Immediate Download Principles and Practice of Marketing 10th Edition Fiona Ellis-Chadwick Ebooks 2024
Immediate Download Principles and Practice of Marketing 10th Edition Fiona Ellis-Chadwick Ebooks 2024
Immediate Download Principles and Practice of Marketing 10th Edition Fiona Ellis-Chadwick Ebooks 2024
com
OR CLICK BUTTON
DOWLOAD NOW
More products digital (pdf, epub, mobi) instant
download maybe you interests ...
https://ebookmeta.com/product/entrepreneurship-marketing-
principles-and-practice-of-sme-marketing-2nd-edition-sonny-
nwankwo/
https://ebookmeta.com/product/principles-and-practice-of-
marketing-9th-edition-david-jobber/
https://ebookmeta.com/product/social-marketing-principles-and-
practice-for-delivering-global-change-4th-edition-gerard-
hastings/
https://ebookmeta.com/product/principles-of-microeconomics-10th-
edition-mankiw/
Educational Psychology: Developing Learners (10th
Edition) Jeanne Ellis Ormrod
https://ebookmeta.com/product/educational-psychology-developing-
learners-10th-edition-jeanne-ellis-ormrod/
https://ebookmeta.com/product/principles-of-marketing-19th-
global-edition-philip-kotler/
https://ebookmeta.com/product/how-to-revise-and-practice-2nd-
edition-fiona-mcpherson/
https://ebookmeta.com/product/principles-of-marketing-1st-
edition-dr-maria-gomez-albrecht/
https://ebookmeta.com/product/cancer-of-the-breast-from-cancer-
principles-and-practice-of-oncology-10th-edition-vincent-t-
devita-theodore-s-lawrence-steven-a-rosenberg/
page i
Tenth Edition
page ii
page iii
Tenth Edition
Fictitious names of companies, products, people, characters and/or data that may
be used herein (in case studies or in examples) are not intended to represent any
real individual, company, product or event.
ISBN-13 9781526849533
ISBN-10 1526849534
eISBN-13 9781526849540
© 2024. Exclusive rights by McGraw-Hill Education for manufacture and export.
This book cannot be re-exported from the country to which it is sold by McGraw-
Hill Education.
page v
Dedication
To Jackson, River, Rosie, Molly, Evie and Bohdi.
page vi
PART 1
Fundamentals of Marketing 1
1 Marketing and the Organization 3
PART 3
Communicating and Delivering Customer Value 463
12 Introduction to Marketing Communications 465
PART 4
Marketing Planning and Strategy 679
17 Marketing Strategy and Planning 681
Glossary 875
Company Index 887
Subject Index 896
page vii
Preface xvii
Guided Tour xx
Technology to Enhance Learning and Teaching xxiii
PART 1
Fundamentals of Marketing 1
1 Marketing and the Organization 3
Introduction to Principles and Practice of Marketing 4
What is Marketing? 5
Adopting a Market Orientation in a Changing World 7
Understanding Market-driven Businesses 11
Creating Customer Value, Satisfaction, Loyalty and Relationships 16
Marketing Planning 21
Does Marketing Have All the Answers? 22
Big Picture: Key Topics in This Chapter 25
Detailed Review 25
Key Terms 27
Study Questions 28
Recommended Reading 28
References 28
CASE 1 The Rivalry Between Coca-Cola and Pepsi 31
CASE 2 H&M and Fast Fashion 35
page viii
PART 2
Creating Customer Value 303
8 Value Through Brands 305
Products and Brands 306
The Product Line and Product Mix 307
Brand Types 307
Why Strong Brands are Important 308
Brand Equity 312
Brand Building 314
Key Branding Decisions 320
Global Branding 330
Big Picture: Key Topics in This Chapter 333
Detailed Review 334
Key Terms 335
Study Questions 336
Recommended Reading 336
References 337
CASE 15 Dr. Martens: Engaging Consumers for More Than Half a
Century 340
CASE 16 Brand Strategy Changes at Burberry 344
We have gone too far away from the subject of this chapter, but we
have shown why it has been considered sufficient to mention only
these (thirteen) out of all His acts; namely, because they are
required for the good government of a country; for the chief aim of
man should be to make himself, as far as possible, similar to God:
that is to say, to make his acts similar to the acts of God, or as our
Sages expressed it in explaining the verse, “Ye shall be holy” (Lev.
xxi. 2): “He is gracious, so be you also gracious; He is merciful, so
be you also merciful.”
