DOVLAAv 1
DOVLAAv 1
Subject Areas:
neuroscience, cognition, behaviour
1. Introduction
Keywords: What is the role of the language system in embodied cognition? This paper offers a
concepts, embodied cognition, grounded theoretical framework for answering this pressing question. Building on Andy
cognition, language, semantic memory Clark’s suggestion that we are natural-born cyborgs [1], it proposes that language
can be thought of as a disruptive cognitive technology that transforms the embo-
died mind. Just as the adoption of new technologies often upends our social,
Author for correspondence:
cultural and economic lives, the acquisition of a natural language alters a child’s
Guy Dove cognitive purview. It disrupts embodied cognition by offering a new medium
e-mail: [email protected] through which to capture experience [2]. Experience with language leads to the
development of a distributed neural system able to manipulate linguistic symbols
in a compositional and productive fashion. The neurologically realized language
system amounts to a distributed action/perception control system that likely
relies on hierarchically organized network hubs. Linguistic forms themselves are
grounded because they involve actions, sights and sounds, but they are free to
capture content in a manner that is not tied to their grounding [3].
On this view, language is an external symbol system—one that has the
computational features associated with amodal symbol systems—that we learn
to manipulate in an embodied and grounded way. It is just one of the externally
sourced symbol technologies that we may acquire [4]. For example, learning how
to perform long division on paper requires a similar grounded manipulation of,
and interaction with, physical symbols [5,6]. The specialness of language has to do
with the pervasive role that it plays in our cognitive lives and the way in which it
complements embodied cognition by enhancing our capacity to encode infor-
mation about the world that goes beyond our immediate experience. This
proposal creates a number of predictions. First and foremost, it predicts that
much of our conceptual system is not grounded in language but is instead directly
grounded in action, emotion and perception systems. Importantly, such thinking
without words has its own compositionality and productivity [7,8]. Second, while
language is likely to contribute to all types of concepts, it is more likely to be help-
ful with abstract ones. Third, as a cognitive tool, the role of language should be
flexible, context-sensitive and experience-dependent. Finally, because a natural
& 2018 The Author(s) Published by the Royal Society. All rights reserved.
language is an acquired neuroenhancement, its influence concepts such as DEMOCRACY, FREEDOM, LEPTON, 2
should change over the course of development. NUMBER and TRUTH may simply represent one end of a spec-
rstb.royalsocietypublishing.org
The purpose of this essay is to outline and defend the dis- trum. Researchers often demarcate abstract concepts by one of
ruptive technology view. The argument proceeds at two several measures, including body–object interaction [20], concre-
levels: the general and the specific. While much of the essay teness [21], context-availability [22], emotional valence [23],
is aimed at the big picture and endeavours to show that the imageability [24], semantic richness [25] and strength of percep-
neuroenhancement view integrates and unifies seemingly tual experience [26]. Importantly, while these measures correlate
disparate threads of current research, the last section exam- to some extent, they are not equivalent [23]. Such divergence
ines the way in which it offers a promising explanation of a suggests that abstract concepts may form a heterogeneous
particular linguistic/conceptual phenomenon—metaphor. class. Indeed, a cogent argument can be made that researchers
Together these elements provide a compelling case for think- have been too cavalier in assuming that abstract concepts are
ing that language augments and extends the cognitive reach homogeneous [27]. In this paper, I shall not make this assump-
rstb.royalsocietypublishing.org
behind them and then offer an overarching theory that inte- In particular, WAT theory predicts that abstract concepts
grates these generalizations and exhibits both explanatory should exhibit a greater tendency to engage language areas
and predictive power. [59,60]. The third tenet is that these neuroanatomical differ-
Embodied cognition posits an intimate link between ences should lead to differences in embodiment: namely, the
cognition and experience, and a great deal of our experience sensorimotor systems associated with speech production and
is with language itself. Some have proposed that this raises perception should be more engaged by abstract concepts [61].
the possibility of merging embodied and distributional Finally, because of their greater reliance on linguistic
approaches to word meaning [42,45–47]. Traditionally, these input, abstract concepts should exhibit greater cross-linguistic
approaches have been viewed as competitors; embodied variability than concrete ones.
