
300–500 citizens—with randomization—to deliberate upon such issues
as the adoption of the Euro in Denmark, the regulation of public utilities
in Texas, and the extent of foreign assistance.32 On an ambitious analyti-
cal interpretation, post-deliberation polls provide insight into what the
people think about a policy issue. Political impact is another matter. As
with citizen juries and planning cells, their political impact—to the ex-
31. Julia Abelson, Pierre-Gerlier Forest, John Eyles, Patricia Smith, Elisabeth Martin, and
Francois-Pierre Gauvin, “Deliberations about Deliberative Methods: Issues in the Design and
Evaluation of Public Participation Processes” in Social Science and Medicine No. 57 (2003):
239–251; Ned Crosby, “Citizens’ Juries: One Solution for Difficult Environmental Questions,”
in O. Renn, T. Webler, and P. Wiedelmann, eds. Fairness and Competence in Citizen Partici-
pation: Evaluating Models for Environmental Discourse (Boston: Kluwer Academic Press,
1995): 157–174; G. Smith and C. Wales, “The Theory and Practice of Citizens’ Juries,” in Policy
and Politics 27, 3 (1999): 295–308; John Gastil, By Popular Demand (Los Angeles: University of
California Press, 2000).
32. For a sketch of polls and implications, see Bruce Ackerman and James Fishkin, Deliber-
ation Day (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2005), esp. chap. 3.
344
R E F L E C T I O N S O N D E L I B E R A T I V E D E M O C R A C Y
tent that they have impact—comes from their capacity to serve in advi-
sory roles and to alter public opinion or to change the minds of public of-
ficials.
Another strategy convenes groups of citizens to deliberate and develop
solutions to particular problems of public concern. Such participatory-
deliberative arrangements—characteristic in different ways of associative
democracy and directly deliberative polyarchy—differ from political ju-
ries in two main ways. Whereas political juries usually consider general
issues, such as economic, health care, or crime policy, these delibera-
tions aim to address more specific problems, such as the management of
an ecosystem, the operation of a public school or a school district, the
prevention of crime in a neighborhood, or the allocation of a city’s re-
sources across projects and neighborhoods. Whereas political juries re-
cruit impartial and disinterested citizens by randomly selecting them,
participatory-deliberative arrangements recruit participants with strong
interests in the problems under deliberation.
Because of the specificity of these arrangements, citizens may well en-
joy advantages in knowledge and experience over officials. In Chicago,
for example, residents deliberate regularly with police officers in each
neighborhood to set priorities on addressing issues of public safety, using
their background knowledge as a basis for deliberation. And in Porto
Alegre, citizens meet regularly at the neighborhood level to agree on pri-
orities for public investment (for example, street paving, sanitation, and
housing); the capital portion of the city’s budget is produced by aggregat-
ing the priorities that emerge from those deliberations.
Participatory-deliberative arrangements—in areas such as education,
social services, ecosystems, community development, and health ser-
vices—show promising contributions to political equality by increasing
popular engagement in political decision-making. As I mentioned ear-
lier, in Chicago’s community policing program, for example, participa-
tion rates in low-income neighborhoods are much higher than those in
wealthy neighborhoods. Similarly, poor people are substantially over-
represented in both the budgeting institutions of Porto Alegre and the
local development and planning initiatives in Kerala, India. Directly
democratic arrangements that address problems of particular urgency to
disadvantaged citizens can invert the usual participation bias in favor of
wealth, education, and high status. They can also, however, create large
potential political inequalities. If systematic and enduring differences—
345
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
7. Final Reflections
So achieving both participation and deliberation is complicated. But be-
cause of their more direct bearing on the exercise of power, participatory-
deliberative arrangements have a particular promise as a strategy for
achieving the ends of radical democracy. Two large challenges, however,
lie on that path.
The first concerns the relationship between conventional institutions
of political representation and participatory-deliberative arrangements.34
Participatory-deliberative arrangements make it possible to address practi-
33. See Lucio Baccaro and Konstantinos Papadakis, “The Downside of Deliberative Public
Administration” (unpublished).
34. For discussion of the issues sketched here, see Cohen and Sabel, “Directly-Deliberative
Polyarchy”; Cohen and Sabel, “Global Democracy?”; and Joshua Cohen and Charles Sabel,
“Sovereignty and Solidarity in the EU,” in Jonathan Zeitlin and David Trubek, eds., Governing
Work and Welfare in a New Economy: European and American Experiments (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2003), 345–375.
346
R E F L E C T I O N S O N D E L I B E R A T I V E D E M O C R A C Y
347
11
TRUTH AND PUBLIC REASON
I believe that these assertions still make sense and do still apply
to the exploration of reality through art. So as a writer I stand
by them but as a citizen I cannot. As a citizen I must ask: What
is true? What is false?
har old pinter , Nobel Prize Lecture (2005)
I presented earlier versions at the Catholic University of Leuven; LUISS Guido Carli; the
Harvard Graduate Conference in Political Theory; the philosophy departments at Columbia
University, Union College, Northwestern University, and Cornell University; the September
Group; the Stanford Law School Legal Theory Colloquium; and as the 2008 Mala Kamm Lec-
ture at NYU. I am grateful to audiences on all these occasions, to the Editors of Philosophy &
Public Affairs, and to Bradley Armour-Garb, Alex Byrne, David Estlund, Erik Freeman, Sam-
uel Freeman, Barbara Fried, David Hills, Erin Kelly, Cristina Lafont, Jon Mandle, Sebastiano
Maffetone, Richard Miller, Ingrid Salvatore, Thomas Scanlon, Seana Shiffrin, and especially
to Paul Horwich for comments and suggestions. I also benefited greatly from generous and il-
luminating comments by Richard Rorty at the Stanford colloquium. I sketch his concerns be-
low in note 55.
348
T R U T H A N D P U B L I C R E A S O N
1. To be sure, Pinter was thinking about the truth and the falsity of assertions about matters
of nonnormative fact: for example, about the absence of weapons of mass destruction from Iraq
in 2002. Nevertheless, because he states his point in more sweeping terms, just as he had ear-
lier stated a perfectly general claim about truth, I think it is appropriate to interpret him as
making a more general claim about the place of truth in the discourse of citizens.
2. I say “conception” or “understanding” rather than “theory,” because I am not supposing
that a conception needs to have the internal structure that we associate with a theory. See be-
low, 372–373 (final two paragraphs of sec. 3).
3. In the way that the political conception of objectivity, associated with political liberalism,
is a genuine conception of objectivity, though different from, and in a way less committal than,
rational intuitionist and Kantian conceptions of objectivity. See John Rawls, Political Liberal-
ism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996), 110–116.
349
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
although less committal than the conceptions that have traditionally oc-
cupied philosophical attention and that have deep roots in our prac-
tices of making and defending assertions (including logically complex
assertions), in our reasoning, and in ordinary understandings about the
content and the correctness of thoughts. Because a political concep-
tion is less committal, it bears some similarity to antimetaphysical, “de-
flationary” theories of truth. Those theories are inspired by the redun-
dancy theories of Frege and Ramsey, according to which the content of
the claim that a proposition is true is the same as the content of the prop-
osition.4 Their main thrust is that truth is not a philosophically deep idea;
the concept is fully captured by the infinitely many instances of the truth
schema (T):
350
T R U T H A N D P U B L I C R E A S O N
7. For discussion of the charge, and the ways that it puzzlingly deploys a passion for truthful-
ness against the concept of truth, see Bernard Williams, Truth and Truthfulness (Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 2002).
351
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
ground of Rawls’s idea that public reason “does without the concept of
truth.” Second, then, I discuss (section 2) why it is hard to understand the
idea that public reason leaves truth aside. To clarify the puzzlement, I
distinguish four views that diminish the place of truth in political argu-
ment: the No Concept view (Rawls’s position), No Truth Bearers, No Sub-
stantive Judgments, and No Big Deal. Third, I sketch a political concep-
tion of truth and offer an account of what having such a conception
available in public political argument comes to (section 3). Fourth, I crit-
icize three arguments that might be offered in support of the No Con-
cept view that truth does not belong to public reason (section 4). Finally,
I distinguish the idea that public reason does without truth from an
evaluatively deflationary view, which I will call the “cultural proposal.”
