Preface Intro
Preface Intro
Where Mathematics
Comes From
How the Embodied Mind
Brings Mathematics
into Being
George Lakoff
Rafael E. Núñez
FIRST EDITION
00 01 02 03 / 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1
0465037704fm.qxd 8/23/00 9:49 AM Page xi
Preface
xi
0465037704fm.qxd 8/23/00 9:49 AM Page xii
xii Preface
But those of us who study the nature of concepts within cognitive science
know, from research in that field, that the study of human ideas is not so sim-
ple. Human ideas are, to a large extent, grounded in sensory-motor experience.
Abstract human ideas make use of precisely formulatable cognitive mecha-
nisms such as conceptual metaphors that import modes of reasoning from sen-
sory-motor experience. It is always an empirical question just what human
ideas are like, mathematical or not.
The central question we ask is this: How can cognitive science bring sys-
tematic scientific rigor to the realm of human mathematical ideas, which lies
outside the rigor of mathematics itself? Our job is to help make precise what
mathematics itself cannot—the nature of mathematical ideas.
Rafael Núñez brings to this effort a background in mathematics education,
the development of mathematical ideas in children, the study of mathematics
in indigenous cultures around the world, and the investigation of the founda-
tions of embodied cognition. George Lakoff is a major researcher in human con-
ceptual systems, known for his research in natural-language semantics, his
work on the embodiment of mind, and his discovery of the basic mechanisms
of everyday metaphorical thought.
The general enterprise began in the early 1990s with the detailed analysis by
one of Lakoff’s students, Ming Ming Chiu (now a professor at the Chinese Uni-
versity in Hong Kong), of the basic system of metaphors used by children to
comprehend and reason about arithmetic. In Switzerland, at about the same
time, Núñez had begun an intellectual quest to answer these questions: How
can human beings understand the idea of actual infinity—infinity conceptual-
ized as a thing, not merely as an unending process? What is the concept of ac-
tual infinity in its mathematical manifestations—points at infinity, infinite
sets, infinite decimals, infinite intersections, transfinite numbers, infinitesi-
mals? He reasoned that since we do not encounter actual infinity directly in the
world, since our conceptual systems are finite, and since we have no cognitive
mechanisms to perceive infinity, there is a good possibility that metaphorical
thought may be necessary for human beings to conceptualize infinity. If so, new
results about the structure of metaphorical concepts might make it possible to
precisely characterize the metaphors used in mathematical concepts of infinity.
With a grant from the Swiss NSF, he came to Berkeley in 1993 to take up this
idea with Lakoff.
We soon realized that such a question could not be answered in isolation. We
would need to develop enough of the foundations of mathematical idea analysis
so that the question could be asked and answered in a precise way. We would need
to understand the cognitive structure not only of basic arithmetic but also of sym-
0465037704fm.qxd 8/23/00 9:49 AM Page xiii
Preface xiii
bolic logic, the Boolean logic of classes, set theory, parts of algebra, and a fair
amount of classical mathematics: analytic geometry, trigonometry, calculus, and
complex numbers. That would be a task of many lifetimes. Because of other com-
mitments, we had only a few years to work on the project—and only part-time.
So we adopted an alternative strategy. We asked, What would be the mini-
mum background needed
xiv Preface
One of the great findings of cognitive science is that our ideas are shaped by
our bodily experiences—not in any simpleminded one-to-one way but indi-
rectly, through the grounding of our entire conceptual system in everyday life.
The cognitive perspective forces us to ask, Is the system of mathematical ideas
also grounded indirectly in bodily experiences? And if so, exactly how?
The answer to questions as deep as these requires an understanding of the
cognitive superstructure of a whole nexus of mathematical ideas. This book is
concerned with how such cognitive superstructures are built up, starting for the
most part with the commonest of physical experiences.