The principal object of this chapter was to show that all attributes
ascribed to God are attributes of His acts, and do not imply that God
has any qualities.
[Contents]
CHAPTER LV
We have already, on several occasions, shown in this treatise that
everything that implies corporeality or passiveness, is to be
negatived in reference to God, for all passiveness implies change;
and the agent producing that state is undoubtedly different from the
object affected by it; and if God could be affected in any way
whatever, another being beside Him would act on Him and cause
change in Him. All kinds of non-existence must likewise be negatived
in reference to Him; no perfection whatever can therefore be
imagined to be at one time absent from Him, and at another present
in Him: for if this were the case, He would [at a certain time] only be
potentially perfect. Potentiality always implies non-existence, and
when anything has to pass from potentiality into reality, another
thing that exists in reality is required to effect that transition. Hence
it follows that all perfections must really exist in God, and none of
them must in any way be a mere potentiality. Another thing likewise
to be denied in reference to God, is similarity to any existing being.
This has been generally accepted, and is also mentioned in the
books of the Prophets; e.g., “To whom, then, will you liken me?”
(Isa. xl. 25); “To whom, then, will you liken God?” (ib. 18); “There is
none like unto Thee” (Jer. x. 6). Instances of this kind are frequent.
In short, it is necessary to demonstrate by proof that nothing can be
predicated of God that implies any of the following four things:
corporeality, emotion or change, non-existence,—e.g., that
something would be potential at one time and real at another—and
similarity with any of His creatures. In this respect our knowledge of
God is aided by the study of Natural Science. For he who is ignorant
of the latter cannot understand the defect implied in emotions, the
difference between potentiality and reality, the non-existence implied
in all potentiality, the inferiority of a thing that exists in potentiâ to
that which moves in order to cause its transition from potentiality
into reality, and the [79]inferiority of that which moves for this
purpose compared with its condition when the transition has been
effected. He who knows these things, but without their proofs, does
not know the details which logically result from these general
propositions; and therefore he cannot prove that God exists, or that
the [four] things mentioned above are inadmissible in reference to
God.
[Contents]
CHAPTER LVI
Similarity is based on a certain relation between two things; if
between two things no relation can be found, there can be no
similarity between them, and there is no relation between two things
that have no similarity to each other; e.g., we do not say this heat is
similar to that colour, or this voice is similar to that sweetness. This
is self-evident. Since the existence of a relation between God and
man, or between Him and other beings has been denied, similarity
must likewise be denied. You must know that two things of the same
kind—i.e., whose essential properties are the same, and which are
distinguished from each other by greatness and smallness, strength
and weakness, etc.—are necessarily similar, though different in this
one way; e.g., a grain of mustard and the sphere of the fixed stars
are similar as regards the three dimensions, although the one is
exceedingly great, the other exceedingly small, the property of
having [three] dimensions is the same in both; or the heat of wax
melted by the sun and the heat of the element of fire, are similar as
regards heat; although the heat is exceedingly great in the one case,
and exceedingly small in the other, the existence of that quality
(heat) is the same in both. Thus those who believe in the presence
of essential attributes in God, viz., Existence, Life, Power, Wisdom,
and Will, should know that these attributes, when applied to God,
have not the same meaning as when applied to us, and that the
difference does not only consist in magnitude, or in the degree of
perfection, stability, and durability. It cannot be said, as they
practically believe, that His existence is only more stable, His life
more permanent, His power greater, His wisdom more perfect, and
His will more general than ours, and that the same definition applies
to both. This is in no way admissible, for the expression “more than”
is used in comparing two things as regards a certain attribute
predicated of both of them in exactly the same sense, and
consequently implies similarity [between God and His creatures].