Drawing on this cultural-political distinction, I suggest (section 5) that a
political world that does without the concept of truth is missing some-
thing important.
8. See “Declaration on Religious Freedom,” The Teachings of the Second Vatican Council:
Complete Texts of the Constitutions, Decrees, and Declarations (Westminster, MD: Newman
Press, 1966), 366–367; John Courtney Murray, “The Problem of Religious Freedom,” in Reli-
gious Liberty: Catholic Struggles with Pluralism (Louisville, KY: Westminster, 1993).
352
T R U T H A N D P U B L I C R E A S O N
353
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
10. In emphasizing Rawls’s concern specifically with truth, I disagree with Joseph Raz’s
claim that Rawls is equally concerned with a variety of terms of normative appraisal, including
“reasonable.” See his “Facing Diversity: The Case of Epistemic Abstinence,” Philosophy &
Public Affairs 19, 1 (Winter 1990): 15 (and esp. note 34). Raz’s article was written before Rawls
had developed a number of the main ideas of political liberalism, so the (mis)interpretation is
understandable. More broadly, I agree with Raz in thinking that Rawls was mistaken in putting
the concept of truth aside. But there are several important points of difference between his
view and mine: (1) Raz does not have the idea of a political conception of truth, and thus does
not see that doctrinal disagreement imposes any conditions on the understanding of truth that
falls within public reason (or perhaps see any need for an account of public reason at all); (2) I
think that Rawls, in emphasizing the importance of the political and the practical, was never
concerned simply with what Raz calls “consensus-based social stability.” Because Raz miscon-
strues Rawls’s concern with the political and the practical, he misinterprets the reasons for ab-
staining from judgments about truth; (3) Raz appears to endorse what I will later call the
Sufficiency and the Full Display arguments, an endorsement that may be associated with skep-
ticism about the idea of public reason.
11. John Rawls, “Justice as Fairness: Political Not Metaphysical,” in Joshua Cohen, Collected
Papers, ed. Samuel Freeman (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), 394.
12. The passages that follow are from Political Liberalism, xxii, 116, and 94. In “The Idea of
Public Reason Revisited,” Rawls does not address the issue of truth at all, though he does not
suggest (except perhaps by the sheer omission) any change of mind.
354
T R U T H A N D P U B L I C R E A S O N
ism,” Rawls says, “rather than referring to its political conception of jus-
tice as true, refers to it as reasonable instead.” Moreover, political liberal-
ism, he says, “has an account of objectivity” that is connected to an
account of “reasonable judgment” and suffices for the purposes of public
justification and “may leave the concept of a true moral judgment to com-
prehensive doctrines” (emphasis added). And, perhaps most fundamen-
tally, political liberalism “does not use (or deny) the concept of truth; nor
does it question that concept, nor could it say that the concept of truth
and its idea of the reasonable are the same. Rather, within itself, the po-
litical conception does without the concept of truth” (emphasis added).
Reasonableness, not truth, is the “standard of correctness,”13 and the ob-
jectivity of judgments about justice is characterized without reference to
the notion of truth. In response to Jürgen Habermas’s claim that political
liberalism cannot avoid issues of truth, Rawls forcefully replies that peo-
ple will “[c]ertainly . . . continue to raise questions of truth and to tax po-
litical liberalism with not discussing them. In the absence of particulars,
these complaints fall short of being objections.”14
Rawls’s point, I emphasize, is that the concept of truth is unavailable
(later I will contrast this No Concept view with a few other views that are
skeptical about a role for truth in political argument). Thus we cannot,
while operating within democracy’s public reason, make claims about
the nature of truth (and whether it has a nature), about its importance, or
about its relationship to justification, objectivity, and reasonableness. Nor
can we make assertions about the truth of any elements of our views, in-
cluding our comprehensive doctrine, or our views about justice, or our
understanding of how the society works.
Consider, for example, justice as fairness, with its two principles of jus-
tice. Assume that justice as fairness is one of several reasonable concep-
tions of justice that would win support among citizens in a democratic
society. The idea, then, is that it would be appropriate in political argu-
ment to think or assert that justice as fairness is reasonable—indeed the
“most reasonable” conception of justice15—and thus to use its principles
13. Political Liberalism, 127.
14. “Reply to Habermas,” in Political Liberalism, 394–395.
15. Political officials and candidates for office have a “duty of civility” to explain their posi-
tions on fundamental issues by reference to the political conception that they take to be most
reasonable. See “The Idea of Public Reason Revisited,” in Collected Papers, 576. The point is
not that it is advisable or obligatory to assert that one’s view is the most reasonable. Instead,
there is a duty to argue by reference to the view that one judges to be most reasonable. Judg-
ments about the reasonableness of one’s views thus belong to the terrain of political reflection
and argument.
355
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
16. Rawls states that he takes justice as fairness, with its two principles, to be the most reason-
able conception. See Political Liberalism, xlvi.
17. Samuel Freeman proposed in correspondence that Rawls wishes to avoid claims only
about the truth of principles of justice not about the truth of consequences drawn from those
principles. We cannot, then, affirm, within public reason, that the principle of equal basic lib-
erties is true, nor can we affirm that it is true that justice requires equal basic liberties. If that
principle is, however, part of the most reasonable conception of justice, then there is no objec-
tion to saying about a law infringing freedom of worship that it is true that it is unjust. The ac-
ceptable claim of truth is made from “within” the conception of justice, whereas the unaccept-
able claim is made about the conception itself. The same distinction, however, does not apply
to the notion of being reasonable (or most reasonable). I do not see a case for interpreting
Rawls this way, and do not, in any case, see the basis for the proposed restriction on the con-
cept of truth. First, if we cannot say that the principles are true, can we nevertheless affirm the
principles, or are we limited to asserting that the principles describe the most reasonable con-
ception? If we affirm the principles, assert them, and believe them, what is the force of with-
holding the judgment that they are true? Second, suppose it is permissible to judge, from
“within” a conception of justice, that it is true that certain policies are unjust. Let’s say that is
because we confine claims about truth to what we can argue for from common ground (not
that I wish to accept that thesis). But then why is it not permissible to judge, from “within pub-
lic reason”—which provides a terrain of argument that different conceptions of justice share—
that certain principles of justice are true because they can be argued for from common
ground? Third, the case for confining truth to judgments made “within” a conception of jus-
tice seems to turn on a sharp distinction, reminiscent of Carnap, between internal questions,
which arise within a linguistic framework, and external questions, about whether to adopt a
framework. But Carnap’s distinction did not permit judgments about which framework or
which language (say, a thing-language or a sense-datum language) is “most reasonable.” Our
attitude to a framework, on Carnap’s account, is a matter of acceptance, not of belief or of as-
sertion: it is, he says, “not of a cognitive nature.” So it is nonsense to describe a framework as
true, but that is because the framework is not a matter of belief at all. See “Empiricism, Se-
mantics, and Ontology,” reprinted in Rudolf Carnap, Meaning and Necessity, 2d ed. (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1956), 205–221. The idea that cognitive appraisal is entirely inter-
nal is foreign to public reason.
356
T R U T H A N D P U B L I C R E A S O N
litical argument that democracy promises. “Once we accept the fact that
reasonable pluralism is a permanent condition of public culture under
free institutions, the idea of the reasonable is more suitable as part of the
basis of public justification for a constitutional regime than the idea of
moral truth. Holding a political conception as true, and for that reason
alone the one suitable basis for public reason, is exclusive, even sectar-
ian, and so likely to foster political division.”18
Rawls does sometimes hint, if only indirectly, an alternative view. “Ra-
tional intuitionism,” he says, “conceives of truth in a traditional way [em-
phasis added] by viewing moral judgments as true when they are both
about and accurate to the independent order of moral values.”19 Rational
intuitionism, which Rawls associates with Cudworth, Clarke, Grotius,
Pufendorf, and Locke, is a species of nonreductive moral realism, treats
our moral thought as an exercise of theoretical reason, and is arguably an
ingredient in much natural law theory.20 His remark about a “traditional
way” of understanding truth and an independent order of values suggests
that it endorses a correspondence theory of truth, and the phrase “a tradi-
tional way” suggests that other conceptions of truth are available. If there
is such an alternative, then it might have a role in public deliberation.21
Moreover, such a conception might fit with the spirit of political liber-
alism. Political liberalism distinguishes comprehensive doctrines, which
include moral ideas that guide people in all aspects of their lives, from
political conceptions, which comprise moral ideas and values expressed
in political judgments. I will not try to characterize the distinction here.