To make our discussion of classical mathematics tractable while still show-
ing its depth and richness, we have limited ourselves to one profound and cen-
tral question: What does Euler’s classic equation, e!i + 1 = 0, mean? This
equation links all the major branches of classical mathematics. It is proved in
introductory calculus courses. The equation itself mentions only numbers and
mathematical operations on them. What is lacking, from a cognitive perspec-
tive, is an analysis of the ideas implicit in the equation, the ideas that charac-
terize those branches of classical mathematics, the way those ideas are linked
in the equation, and why the truth of the equation follows from those ideas. To
demonstrate the utility of mathematical idea analysis for classical mathemat-
ics, we set out to provide an initial idea analysis for that equation that would
answer all these questions. This is done in the case-study chapters at the end of
the book.
To show that mathematical idea analysis has some importance for the phi-
losophy of mathematics, we decided to apply our techniques of analysis to a
pivotal moment in the history of mathematics—the arithmetization of real
numbers and calculus by Dedekind and Weierstrass in 1872. These dramatic de-
velopments set the stage for the age of mathematical rigor and the Foundations
of Mathematics movement. We wanted to understand exactly what ideas were
involved in those developments. We found the answer to be far from obvious:
The modern notion of mathematical rigor and the Foundations of Mathematics
movement both rest on a sizable collection of crucial conceptual metaphors.
In addition, we wanted to see if mathematical idea analysis made any differ-
ence at all in how mathematics is understood. We discovered that it did: What
is called the real-number line is not a line as most people understand it. What
is called the continuum is not continuous in the ordinary sense of the term.
And what are called space-filling curves do not fill space as we normally con-
ceive of it. These are not mathematical discoveries but discoveries about how
mathematics is conceptualized—that is, discoveries in the cognitive science of
mathematics.
0465037704fm.qxd 8/23/00 9:49 AM Page xv
Preface xv
xvi Preface
But the more we have applied what we know about cognitive science to un-
derstand the cognitive structure of mathematics, the more it has become clear
that this romance cannot be true. Human mathematics, the only kind of mathe-
matics that human beings know, cannot be a subspecies of an abstract, transcen-
dent mathematics. Instead, it appears that mathematics as we know it arises from
the nature of our brains and our embodied experience. As a consequence, every
part of the romance appears to be false, for reasons that we will be discussing.
Perhaps most surprising of all, we have discovered that a great many of the
most fundamental mathematical ideas are inherently metaphorical in nature:
And as we shall see, Núñez was right about the centrality of conceptual
metaphor to a full understanding of infinity in mathematics. There are two in-
finity concepts in mathematics—one literal and one metaphorical. The literal
concept (“in-finity”—lack of an end) is called “potential infinity.” It is simply a
process that goes on without end, like counting without stopping, extending a
line segment indefinitely, or creating polygons with more and more sides. No
metaphorical ideas are needed in this case. Potential infinity is a useful notion
in mathematics, but the main event is elsewhere. The idea of “actual infinity,”
where infinity becomes a thing—an infinite set, a point at infinity, a transfinite
number, the sum of an infinite series—is what is really important. Actual in-
finity is fundamentally a metaphorical idea, just as Núñez had suspected. The
surprise for us was that all forms of actual infinity—points at infinity, infinite
intersections, transfinite numbers, and so on—appear to be special cases of just
one Basic Metaphor of Infinity. This is anything but obvious and will be dis-
cussed at length in the course of the book.
As we have learned more and more about the nature of human mathematical
cognition, the Romance of Mathematics has dissolved before our eyes. What has
0465037704fm.qxd 8/23/00 9:49 AM Page xvii
Preface xvii
emerged in its place is an even more beautiful picture—a picture of what math-
ematics really is. One of our main tasks in this book is to sketch that picture
for you.
None of what we have discovered is obvious. Moreover, it requires a prior un-
derstanding of a fair amount of basic cognitive semantics and of the overall cog-
nitive structure of mathematics. That is why we have taken the trouble to write
a book of this breadth and depth. We hope you enjoy reading it as much as we
have enjoyed writing it.
