Tychonoff's Theorem - Wikipedia
Tychonoff's Theorem - Wikipedia
theorem
Tychonoff's theorem is often considered as perhaps the single most important result
in general topology (along with Urysohn's lemma).[2] The theorem is also valid for
topological spaces based on fuzzy sets.[3]
Topological definitions
The theorem depends crucially upon the precise definitions of compactness and of
the product topology; in fact, Tychonoff's 1935 paper defines the product topology for
the first time. Conversely, part of its importance is to give confidence that these
particular definitions are the most useful (i.e. most well-behaved) ones.
Indeed, the Heine–Borel definition of compactness—that every covering of a space by
open sets admits a finite subcovering—is relatively recent. More popular in the 19th
and early 20th centuries was the Bolzano-Weierstrass criterion that every bounded
infinite sequence admits a convergent subsequence, now called sequential
compactness. These conditions are equivalent for metrizable spaces, but neither one
implies the other in the class of all topological spaces.
It is almost trivial to prove that the product of two sequentially compact spaces is
sequentially compact—one passes to a subsequence for the first component and
then a subsubsequence for the second component. An only slightly more elaborate
"diagonalization" argument establishes the sequential compactness of a countable
product of sequentially compact spaces. However, the product of continuum many
copies of the closed unit interval (with its usual topology) fails to be sequentially
compact with respect to the product topology, even though it is compact by
Tychonoff's theorem (e.g., see Wilansky 1970, p. 134).
Applications
Tychonoff's theorem has been used to prove many other mathematical theorems.
These include theorems about compactness of certain spaces such as the Banach–
Alaoglu theorem on the weak-* compactness of the unit ball of the dual space of a
normed vector space, and the Arzelà–Ascoli theorem characterizing the sequences of
functions in which every subsequence has a uniformly convergent subsequence. They
also include statements less obviously related to compactness, such as the De
Bruijn–Erdős theorem stating that every minimal k-chromatic graph is finite, and the
Curtis–Hedlund–Lyndon theorem providing a topological characterization of cellular
automata.
As a rule of thumb, any sort of construction that takes as input a fairly general object
(often of an algebraic, or topological-algebraic nature) and outputs a compact space
is likely to use Tychonoff: e.g., the Gelfand space of maximal ideals of a commutative
C*-algebra, the Stone space of maximal ideals of a Boolean algebra, and the
Berkovich spectrum of a commutative Banach ring.
Proofs of Tychonoff's
theorem
1) Tychonoff's 1930 proof used the concept of a complete accumulation point.
More modern proofs have been motivated by the following considerations: the
approach to compactness via convergence of subsequences leads to a simple and
transparent proof in the case of countable index sets. However, the approach to
convergence in a topological space using sequences is sufficient when the space
satisfies the first axiom of countability (as metrizable spaces do), but generally not
otherwise. However, the product of uncountably many metrizable spaces, each with
at least two points, fails to be first countable. So it is natural to hope that a suitable
notion of convergence in arbitrary spaces will lead to a compactness criterion
generalizing sequential compactness in metrizable spaces that will be as easily
applied to deduce the compactness of products. This has turned out to be the case.
3) The theory of convergence via filters, due to Henri Cartan and developed by
Bourbaki in 1937, leads to the following criterion: assuming the ultrafilter lemma, a
space is compact if and only if each ultrafilter on the space converges. With this in
hand, the proof becomes easy: the (filter generated by the) image of an ultrafilter on
the product space under any projection map is an ultrafilter on the factor space,
which therefore converges, to at least one xi. One then shows that the original
ultrafilter converges to x = (xi). In his textbook, Munkres gives a reworking of the
Cartan–Bourbaki proof that does not explicitly use any filter-theoretic language or
preliminaries.
5) A proof using nets but not universal nets was given in 1992 by Paul Chernoff.
On the other hand, the statement that every filter is contained in an ultrafilter does not
imply AC. Indeed, it is not hard to see that it is equivalent to the Boolean prime ideal
theorem (BPI), a well-known intermediate point between the axioms of Zermelo-
Fraenkel set theory (ZF) and the ZF theory augmented by the axiom of choice (ZFC). A
first glance at the second proof of Tychnoff may suggest that the proof uses no more
than (BPI), in contradiction to the above. However, the spaces in which every
convergent filter has a unique limit are precisely the Hausdorff spaces. In general we
t l t f h l t f th i d t l t f th t t f
limits of the projected ultrafilter base, and of course this uses AC. However, it also
shows that the compactness of the product of compact Hausdorff spaces can be
proved using (BPI), and in fact the converse also holds. Studying the strength of
Tychonoff's theorem for various restricted classes of spaces is an active area in set-
theoretic topology.
The analogue of Tychonoff's theorem in pointless topology does not require any form
of the axiom of choice.
Let {Ai} be an indexed family of nonempty sets, for i ranging in I (where I is an arbitrary
indexing set). We wish to show that the cartesian product of these sets is nonempty.
Now, for each i, take Xi to be Ai with the index i itself tacked on (renaming the indices
using the disjoint union if necessary, we may assume that i is not a member of Ai, so
simply take Xi = Ai ∪ {i}).
along with the natural projection maps πi which take a member of X to its ith term.
We give each Xj the topology whose open sets are: the empty set, the singleton {i}, the
set Xi. This makes Xi compact, and by Tychonoff's theorem, X is also compact (in the
product topology). The projection maps are continuous; all the Ai's are closed, being
complements of the singleton open set {i} in Xi. So the inverse images πi−1(Ai) are
closed subsets of X. We note that
and prove that these inverse images have the FIP. Let i1, ..., iN be a finite collection of
indices in I. Then the finite product Ai × ... × Ai is non-empty (only finitely many
1 N
choices here, so AC is not needed); it merely consists of N-tuples. Let a = (a1, ..., aN)
be such an N-tuple. We extend a to the whole index set: take a to the function f
defined by f(j) = ak if j = ik, and f(j) = j otherwise. This step is where the addition of the
extra point to each space is crucial, for it allows us to define f for everything outside of
the N-tuple in a precise way without choices (we can already choose, by construction,
j from Xj ). πi (f) = ak is obviously an element of each Ai so that f is in each inverse
k k
By the FIP definition of compactness, the entire intersection over I must be nonempty,
and the proof is complete.
See also
Notes
References
External links
Retrieved from
"https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?
title=Tychonoff%27s_theorem&oldid=123544
8814"
This page was last edited on 19 July 2024, at
09:49 (UTC). •
Content is available under CC BY-SA 4.0
unless otherwise noted.