When they ascribe to God essential attributes, these so-called
essential attributes should not have any similarity to the attributes of
other things, and should according to their own opinion not be
included in one of the same definition, just as there is no similarity
between the essence of God and that of other beings. They do not
follow this principle, for they hold that one definition may include
them, and that, nevertheless, there is no similarity between them.
Those who are familiar with the meaning of similarity will certainly
understand that the term existence, when applied to God and to
other beings, is perfectly homonymous. In like manner, the terms
Wisdom, Power, Will, and Life are applied to God and to other beings
by way of perfect homonymity, admitting [80]of no comparison
whatever. Nor must you think that these attributes are employed as
hybrid terms; for hybrid terms are such as are applied to two things
which have a similarity to each other in respect to a certain property
which is in both of them an accident, not an essential, constituent
element. The attributes of God, however, are not considered as
accidental by any intelligent person, while all attributes applied to
man are accidents, according to the Mutakallemim. I am therefore at
a loss to see how they can find any similarity [between the attributes
of God and those of man]; how their definitions can be identical, and
their significations the same! This is a decisive proof that there is, in
no way or sense, anything common to the attributes predicated of
God, and those used in reference to ourselves; they have only the
same names, and nothing else is common to them. Such being the
case, it is not proper to believe, on account of the use of the same
attributes, that there is in God something additional to His essence,
in the same way as attributes are joined to our essence. This is most
important for those who understand it. Keep it in memory, and study
it thoroughly, in order to be well prepared for that which I am going
to explain to you.
[Contents]
CHAPTER LVII
On attributes; remarks more recondite than the preceding. It is
known that existence is an accident appertaining to all things, and
therefore an element superadded to their essence. This must
evidently be the case as regards everything the existence of which is
due to some cause; its existence is an element superadded to its
essence. But as regards a being whose existence is not due to any
cause—God alone is that being, for His existence, as we have said, is
absolute—existence and essence are perfectly identical; He is not a
substance to which existence is joined as an accident, as an
additional element. His existence is always absolute, and has never
been a new element or an accident in Him. Consequently God exists
without possessing the attribute of existence. Similarly He lives,
without possessing the attribute of life; knows, without possessing
the attribute of knowledge; is omnipotent without possessing the
attribute of omnipotence; is wise, without possessing the attribute of
wisdom; all this reduces itself to one and the same entity; there is
no plurality in Him, as will be shown. It is further necessary to
consider that unity and plurality are accidents supervening to an
object according as it consists of many elements or of one. This is
fully explained in the book called Metaphysics. In the same way as
number is not the substance of the things numbered, so is unity not
the substance of the thing which has the attribute of unity, for unity
and plurality are accidents belonging to the category of discrete
quantity, and supervening to such objects as are capable of receiving
them.
The same is the case when we say God is the First (Kadmon), to
express that He has not been created; the term “First” is decidedly
inaccurate, for it can in its true sense only be applied to a being that
is subject to the relation of time; the latter, however, is an accident
to motion which again is connected with a body. Besides the
attribute “first” is a relative term, being in regard to time the same
as the terms “long” and “short” are in regard to a line. Both
expressions, “first” and “created,” are equally inadmissible in
reference to any being to which the attribute of time is not
applicable, just as we do not say “crooked” or “straight” in reference
to taste, “salted” or “insipid” in reference to the voice. These
subjects are not unknown to those who have accustomed
themselves to seek a true understanding of the things, and to
establish their properties in accordance with the abstract notions
which the mind has formed of them, and who are not misled by the
inaccuracy of the words employed. All attributes, such as “the First,”
“the Last,” occurring in the Scriptures in reference to God, are as
metaphorical as the expressions “ear” and “eye.” They simply signify
that God is not subject to any change or innovation whatever; they
do not imply that God can be described by time, or that there is any
comparison between Him and any other being as regards time, and
that He is called on that account “the first” and “the last.” In short,
all similar expressions are borrowed from the language commonly
used among the people. In the same way we use “One” in reference
to God, to express that there is nothing similar to Him, but we do
not mean to say that an attribute of unity is added to His essence.