0465037704fm.qxd 8/23/00 9:49 AM Page xviii
0465037704-01.qxd 8/23/00 9:52 AM Page 1
Introduction:
Why Cognitive Science
Matters to Mathematics
1. Exactly what mechanisms of the human brain and mind allow human
beings to formulate mathematical ideas and reason mathematically?
2. Is brain-and-mind-based mathematics all that mathematics is? Or is
there, as Platonists have suggested, a disembodied mathematics tran-
scending all bodies and minds and structuring the universe—this uni-
verse and every possible universe?
1
0465037704-01.qxd 8/23/00 9:52 AM Page 2
2 Introduction
Question 1 asks where mathematical ideas come from and how mathemati-
cal ideas are to be analyzed from a cognitive perspective. Question 1 is a scien-
tific question, a question to be answered by cognitive science, the
interdisciplinary science of the mind. As an empirical question about the
human mind and brain, it cannot be studied purely within mathematics. And
as a question for empirical science, it cannot be answered by an a priori philos-
ophy or by mathematics itself. It requires an understanding of human cognitive
processes and the human brain. Cognitive science matters to mathematics be-
cause only cognitive science can answer this question.
Question 1 is what this book is mostly about. We will be asking how normal
human cognitive mechanisms are employed in the creation and understanding
of mathematical ideas. Accordingly, we will be developing techniques of math-
ematical idea analysis.
But it is Question 2 that is at the heart of the philosophy of mathematics. It
is the question that most people want answered. Our answer is straightforward:
Introduction 3
This book aspires to tell you what human mathematics, conceptualized via
human brains and minds, is like. Given the present and foreseeable state of our
scientific knowledge, human mathematics is mathematics. What human math-
ematical concepts are is what mathematical concepts are.
We hope that this will be of interest to you whatever your philosophical or
religious beliefs about the existence of a transcendent mathematics.
There is an important part of this argument that needs further elucidation.
What accounts for what the physicist Eugene Wigner has referred to as “the un-
reasonable effectiveness of mathematics in the natural sciences” (Wigner,
1960)? How can we make sense of the fact that scientists have been able to find
or fashion forms of mathematics that accurately characterize many aspects of
the physical world and even make correct predictions? It is sometimes assumed
that the effectiveness of mathematics as a scientific tool shows that mathe-
matics itself exists in the structure of the physical universe. This, of course, is
not a scientific argument with any empirical scientific basis.
We will take this issue up in detail in Part V of the book. Our argument, in
brief, will be that whatever “fit” there is between mathematics and the world
occurs in the minds of scientists who have observed the world closely, learned
the appropriate mathematics well (or invented it), and fit them together (often
effectively) using their all-too-human minds and brains.
0465037704-01.qxd 8/23/00 9:52 AM Page 4
4 Introduction
These arguments will have more weight when we have discussed in detail
what human mathematical concepts are. That, as we shall see, depends upon
what the human body, brain, and mind are like. A crucial point is the argument
in (3)—that conceptual metaphor structures mathematics as human beings con-
ceptualize it. Bear that in mind as you read our discussions of conceptual
metaphors in mathematics.
Introduction 5
1. The embodiment of mind. The detailed nature of our bodies, our brains,
and our everyday functioning in the world structures human concepts
and human reason. This includes mathematical concepts and mathe-
matical reason.
2. The cognitive unconscious. Most thought is unconscious—not re-
pressed in the Freudian sense but simply inaccessible to direct con-
scious introspection. We cannot look directly at our conceptual systems
and at our low-level thought processes. This includes most mathemat-
ical thought.
3. Metaphorical thought. For the most part, human beings conceptualize
abstract concepts in concrete terms, using ideas and modes of reasoning
grounded in the sensory-motor system. The mechanism by which the
abstract is comprehended in terms of the concrete is called conceptual
metaphor. Mathematical thought also makes use of conceptual
metaphor, as when we conceptualize numbers as points on a line.
