In The Workshop of History - Furet, François, 1927-1997 - 1984 - Chicago - University of Chicago Press - 9780226273365 - Anna's Archive
In The Workshop of History - Furet, François, 1927-1997 - 1984 - Chicago - University of Chicago Press - 9780226273365 - Anna's Archive
In The Workshop of History - Furet, François, 1927-1997 - 1984 - Chicago - University of Chicago Press - 9780226273365 - Anna's Archive
àNi a st
=
frere
fat
reer f
ue there sees
re HU
#4
fete
Digitized by the Internet Archive
in 2023 with funding from
No Sponsor
https://archive.org/details/inworkshopofhist000Ofure
*
‘ - ae
| oo ri É
. :* | +a 7
i
7 bd
ol |
. ?
| 4
La
-
A . Tr.
ee
,
Le *
Li * L
,
. * L
FRANCOIS
FURET
Translated by Jonathan Mandelbaum
This book was first published as L’ Atelier de l’histoire, © 1982, Flammarion, Paris.
Introduction
Notes 243
Index 253
INTRODUCTION”
Pages 1-19 of this Introduction first appeared as “En marge des Annales: histoire et sciences
sociales,” Le Débat, no. 17 (December 1981), 112-26. A slightly different form of the
English version was published in the Journal of Modern History.
2 Introduction
supposed to have transformed its methods and subject matter. Nor is this
revolution itself easy to define, and it emerges more sharply by contrast to
its adversaries’ profile than by virtue of its founders’ concepts. That is
perhaps one of the reasons for the frequency of polemical arguments in
the prewar and postwar Annales, especially when Lucien Febvre was
involved. The martial vocabulary, the call to battle in defense of worthy
causes, the sense of adventure intellectually heightened by the breathless
prose—all these are telling signs of the extent to which the opening of the
discipline to new objects was a reaction against traditional historiogra-
phy. Indeed, now that these new objects have become the common
property of our profession, it is hard for us to imagine how eccentric they
once appeared. What, then, is the Annales School if the territory it
claimed for history has become a public domain?
It seems to me that the simplest way of describing the ambition and
development of the school is to consider jointly two objectives—two
ideas: first, that history should add to its subjects and methods by borrow-
ing from neighboring disciplines and even by the temporary abolition of
divisions between disciplines; and, second, that it should nevertheless
remain an all-embracing and ecumenical discipline, bringing together the
conditions required for the fullest understanding of social phenomena.
Neither of these two ideas is simple or clear; nor is their compatibility
self-evident, unless one regards it as a wish, a program, or an ultimate
ambition. Instead of paving the way for its intellectual unity, history’s
borrowings from the social sciences only add to the diversity of the
discipline by expanding its field of inquiry almost to infinity. But, while
these borrowings provide history with greater methodological eclecti-
cism, they do not necessarily guarantee additional knowledge—unless, of
course, history would precisely exploit this greater conceptual indeter-
minacy in order to assert its superiority over the social sciences. By
borrowing right and left, history does not tie itself to any one of its
creditors; on the contrary, it claims to bestow its own preeminent dignity
on all of them. Thus, in its comprehensive embrace, history absorbs the
social sciences instead of simply representing their temporal dimension.
In order to examine the situation of history today, a half century after
the founding of the Annales, one can therefore begin by examining its
relation to the social sciences. This is probably the least unreliable
instrument for a methodical assessment.
The social sciences aim, like Marxism, to explain social facts. But they
do not constitute a unified body of doctrines, nor even a corpus of partial
interpretations that could be unanimously accepted. The social sciences
delimit specialties, or objects of study, or approaches to a problem,
without ever securing the consensus of specialists. Consequently, they
have renounced the ambition of providing comprehensive explanations
and scientific forecasts of contemporary phenomena. Indeed, the social
sciences define their positivity by their distrust of the philosophy of
Introduction 5
history; to this extent, they cannot escape—any more than any other
intellectual examination of our world—the fact of being rooted in their
time. They express this rootedness by recognizing their limitations and no
longer by voicing vast ambitions.
However, the social sciences have not easily accepted this renuncia-
tion of their capacity, or of their claim, to provide a total explanation. All
they need is to adopt the singular form—social science—in order to
regain the prestige of the scientistic prophecy: from Auguste Comte to
Durkheim, the sociologist propounded and embodied the notion that not
only is it possible to study man in society, but the analysis of his social
determinants can alone provide the key to the celebrated “essence” of
man. More recently, the same hopes have been pinned on structural
anthropology, in circumstances that one of the essays in this book
attempts to elucidate: the search for constants within the diversity of
social manifestations in space (rather than time) can or must lead to a
unitary theory of man.
In its renewed form, history remains actively engaged in that rivalry
among the social sciences in which each aims, by claiming a higher
objectivity and an all-embracing knowledge, to subsume the others. Its
claims are no longer “historicist.” It no longer regards the time scale as
the yardstick for stages in human progress, stages punctuated by the
creation of nation-states and the spread of ‘‘civilization,”’ that is, of the
European model. On the contrary, history today is no longer endowed
with the primal, implicit significance attributed to time; it has abandoned
the linear vision that made it a royal discipline whose task was to weigh
the merits of the various ‘‘periods” of the past. At the same time, history
has turned to a broader range of topics. It confers its dignity less selec-
tively: everything has become historical, from an apparently ‘“‘nonhistor-
ical” gesture to the bill of fare in an inn to the division of a plot of land.
Thus, history has constantly encountered the social sciences. Indeed, it is
hard to say whether it is the discovery of new research areas that has led
history to an apprenticeship in more specialized disciplines or whether,
on the contrary, it has borrowed from social sciences such as economics
or demography certain objects of research that have already been defined
outside history. The two phenomena have been concurrent and have
influenced each other.
This process, which corresponds very roughly to the establishment and
growth of what is known as the Annales School of history, has been
accompanied by a claim on the part of history to exercise hegemony over
the social sciences, as if history alone, armed with the partial forms of
knowledge developed by neighboring disciplines, were destined to pre-
sent a unified vision of man under the name of “‘total history.” Such a
claim is, in a sense, a way of making up for the fragmentation and
specialization of the objects of historical analysis. Even as it ceases to act
as an organized representation of time, providing mankind with the
vision of its progress, history still maintains the notion of its superiority
6 Introduction
on the grounds that it alone can study certain objects exhaustively, from
every angle—whereas in actual fact, like other disciplines, it deals with
limited objects. Thus, in the midst of a crisis in historicist history, the
historian has fallen back on a less charismatic notion of his learning
without suffering any epistemological loss.
