Chapter 2 HISTORY OF MATHEMATICS
Chapter 2 HISTORY OF MATHEMATICS
MATHEMATICS
CHAPTER 2: THE DEVELOPMENT OF MATHEMATICS: A
HISTORICAL OVERVIEW: MEDIEVAL PERIOD
Lesson 1: Medieval Period and Renaissance
A. Medieval Period
Europe during the Middle Ages
With the third century after Christ begins an era of migration of nations in
Europe. The powerful Goths quit their swamps and forests in the North and sweep
onward in steady southwestern current, dislodging the Vandals, Sueves, and
Burgundians, crossing the Roman territory, and stopping and recoiling only when
reaching the shores of the Mediterranean. The Roman Empire falls to pieces, and the
Dark Ages begin. But dark though they seem, they are the germinating season of the
institutions and nations of modern Europe. The Teutonic element, partly pure, partly
intermixed with the Celtic and Latin, produces that strong and luxuriant growth, the
modern civilization of Europe. Almost all the various nations of Europe belong to the
Aryan stock. As the Greeks and the Hindoos -- both Aryan races -- were the great
thinkers of antiquity, so the nations north of the Alps became the great intellectual
leaders of modern times.
A. Medieval Period
Introduction of Roman Mathematics
After the time of Boethius and Cassiodorius mathematical
activity in Italy died out. The first slender blossom of science among
tribes that came from the North was an encyclopedia entitled
Origines, written by Isidorus (died 636 as bishop of Seville). This
work is modelled after the Roman encyclopaedias of Martianus
Capella of Carthage and of Cassiodorius. Part of it is devoted to the
quadrivium, arithmetic, music, geometry, and astronomy.
Bede the Venerable (672-735), the most learned man of his time. His works
contain treatises on the Computus, or the computation of Easter-time, and on
finger-reckoning. It appears that a finger symbolism was then widely used for
calculation. It became desirable to have at least one monk at each monastery who
could determine the day of religious festivals and could compute the calendar.
Such determinations required some knowledge of arithmetic.
A. Medieval Period
Introduction of Roman Mathematics
The year in which Bede died, Alcuin (735-804) was born. Alcuin was
educated in Ireland, and was called to the court of Charlemagne to direct the
progress of education in the great Frankish Empire. In the great sees and
monasteries he founded schools in which were taught the psalms, writing,
singing, computation (computus), and grammar. It is not likely that Alcuin
was familiar with the apices of Boethius or with the Roman method of
reckoning on the abacus. He belongs to that long list of scholars who dragged
the theory of numbers into theology. Thus the number of beings created by
God, who created all things well, is 6, because 6 is a perfect number (the sum
of its divisors being 1 + 2 + 3 = 6); 8, on the other hand, is an imperfect
number (1+2+4 < 8); hence the second origin of mankind emanated from the
number 8, which is the number of souls said to have been in Noah's ark.
A. Medieval Period
Introduction of Roman Mathematics
Gerbert. he engaged in study, chiefly of mathematics, in Spain.
-Such was the career of the greatest mathematician of the tenth century in Europe.
By his contemporaries his mathematical knowledge was considered wonderful.
Many even accused him of criminal intercourse with evil spirits.
-he found the geometry of Boethius. It was at that time the only book from
which European scholars could learn the elements of geometry.
-He generally believed himself to be the author of geometry.
-He explained the reason why the area of a triangle, obtained
“geometrically" by taking the product of the base by half its altitude, differs
1
from the area calculated “arithmetically," according to the formula a(a +
2
1), used by surveyors.
-He died in 1003, after a life intricately involved in many political and
ecclesiastical quarrels.
A. Medieval Period
Translation of Arabic Manuscripts
Gerbert infused new life into the study not only of mathematics, but
also of philosophy. Pupils from France, Germany, and Italy gathered at
Rheims to enjoy his instruction. When they themselves became
teachers, they taught of course not only the use of the abacus and
geometry, but also what they had learned of the philosophy of Aristotle.
This led them finally to search for and translate Arabic manuscripts.
During this search, mathematical works also came to their notice, and
were translated into Latin. Though some few unimportant works may
have been translated earlier, yet the period of greatest activity began
about 1100.