accounts have focused on situated interactions with the world In sum, there are at least three distinct general conceptions
rstb.royalsocietypublishing.org
novel or radical. Indeed, several recent reviews [11,63,70] [85], for instance, articulates a radically interactive view of
suggest that weak embodiment has become the favoured neural reuse while explicitly remaining committed to embo-
view among supporters of embodied and grounded cognition. diment. Nevertheless, one may think that the dependence
The second part of my strategy involves developing a theoreti- of this approach on intermediate representations undermines
cal account of the way in which our experience with language the theoretical bite of embodiment [86]. My response to this
augments our concepts. The key idea will be that language not worry is similar to the one offered above: what ultimately
only provides access to new sources of information about the matters is getting the theory right. If the conjunction of the
world, but also transforms us as thinkers. flexible mind hypothesis and the appeal to the language
system amounts to an abandonment of authentic embodied
cognition, then so be it.
rstb.royalsocietypublishing.org
that is independent of the combinatorial properties of essay not only because it may play a role in the acquisition of
non-linguistic embodied and grounded cognition. This inde- some abstract concepts, but also because it serves as a useful
pendent structural flexibility may make it easier to generate test case for the disruptive technology approach.
new thoughts and encode unexpected connections between Metaphor has traditionally been seen as both a source of
thoughts [95,96]. Developing this idea further, Lynott & evidence for embodiment and a potential means of solving
Connell [97] propose that conceptual combination arises from the problem abstract concepts. Working from observations
the interaction between the linguistic and simulation systems. concerning language use, cognitive linguists have shown that
Some researchers who acknowledge that linguistic represen- a great deal of our discourse is organized around experiential
tations have a role to play in conceptual tasks suggest that this metaphors [101,102]. Several have proposed that we rely on
role is typically more superficial and less effective than that of embodied conceptual metaphors to understand abstract con-
rstb.royalsocietypublishing.org
linguistic associations. This prediction fits with the hypothesis the present is light), congruency effects were found in the
that some metaphors may undergo a gradual process of conven- weight judgements of books that appeared new or old [133].
tionalization as they become more familiar [126]. Desai et al. It is also supported by the fact that providing participants
[127] examine the brain activation elicited by four types of sen- with a brief exposure to mirror-reversed orthography can
tences: literal action sentences (The instructor is grasping the reverse the orientation of the congruency effects on temporal
steering wheel very tightly.), non-idiomatic metaphor sentences judgements associated with a particular language [134]. Some
(The congress is grasping the state of affairs.), idiomatic meta- recent evidence also suggests that language-specific metaphors
phor sentences (The congress is grasping at straws in the may build upon preexisting non-linguistic embodied map-
crisis.) and abstract sentences (The congress is causing a big pings. Whereas speakers of Dutch tend to talk of musical
trade deficit again.). They found that higher-level sensorimotor pitch in terms of height (the way that we do in English), speak-
References
1. Clark A. 2003 Natural-born cyborgs. New York, NY: 3. Dove G. 2011 On the need for embodied and dis- 5. Landy D, Allen C, Zednik C. 2014 A perceptual
Oxford University Press. embodied cognition. Front. Psychol. 1, 242. (doi:10. account of symbolic reasoning. Front. Psychol. 5,
2. Dove G. 2014 Thinking in words: language 3389/fpsyg.2010.00242) 275. (doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00275)
as an embodied medium of thought. 4. Clark A. 2011 Supersizing the mind: embodiment, 6. Landy D, Goldstone RL. 2007 How abstract is symbolic
Topics Cogn. Sci. 6, 371–389. (doi:10.1111/ action, and cognitive extension. New York, NY: thought? J. Exp. Psychol. Learn. Mem. Cogn. 33,
tops.12102) Oxford University Press. 720–733. (doi:10.1037/0278-7393.33.4.720)
7. Barsalou L. 1999 Perceptual symbol systems. Behav. Verb. Behav. 16, 217– 231. (doi:10.1016/S0022- language modulates motor system activity. Q. 7
Brain Sci. 22, 577 –609. (doi:10.1017/S0140525X 5371(77)80048-0) J. Exp. Psychol. 61, 905–919. (doi:10.1080/
rstb.royalsocietypublishing.org
9002149) 22. Schwanenflugel PJ, Shoben E. 1983 Differential 17470210701625550)
8. Barsalou LW, Prinz JJ. 1997 Mundane creativity in context effects in the comprehension of abstract and 39. Guan CQ, Meng W, Yao R, Glenberg AM. 2013
perceptual symbol systems. In Creative thought: an concrete verbal materials. J. Exp. Psychol. 9, 82 – The motor system contributes to comprehension of
investigation of conceptual structures and processes 102. (doi:10.1037/0278-7393.9.1.82) abstract language. PLoS ONE 8, e75183. (doi:10.