Yet the idea of total history is elusive. Naturally, it no longer denotes
the nineteenth-century view of history as a privileged discipline, designed
to encompass all the significant manifestations of man in society and to
interpret the development of these manifestations as so many necessary
stages in a history of mankind. Total history merely expresses the ambi-
tion of providing a fuller perspective, a more exhaustive description, a
more comprehensive explanation of a given object or problem than can
be provided by the social sciences whose conceptual and methodological
innovations it has borrowed. But if the secret of the flow of time is no
longer vested by definition in history, how can history still be regarded as
a superior discipline? Is this privilege justified by the temporal dimension
that history is thought to bring to the study of social phenomena? All the
social sciences—no less than history—deal of necessity with problems
whose past constitutes the only available laboratory in which they can be
studied. Admittedly, history’s central purpose is to analyze the develop-
ment of any number of those problems, sometimes over very long
periods; but this temporal dimension, however far back it may reach,
does not in itself justify a peculiar privilege of “totality.” It enables
historians to describe and analyze the series of changes and transforma-
tions of the phenomenon in question and thus to introduce, with the aid
of time, an implicitly comparative perspective that is essential, since it
enables one to enrich the concept or concepts used in the analysis—but
no more: temporality cannot lead us to what does not exist, that is, to a
concept capable of explaining every aspect of the object under study.
Social science tout court remains the goal of all the social sciences, but
it cannot constitute the “‘true”’ essence of any of them. If history, after
sociology and along with anthropology, has staked a claim to such intel-
lectual authority, that claim must not be taken for granted; such pre-
sumption stems both from the pathological tendency to generalize that
contaminates every important study of society undertaken in France and
from the rivalry among university disciplines for supreme legitimacy.
Having been enticed out of its position as the soothsayer of national
destiny and prophet of human progress, history has studied the social
sciences only the better to appropriate for its own advantage the ambition
of Durkheimian sociology.
But the important feature of history’s recent development is not this
illusory ambition; it is, on the contrary, what that ambition masks and
perhaps serves to make up for: the fact that the historian, like the
demographer or the anthropologist, constructs the object of his research.
Having abandoned the naive notion that facts speak for themselves—a
Introduction of
naive notion because it assumes without ever saying so that time has a
predetermined meaning—the historian has by the same token abandoned
the superstition of chronological divisions and periodization. If phe-
nomena of every sort are no longer primarily interpreted in a temporal
framework, one must first define objects of research and then determine,
by trial and error, the relevant time span for describing and analyzing
them. Hence, specialization in a given period, for so long a basic feature
of the profession, has become a lesser imperative compared to familiarity
with a particular issue or problem. The historian of what used to “‘consti-
tute” the reign of Louis XIV is less a historian of the seventeenth century
than, let us say, a specialist on absolutism or on the court phenomenon.
In other words, history is no longer wholly contained in a genealogical
construct in which earlier events explain later ones and must conse-
quently be reconstituted with painstaking attention down to their re-
motest origins. Indeed, history used to be a form of learning obsessed
with origins, seeking through erudition to assign an ever-earlier date to
the great secret of beginnings. Moreover, the entire process that it
ennobled was, by definition, a genealogy of the nation or of mankind: in
its bibliographical classifications, seventeenth- and eighteenth-century
European culture distinguished between the inventory of time—the ob-
ject of history—reserved for European peoples and states, and the inven-
tory of space, the realm of travelers, an immense repository of immobile
societies. In the non-European portion of the inhabited globe, these
societies also testified, in a certain sense, to the origin of man, since the
savage was the ancestor of civilized man. Thus, in the order of knowl-
edge, space was subordinated to time, and travel to history. This was a
way of depicting human progress. Somewhat later, when ethnology and
anthropology emerged as disciplines, they dealt only with societies whose
culture was unwritten, leaving outside their purview, for instance, the
great oriental civilizations. Here again, the division was based on the
same principle: China and India share with European nations the priv-
ilege of historicity; their time, too, has meaning.
If all societies today have regained a history, it is not only in the sense
that universal history, through the world market, colonization, and de-
colonization, has integrated them into its vast currents; it is also because
history, as a form of knowledge rather than an actual process, is no longer
the preserve of a small number of societies or nations but a discipline that
can apply to any one of them. While totally distinct, these two phe-
nomena are not in fact unconnected, for the spread of nationalism to the
entire planet has led to a resurgence of the genealogical history of
nations, on the old European model. But, in order to assess the present
situation of history, it is better not to focus on this contamination of the
present by the past but to concentrate on what is truly new: the fact that
everything has been historicized.
Such an assertion seems obvious, but in fact it is not. For example,
8 Introduction
why the language of the social sciences is partly in contradiction with that
of ‘“‘historicist” history. The social sciences focus primarily on unchanging
phenomena so as to simplify—that is, to make possible—the mode of
reasoning that underlies their language. And it is no accident if histo-
rians, thanks to the social sciences, have rediscovered the long term—the
longue durée—and even “‘immobile”’ history. For historians, this is a way
of saying in their own language that there exists a category of historical
objects on which time has only very gradual effects. Concentrating on
these categories of objects, historians harmonize their practice with the
concepts they borrow from the social sciences.
In so doing, historians have been led to give up not only the major form
of their discipline—narrative—but also its favorite subject matter—poli-
tics. Just as narrative was the logical way of presenting an interpretation
based on temporal significance, so the analysis of a problem in the light of
data developed for that particular purpose obeys the logic of demonstra-
tion. The only common element in the two genres is the apparatus of
scholarly notes that establishes or discusses the nature of the data or their
veracity. But the internal structure of the two discourses is radically
different, even when they happen to mingle and when the old one lives on
by force of habit after the appearance of the new. Finally, their respective
contents have also, by force of circumstance, been dissociated. As we
have seen, the historical narrative genre is chiefly concerned with the
realm of political facts, the uppermost ridge of the past, the memory of
human action, the patrimony of nations, but is also a laboratory for
change and progress. It is in the study of politics, of human choice, that
history best expresses its capacity to create and to constitute the arena for
the study of man. However, the price paid by history for remodeling itself
on the pattern of the social sciences is that it focuses primarily on what
underlies those choices, on what determines them and makes them
inevitable despite the appearance of freedom. It prefers to analyze
deeper trends rather than superficial changes, to study collective be-
havior rather than individual choices, to examine economic and social
determinants rather than institutions or government decisions. Thus,
demography, economics, and sociology have taken over a field in-
creasingly deserted by its traditional inhabitants—kings, notables, na-
tions, and the theater of power around which they never ceased to
gravitate.
question or questions raised externally, since its contents are the fruit of
chance and, by definition, cannot be compared to those of a neighboring
depository despite the uniform system of classification. And the histo-
rian’s activity par excellence is the researcher’s colloquy with his archives,
provided he accepts beforehand that they are to have the “‘last word”’ (p.