Suffice it to say that ideas with a role in comprehensive doctrines can
also play a role in political conceptions, if those ideas are given a “politi-
cal” interpretation, as with political conceptions of justice, the person,
objectivity, reasonableness, autonomy, and liberalism itself. The political
18. Political Liberalism, 129. I will come back later to this passage, which ties together two ar-
guably very different ideas, one about holding a political conception as true, the other about
holding it as the one suitable basis for public reason in virtue of its being true.
19. Ibid., 92. See also 111 (“in the familiar way”) and 114 (“this idea of truth”).
20. On rational intuitionism and the idea of an independent order of moral values, see Polit-
ical Liberalism, 91–92; John Rawls, Lectures on the History of Moral Philosophy, ed. Barbara
Herman (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000), 69–83, esp. 70–72.
21. When Rawls states that political liberalism “does without the concept of truth,” he iden-
tifies this as one of four elements in the contrast between rational intuitionism and political
constructivism. See Political Liberalism, 91–94. But, logically speaking, the alternative to en-
dorsing a “traditional conception” of truth is to not endorse a traditional conception. There are
two ways to do that: do without the concept of truth altogether, or endorse a nontraditional
(that is, noncorrespondence) interpretation of truth.
357
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
conceptions are intended, roughly, to play a role when citizens reason to-
gether about political affairs. Thus, a political conception of persons as
free says, for example, that no particular ends are mandatory or obligatory
from a public point of view, that obligations a person has in virtue of his
or her moral or religious outlook do not have public standing as obliga-
tions, and that civil standing does not shift with shifts in fundamen-
tal aims, no matter how much or how deeply a person’s self-conception is
bound up with those aims.22 This political conception of persons as free
is meant to be available to adherents of views that endorse distinct and
incompatible philosophical conceptions of the free person, as an autono-
mous self-legislator with a will sensitive to reflective judgments, or as cre-
ated in God’s image, subject to His laws, and free when in willing com-
pliance with those laws. Similarly, a political conception of liberalism as
assigning equal liberties to all is meant to be available to both proponents
and critics of the moral-liberal view that individual, reflective self-direc-
tion is essential to a good life.
Why not, then, a political conception of truth, understood as a con-
ception of truth suited to play a role in democracy’s public reason? Rawls
did not pursue this path. Perhaps he thought that the concept of truth is
unavoidably metaphysical, originally owned by Platonists, and passed
along to their rational intuitionist descendants. As applied to moral
thought, he might have supposed that truth comes packaged with the ra-
tional intuitionist’s notion of an independent order of values. Or per-
haps he thought that the alternatives are a correspondence theory, a
coherence theory, an antimetaphysical deflationism, or some other unac-
ceptably philosophically demanding theory. In any case, he proposed to
“leave the concept of a true moral judgment to comprehensive moral
doctrines.”
I think that Rawls is mistaken and that affirmations of the truth of prop-
ositions about justice are a perfectly legitimate part of democracy’s public
reason. But to address the animating concerns about the tensions be-
tween truth and public reason, we need a political conception of truth.
To understand why, it will help to say more about Rawls’s proposed re-
sponse to these tensions and about why that response is deeply puzzling.
22. On the political conception of the person, see Political Liberalism, 18–20, 29–35, 48–54,
and 86–88.
358
T R U T H A N D P U B L I C R E A S O N
23. On the relevant kind of fatality, see Williams, Truth and Truthfulness, 67–68. On truth as
standard of correctness, see Nishi Shah, “How Truth Governs Belief,” Philosophical Review
112, 4 (October 2003): 447–482; and Nishi Shah and David Velleman, “Doxastic Deliberation,”
The Philosophical Review 114, 4 (2005): 497–534.
24. See Donald Davidson, Truth and Predication (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press, 2005), chap. 3.
25. Gottlob Frege, Basic Laws of Arithmetic, sec. 5, in Translations from the Philosophical
Writings of Gottlob Frege, ed. Peter Geach and Max Black (Oxford: Blackwell, 1970), 156.
26. Frege, Posthumous Writings, ed. H. Hermes, F. Kambartel, and F. Kaulbach, trans. P.
Long and R. White (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1979), 129. Neither this remark of
Frege’s about assertion, nor the previous remark about judgment, depends on his redundancy
theory of truth, much less on his view that true sentences denote the same object.
359
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
27. On the good of accuracy and sincerity, see Williams, Truth and Truthfulness, chap. 3.
28. For an illuminating discussion of Heidegger on truth, see Cristina Lafont, Heidegger,
Language, and World-Disclosure (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), chap. 3.
360
T R U T H A N D P U B L I C R E A S O N
29. Allan Gibbard initially defended an expressivist account of normative discourse and ar-
gued that such discourse is not fact-stating or truth-apt. See Wise Choice, Apt Feelings (Cam-
bridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990), 8, 10. For criticisms, see Paul Horwich,
“Gibbard’s Theory of Norms,” Philosophy & Public Affairs 22, 1 (1993): 67–78. More recently,
Gibbard proposes an expressivist explanation of normative discourse but recognizes that the
expressivist strategy—which starts by asking what states of mind normative claims express—can
help itself to notions of truth and fact. See Thinking How to Live (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 2003), esp. chap. 9.
361
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
362
T R U T H A N D P U B L I C R E A S O N
lic reason can be put more strongly. The reason that the concept of truth
has no place cannot be that the claims made by a political conception are
not truth-apt; those claims must be truth-apt, even if the political concep-
tion itself somehow abjures the concept of truth. They must be, if there is
to be a common ground of argument under conditions of doctrinal dis-
agreement. To deny the truth-aptness of the claims made on the terrain
of public reason would offend against the essential idea of public reason.
That is because the very propositions advanced in public political argu-
ment—even if not taken as or presented in that context as true—might
be judged true by the religious or moral doctrine affirmed by a citizen.
Consider an example. Suppose I endorse a Catholic natural law view. I
will say with Dignitatis Humanae that it is true that citizens have a right
to religious freedom. But also, with Veritatis Splendor, I will say that “the
splendour of truth” is the foundation of morality and political justice,
that there is a “moral obligation, and a grave one at that, to seek the truth
and to adhere to it once it is known,” and that there is an “inseparable
connection between truth and freedom—which expresses the essential
bond between God’s wisdom and will.”32 Moreover, with the conviction
that Christ is “the way, the truth, and the life,” and, resisting the tempta-
tion of “detaching human freedom from its essential and constitutive re-
lationship to truth,”33 I will hold that the truth of the (political) proposi-
tion—that individuals have a basic right to religious freedom—follows
from the truth of an account of human dignity founded on the doctrine
that human beings, created in God’s image, are bound by His laws. If that
is all correct, then the political claim expressed on the terrain of public
reason—that there is a right to religious freedom—must be truth-apt. It
must be capable of being true or false, because that very proposition can
be judged to be true from the standpoint of Catholic doctrine, and it is
said to be derivable from the underlying truths about human dignity.
It would conflict with the essentials of public reason to deny any of
this: to deny that the proposition that individuals have a right to liberty of
conscience is true or to deny that its truth follows from the basic truths
about the right way to live as fixed by natural law. Lacking the concept of
truth, a political conception used for public reasoning can issue no such
32. Veritatis Splendor, paragraphs 34, 99. This is an encyclical by Pope John Paul II on
moral theology. See http://www.vatican.va/holy_father/john_paul_ii/encyclicals/documents/
hf_jp-ii_enc_06081993_veritatis-splendor_en.html.