[Contents]
CHAPTER LVIII
This chapter is even more recondite than the preceding. Know that
the negative attributes of God are the true attributes: they do not
include any incorrect notions or any deficiency whatever in reference
to God, while positive attributes imply polytheism, and are
inadequate, as we have already shown. It is now necessary to
explain how negative expressions can in a certain sense be
employed as attributes, and how they are distinguished from positive
attributes. Then I shall show that we cannot describe the Creator by
any means except by negative attributes. An attribute does not
exclusively belong to the one object to which it is related; while
qualifying one thing, it can also be employed to qualify other things,
and is in that case not peculiar to that one thing. E.g., if you see an
object from a distance, and on enquiring what it is, are told that it is
a living being, you have certainly learnt an attribute of the object
seen, and although that attribute does not exclusively belong to the
object perceived, it expresses that the object is not a plant or a
mineral. Again, if a man is in a certain house, and [82]you know that
something is in the house, but not exactly what, you ask what is in
that house, and you are told, not a plant nor a mineral. You have
thereby obtained some special knowledge of the thing; you have
learnt that it is a living being, although you do not yet know what
kind of a living being it is. The negative attributes have this in
common with the positive, that they necessarily circumscribe the
object to some extent, although such circumscription consists only in
the exclusion of what otherwise would not be excluded. In the
following point, however, the negative attributes are distinguished
from the positive. The positive attributes, although not peculiar to
one thing, describe a portion of what we desire to know, either some
part of its essence or some of its accidents; the negative attributes,
on the other hand, do not, as regards the essence of the thing which
we desire to know, in any way tell us what it is, except it be
indirectly, as has been shown in the instance given by us.
It has thus been shown that every attribute predicated of God either
denotes the quality of an action, or—when the attribute is intended
to convey some idea of the Divine Being itself, and not of His actions
—the negation of the opposite. Even these negative attributes must
not be formed and applied to God, except in the way in which, as
you know, sometimes an attribute is negatived in reference to a
thing, although that attribute can naturally never be applied to it in
the same sense, as, e.g., we say, “This wall does not see.” Those
who read the present work are aware that, notwithstanding all the
efforts of the mind, we can obtain no knowledge of the essence of
the heavens—a revolving substance which has been measured by us
in spans and cubits, and examined even as regards the proportions
of the several spheres to each other and respecting most of their
motions—although we know that they must consist of matter and
form; but the matter not being the same as sublunary matter, we
can only describe the heavens in terms expressing negative
properties, but not in terms denoting positive qualities. Thus we say
that the heavens are not light, not heavy, not passive and therefore
not subject to impressions, and that they do not possess the
sensations of taste and smell; or we use similar negative attributes.
All this we do, because we do not know their substance. What, then,
can be the result of our efforts, when we try to obtain a knowledge
of a Being that is free from substance, that is most simple, whose
existence is absolute, and not due to any cause, to whose perfect
essence nothing can be superadded, and whose perfection consists,
as we have shown, in the absence of all defects. All we understand
is the fact that He exists, that He is a Being to whom none of His
creatures is similar, who has nothing in common with them, who
does not include plurality, who is never too feeble to produce other
beings, and whose relation to the universe is that of a steersman to
a boat; and even this is not a real relation, a real simile, but serves
only to convey to us the idea that God rules the universe; that is,
that He gives it duration, and preserves its necessary arrangement.
This subject will be treated more fully. Praised be He! In the
contemplation of His essence, our comprehension and knowledge
prove insufficient; in the examination of His works, how they
necessarily result from His will, our knowledge proves to be
ignorance, and in the endeavour to extol Him in words, all our
efforts in speech are mere weakness and failure!
[Contents]
CHAPTER LIX
The following question might perhaps be asked: Since there is no
possibility of obtaining a knowledge of the true essence of God, and
since it has also been proved that the only thing that man can
apprehend of Him is the fact that He exists, and that all positive
attributes are inadmissible, as has been shown; what is the
difference among those who have obtained a knowledge of God?