15). This does not simply mean that, where he hesitates about a fact or an
interpretation, the document itself will decide; it means, more pro-
foundly, that the archives mined by the researcher are ultimately re-
sponsible for determining the content and horizon of his research. Hence
the sort of professional priority assigned not to the object of research but
to the geographical boundaries within which it is to take place and to the
site, that is, the depository, that is to be its center stage.
This concept of history and of the historian conceals a number of
elements that are worth bringing to light. First, at the most invisible level,
there is the existential choice of a way of life and a culture. The manu-
script document and the archive are the images and instruments of
cultural differentiation; they allow the historian to embark on the same
imaginary voyage that physical travel offers to the anthropologist. The
traveler is taken to an apparently exotic field, which he can master by
learning the ways of otherness. Indeed, in Richard Cobb’s mind, the two
varieties of exoticism—temporal and spatial—are combined, since the
British historian must become familiar with the “‘savage”’ territory called
France, and the sign of his success is his being told by the local archivist
that he has become an ‘excellent joueur de boules” (p. 24). France is a
museum, both in its past and in its present, and one can “learn” it by
studying not only its archives but also its present customs, provided they
have not changed too much. The passion for history is rooted here in a
choice at once aesthetic and moral: Oxonians do not like all the fuss being
made over change and modernity.
At the same time, the subjects and even the spirit of this history are
determined and bounded by that choice: it is a history that aims at
reconstituting the past, not at interpreting it. For that matter, the term
reconstituting itself contains an ambiguity: if it means that the historian’s
work must bring the past “back to life,” it is stating an ambition that is
either absurd or solely dependent on the techniques of the art—in which
case, the existence or nonexistence of documents and the historian’s
faithfulness to them are not crucial. Reconstitution makes sense only if it
means that history reconstructs not only what actually happened but the
way in which what happened was perceived by contemporaries. The first
part of the program is intellectually the simpler; the second, having an
ill-defined object, contains an irreducible element of uncertainty. But it is
true that the modes of reaction to (and, thus, of perception of) an event
are essential historical phenomena; it remains to be determined where
and how to find them.
This type of history-as-reconstitution, which I am distinguishing here
14 Introduction
the ‘‘new”’ variety, however misused the adjective, and the broadening of
the historiographic field. That this broadening is related to curiosity or to
feelings rooted in the present does not suffice to make it a novelty; the
study of the past has always been inseparable from the historian’s relation
to the present. And the example of history a la Cobb shows that, to the
extent that this relation remains purely emotional and devoid of ques-
tions and concepts, the wholesale conferral of historical dignity on the
lower classes and marginal individuals in no way alters the nature of this
variety of history, which still remains a narrative of bygone times.
For the most part, the so-called histoire des mentalités, even when it
styles itself ‘‘ethnological,”’ still belongs to such a breed of history. The
reference to ethnology, when it simply indicates that the historian is
dealing with subjects that used to be considered outside his province and
were invented by that neighboring discipline (marriage, kinship, the
constraints of sociability, for example), is only a token homage to the
interdisciplinary approach. Far from establishing or even maintaining the
cultural distance between the observer and the observed—a distance that
lies at the very heart of ethnological analysis—it reflects precisely the
opposite: a return to Peter Laslett’s “‘world we have lost,” the search for
an anchorage in the deepest stratum of the familiar, below the sediments
modernity has deposited in us. The reference to ethnology extends the
scope of genealogical research, adapting it to our feelings toward the
present, but it does not alter the nature of that research; history has
moved from the genealogy of nations to the genealogy of societies. To be
convinced of this, one need only consider the fact that ethnohistory as
practiced in France does not represent a comparative form of knowledge
but remains confined to French rural society. Furthermore, as it seeks
less to explain the unfamiliar than to discover the familiar behind the
illusion of the unfamiliar, it is subjected to the temptation of the pictur-
esque, which constitutes its link with the general public.
Thus, for history to proclaim its indebtedness to another discipline is
not enough to turn it into a form of knowledge different from what it was
fifty or a hundred years ago. This claim or assertion can mean only that
history has broadened its scope, not that it has transformed its intellectual
approach to the past. In this respect, one can understand the irritation of
an aggressively traditionalist historian such as Richard Cobb when con-
fronted with the “‘interdisciplinary”’ inflation that characterizes the pres-
ent-day vocabulary of historical studies in France. This almost compul-
sory terminology can sometimes apply, in fact, to a type of research or
exposition entirely similar to those practiced and cherished by the British
historian: old events, found in unpublished documents, used in a narra-
tive to reconstruct the particular atmosphere of a period through the life
of one or more individuals. Like all forms of extremism, Cobb’s reaction-
ary radicalism—in addition to its literary charm—has the advantage of
exposing the duplicity of words.
Actually, the distinction I am trying to draw between two types of
18 Introduction
that calls itself new because it borrows part of its equipment from nearby
disciplines, the opposition is neither as sharp nor as genuine as the second
type of history would have us believe. The confusion stems from the fact
that the renewal and extension of history’s subject matter—phenomena
on which all historians now agree—do not necessarily entail a change in
the way of treating that subject matter. Richard Cobb, too, is a ‘“‘new”’
historian, in his fashion—even though he loathes the Annales—since he
devotes himself with such ardent solicitude to beggars and vagrants, the
forgotten individuals of traditional historiography. He has swapped
dukes for tramps, respectable folk for the destitute, great men for small
fry, deeds for daily life. Although staged on another scene, the show he
produces nonetheless observes conventions that Georges Lenôtre would
not repudiate. To open the noble realm of history to other heroes and
other actions—a gesture that all historians applaud—does not necessarily
imply that one looks at them differently or that one bestows on them an
original intellectual treatment.