33. Ibid., paragraph 4.
363
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
denial. At the same time, the Rawlsian proposal is that the very proposi-
tion about religious liberty that the natural law adherent affirms as true
and as a consequence of more fundamental truths is available for asser-
tion in political reflection and argument, available to be used as a prem-
ise in reasoning. The natural law adherent is simply not permitted to say
everything he or she believes about that proposition—in particular, that
it is true and a consequence of more fundamental truths.
In short, Rawls’s proposal is to endorse a cognitivist understanding of
political conceptions of justice and political argument on which notions
of judgment, reasoning, and argument are fully in play, while denying
the availability of the concept of truth within such conceptions. The con-
cern is specifically with the concept of truth, and the reason for leaving it
out cannot be that political discourse traffics in something other than
truth bearers. Someone might offer that rationale for the view that truth
has no place in political argument, but not if they think of political argu-
ment as an exercise of public reason.
34. David Estlund, “The Insularity of the Reasonable: Why Political Liberalism Must Admit
the Truth,” Ethics 108 (January 1998): 253. Habermas also misinterprets the claim that the con-
cept is unavailable. He attributes to Rawls the view that “a theory of justice cannot be true or
false” and mentions a “weak interpretation” of this thesis on which it asserts that “normative
statements do not describe an independent order of moral facts.” See “Reconciliation Through
the Public Use of Reason,” Journal of Philosophy 92, 3 (March 1995): 123. A political concep-
tion of justice cannot make either of these claims, on Rawls’s account. Lacking the concept of
truth, it cannot make any claims about the truth or the falsity of conceptions of justice, includ-
ing the claim that they cannot be true or false. Moreover, endorsing the moral constructivist
thesis that normative statements do not describe an independent order of moral facts (the so-
called weak interpretation) would put it directly in conflict with rational intuitionism. See Po-
litical Liberalism, 113. What political constructivism does say is that “once, if ever, reflective
equilibrium is attained, the principles of political justice (content) may be represented as the
outcome of a certain procedure of construction (structure)” (Rawls, Political Liberalism, 89–
364
T R U T H A N D P U B L I C R E A S O N
90). The italicized phrase is essential. It would defeat the purpose of political constructivism to
say that the principles of justice are the product of a procedure of construction and, therefore,
“do not describe an independent order of moral facts.” The rational intuitionist may well agree
with the political constructivist claim about how the principles “may be represented,” while re-
jecting the moral constructivist claim about what those principles are.
35. In saying that it is very different, I am not criticizing the view. My aim in this section is
simply to clarify the No Concept account.
365
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
Substantive Judgments says that public reason has the concept but ab-
jures substantive applications of it. I will not discuss this view further.
Suffice it to say that the motivations for it are not very clear. After all, it is
perfectly consistent to say that reasonableness is necessary and sufficient
for the admissibility of a consideration into public reason—for its use in
public justification—and to say that it is permissible to present substan-
tive moral and political claims views as true. Once truth is available, it is
not clear why it should be cabined in the way suggested.
366
T R U T H A N D P U B L I C R E A S O N
Hobbes says, there are no unjust laws, because, antecedent to the sover-
eign’s law-making activity, there is no just or unjust distinction for laws to
be answerable to. So when Hobbes says that truth does not make law, he
means that legal validity does not depend on truths about rightness. But
that is in part because there are no normative truths available prior to au-
thority that might enter into determinations of legal validity. If that is in-
deed the rationale for legal positivism, then it follows as well that the
truth—that is, truths about what is just and unjust, right and wrong—
cannot figure in assessing valid laws as just or unjust, because the justice-
making facts, too, are exercises of sovereign legislative authority.
Once more, in semantic ascent, we might report this view by saying
that truth does not make justice. Nevertheless, the concept of truth can
be used in assertions about propositions concerning the justice of valid
laws. There is no trouble affirming that the proposition that theft is unjust
is true, no more trouble than in affirming simply that theft is unjust or
that theft violates the law. What makes theft unjust is that authorities
make laws defining and enforcing property rights. Nothing beyond that
illegality is needed to make theft unjust and therefore to make the propo-
sition that theft is unjust true. As a result, claims about the truth of propo-
sitions concerning justice are available in political argument, even
though truth does not make the justice of the laws.
Truth is available for the normative-positivist, then, but its relevance is
limited. The limits come not from the conception of truth as a device for
expressing generalizations but from the positivist view that justice is fixed
by the social facts of sovereign enactment. That view limits the force of
worries about whether our views about justice are true, about whether we
have it right about justice. The concern is intelligible. I might think that
I have been misinformed about the laws in a jurisdiction and so wonder
whether my beliefs are true. But once I know what the social facts are—
in particular, what the authority has decided—I have no basis for further
concern about whether justice is what I suppose it to be.
Drawing these points together, we have four views in play, each inter-
preting the general idea that, roughly stated, truth is not important in po-
litical argument:
3. Including Truth
I said at the beginning that political argument in democracies is in part a
matter of reasoning and judging on the basis of considerations of justice.
Such reasoning and judging might appeal, for example, to the principle
that all citizens are entitled to the same basic liberties, to the abstract idea
that a just society must treat its members as being of equal importance,
and to the arguments showing that a just society must secure equal basic
liberties in part because securing those liberties is essential to treating
members as being of equal importance. All of this—the principles as well
as the reasoning—lies, I will assume, on the terrain of democracy’s pub-
lic reason.
What, then, would it mean to say that a conception of justice—say, a
conception that includes the proposition that justice requires equal basic
368
T R U T H A N D P U B L I C R E A S O N
deeper theory, fully explains everything about the property of being true;
that a grasp of the concept of truth consists in a disposition to affirm all
the instances of the truth schema; and that truth is not a substantial prop-
erty and lacks a nature. Moreover, it says that the sole point of having a
truth predicate is to be able to express generalizations: for example, to say
that everything that Einstein said is true, or that all propositions of a cer-
tain form are true, or that the truth of normative propositions is not rele-
vant to legal validity.38 If you hold such a minimalist theory, then you will
think that having the phrase “is true,” and all the sentences that can be
used to express instances of the truth schema are—assuming competent
speakers, who are disposed to affirm all instances of the schema—what
having the concept of truth in the political conception consists in.
But neither minimalism of this kind, nor any other form of defla-
tionism, can provide the account of what it is to have the concept of truth
in the political conception. Although the instances of the schema and
the inferences deploying the schema can be part of democracy’s public
reason, the minimalist theory of truth cannot be, and for two reasons
(parallel considerations apply to other forms of deflationism).
First, minimalism does not say, on its face, anything about the fact that
truth is important or about why it might be important: that our beliefs
and assertions ought to be true; that it is good that they be true. Under-
standing the equivalence schema and being disposed to assert its in-
stances while not knowing anything about the point of classifying propo-
sitions as true and as false is like knowing the rules of a game without
knowing that the point of the game is to win. Grasping the significance of
truth is arguably (I come back below to the force of this qualification) not
something you understand simply by virtue of understanding that the
use of the concept of truth is captured by the instances of the schema or
that mastery of the concept consists in a disposition to affirm those in-
stances.39 A conception of justice, even when its formulation is under-
stood to include the term “is true” and all the instances of the schema,
38. See Paul Horwich, Truth.
39. See Michael Dummett, “Truth,” in Truth and Other Enigmas (Cambridge, MA: Har-
vard University Press, 1978), 2–3; on the importance of giving an account of the point of the
concept of truth, see as well, Davidson, Truth and Predication; Williams, Truth and Truthful-
ness; and Crispin Wright, Truth and Objectivity (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,
1992). Dummett focuses on Frege’s redundancy theory. “It is part of the concept of truth,”
Dummett says, “that we aim at making true statements,” but Frege’s account of truth “leaves
this quite out of account.” For criticisms, see Tyler Burge, “Frege on Truth,” in Truth, Thought,
Reason (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005), 130, and more generally, 88–93 (esp. note 3).
370
T R U T H A N D P U B L I C R E A S O N
may nevertheless arguably be said not yet to include the concept of truth.