Must not the knowledge obtained by our teacher Moses, and by
Solomon, be the same as that obtained by any one of the lowest
class of philosophers, since [84]there can be no addition to this
knowledge? But, on the other hand, it is generally accepted among
theologians and also among philosophers, that there can be a great
difference between two persons as regards the knowledge of God
obtained by them. Know that this is really the case, that those who
have obtained a knowledge of God differ greatly from each other;
for in the same way as by each additional attribute an object is more
specified, and is brought nearer to the true apprehension of the
observer, so by each additional negative attribute you advance
toward the knowledge of God, and you are nearer to it than he who
does not negative, in reference to God, those qualities which you are
convinced by proof must be negatived. There may thus be a man
who after having earnestly devoted many years to the pursuit of one
science, and to the true understanding of its principles, till he is fully
convinced of its truths, has obtained as the sole result of this study
the conviction that a certain quality must be negatived in reference
to God, and the capacity of demonstrating that it is impossible to
apply it to Him. Superficial thinkers will have no proof for this, will
doubtfully ask, Is that thing existing in the Creator, or not? And
those who are deprived of sight will positively ascribe it to God,
although it has been clearly shown that He does not possess it. E.g.,
while I show that God is incorporeal, another doubts and is not
certain whether He is corporeal or incorporeal; others even positively
declare that He is corporeal, and appear before the Lord with that
belief. Now see how great the difference is between these three
men; the first is undoubtedly nearest to the Almighty; the second is
remote, and the third still more distant from Him. If there be a
fourth person who holds himself convinced by proof that emotions
are impossible in God, while the first who rejects the corporeality, is
not convinced of that impossibility, that fourth person is undoubtedly
nearer the knowledge of God than the first, and so on, so that a
person who, convinced by proof, negatives a number of things in
reference to God, which according to our belief may possibly be in
Him or emanate from Him, is undoubtedly a more perfect man than
we are, and would surpass us still more if we positively believed
these things to be properties of God. It will now be clear to you, that
every time you establish by proof the negation of a thing in
reference to God, you become more perfect, while with every
additional positive assertion you follow your imagination and recede
from the true knowledge of God. Only by such ways must we
approach the knowledge of God, and by such researches and studies
as would show us the inapplicability of what is inadmissible as
regards the Creator, not by such methods as would prove the
necessity of ascribing to Him anything extraneous to His essence, or
asserting that He has a certain perfection, when we find it to be a
perfection in relation to us. The perfections are all to some extent
acquired properties, and a property which must be acquired does
not exist in everything capable of making such acquisition.
You must bear in mind, that by affirming anything of God, you are
removed from Him in two respects; first, whatever you affirm, is only
a perfection in relation to us; secondly, He does not possess
anything superadded to this essence; His essence includes all His
perfections, as we have shown. Since it is a well-known fact that
even that knowledge of God which is accessible to man cannot be
attained except by negations, and that negations [85]do not convey a
true idea of the being to which they refer, all people, both of past
and present generations, declared that God cannot be the object of
human comprehension, that none but Himself comprehends what He
is, and that our knowledge consists in knowing that we are unable
truly to comprehend Him. All philosophers say, “He has overpowered
us by His grace, and is invisible to us through the intensity of His
light,” like the sun which cannot be perceived by eyes which are too
weak to bear its rays. Much more has been said on this topic, but it
is useless to repeat it here. The idea is best expressed in the book of
Psalms, “Silence is praise to Thee” (lxv. 2). It is a very expressive
remark on this subject; for whatever we utter with the intention of
extolling and of praising Him, contains something that cannot be
applied to God, and includes derogatory expressions; it is therefore
more becoming to be silent, and to be content with intellectual
reflection, as has been recommended by men of the highest culture,
in the words “Commune with your own heart upon your bed, and be
still” (Ps. iv. 4). You must surely know the following celebrated
passage in the Talmud—would that all passages in the Talmud were
like that!—although it is known to you, I quote it literally, as I wish
to point out to you the ideas contained in it: “A certain person,
reading prayers in the presence of Rabbi Ḥaninah, said, ‘God, the
great, the valiant and the tremendous, the powerful, the strong, and
the mighty.’—The rabbi said to him, Have you finished all the praises
of your Master? The three epithets, ‘God, the great, the valiant and
the tremendous,’ we should not have applied to God, had Moses not
mentioned them in the Law, and had not the men of the Great
Synagogue come forward subsequently and established their use in
the prayer; and you say all this! Let this be illustrated by a parable.