(eds TB Ward, SM Smith, J Vaid), pp. 267– 307. 23. Kousta S-T, Vigliocco G, Vinson DP, Andrews M, Del 1371/journal.pone.0075183)
Washington, DC: American Psychological Campo E. 2011 The representation of abstract 40. Lynott D, Connell L. 2010 Embodied conceptual
Association. words: why emotion matters. J. Exp. Psychol. 140, combination. Front. Psychol. 1, 212. (doi:10.3389/
9. Barsalou LW. 2008 Grounded cognition. Annu. Rev. 14 –34. (doi:10.1037/a0021446) fpsyg.2010.00212)
Psychol. 59, 617 –645. (doi:10.1146/annurev.psych. 24. Paivio A. 1986 Mental representations: a dual coding 41. Barsalou LW, Santos A, Simmons KW, Wilson CD.
59.103006.093639) approach. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. 2008 Language and simulations in conceptual
rstb.royalsocietypublishing.org
53. Pulvermüller F. 2017 Neural reuse of action (doi:10.1016/j.tics.2013.09.012) perception and action in memory, language, and
perception circuits for language, concepts, and 70. Barsalou LW. 2016 On staying grounded and thought (eds D Pecher, R Zwaan), pp. 224–245.
communication. Prog. Neurobiol. 160, 1–44. avoiding quixotic dead ends. Psychon. Bull. Rev. 23, New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
(doi:10.1016/j.pneurobio.2017.07.001) 1122 –1142. (doi:10.3758/s13423-016-1028-3) 88. Fodor JA. 1975 The language of thought.
54. Lupyan G, Bergen B. 2016 How language programs 71. Wilson AD, Golonka S. 2013 Embodied cognition is Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
the mind. Topics Cogn. Sci. 8, 408 –424. not what you think it is. Front. Psychol. 4, 58. 89. Pylyshyn ZW. 1989 Computation and cognition:
55. Edmiston P, Lupyan G. 2015 What makes words (doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00058) toward a foundation for cognitive science.
special? Words as unmotivated cues. Cognition 143, 72. Yee E, Thompson-Schill SL. 2016 Putting concepts Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
93 –100. (doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2015.06.008) into context. Psychon. Bull. Rev. 23, 1015–1027. 90. Vygotsky L. 1986 Thought and language.
56. Lupyan G, Thompson-Schill SL. 2012 The evocative (doi:10.3758/s13423-015-0948-7) Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
rstb.royalsocietypublishing.org
Cognition 36, 1047 –1056. Psychol. 12, 289–297. (doi:10.1037/0012-1649.12. 128. Casasanto D. 2008 Who’s afraid of the big bad
107. Boroditsky L, Ramscar M. 2002 The roles of body 4.289) whorf? Crosslinguistic differences in temporal
and mind in abstract thought. Psychol. Sci. 13, 119. MacKay G, Shaw A. 2004 A comparative study of language and thought. Lang. Learn. 58(Suppl. 1),
185–188. (doi:10.1111/1467-9280.00434) figurative language in children with autistic 63– 79. (doi:10.1111/j.1467-9922.2008.00462.x)
108. Casasanto D, Boroditsky L. 2008 Time in the mind: spectrum disorders. Child Lang. Teach. Therapy 20, 129. Gentner D, Goldin-Meadow S (eds). 2003 Language
using space to think about time. Cognition 106, 13 –32. (doi:10.1191/0265659004ct261oa) in mind: advances in the study of language and
579–593. (doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2007.03.004) 120. Boulenger V, Shtyrov Y, Pulvermüller F. 2012 When thought, pp. 157 –192. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
109. Ouellet M, Santiago J, Israeli Z, Gabay S. 2010 Is the do you grasp the idea? MEG evidence for 130. Lupyan G. 2012 What do words do? Toward a
future the right time? Exp. Psychol. 57, 308 –314. instantaneous idiom understanding. Neuroimage theory of language-augmented thought. In The
(doi:10.1027/1618-3169/a000036) 59, 3502–3513. (doi:10.1016/j.neuroimage.2011. psychology of learning and motivation, vol. 57,