Including the concept as part of public reason also requires incorporating
some account of the point of judging claims to be true and of the classi-
fications that employ the concept of truth. I will return to this point in a
moment.
More fundamentally, second, minimalism is a contested theory about
truth. In contrast to correspondence, coherence, and pragmatic theories,
it says that truth has no nature and is not a substantial property. It thus
puts public reason needlessly at odds with philosophical doctrines—say,
the rational intuitionism associated with some formulations of natural
law theory—that embrace metaphysically more demanding theories of
truth. It says more than is necessary for the purposes of including the
concept of truth within democracy’s public reason. Minimalism is an
antimetaphysical theory of truth. In contrast, a political conception of
truth cannot—as I said earlier—be antimetaphysical. It should be, how-
ever, nonmetaphysical, which will give it significant overlap with an
antimetaphysical theory: it will not make claims about the real nature of
truth or affirm that it is substantial property, nor will it make claims about
what substantial property it is. But it needs to say less than minimalism
does so that it does not impose unnecessary barriers to entry onto the ter-
rain of public reason (it will not deny claims about the nature of truth
either).
In short, minimalism says too much (denies too much) and perhaps
says too little to serve as a conception of truth in public reason. For the
concept of truth to have a place in public reason, we need both more and
less. The political conception of truth needs, first, to avoid asserting any
theory about the nature of truth or its lack of a nature. Such assertions
impose unnecessary hurdles and seem to serve no purpose within public
reasoning.
Then, second, the political conception needs to include at least four
commonplaces about truth:40
• Attitudes: Believing (asserting, judging) is believing (asserting, judg-
ing) true, where this slogan is understood to mean that truth is the
norm governing beliefs, assertions, and judgments;
40. See Crispin Wright, “Truth: A Traditional Debate Reviewed,” in Truth, ed. Simon
Blackburn and Keith Simmons (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), 203–238; and Wright,
Truth and Objectivity, chap. 2.
371
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
41. A distinction of some kind between truth and warrant seems important to understanding
the practice of deductive argument. Deductive argument is both compelling and useful. It is
compelling because it is truth-preserving. But it is useful because often we are not anteced-
ently warranted in endorsing the conclusion of a deductive argument or warranted in endors-
ing the conclusion independently of its issuing from that argument. See Michael Dummett,
The Logical Basis of Metaphysics (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1991), chap. 7.
42. Horwich, Truth; idem, “Norms of Truth and Meaning,” in Reflections on Meaning (Ox-
ford: Oxford University Press, 2005), 104–133; and “The Value of Truth,” Noûs 40 (2006): 347–
360, esp. sec. 10, on how to explain the desirability of truth without supposing that the concept
is “constitutionally normative.”
372
T R U T H A N D P U B L I C R E A S O N
plural. Thus, inconsistent propositions cannot both be true, and their ad-
herents cannot therefore all believe the truth, whereas inconsistent prop-
ositions can both be reasonable to believe, and their adherents can all
hold reasonable beliefs. It is not a philosophical theory, but a common-
place about the concept of reasonableness that reasonable people dis-
agree about certain matters. The singularity argument turns this logical
distinction between truth and reasonableness into a rationale for drop-
ping truth while keeping reasonableness.
Rawls suggests the singularity argument when he says, “Holding a po-
litical conception as true, and for that reason alone the one suitable basis
of public reason, is exclusive, even sectarian, and so likely to foster politi-
cal division.”43 I will return later to the phrase “and for that reason alone.”
Putting it aside for now, the essential point is that if I assert that my ac-
count of justice is true, and if yours conflicts with mine, then I am com-
mitted to denying that yours is true. But I may assert that my view is rea-
sonable, while accepting that yours is, too. Why bring truth in, with this
potentially troubling exclusiveness? Hannah Arendt gives forceful expres-
sion to this concern, suggesting that truth claims are divisive in ways that
are hostile to political life: “Factual truth, like all other truth, perempto-
rily claims to be acknowledged and precludes debate, and debate consti-
tutes the very essence of political life. The modes of thought and com-
munication that deal with truth, if seen from a political perspective, are
necessarily domineering; they don’t take into account other people’s
opinions, and taking these into account is the hallmark of all strictly po-
litical thinking.”44
A first trouble with the singularity argument is that truth has close
competitors in the divisive singularity market. Even if truth is not in play,
other standards of appraisal seem not only divisively singular but also un-
avoidable, at least on the broadly cognitivist understanding of political
discourse associated with public reason. So, for example, while there are
a variety of different political conceptions of justice, and though reason-
ableness is plural, only one can be the most reasonable conception; “most
reasonable” is as singular as “true.”45 Indeed, even “more reasonable”
43. Political Liberalism, 129.
44. Hannah Arendt, “Truth and Politics,” in Between Past and Future (New York: Penguin,
1977), 241. For an instructive discussion of the complexities of Arendt’s views, see Linda Zerilli,
“Truth and Politics,” Theory & Event 9, 4 (2006).
45. Rawls says that citizens fulfill their duty of civility when they explain their positions to
other citizens by reference to “the political conception of justice they regard as the most rea-
374
T R U T H A N D P U B L I C R E A S O N
sonable” (“Idea of Public Reason Revisited,” 576). To be sure, as Philip Kitcher reminded me,
several views may be tied for the most reasonable. The relevance of this is uncertain, because
you are still left with the judgment that some are less reasonable. Public reason is animated by
concerns about tolerance, not by an unwillingness to make judgments.
375
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
46. Political Liberalism, 42; “Idea of Public Reason Revisited,” 766; Political Liberalism, 243.
Emphases added. A number of other passages in Political Liberalism also focus their concern
on appeals to the “whole truth.” See 216, 218–219, 225, 242–243.
376
T R U T H A N D P U B L I C R E A S O N
gay marriage should not be permitted because it violates the duality es-
sential to God’s creation, or that social insurance ought to be eliminated
because the best human life is a life of personal independence at odds
with social insurance that protects against life’s risks. In each of these
three cases, an argument can be made for excluding the consideration
from democracy’s public reason, because proponents cannot reasonably
expect others to endorse the consideration. (I am not defending this idea
here: it is part of the background to the discussion.) But when presented
with that case, the proponent might say, for example, “But it is true that
God ensouls the fetus at quickening, and therefore true that abortion af-
ter 18 weeks is murder. How could these truths—universal and objec-
tive—not matter in deciding what to do?”
This appeal to truth carries no weight, and the availability of the con-
cept changes nothing. If the proposition that God ensouls the fetus at
quickening is not relevant, then the truth of that proposition is not rele-
vant. After all, the case for its being irrelevant in public justification
could not depend on the claim that it is false, since that claim would de-
feat the point of public reason. Correspondingly, the assertion that it is
true does not add anything to the case for its relevance.
This point—that if the proposition that p is not relevant, then it is true
that p is also not relevant—may seem to depend on endorsing a redun-
dancy theory of truth, according to which the attributing truth to a propo-
sition adds nothing to an assertion of the proposition itself. That is, the ar-
gument against truth as a license may be seen as semantic: If a person
who asserts the truth of some proposition says nothing more than a per-
son who asserts the proposition, then how could the former be relevant if
the latter is not? Consider a person who rejects the redundancy theory
and says that when he claims that the proposition about the fetus is true
he is adding something. He is asserting, he might say, that the proposition
corresponds to the facts about the fetus—to how things really are—and
that it is true that abortion is murder because God decided the issue and
our belief fits the facts as they are, independently of our decisions and
judgments. How, he might say, could that not be of decisive relevance?