Mathematics is one of the most profound and beautiful endeavors of the imag-
ination that human beings have ever engaged in. Yet many of its beauties and
profundities have been inaccessible to nonmathematicians, because most of the
cognitive structure of mathematics has gone undescribed. Up to now, even the
basic ideas of college mathematics have appeared impenetrable, mysterious,
and paradoxical to many well-educated people who have approached them. We
0465037704-01.qxd 8/23/00 9:52 AM Page 6
6 Introduction
believe that cognitive science can, in many cases, dispel the paradoxes and clear
away the shrouds of mystery to reveal in full clarity the magnificence of those
ideas. To do so, it must reveal how mathematics is grounded in embodied ex-
perience and how conceptual metaphors structure mathematical ideas.
Many of the confusions, enigmas, and seeming paradoxes of mathematics
arise because conceptual metaphors that are part of mathematics are not recog-
nized as metaphors but are taken as literal. When the full metaphorical charac-
ter of mathematical concepts is revealed, such confusions and apparent
paradoxes disappear.
But the conceptual metaphors themselves do not disappear. They cannot be
analyzed away. Metaphors are an essential part of mathematical thought, not
just auxiliary mechanisms used for visualization or ease of understanding. Con-
sider the metaphor that Numbers Are Points on a Line. Numbers don’t have to
be conceptualized as points on a line; there are conceptions of number that are
not geometric. But the number line is one of the most central concepts in all of
mathematics. Analytic geometry would not exist without it, nor would
trigonometry.
Or take the metaphor that Numbers Are Sets, which was central to the Foun-
dations movement of early-twentieth-century mathematics. We don’t have to
conceptualize numbers as sets. Arithmetic existed for over two millennia with-
out this metaphor—that is, without zero conceptualized as being the empty set,
1 as the set containing the empty set, 2 as the set containing 0 and 1, and so on.
But if we do use this metaphor, then forms of reasoning about sets can also
apply to numbers. It is only by virtue of this metaphor that the classical Foun-
dations of Mathematics program can exist.
Conceptual metaphor is a cognitive mechanism for allowing us to reason
about one kind of thing as if it were another. This means that metaphor is not
simply a linguistic phenomenon, a mere figure of speech. Rather, it is a cogni-
tive mechanism that belongs to the realm of thought. As we will see later in the
book, “conceptual metaphor” has a technical meaning: It is a grounded, infer-
ence-preserving cross-domain mapping—a neural mechanism that allows us to
use the inferential structure of one conceptual domain (say, geometry) to reason
about another (say, arithmetic). Such conceptual metaphors allow us to apply
what we know about one branch of mathematics in order to reason about an-
other branch.
Conceptual metaphor makes mathematics enormously rich. But it also brings
confusion and apparent paradox if the metaphors are not made clear or are taken
to be literal truth. Is zero a point on a line? Or is it the empty set? Or both? Or
is it just a number and neither a point nor a set? There is no one answer. Each
0465037704-01.qxd 8/23/00 9:52 AM Page 7
Introduction 7
8 Introduction
And yet we are told that the answer is –1. The typical proof is of no help here.
It proves that e!i + 1 = 0 is true, but it does not tell you what e!i means! In the
course of this book, we will.
In this book, unlike most other books about mathematics, we will be con-
cerned not just with what is true but with what mathematical ideas mean, how
they can be understood, and why they are true. We will also be concerned with
the nature of mathematical truth from the perspective of a mind-based mathe-
matics.
One of our main concerns will be the concept of infinity in its various man-
ifestations: infinite sets, transfinite numbers, infinite series, the point at infin-
ity, infinitesimals, and objects created by taking values of sequences “at
infinity,” such as space-filling curves. We will show that there is a single Basic
Metaphor of Infinity that all of these are special cases of. This metaphor origi-
nates outside mathematics, but it appears to be the basis of our understanding
of infinity in virtually all mathematical domains. When we understand the
Basic Metaphor of Infinity, many classic mysteries disappear and the apparently
incomprehensible becomes relatively easy to understand.