As for the history I like, now defined not negatively but positively, the
studies that follow aim precisely at delineating its contours. I am deliber-
ately using this vague expression, for these texts do not pretend to be
normative. History, even scholarly history, is not and never will be an
exact discipline, as one speaks of the exact sciences. There will never be a
consensus among those who write history as to the criteria that distin-
guish scientific from nonscientific history. The only rules of the trade are
the procedural rules developed by European scholars between the six-
teenth and nineteenth centuries. These rules remain essential, indeed
indispensable, but all they define is a profession not a science. To estab-
lish a ‘“‘true”’ fact in its complexity is one thing; to find the law that governs
its emergence or existence is another. And if historians attach an almost
fetishistic importance to mastering professional “skills,” which concern
only the documentary aspect of their work, it is because they have no
other criteria for defining their guild.
Scholarship must serve as the basis for all imaginable types of history,
from the most narrative to the most conceptual. In other words, scholar-
ship makes it possible to distinguish between good and bad history but
not to establish a hierarchy of historical genres. It constitutes a minimum
requirement, beyond which the range of intellectual preferences remains
open almost to infinity. I believe that one must remain firmly attached
both to that obligation and to that freedom—to that obligation because
the damage caused by amateurism and shoddiness has perhaps never
been so visible as today; to that freedom because it is periodically being
called into question by conflicting but equally superficial dogmatic
approaches, one of which clings to the intransigent cult of narrative, the
other to the pretense of a “‘scientific’’ form of knowledge.
In the relatively vast area within which the discipline is fluctuating
20 Introduction
In the same way, the explicit discussion of his relation to the present is an
intellectual exercise that enables him to understand his own ‘‘objectiv-
ity.” The celebrated point “from which” he speaks is constantly being
explored in the shuttling comparison between past and present. How-
ever, the present must not be reconstructed as the only possible outcome
of that past but analyzed as what turned out to be the most probable
outcome, independent of the intentions or predictions of historical
agents. Thus, the historian can rediscover the gap between intention and
real process, a gap that characterizes his type of inquiry since it defines
the two poles of historical investigation.
There are no concepts for explaining the past that do not bear the
stamp of the present and do not therefore date the historian. Conversely,
however, without an analysis of the present there can be no concepts at
all. The first proposition is not enough to define a good conceptual
history, for it does not guarantee a choice of sound analytical tools; but it
does lay down a minimum requirement. It accepts the limits of historical
objectivity the better to abandon the fallacy of “bringing the past back to
life” or the temptation to tell a mere story.
From this point of view, the distinction of sorts sometimes drawn
between contemporary history and plain “history,” reputedly more reli-
able, seems to me to have no other justification than the vantage point
involved: the closer one gets to the present, the less “‘distance”’ one has.
For example, the consequences of the Reformation for the history of
mankind are easier to understand than those of the Bolshevik revolution,
since there are four and a half centuries of temporal distance in which to
study them. But this perceptual advantage, which, moreover, varies
according to the subject treated, does not in itself confer intellectual
merit: depending on the historian or the work, one can encounter super-
ficial histories of Protestantism and insightful histories of Bolshevism.
And the contemporary world can offer the attentive observer a host of
considerations that will help him understand the past, if only the historian
displays an interest in the present.
Indeed, the contemporary world, in its natural state, provides him
with the central problem of historical analysis: the problem of change and
of interpreting change. As regards “what happens” every day—the
events rehashed by endless comment in the media—the historian’s famil-
iarity with the past enables him to come up with additional questions or to
establish new connections between events. The raw form of change that
constitutes what we call ‘‘news” must immediately be made as intelligible
as circumstances permit. But the historian is best equipped to restore
these developments to their unfamiliar dimension, precisely by focusing
on the features that make them comparable to past events. Thus, he can
isolate the repetitive element and the totally new aspects of current
events. Admittedly, as an actor in his own epoch the historian is not
immune to the temptation to adopt any one of the explanations of ‘what
29 Introduction
Wi Cape Ara
! a Ge re see
Er” 2 ne Je 7
_
| Eu 14 Ate van
= ETS = v
e > ur
ell UT AI Ter CASE
POTN 2 LN stl > 5
vArs
i | LEE Cure
:
Ds ed
Val
,<8
x :
— 7 RER
>
= AR |
sont |
‘hr
of 5 a 4
; ea
TA
me |
Alaa
Stu ap TO
j .
N Sh
Do ad
SH
à CE" LES
de 6
= <i
« ai
L2
a? LE
ad :
a]
PF
s =
Le vine
é f°
an
5 oh
cy :
P4
1
&
PU Aged
Le
«ge nl
z 7 Leon
t
: "
~~
-
PART Sens
LR
French Intellectuals:
From Marxism to Structuralism
First published in Preuves, no. 92 (February 1967). An English translation entitled “The
French Left: From Marxism to Structuralism” appeared in Survey, no. 62 (January 1967),
72-83. The present text is a slightly revised and expanded reprint of that translation.
27
28 History Today
the heroic age, but France itself is no longer France. The French intellec-
tual, heir to a prestige less fragile than power and unconsciously used to a
universal radiation of his culture, is not yet reduced to the sad state of the
Belgian, but he is increasingly aware of being a citizen of a country that,
in spite of Gaullist rhetoric, senses it is no longer making human history.
Having been expelled from history, the France in which he lives consents
the more willingly to expel history. It can look at the world with eyes no
longer veiled by its own example and civilizing obsession, with eyes now
sceptical about the “‘lessons”’ and “‘meaning” of history. Valéry admira-
bly foresaw this phenomenon after the First World War in his Regards sur
le monde actuel.
Thus, the recent disappointments of the French intellectuals and the
general political situation combine to cast doubt on history—for so long a
tyrannical mistress before she became an unfaithful one.
It is without doubt this situation that explains the great impact of the
thinking of which Lévi-Strauss is generally regarded as both a model and
a representative. It is, however, uncertain—even unlikely—that Lévi-
Strauss, who has a passion for accuracy, would accept this vague and
general attribution of paternity affixed to him under the label of “‘struc-
turalism.” But, from the point of view of the social character of his
audience, that matters little. On the other hand, it is significant that a
work as specific and as technical as his should have had so widespread an
impact on men of letters, art critics, and philosophers. To enumerate its
great themes and aspirations is not to evade the significance of the
intellectual movement that reflects the scope of its influence, since that is
precisely what has to be understood.