These claims indicate that the proponent rejects the redundancy the-
ory but add no politically relevant argument. They tell us what makes it
wrong to have an abortion, from which it follows that it is true. If some-
one, then, argues for the relevance of truth along the lines just suggested,
the answer is that if the wrong-making facts did not suffice to establish
377
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
378
T R U T H A N D P U B L I C R E A S O N
vant normative claims to the view that all truths are relevant, the slide
from nothing but the truth to the whole truth, is by pointing to the error
in that inference, not by denying a role for truth. The inference may be
tempting because of the thought that there would be no good reason to
affirm the truth of a proposition in the practical setting of a political dis-
cussion if the sufficiency thesis were not true, that it would be practically
idle to affirm the truth of a claim unless an affirmation of truth sufficed
to establish the relevance of a claim and the use of it as a conversation-
stopping rebuttal to all objections. But familiar reasons about the use of
truth as a device of generalization show that this is wrong.48 Consider
again the jury setting. Imagine that the jury hears from a particularly con-
vincing witness, and one of the jurors says: “I think that everything she
said was true.” (Assume that nothing the juror said was ruled out of or-
der.) Alternatively, one of the jurors might say that the essential thing the
jury needs to settle on is whether “Jones is speaking the truth.” The other
jurors agree, and that common conviction is a working premise in their
subsequent deliberations. But the fact that that working premise is ex-
pressed using the concept of truth does nothing to establish the relevance
of my claim to be speaking the truth when I say that the defendant
robbed me.
In short, truth may be relevant without being sufficient. Our (intellec-
tual) response to those who aim to win the world for the whole truth is
not to yield the concept of truth. Instead, the response is to underscore
the phenomena of reasonable doctrinal disagreement, explain the value
of a shared ground of argument among equals, point out that the case for
a shared ground is not founded on a skeptical or a relativist outlook, and
clarify the appropriate but limited role of judgments about truth on that
shared ground—thus denying the sufficiency of truth.
48. For a sketch of the familiar point, see Horwich, Truth, 2–5. Horwich begins his discus-
sion by saying that “the truth predicate exists solely for the sake of a certain logical need.” The
political conception does not include any such story about the sole reason, but it can incorpo-
rate the rest of what is said.
379
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
380
T R U T H A N D P U B L I C R E A S O N
(assuming that he or she has one)—that the rule, in the space of reasons,
is in for a penny, in for a pound. Recall that democracy’s public reason is
a terrain of argument, and it may suffice, when challenged, to present a
case for liberty of conscience, for example, that lies on common ground,
with shared premises. If the premises are assumed to be true, then noth-
ing more is needed to make a case for the assertion that that proposition
is true. An assertion about truth need not be understood as committing
the speaker to presenting a full display, any more than the assertion that
justice requires liberty of conscience needs to be understood that way.
Even if assertions commit a speaker to presenting a justification, they
need not express commitments to depth. Truth is not depth. Sometimes,
as Rawls observed, the point of philosophy is “to extend the range of some
existing consensus.”50
Second, whatever commitments about presenting reasons may follow
from asserting that a proposition is true presumably also follow from as-
serting the proposition itself. If we are required to get into excessively
deep waters when we assert that it is true that justice requires liberty of
conscience, we also get into those waters when we assert that justice re-
quires liberty of conscience. If there is a culprit, it is assertion (and the
norms governing it), not truth.
Third, assertions about truth may not call for any display of argument
at all. Suppose Smith says that he agrees with Mill’s harm principle but
not with Mill’s views about equality and democracy. If Jones says in re-
sponse that she thinks that more or less everything Mill said was true, I
cannot see that she has advanced any claim at all about the kind of argu-
ment that can or needs to be given for Mill’s conclusions—in particular,
and following on the second point, that she now has a justificatory bur-
den greater than the one she would have had if she had simply said that
she agreed with various claims Mill made about equality and democracy
and had not said anything about truth.
Fourth, even if claims about truth do invite a full display, there may be
nothing objectionable about presenting a full display of a doctrine that
leads one onto common ground. I might say that I have a case, founded
on a broader doctrine that underwrites my view that a principle of equal
basic liberties is true. At the same time, I am fully aware that others dis-
agree with the doctrine and have their own reasons for endorsing the lib-
erty principle. What we share is an understanding of what justice re-
50. John Rawls, A Theory of Justice, revised edition (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press, 1999), 509.
381
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
5. Getting It Right
The political conception of truth, I have argued, spares us from the horns
of a dilemma. It enables us to respect the limits of public reason and to
preserve a place for truth. The political conception thus addresses what
might be seen as a fundamental objection to the idea of public reason. I
want to conclude now with some comments that will set the discussion
in a wider context and will clarify what is at stake.
Consider the following remarks:
1. “[Fania Pascal’s] statement [‘I feel just like a dog that has been run
over’] is grounded neither in a belief that it is true nor, as a lie
must be, in a belief that it is not true. It is just this lack of connec-
tion to a concern with truth—this indifference to how things really
are—that I regard as the essence of bullshit.”52
3. “[We] need to take seriously the idea that to the extent that we
lose a sense of the value of truth, we shall certainly lose something
and may well lose everything.”54
51. Here I follow Rawls’s discussion of “declaration,” in “Idea of Public Reason Revisited,”
594.
52. Harry Frankfurt, On Bullshit (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2005), 33–34.
53. John Stuart Mill, On Liberty (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1978), chap. 2, paragraph 10.
54. Williams, Truth and Truthfulness, 7.
382
T R U T H A N D P U B L I C R E A S O N
383
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
colloquium in October 2006, Rorty disagreed that truth is a norm distinct from warrant, for rea-
sons that struck me as assuming some form of pragmatism, and resisted my attribution to him
of the cultural proposal. But once we accept that truth and warrant are distinct norms, and dis-
tinguish the word “true” from the concept of truth, then we must conclude that Rorty is en-
dorsing something along the lines of the cultural proposal. Or so it still seems to me.
56. Rorty notes the wavering in ibid., 21–22.
57. See Hilary Putnam, “Does the Disquotational Theory Solve All Problems,” in Words
and Life (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1994), 264–278.
58. Rorty, “Is Truth a Goal,” 29, 41.
384
T R U T H A N D P U B L I C R E A S O N
385
P H I L O S O P H Y , P O L I T I C S , D E M O C R A C Y
Suppose, then, we put aside the cultural proposal about dropping truth
from the culture, not because the cultural proposal is wrong, but because
it is not our topic. The disagreement at issue here is not between Rorty
and Williams (or Frankfurt or Mill), but between Rawls and Pinter. As-
sume, then, a culture in which the concept of truth is available: some
people think we have already lost this culture; others regret that they are
wrong. And suppose that we are tempted to reject the Rawlsian view
about keeping truth out of public reason: we agree that it is hard to un-
derstand what it means to drop the concept (unless we are also prepared
to drop, among others, the concepts of belief, assertion, judgment), that a
nonmetaphysical (not antimetaphysical) understanding of truth is avail-
able, and that the reasons for dropping it are not compelling. So we are
prepared to keep the concept of truth (interpreted along the political
lines I described earlier) in political justification and to acknowledge
that truth is different from (even ideal) warrant. In rejecting the Rawlsian
proposal, aren’t we still recommending the public anxiety that the cul-
tural proposal condemns? The objection to keeping the concept of truth
raised by the cultural proposal may still have force even when our focus
is narrowed to the arena of public political discourse.
It may. But should the alleged anxiety be laid at the doorstep of truth?
Why not say instead that it comes with the territory of justice, thus with
the territory of public reason?
We are concerned to do what justice requires: anyway, that is what we
say; that is what we want other people to think we are committed to; it is
what we want to take ourselves to be committed to. Not simply what we
think justice requires, or what we warrantedly believe it to require, but
what justice requires. But caring about justice, as the political concep-
tion indicates, requires caring about the truth about justice. If a concern
about justice has—as I said at the outset—a place in democracy’s public
reason, then so, too, does a concern about getting it right, that is, about
the truth about justice. We of course should, while keeping a concern for
the truth, steer clear of needless controversy about the nature of truth: the
political conception of truth suffices to meet that aim; nothing either so
extreme or so fugitive as leaving the concept of truth out is needed.
As for the anxiety that comes with the concern to get justice right: that
comes with the territory of taking justice seriously. We can live with it,
should not live without it, and should not enlist philosophy to provide
therapy for that anxiety.