The results of our inquiry are, for the most part, not mathematical results but
results in the cognitive science of mathematics. They are results about the
human conceptual system that makes mathematical ideas possible and in
which mathematics makes sense. But to a large extent they are not results re-
flecting the conscious thoughts of mathematicians; rather, they describe the un-
conscious conceptual system used by people who do mathematics. The results
of our inquiry should not change mathematics in any way, but they may radi-
cally change the way mathematics is understood and what mathematical re-
sults are taken to mean.
Some of our findings may be startling to many readers. Here are some examples:
• Symbolic logic is not the basis of all rationality, and it is not absolutely
true. It is a beautiful metaphorical system, which has some rather
bizarre metaphors. It is useful for certain purposes but quite inadequate
for characterizing anything like the full range of the mechanisms of
human reason.
• The real numbers do not “fill” the number line. There is a mathemati-
cal subject matter, the hyperreal numbers, in which the real numbers
are rather sparse on the line.
• The modern definition of continuity for functions, as well as the so-
called continuum, do not use the idea of continuity as it is normally
understood.
0465037704-01.qxd 8/23/00 9:52 AM Page 9
Introduction 9
These are not new mathematical findings but new ways of understanding
well-known results. They are findings in the cognitive science of mathemat-
ics—results about the conceptual structure of mathematics and about the role
of the mind in creating mathematical subject matters.
Though our research does not affect mathematical results in themselves, it
does have a bearing on the understanding of mathematical results and on the
claims made by many mathematicians. Our research also matters for the phi-
losophy of mathematics. Mind-based mathematics, as we describe it in this
book, is not consistent with any of the existing philosophies of mathematics:
Platonism, intuitionism, and formalism. Nor is it consistent with recent post-
modernist accounts of mathematics as a purely social construction. Based on
our findings, we will be suggesting a very different approach to the philosophy
of mathematics. We believe that the philosophy of mathematics should be con-
sistent with scientific findings about the only mathematics that human beings
know or can know. We will argue in Part V that the theory of embodied math-
ematics—the body of results we present in this book—determines an empiri-
cally based philosophy of mathematics, one that is coherent with the
“embodied realism” discussed in Lakoff and Johnson (1999) and with “ecologi-
cal naturalism” as a foundation for embodiment (Núñez, 1995, 1997).
Mathematics as we know it is human mathematics, a product of the human
mind. Where does mathematics come from? It comes from us! We create it, but
it is not arbitrary—not a mere historically contingent social construction. What
makes mathematics nonarbitrary is that it uses the basic conceptual mecha-
nisms of the embodied human mind as it has evolved in the real world. Mathe-
matics is a product of the neural capacities of our brains, the nature of our
bodies, our evolution, our environment, and our long social and cultural history.
By the time you finish this book, our reasons for saying this should be clear.
10 Introduction
Introduction 11
spective throughout the book, the study of Euler’s equation demonstrates the
power of the analysis of ideas in mathematics, by showing how a single equa-
tion can bring an enormously rich range of ideas together—even though the
equation itself contains nothing but numbers: e, !, ÷–1, 1, and 0. We will be ask-
ing throughout how mere numbers can express ideas. It is in the case study that
the power of the answer to this question becomes clear.
Finally, there is an educational motive. We believe that classical mathemat-
ics can best be taught with a cognitive perspective. We believe that it is impor-
tant to teach mathematical ideas and to explain why mathematical truths
follow from those ideas. This case study is intended to illustrate to teachers of
mathematics how this can be done.
We see our book as an early step in the development of a cognitive science of
mathematics—a discipline that studies the cognitive mechanisms used in the
human creation and conceptualization of mathematics. We hope you will find
this discipline stimulating, challenging, and worthwhile.