In the first place, however abstract and high-powered it may be, the
effect of his work is to revive something like the great Rousseauist
paradox that split the eighteenth century. One feels it to be suffused by
love of nature, the countryside and flowers, a fondness for “‘primitive”’
man that inevitably stimulates nostalgia for a happiness lost by industrial
societies. Lévi-Strauss writes of a world in which the eagle, the bear, and
meadow sage still exist, but he believes no more than Rousseau, who is
one of his favorite authors, in a return to a primitive happiness that has
disappeared forever. The heir to Boas and Mauss knows that there is no
such thing as a state of nature but, rather, myriad communities and
cultures, each representing a different form of man’s confrontation with
nature; and he also realizes that there is no objective way of establishing
any hierarchy among them. Thus, the industrial society of Europe or
America loses the privileged position to which it believes itself entitled in
relation to tribes buried in the forests of the Amazon. “A great deal of
egocentricity and naiveté is required if one is to believe that the whole of
man has taken refuge in a single one of his historical or geographical
modes of being, while the truth about man lies in the system of their
32 History Today
the fifties that was so characteristic of the ideological age. Hence, there
was a receptiveness of intellectual opinion, a kind of expectation—rather
as a century ago the inglorious failure of the romantics of 1848 preceded
and facilitated the formation of the realist and positivist generation. But
it helped this generation to emerge; it did not create it: this intellectual
change does not itself call for sociological explanation. At the present
time, the political disappointments suffered by progressivism have pro-
foundly weakened the influence of Marxism among the left-wing intellec-
tuals, but it is Lévi-Strauss and not Raymond Aron who reigns in the void
thus created. What prevails is not a liberal and empirical criticism of
Marxism but a hyperintellectual and systematic way of thinking that aims
at a general theory of man. Not only have Marxists or former Marxists
been able to invest their past in this without repudiating it; they have also
rediscovered in it their ambition for a comprehensive science of man and
their old all-embracing dream, “‘deideologized” and freed from the
naivetés of commitment and of the meaning of history. To that extent
perhaps the case of the French intellectuals deserves to become a classic;
the end of the ideological age has found its doctrinaires.
Quantitative History
40
Quantitative History 41
To avoid any misunderstanding, let me say at once that this essay does
not set out to prescribe quantitative history as the only kind permissible.
During the last ten or twenty years, serial history has turned out to be one
of the most fertile approaches in the advancement of historical knowl-
edge. It has also the immense advantage of introducing into the ancient
discipline of history a rigor and efficiency superior to those of qualitative
methodology. But it is nevertheless true that there are important sectors
of historical reality that it is by nature unable to treat or even to approach,
either for circumstantial reasons such as irremediable lack of data or for
fundamental reasons such as the irreducibly qualitative nature of the
Quantitative History 43
for several reasons such a series cannot be constructed. In the first place,
there is no unique and homogeneous source for such revolts over a long
period. Moreover, there is every reason to believe that the survival of
such a collection as the Fonds Séguier in Leningrad, a collection espe-
cially rich in this respect but limited to the papers of one family and thus
subject to the hazards and possible distortions of individuals’ careers,
falsifies our chronological perception of the subject. In any case, a
Jacquerie is a story without direct sources, a rising of illiterates. We can
glimpse it today through the medium of administrative or legal archives,
but by this very fact, as Charles Tilly has remarked, every revolt that
escapes repression escapes history. The relative richness of our sources
during a given period may be a sign of changes that are institutional
(reinforcement of the apparatus of repression) or purely individual (spe-
cial vigilance on the part of a particular official), rather than of any
unusual frequency in the phenomenon itself. The difference between the
number of peasant risings under Henry II and under Louis XIII may
reflect first and foremost the progress of monarchical centralization.
Therefore, in handling serial sources the historian is forced to think
carefully about the influence that the way they were constituted may have
on their quantitative application. I think we may distinguish between
such sources as follows, in order of increasing complexity in their conver-
sion into series.
1. Structurally numerical sources, grouped together as such and used
by the historian to answer questions directly connected with their original
field of investigation; for example, French parish registers for the demo-
graphic historian, prefectoral inquiries into industrial or agricultural
statistics in the nineteenth century for the economic historian, the data on
American presidential elections for the specialist in sociopolitical history.
These sources sometimes need standardizing (as when there is a variation
in local units or a modification of the classifying criterion); also, when
there are gaps in the documentary sequence, one may have to extrapolate
certain elements. But in such cases both operations are carried out with
the minimum of uncertainty.
2. Sources that are structurally numerical but used by the historian
substitutively, to find the answers to questions completely outside their
original field of investigation; for example, the analysis of sexual behavior
on the basis of parish registers, the study of economic growth through
price series, the socioprofessional evolution of a population through a
series relating to taxes. Here the historian encounters a double difficulty.
He has to define his questions all the more meticulously because the
documentary material was not assembled with them in mind, and the
question is constantly before him of the relevance of such material to such
questions. He usually has to reorganize the material completely in order
to make it usable and in so doing makes it more arbitrary and so more
open to objection.
48 History Today
3. Sources that are not structually numerical but that the historian
wants to use quantitatively, by a process involving two substitutions. In
such cases he has to find in his sources a univocal significance in relation to
the question he is asking. He also has to be able to reorganize them in
series, that is, in comparable chronological units, and this demands an
even more complex process of standardization than in the preceding
paragraph. Data of this third type, which become more and more fre-
quent the further one goes back into the past, can be subdivided into two
classes: first, nonnumerical sources that are nevertheless serial and thus
easily quantifiable, such as modern European marriage contracts drawn
up by notaries, which, according to the historian’s choice, can give
evidence about endogamy, social mobility, income, literacy, and so on;
second, the sources that are strictly qualitative, and therefore not serial,
or at least particularly difficult to standardize and arrange in series, such
as the administrative and legal series referred to above or iconographical
survivals of forgotten faiths.