A. Medieval Period
Translation of Arabic Manuscripts
At this time Cardan was writing his Ars Magna, and he knew no better way to
crown his work than by inserting the much sought for rules for solving
cubics. Thus Cardan took all recognitions about cubics but Tartaglia
reclaimed them all by challenging Cardan and his students for a battle. After
having recovered himself again, Tartaglia began, in 1556, the publication of
the work which he had had in his mind for so long; but he died before he
reached the consideration of cubic equations. Thus the fondest wish of his life
remained unfulfilled; the man to whom we owe the greatest contribution to
algebra made in the sixteenth century was forgotten, and his method came to
be regarded as the discovery of Cardan and to be called Cardan's solution.
A. Renaissance
Algebraic Equations
In the fall of 1661, the same date that Newton entered Cambridge, Leibniz became
a student at the university of his native city, Leipzig. Only 15 at the time, he was
regarded as something of a prodigy and soon outstripped all his contemporaries.
Arithmetic was taught at an elementary level, prescribed by the textbooks of the
German Jesuit Christoph Clavius (1537–1612). Leibniz was given a teaching
position in the philosophical faculty at Leipzig, for which he qualified by writing
Disputatio Arithmetica de Complexionibus; this work, which was expanded into Ars
Combinatoria (1666), extensively develops the theory of permutations and
combinations for the purpose of making logical deductions. Moreover, Leibniz
suggested that a calculus of reasoning could be devised that would provide an
automatic method of solution for all problems that could be expressed in his
scientific language.
Birth of Calculus
Leibniz’s Creation of the Calculus
In the years from 1672 to 1676, spent in Paris, Leibniz’s slowly powering
mathematical genius matured. (This concentrated period of creativity is
reminiscent of Newton’s golden years” 1664–1666 at Woolsthorpe.) During this
time, he developed the principal features and notation of his version of the
calculus. Various methods had been invented for determining the tangent lines
to certain classes of curves, but as yet nobody had made known similar
procedures for solving the inverse problem, that is, deriving the equation of the
curve itself from the properties of its tangents. Leibniz stated the inverse
tangent problem thus: “To find the locus of the function, provided the locus
which determines the subtangent is known.”
Birth of Calculus
Newton’s Fluxional Calculus
Before Leibniz left Paris in the autumn of 1676, he found himself
in possession of the rules and notation of his calculus. He
suspected, but could not be sure, that Newton had developed an
equivalent approach, one far more geometrically slanted. This was
precisely the case. Newton was in his twenties, during the same
period in which he had discovered the binomial theorem. The bulk
of Newton’s early work on calculus was condensed into a small
treatise of some 30 crowded pages, covering such things as
tangency, curvature, centers of gravity, and area. The work, which
Newton seems never to have given a definite title, is known in the
learned literature as the October 1666 Tract.
Birth of Calculus
Newton’s Fluxional Calculus
Throughout the year, Leibniz had become keenly interested in the mathematical
writings of Newton and had asked Oldenburg for further information about them.
The first letter contained the binomial theorem, as well as a summary of Newton’s
more important work on series. Although nothing was said of his secret discovery of
uxions, there was a vague hint that Newton had an important method in mind.
Newton could not refuse Oldenburg’s request to give Leibniz the information he
wanted but was still disinclined to divulge his secret. Thus it came about that
although Newton had invented his method of uxions many years before Leibniz had
invented his rival method of “differences,” Leibniz was the first of the two to publish
and to make known to the learned world his results. Had Newton secured
publication for his De Methodis Fluxionum when it was originally written in 1671, he
would have had no competitor, and mathematical history might well have taken a
different course.
HISTORY OF
MATHEMATICS
CHAPTER 2: THE DEVELOPMENT OF MATHEMATICS: A
HISTORICAL OVERVIEW: MEDIEVAL PERIOD
Lesson 3. Euler, Fermat and Descartes
Euler, Fermat and Descartes
René Descartes
In the Greek geometry, the idea of motion was wanting, but with
Descartes it became a very fruitful conception. By him a point on
a plane was determined in position by its distances from two
fixed right lines or axes. These distances varied with every change
of position in the point. This geometric idea of co-ordinate
representation, together with the algebraic idea of two variables
in one equation having an indefinite number of simultaneous
values, furnished a method for the study of loci, which is
admirable for the generality of its solutions. Thus the entire conic
sections of Apollonius is wrapped up and contained in a single
equation of the second degree.
Euler, Fermat and Descartes
René Descartes