There was once an earthly king, possessing millions of gold coin; he
was praised for owning millions of silver coin; was this not really
dispraise to him?” Thus far the opinion of the pious rabbi. Consider,
first, how repulsive and annoying the accumulation of all these
positive attributes was to him; next, how he showed that, if we had
only to follow our reason, we should never have composed these
prayers, and we should not have uttered any of them. It has,
however, become necessary to address men in words that should
leave some idea in their minds, and, in accordance with the saying
of our Sages, “The Torah speaks in the language of men,” the
Creator has been described to us in terms of our own perfections;
but we should not on that account have uttered any other than the
three above-mentioned attributes, and we should not have used
them as names of God except when meeting with them in reading
the Law. Subsequently, the men of the Great Synagogue, who were
prophets, introduced these expressions also into the prayer, but we
should not on that account use [in our prayers] any other attributes
of God. The principal lesson to be derived from this passage is that
there are two reasons for our employing those phrases in our
prayers: first, they occur in the Pentateuch; secondly, the Prophets
introduced them into the prayer. Were it not for the first reason, we
should never have uttered them; and were it not for the second
reason, we should not have copied them from the Pentateuch to
recite them in our prayers; how then could we approve of the use of
those numerous attributes! You also learn from this that we ought
not to mention and employ in our prayers all the attributes we find
applied [86]to God in the books of the Prophets; for he does not say,
“Were it not that Moses, our Teacher, said them, we should not have
been able to use them”; but he adds another condition—“and had
not the men of the Great Synagogue come forward and established
their use in the prayer,” because only for that reason are we allowed
to use them in our prayers. We cannot approve of what those foolish
persons do who are extravagant in praise, fluent and prolix in the
prayers they compose, and in the hymns they make in the desire to
approach the Creator. They describe God in attributes which would
be an offence if applied to a human being; for those persons have
no knowledge of these great and important principles, which are not
accessible to the ordinary intelligence of man. Treating the Creator
as a familiar object, they describe Him and speak of Him in any
expressions they think proper; they eloquently continue to praise
Him in that manner, and believe that they can thereby influence Him
and produce an effect on Him. If they find some phrase suited to
their object in the words of the Prophets they are still more inclined
to consider that they are free to make use of such texts—which
should at least be explained—to employ them in their literal sense,
to derive new expressions from them, to form from them numerous
variations, and to found whole compositions on them. This license is
frequently met with in the compositions of the singers, preachers,
and others who imagine themselves to be able to compose a poem.
Such authors write things which partly are real heresy, partly contain
such folly and absurdity that they naturally cause those who hear
them to laugh, but also to feel grieved at the thought that such
things can be uttered in reference to God. Were it not that I pitied
the authors for their defects, and did not wish to injure them, I
should have cited some passages to show you their mistakes;
besides, the fault of their compositions is obvious to all intelligent
persons. You must consider it, and think thus: If slander and libel is
a great sin, how much greater is the sin of those who speak with
looseness of tongue in reference to God, and describe Him by
attributes which are far below Him; and I declare that they not only
commit an ordinary sin, but unconsciously at least incur the guilt of
profanity and blasphemy. This applies both to the multitude that
listens to such prayers, and to the foolish man that recites them.
Men, however, who understand the fault of such compositions, and,
nevertheless, recite them, may be classed, according to my opinion,
among those to whom the following words are applied: “And the
children of Israel used words that were not right against the Lord
their God” (2 Kings xvii. 9); and “utter error against the Lord” (Isa.
xxxii. 6). If you are of those who regard the honour of their Creator,
do not listen in any way to them, much less utter what they say, and
still less compose such prayers, knowing how great is the offence of
one who hurls aspersions against the Supreme Being. There is no
necessity at all for you to use positive attributes of God with the
view of magnifying Him in your thoughts, or to go beyond the limits
which the men of the Great Synagogue have introduced in the
prayers and in the blessings, for this is sufficient for all purposes,
and even more than sufficient, as Rabbi Ḥaninah said. Other
attributes, such as occur in the books of the Prophets, may be
uttered when we meet with them in reading those books; but we
must bear in mind what has already been explained, that they are
either attributes of God’s actions, or expressions [87]implying the
negation of the opposite. This likewise should not be divulged to the
multitude; but a reflection of this kind is fitted for the few only who
believe that the glorification of God does not consist in uttering that
which is not to be uttered, but in reflecting on that on which man
should reflect.