Whichever kind of source he is dealing with, the historian of today has
to rid himself of any methodological naiveté and devote a good deal of
thought to the way in which his knowledge is to be established. The
computer gives him the leisure to do so by freeing him from what used to
take up most of his time—the recording and card-indexing of data—but
at the same time it demands from him rigorous preliminary work on the
organization of series and their meaning in relation to the inquiry. Like
all the social sciences, but perhaps with a slight time lag, history is passing
from the implicit to the explicit. The encoding of data presupposes their
definition; their definition implies a certain number of choices and
hypotheses, made all the more consciously because they have to conform
to the logic of a program. And so the mask finally falls away of that
historical objectivity that was supposed to lie concealed in the facts and to
reveal itself at the same time as them. Henceforward the historian is
bound to be aware that he has constructed his own “facts” and that the
objectivity of his research resides in the use of correct methods for
elaborating and processing them and in their relevance to his hypotheses.
So serial history is not only, or even primarily, a transformation of the
raw material of history; it is a revolution in the historiographical con-
sciousness.
narrative of certain selected “‘events’’ along the time axis. First and
foremost, it is based on the idea that these events are unique and cannot
be set out statistically and that the unique is the material par excellence of
history. That is why this kind of history paradoxically deals at one and the
same time in the short term and in a finalistic ideology. Since the event, a
sudden irruption of the unique and the new into the concatenation of
time, cannot be compared to any antecedent, the only way of integrating
it into history is to give it a teleological meaning. And as history, espe-
cially since the nineteenth century, has developed primarily as a mode of
interiorizing and conceptualizing the sense of progress, the ‘‘event”
usually marks some stage in the advent of a political or philosophical
ideal—republic, liberty, democracy, reason, and so forth. The historian’s
ideological consciousness can assume very subtle forms. It may group
knowledge relating to a certain period around unifying schemas not
directly linked to political options or values; for example, the spirit of an
age, its Weltanschauung. But basically the same compensating mecha-
nism is at work: in order to be intelligible, the event needs a general
history apart from itself and independently determined. Hence the classic
conception of historical time as a series of discontinuities described in the
mode of continuity—that is, as narrative.
Serial history, on the other hand, describes continuities in the mode of
discontinuity: it is a problem-oriented history instead of a narrative one.
Because it has to distinguish between the levels of historical reality, it
breaks down all previous conceptions of general history, calling in ques-
tion the old postulate that all the elements of a society follow a
homogeneous and identical evolution. The analysis of series has meaning
only if it is done on a long-term basis, so as to show short or periodic
variations within trends. The series reveals a time that is no longer the
mysterious occasional spurt of the event but an evolutionary rhythm that
is measurable, comparable, and doubly differential in that it can be
examined within one series or as between two or more.
A wedge has thus been driven into the old carefully enclosed empire of
classical historiography, and this by means of two distinct but connected
operations. First, by the analytical breakdown of reality into different
levels of description, serial history has opened history in general to
concepts and methods imported from the more specifically constituted
social sciences, such as political economy. This opening has probably
been the operative factor in the recent historical revival. Second, by
quantitatively analyzing the different evolutionary rhythms of the differ-
ent levels of reality, it has at last turned into a scientifically measurable
object the dimension of human activity that is history’s raison d’être—
time.
2. Now that the historian’s hypothesis has shifted from the level of the
philosophy of history to that of a series of data both particular and
homogeneous, it usually reaps the advantage of becoming explicit and
50 History Today
formulable; but, at the same time, historical reality is broken down into
fragments so distinct that history’s classic claim to give a universal view of
things is endangered. Must the claim be abandoned?
I would say it may probably be kept as a goal on the horizon but that, if
history wants to go forward, it should abandon this ambition as a point of
departure. Otherwise, it might fall once more into the teleological illu-
sion described above. Present-day historiography can progress only in-
sofar as it delimits its object, defines its hypotheses, and constitutes and
describes its sources as carefully. as possible. This does not mean it has to
restrict itself to microscopic analysis of one chronological series. It can
group several series together and put forward an interpretation of a
system or subsystem. But today a comprehensive analysis of the “system
of systems” is probably beyond its power.
We may take as examples demographic and economic history, the
most advanced sectors now in France and probably elsewhere. It so
happens that for the past twenty years or so the period that in France is
called ‘‘modern’’—that is, the period between the end of the Middle Ages
and 1789—has been the subject of the largest number of studies in serial
history, both demographic and economic. So it is the one we are least
ignorant about from this point of view. French historiography,’ starting
out from reconstructed commodity price series, has compared these with
the evolution in the number of people as shown in demographic series.
Thus, there has gradually been built up the concept of an “economic
ancien régime,” based on the preponderance of a cereal production
exposed to the vagaries of meteorology and on the periodic purging of the
system by recurrent crises. These crises are indicated by sudden steep
rises in price curves and the collapse of those indicating size of popula-
tion.
But the price series, the meanings of which can be quite varied and
ambiguous, have been supplemented by more specific indications con-
cerning volume of production and by the use of series relating to the
evolution of supply and demand, itself a factor in the evolution of prices.
On the subject of production, though the tithe records concern the same
percentage of the harvest every year and so tell us nothing absolute, they
are valuable because of their relative comparability. For production we
also have the protostatistical sources brought together by the administra-
tion of the ancien régime and possibly reorganized on a national scale. On
the subject of demand, in addition to general demographic records, we
can also turn to the reconstruction of the great masses of liquid money:
the treasuries of communes and seigneuries, tithes, rents, profits, wages.
The combination of many demographic and economic series has re-
cently enabled Emmanuel Le Roy Ladurie to make a wider analysis of
the old agrarian economy.‘ His book gives a sampling of data covering the
whole of the Languedoc, a long-term chronology (from the fifteenth to
the eighteenth century), and a rich and varied quantitative documenta-
Quantitative History 51
tion. Thanks to the cadastral surveys, the latter makes possible a study of
rural property owning. The fifteenth to the eighteenth centuries tell the
story of a very long agrarian cycle characterized at the same time by a
general equilibrium and by a series of states of disequilibrium. The
general equilibrium roughly corresponds to the Malthusian model—the
model that Malthus discovered and made immortal at the very moment it
ceased to be true, at the time of England’s takeoff. The economy of early
rural Languedoc was dominated in the long term by the relation between
agricultural production and the number of men. Society’s inability to
raise agrarian productivity and the absence of an unlimited reserve of
cultivable land, together with the famous “monetary famine” beloved of
the price historians, presented structural obstacles to decisive growth.