386
INDEX
387
I N D E X
388
I N D E X
pression and, 32–34, 32nn33–34, 34nn35–36; democracy and, 200–201; collective authori-
ideal, 23–25, 23nn22–23, 31–32, 160–164; insti- zation and, 191–192, 191n17; constitutional
tutional structures issues and, 17, 25, 28, 29, courts and, 212–216; constitutional issues and,
31, 34–37, 34n38, 36n40, 346–347; introduc- 201, 213–214, 215; deliberation and, 201–207,
tion to, 5, 8–11, 14, 16–17, 326–329, 328n4; 202n24; described, 181, 187–188, 189, 196, 199,
irrelevance objection to, 34–35, 34–35nn38– 221–222; egalitarianism, and effects of, 216;
39; justice and, 334; majority rule and, 25, 31, introduction to, 5, 12–13, 181–186, 183nn4–5;
68, 162, 191–192, 204, 237, 256, 259–260, legislatures and, 211–212; membership issues
263n70, 331–332; naiveté about power, and and, 209–210; political institutions and, 200–
skepticism about, 339–341; participatory de- 201, 211–216; problem-solving effectiveness
mocracy, and tensions with, 175–180, and, 210–211; public goods and, 13, 18n5, 208;
177nn46–47, 179nn49–50, 341–343, 342n28; radical-democratic concepts of the public
public goods and, 17–18, 35, 337–338, 337n20; and, 2, 216–221, 217–218nn34–35, 219n37,
public sphere large-scale decisions, and chal- 219n39, 220n42, 221n45; state and market is-
lenges to, 347; Rawls on, 16, 17–21; reasonable sues and, 207–209, 208nn29–30; virtues of de-
pluralism and, 305, 306–307, 309; reason- mocracy as political ideal and, 188–191, 188–
giving argument for, 334–335; sectarianism 189nn10–12, 191n17
and, 29–30, 45, 53–54, 112–113, 120–121, 373– disclosure of personal matters, and privacy
376 rights, 312–313, 312n10
deliberative inclusion, 164–166, 166nn17–18, discrimination: collective authorization, and
225, 241–243, 243nn29–30 protection against, 159, 159nn11–12, 164; con-
deliberative polyarchy. See directly deliberative tent-discriminatory regulations and, 125–126,
polyarchy 142, 144–145, 144n125, 147n129, 150–151; hate
democracy: aggregative concept of, 191–192, speech and, 99, 100, 152; sex, 144n125
223–224, 224n3, 264–265; authorization and, doctrinal pluralism, and truth, 353
157–160, 157n5, 158–159nn8–12, 223, 223n1; Doe v. Michigan, 100, 100n8
Buckley and, 11–12, 302; collective authoriza- “Domain of the Political, The” (Rawls), 41
tion and, 154–155, 154n1, 156, 223; conception Dryzek, John, 333–334
of, 5–8, 6n4; Dahl on, 158n10, 189n12, 224n3; Duflo, Esther, 338
deliberative-direct, 193–194, 193n20; egalitari- Dummett, Michael, 370n39
anism and, 189, 189n12, 189n14; electoral duty of civility, and privacy conventions, 305,
finance system and, 292–302, 293n43, 302n56; 321–322
institutional structures issues and, 194–199, Dworkin, Ronald: on abortion, 315; on citizen’s
196n22, 198n24; majority rule and, 191, 191n17; role in elections, 299n51; on consumption of
philosophy, and role in ideal, 15, 386; privacy pornography, 109; on education of citizens,
rights and, 305; procedure of, 156–158, 161– 109, 330; on egalitarianism, 274n10; on free-
163, 170; public reason and, 309–310; reli- dom of speech, 109n32; on liberal tolerance,
gious freedom and, 154–155; theory of, 61; vir- 255; Life’s Dominion, 315; on objection to de-
tues of, 188–189nn10–12, 189nn14–15, 188–191, liberative democracy, 32n34; on reflective
191n17 endorsement of morality, 257–258, 257n58
“Democracy and Morality” (Devlin), 256
Devlin, Sir Patrick, 255–256, 257, 260, 321 education of citizens, 69, 109, 330
difference principle, 169–170 egalitarianism: associative democracy and, 63–
Dignitatis Humanae, 363 66, 64nn5–7, 67; deliberative democracy
directly deliberative polyarchy: aggregative con- and, 18–19, 18n9, 18n11, 306, 309, 336–337;
cept of democracy and, 191–192; associative democracy and, 189, 189n12, 189n14; directly
389
I N D E X
390
I N D E X
391
I N D E X
life, death, and sex issues (continued) natural law theory, 49n20, 166n18, 229n12, 357,
and, 305, 311–312; right to die and, 313–316, 363, 364, 366n37
314–315n13; sexual intimacy and, 313–316, nihilism, and freedom of expression, 101,
314–315n13, 316–317, 317n16, 317nn18–19 101n10, 128–131
Life’s Dominion (Dworkin), 315 Nixon v. Shrink, 270, 290, 298, 302n56
Lincoln, Abraham, 2, 15, 155n3 Noble, William, 118n59
Locke, John, 7, 49n20, 188n10, 258, 259, 357 Nozick, Robert, 5, 6, 239n22
Lowi, Theodore, 197
O’Connor, Sandra Day, 291
MacKinnon, Catharine, 107, 139–140, 251, On Democracy (Cohen and Rogers), 6, 10,
253 36n40
Madison, James, 32n34, 35n39, 77, 77n21, 123
majority rule, 25, 31, 68, 191, 191n17 Panglossian outlook, 15
Mansbridge, Jane, 336 participatory democracy: associative democracy,
market issues, state and, 207–209. See also pub- and resolution of tensions between delibera-
lic goods tive democracy and, 175–180, 177nn46–47,
Marx, Karl, 46 179nn49–50; deliberative democracy, and
Mathews, John, 62n4 tensions with, 175–180, 177nn46–47,
McClosky, Herbert, 228n10 179nn49–50, 341–343, 342n28; described, 328–
McConnell, Michael, 231n14 329, 341; egalitarianism and, 336–337, 337n21
Meiklejohn, Alexander, 125, 248–249 philosophy, and role in ideal democracy, 1–5,
Metro Broadcasting, Inc. v. FCC, 137n107 3n3, 6, 6n4, 15, 386
Mill, J. S.: on censorship, 119, 119n61, 137, 289– Pinter, Harold, 348, 349, 349n1
290; on doctrinal pluralism, 353; harm princi- Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pennsylva-
ple of, 255, 257; on moral liberty, 124n75, 254, nia et al. v. Casey. See Casey decision
259 Plato, 330, 358
Miller v. California, 148 police enforcement, 109, 184, 184n5, 263,
Mora, Alberto, 2 263n70, 336, 345
moral liberty, 124n75, 254–264, 257n54, political legitimacy, and liberty, 266–267
257nn56–58, 261n64, 261n66, 310–311 Political Liberalism (Rawls), 348, 349, 376n46
moral pluralism: common ground for, 49–50, political parties, 17n3, 18, 24, 36, 36n40, 170n30,
49nn20–21; consensus and, 38, 38n3, 39, 41, 174–175, 175n42, 192n19, 218, 279–281, 286,
50–51, 55–56; egalitarianism and, 41, 47–49; 291, 293, 327–328, 343
exclusion of views and, 56–58, 58n30; as fun- political speech, and freedom of expression,
damental good, 43–44, 44n11; historical back- 114nn59–60, 117–118, 250–251
ground for, 45–46nn13–15, 45–47, 59, 59n31; polyarchy. See directly deliberative polyarchy
overview of objections to, 41–42; Rawls on, 8– pornography issues, 10, 103, 107, 109, 111n40,
9, 9n10, 38, 38n2, 41, 43–44, 44n12, 52, 52n25, 132–134, 133nn98–99, 134n102, 140–141, 148–
55–56, 59–60; reasonable pluralism and, 52– 151, 149–150nn134–135
55, 52nn24–25, 54n28, 155, 228–229nn10–12; Porto Alegre, Brazil, 207n28, 337, 338, 345
summary of, 8–9, 9n10, 38–41, 38nn2–3, 58– Posner, Richard, 337n20