I have already told you that all these attributes, whatever perfection
they may denote according to your idea, imply defects in reference
to God, if applied to Him in the same sense as they are used in
reference to ourselves. Solomon has already given us sufficient
instruction on this subject by saying, “For God is in heaven, and thou
upon earth; therefore let thy words be few” (Eccles. v. 2).
[Contents]
CHAPTER LX
I will give you in this chapter some illustrations, in order that you
may better understand the propriety of forming as many negative
attributes as possible, and the impropriety of ascribing to God any
positive attributes. A person may know for certain that a “ship” is in
existence, but he may not know to what object that name is applied,
whether to a substance or to an accident; a second person then
learns that the ship is not an accident; a third, that it is not a
mineral; a fourth, that it is not a plant growing in the earth; a fifth,
that it is not a body whose parts are joined together by nature; a
sixth, that it is not a flat object like boards or doors; a seventh, that
it is not a sphere; an eighth, that it is not pointed; a ninth, that it is
not round-shaped; nor equilateral; a tenth, that it is not solid. It is
clear that this tenth person has almost arrived at the correct notion
of a “ship” by the foregoing negative attributes, as if he had exactly
the same notion as those have who imagine it to be a wooden
substance which is hollow, long, and composed of many pieces of
wood, that is to say, who know it by positive attributes. Of the other
persons in our illustration, each one is more remote from the correct
notion of a ship than the next mentioned, so that the first knows
nothing about it but the name. In the same manner you will come
nearer to the knowledge and comprehension of God by the negative
attributes. But you must be careful, in what you negative, to
negative by proof, not by mere words, for each time you ascertain
by proof that a certain thing, believed to exist in the Creator, must
be negatived, you have undoubtedly come one step nearer to the
knowledge of God.
It is in this sense that some men come very near to God, and others
remain exceedingly remote from Him, not in the sense of those who
are deprived of vision, and believe that God occupies a place, which
man can physically [88]approach or from which he can recede.
Examine this well, know it, and be content with it. The way which
will bring you nearer to God has been clearly shown to you; walk in
it, if you have the desire. On the other hand, there is a great danger
in applying positive attributes to God. For it has been shown that
every perfection we could imagine, even if existing in God in
accordance with the opinion of those who assert the existence of
attributes, would in reality not be of the same kind as that imagined
by us, but would only be called by the same name, according to our
explanation; it would in fact amount to a negation. Suppose, e.g.,
you say He has knowledge, and that knowledge, which admits of no
change and of no plurality, embraces many changeable things; His
knowledge remains unaltered, while new things are constantly
formed, and His knowledge of a thing before it exists, while it exists,
and when it has ceased to exist, is the same without the least
change: you would thereby declare that His knowledge is not like
ours; and similarly that His existence is not like ours. You thus
necessarily arrive at some negation, without obtaining a true
conception of an essential attribute; on the contrary, you are led to
assume that there is a plurality in God, and to believe that He,
though one essence, has several unknown attributes. For if you
intend to affirm them, you cannot compare them with those
attributes known by us, and they are consequently not of the same
kind. You are, as it were, brought by the belief in the reality of the
attributes, to say that God is one subject of which several things are
predicated; though the subject is not like ordinary subjects, and the
predicates are not like ordinary predicates. This belief would
ultimately lead us to associate other things with God, and not to
believe that He is One. For of every subject certain things can
undoubtedly be predicated, and although in reality subject and
predicate are combined in one thing, by the actual definition they
consist of two elements, the notion contained in the subject not
being the same as that contained in the predicate. In the course of
this treatise it will be proved to you that God cannot be a compound,
and that He is simple in the strictest sense of the word.