Though the monetary explanation loses its central role, it is integrated
into an interpretation both more complex and more unified.
The structure of the old economy acted in the long term as an internal
regulator. Nevertheless, within the system, the different variables—
number of men, evolution of property, distribution of income from rents,
fluctuations in productivity and prices, and so on—make it possible to
distinguish separate periods in accordance with the position each variable
occupies in relation to the whole, in terms of the annual rhythms and
cycles of each particular curve. The complete structure thus chronologi-
cally comprises several types of combinations of series, that is, several
different situations. And, in fact, it is through the careful examination of
these successive situations, and the features they have in common or in
which they differ, that the structure itself emerges. This, incidentally,
may shed some light on the dispute over synchronic and diachronic,
which often divides anthropologists and historians and which at present is
at the heart of the evolution of the social sciences. The short- or medium-
term periodic movement that constitutes an “event” on the economic
plane does not necessarily clash with the theory of general equilibrium.
On the contrary, an empirical description of such movements may make
it possible to define the theoretical conditions of the equilibrium, whose
elasticity indicates the limits within which it operates.
3. The Languedoc example quoted above is a special case in that the
correlation there between the different demographic and economic series
is made within a comparatively homogeneous region and a limited sphere
of human activity (agrarian economy). The sectional application of serial
history to different areas usually leads to the analysis of regional or
national disequilibriums. And general, or would-be general, serial his-
tory, even when restricted to a limited geographical area, tends to lead to
the analysis of temporal disequilibriums between the different evolution-
ary rhythms of each level of human activity.
The first point is now well known, thanks to the increasing number of
studies on regional economic history. The specialist is used to the idea of
there being measurable differences between different countries and be-
52 History Today
54
From Narrative History to Problem-oriented History o>
The best way to tackle this very old problem is to study some examples, in
increasing order of complexity and uncertainty. I shall borrow them from
the field of historical demography, one of the most studied areas of
French historiography in the past twenty years. It is also one of the fields
that provide the greatest opportunities for formulating problems mathe-
matically. This special position is-due to the particular nature of the
discipline and to the sacrifices it has made for the sake of defining its
object clearly. Demography is entirely predicated on the principle of
abstract equality, according to which Napoleon’s birth has exactly the
same importance as that of any one of his future soldiers. Having adopted
a hypothesis that sacrifices all the particular aspects in the life of indi-
viduals—in other words, the essence of their history—it transforms his-
torical individuals into interchangeable and measurable units, by means
of unvarying and comparable events: birth, marriage, and death.
Stripped of the layers of meaning that each civilization has in its own way
given them, these events are reduced to their most fundamental charac-
teristic: the stark fact that they took place.
I am deliberately describing them all as “events,” since I do not see, a
priori, what distinguishes one particular historical fact from another—for
example, a birth, however anonymous, from a battle, however famous.
In this respect, the current distinction between structural and narrative
history is irrelevant to historical data themselves: there is no such thing as
a difference between facts that are events and facts that are not events.
History is a permanent event. However, some classes of events can be
more easily conceptualized than others, that is, integrated into an intel-
ligible system—as in the case of demographic events.
The raw and particularly simple data on births, marriages, and deaths
have become the object of a specific discipline: demography. They can
thus form the basis for a certain number of calculations and analyses,
which themselves are prefabricated objects of historical research. In
other words, they are objects or concepts elaborated by a discipline other
than history—in this case, demography, for which history, however, also
supplied primary material in the form of birth, marriage, and death
From Narrative History to Problem-oriented History 61
external constraints imposed, in this case, by church and clergy. But there
are no appropriate data—nor will there ever be—that can provide
answers to hypotheses concerning the psychology of historical agents.
The agents are dead, and very few of them, even among the fraction who
wrote about themselves, bothered with the part of their being that,
before Freud, they had neither the means nor even the curiosity to
explore. Thus the historian of what is now referred to by the very vague
term of mentalités must either base his investigation on scattered or
ambiguous texts or find an indicator not of his subjects’ psychology but of
their behavior in order to deduce the psychological roots of this behavior.
In the first approach, the historian encounters the difficulty of assess-
ing the significance of a both subjective and exceptional piece of evi-
dence. Admittedly, all historical data (except the vestiges of men’s mate-
rial existence) are to a certain extent subjective. Even the registration of a
birth or the accounts of an estate were, at a certain moment in time, put
down on paper by an individual. But the constraints that govern the
recording of an event differ considerably according to the phenomenon
observed, the nature of the observation, and that of the observer; accord-
ing to whether the event is normal and repetitive—that is, comparable to
an earlier one—or extraordinary and therefore recorded precisely be-
cause it lies outside the norm of habit; according to whether one is dealing
with a systematic observation governed by certain rules or with a chance
testimony, a census, or an impression; finally, according to whether the
relationship linking the observer to the object observed is or is not in the
nature of knowledge.
With regard to my example, the historical evidence that can tell us
about the psychological roots of behavior dating back several centuries is
naturally of a literary nature. I use literary in the broad sense to include
certain texts that posterity has not elevated to that rank: the handful of
unpublished private diaries and of old manuscripts that can cast some
light on the subject. But such evidence is scarce, impossible to use in
systematic temporal series, and limited to a very narrow social environ-
ment. In order to bypass its random character, one will have to consult a
different kind of documentation, this time of a normative type: manuals
of good manners or specialized treatises on religious morality, such as
penitentials. However, texts of this kind present the same ambiguity as
government legislation. They prescribe an optimal conduct, but one can
never determine to what extent it was accepted, obeyed, or internalized.
Is the reiteration of rules of conduct over a long period a sign of their
having penetrated into society or, rather, of the resistance they have
provoked? The second hypothesis is as probable as, if not more probable
than, the first. In this case, the normative text is more interesting for its
“preamble” and whatever observations of actual behavior it may contain
than for what it forbids or orders. But it serves primarily as evidence
From Narrative History to Problem-oriented History 65
able nor necessarily clear. Interpretation more often than not involves
hypotheses that are not proven or not provable.
The problem posed by recent historiographical developments, partic-
ularly by the use of strict demonstration procedures, is not to determine
whether history itself can become a science. Considering the indeter-
minacy of history’s object of study, the answer to that question is un-
doubtedly negative. The problem is to determine the limits within which
those procedures can be of use in a basically unscientific discipline.