60, 59n31 Post, Robert, 119n62
Mutz, Diana, 342n28 Prison Notebooks (Gramsci), 3
privacy conventions: costs of reticence and,
Nagel, Thomas, 54n28, 263n70, 304, 317–318, 319–321; duty of civility and, 305, 321–322;
320, 325 freedom of expression restraint and, 321, 323–
national identity, 155n3 325; introduction to, 305; pressure to conform
392
I N D E X
and, 321–323; public and private boundaries ference principle, 169–170; “The Domain of
and, 317–319 the Political,” 41; on justice, 356n16, 374–
privacy rights: abortion and, 18–19, 313–316, 375n45; on justification, 47; on liberalism,
314–315n13, 317n16; aggregative concept of 307, 352, 357n21; on liberty, 115n47, 117n53,
democracy and, 307–308, 308n6; cultural de- 137n106; on moral pluralism, 8–9, 9n10, 38,
mocracy system, 305, 319, 320, 322, 324–325; 38n2, 41, 43–44, 44n12, 52, 52n25, 55–56, 59–
deliberative democracy and, 11; democracy 60; on philosophy of democracy, 5, 6, 6n4;
and, 305; disclosure of personal matters and, on pluralism, 8–9, 9n10, 38, 38n2, 41; Politi-
312–313, 312n10; egalitarianism and, 306, 309; cal Liberalism, 348, 349, 376n46; on private
freedom of expression and, 310–311; indepen- sphere, 303; on public reason, 351; A Theory
dence in decisions and, 312–313, 312n10; in- of Justice, 5, 38, 46–48, 59, 61; on truth, 348,
formal public sphere and, 12, 305; liberalism 349, 351–358, 354n10, 354n12, 356nn16–17,
and, 307, 307n5; life, death, and sex issues 357n21, 364–365n34, 373–382, 374–375n45,
and, 305, 311–312; moral liberty and, 310–311; 380n49
reasonable pluralism and, 11, 305, 306–307, Raz, Joseph, 54n28, 120n63, 257n54, 354n10, 378
309; right to die and, 313–316, 314–315n13; sex- reasonable pluralism: comprehensive doctrine
ual intimacy and, 313–315, 314–315n13, 316– concept and, 225–226, 231–232; deliberative
317, 317n16, 317nn18–19; summary of, 12, 303– democracy and, 305, 306–307, 309; democ-
305 racy and, 155–156, 180; liberty and, 225–232,
proscribable expression, 143 227n8, 228–229nn10–12, 231n14; moral plural-
Przeworski, Adam, 196n22, 237 ism and, 52–55, 52nn24–25, 54n28, 155, 228–
public and private, 317–319 229nn10–12; privacy rights and, 11, 305, 306–
public goods, 337, 337n20, 338; deliberative de- 307, 309; religious freedom and, 8, 38n2,
mocracy and, 17–18, 35, 337–338, 337n20; di- 115n47, 156
rectly deliberative polyarchy and, 13, 208; pri- reflectiveness, and liberty, 249, 251, 257–259,
vacy rights and, 337, 337n20, 338 257nn56–58
public reason: democracy and, 309–310; liberty Rehnquist, William H., 254, 291
and, 232–237, 235–236nn16–17; Rawls on, 351; religious freedom: Catholic doctrine on,
religious freedom and, 234–235, 235n16; truth 229n12, 352; deliberative inclusion and, 164–
and, 14, 350–351, 352–358, 354n10, 354n12, 166, 166nn17–18; deliberative justification
356nn16–17, 357n21 and, 11; democracy and, 154–155; historical
public sphere, 12, 271, 277, 287, 305, 318, 343, context for, 10, 157, 159; liberty and, 234–235,
347 235n16, 243–248, 243nn29–30, 245n32,
247nn35–36; privacy rights and, 310–311; pub-
radical-democratic concepts, 2, 216–221, 217– lic reason and, 234–235, 235n16; reasonable
218nn34–35, 219n37, 219n39, 220n42, 221n45, pluralism and, 8, 38n2, 115n47, 156
326–327. See also deliberative democracy; di- right to die, 313–316, 314–315n13
rectly deliberative polyarchy; participatory Riker, William, 7, 31, 64
democracy Roe v. Wade, 314
rationalist fundamentalists, and denial of free- Roe v. Whalen, 312
dom of expression, 131, 131nn92–94 Rogers, Joel, 6, 10, 12–13, 36n40, 61, 327n2
R. A. V. v. St. Paul, 103, 141–142, 147n129 Rorty, Richard, 383–384, 383–384nn55–56
Rawls, John: on “background culture,” 271, 303, Rosati, Connie, 111n37
318; on “burdens of reason,” 52n25; on com- Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 7, 34n38, 327, 327n3
prehensive doctrine concept, 8, 225–226, 300,
306; on consensus, 39, 40, 41–42, 59; on de- Sabel, Charles, 13, 181, 327n2
liberative democracy, 16, 17–21, 331n8; on dif- Sandel, Michael, 183n50, 244, 268
393
I N D E X
Scalia, Antonin, 103, 141–142, 145n126, 148n130, 384nn55–56; deflationary theories and, 350,
255, 290, 291, 314–315n13 350n5, 352, 369–370; doctrinal pluralism and,
Scanlon, T. M., 110n34, 111n38, 122n69, 162, 353; importance of political conception of,
162n16, 245n32, 322–323 382–386; justification, and conception of, 14,
Schlozman, Kay Lehman, 280 349–350, 349nn2–3, 350n5, 351, 368–373,
Schmitt, Carl, 170n31, 329, 333 370n39; minimalism, and concept of, 370–
Schumpeter, Joseph, 12, 31, 269, 269n1, 299, 301 371, 370n39, 372; political conception of, 358,
Scruton, Roger, 261n64 382–386; political liberalism and, 352, 357,
sectarianism, and deliberative democracy, 29– 357n21; public reason and, 14, 350–351, 352–
30, 45, 53–54, 112–113, 120–121, 373–376 358, 354n10, 354n12, 356nn16–17, 357n21;
sex discrimination, 144n125 Rawls on, 348, 349, 351–358, 354n10, 354n12,
sexual intimacy, 313–315, 314–315n13, 316–317, 356nn16–17, 357n21, 364–365n34, 373–382,
317n16, 317nn18–19; liberty and, 254–255, 256, 374–375n45, 380n49; value, and concept of,
260–263, 261n64, 261n66, 262n69, 320 372
slavery, 1, 27, 49, 99, 230, 362 Tu Wei-ming, 229n12
Snyder, James M., 337–338
sodomy, consensual, 254–255, 261 Unger, Roberto, 166n19, 243n29, 248
Souter, David, 270, 291 Universal Declaration of Human Rights, 2
state and market, 207–209, 208nn29–30 University of Michigan hate speech case, 98–
Stevens, John Paul, 312 99, 100
Strauss, David, 111n38, 111n40
Sullivan, Kathleen, 277n14, 297–298 Verba, Sidney, 280
Sunstein, Cass: on congressional control, 82n25; Veritatis Splendor, 363
on constitutionalism, 197; on deliberative de- Voice and Equality (Verba, Schlozman, and
mocracy, 16n1; on freedom of expression, Brady), 280
102n15, 117, 117n53, 118n60, 248, 249; on moral voluntary public financing, and electoral
pluralism, 18n5; on pornographic expression finance, 175, 269–270, 270n3, 282–283n22,
defined, 134n102 288–289, 291–292, 293n44, 294
voucher scheme, and electoral finance, 175,
Theory of Justice, A (Rawls), 5, 38, 46–48, 59, 61 293, 293n44
Thomas, Clarence, 291
Thompson, Dennis, 333 Wenar, Leif, 227n8
Title VII, and freedom of expression, 144n125, Whitney v. California, 118n60, 136
145nn126–127 Williams, Bernard, 14, 382–383, 385, 386
Tocqueville, Alexis de, 69, 329 Wright, Crispin, 371n40
truth: comprehensive doctrine concept and, Wright, Erik Olin, Politics and Society, 13
353, 355, 357; concept of, 359–368, 359n26;
correspondence, and concept of, 372; the cul- Zaller, John, 228n10
tural proposal and, 352, 383–386, 383–
394