Although these limits are obvious, one should not deduce that history
should revert to its former function as fortune-teller. Instead, the un-
reasonable ambitions of “total history” should be lowered and, in our
exploration of the past, we should make the utmost use of the sectorial
discoveries and methods of certain disciplines and of the conceptual
hypotheses emerging from the great contemporary potpourri called the
human sciences. The cost of this change is the breakup of history into
many histories and the renunciation by historians of their role as social
authorities. However, the epistemological gains may be worth such sac-
rifices. History will probably always oscillate between the art of narrative,
conceptual understanding, and the rigor of proofs; but, if its proofs are
more solid and its concepts more explicit, knowledge will stand to gain
and narrative will have nothing to lose.
History and Ethnology
68
History and Ethnology 69
to human history—a final phase that would perpetuate itself through the
Holy Empire of medieval Christendom. The Old Testament legend suc-
cumbed first to humanist pressure, then to Protestant pressure, and
finally to the rise of the nation-state. Humanist philosophers were too
fascinated by antiquity to develop a historicist vision of the past. But
humanism provided at least the intellectual groundwork for such a vision
be inventing scholarship and distinguishing between ‘‘fables”’ and “‘true”’
history. In any event, the religious schism clouded the meaning of Scrip-
ture; it shifted the locus of the narrative of origins at the same time as it
transformed eschatology. But the Protestant rejection of the Apocalypse
and the church was a sign that the activity of deciphering the past could
now focus on other objects—on the state, the notion of irreversibility,
and the obsession with origins. History became secularized even as it
turned to the study of nations. This phenomenon is clear in the French
case, with Jean Bodin, La Popeliniére, and the Chancelier Pasquier.
Gallican history emerged as a reaction by French jurists against “‘Italian”’
humanism, which they suspected of embodying a double form of Roman
imperialism: the imperialism of antiquity and that of the papacy. The
French jurists were concerned with justifying royal power, particularly in
the struggle against the extremism of the Ligues.'
Thus, between the sixteenth century and the Enlightenment, history—
at least profane history, which was carefully distinguished from sacred
history—was above all the history of nations, that is, of the states and
peoples of Europe. Even Voltaire, who tried to adopt a broader perspec-
tive, used Louis XIV’s state—the apogee of civilization—as the implicit
point of reference for his universal history. The history of human prog-
ress is signposted by the nation-state. Fledgling anthropology was re-
served for undeveloped peoples.
Accordingly, by the eighteenth century, when the description of
“primitive” peoples was becoming a fairly systematic discipline, a single
hierarchy of values ranked the study of time above travel literature. The
national societies explored by the historian became the ideal model for
the future of the groups described by the traveler.
The nineteenth century probably deepened the rift between the two
disciplines by abolishing their complementary character. The imaginary
temporal and spatial link between two universal phases—infant man and
adult man, primitive society and civilized society—was destroyed by the
notion that these were elusive and distinctive phenomena. The nation-
state ceased to embody the collective progress of mankind and became
the locus par excellence of antagonism and differentiation. Moreover,
history was no longer dependent on a frame of reference that charted the
stages of human development. It was now torn by an endlessly shifting
balance of power and by conflicting justifications. The ideology of pro-
gress, which somewhat hastily extrapolated the extraordinary rhythms of
economic change into the whole scope of human activity, transformed
70 History Today
Even the West, when it tries to counteract the intellectual spread of its
most radical ideas, has no clear-cut frontiers left other than those pro-
vided by economic history, such as Rostow’s model of takeoff. Perhaps
this is an underhand manner of continuing to put oneself forward as an
example by constructing a linear schema in which “‘postindustrial’’ so-
ciety constitutes a horizon for mankind. At least it is a way of bringing
mankind back into the realm of history.
Space has thus become historicized, but at the cost of a fragmentation
of time. As history gradually absorbs the whole of mankind and becomes
less Europocentric, it faces the ethnological challenge represented by the
multiplicity of societies and cultures. This multiplicity undermines the
notion of homogeneous time. Not only do societies evolve at different
rhythms, but even within a given society the different levels of reality that
compose it are not governed by an all-embracing and homogeneous
temporality. “Change” has become a concept measurable in economic
terms, in its various aspects; but it also reveals resistance to change.
“Takeoff,” “modernization,” and the universalization of material prog-
ress and economic growth are thought of as the keys to the significance of
contemporary history; but they clash with heritage, tradition, and the
entire range of sociocultural patterns of inertia. Thus, by extending its
field to the human world, history has discovered that it is also nonhistory:
change reveals immobility. The great nineteenth-century historical tradi-
tion, inspired by both Manchester and Marx and predicated upon univer-
sal progress through economic development, is consequently being
undermined by the crises of the contemporary world and by the applica-
tion of its hypotheses to non-European areas. It is therefore no surprise
that, while desperately trying to preserve its hegemony as a standard-
bearer of “modernization,” history is returning to ethnology as if it were
aware of its own failures.
2. A second and probably less visible series of changes in the relations
between history and ethnology is inherent in history itself and in its
development as a discipline over the last thirty or forty years. I am
referring to what is called in France, using a vague and moreover negative
term, the replacement of a “history of events” (histoire événementielle)
by a “‘non-event-oriented history” (histoire non événementielle).
Let us try to define these terms by abstracting them from the context of
a pointless dispute. The history of “events” seems to me to be both a way
of describing the past and a way of selecting events. Such history, which is
informed by the desire to reconstruct “what happened” and to recount it
in the narrative mode, chooses its material in accordance with these aims;
in other words, the material—the celebrated events—is selected and
arranged along the time axis in such a way as to give substance to the
narrative as it unfolds. Change thereby becomes inherent in events, and
the chain of events is supposed to give a meaning to the succession of
changes. That is why history of this kind is marked, in contradictory
72 History Today
fashion, both by the short term and by teleology. Since an event, a sudden
irruption of the unique and the new into the concatenation of time,
cannot be compared with any antecedent, the only way to integrate it into
history is to endow it with a teleological significance. And as history has
developed as a mode of internalizing and conceptualizing the feeling of
progress, “events” in most cases constitute stages in an advent, for
instance, of the Republic, of freedom, of democracy, or of reason.
However patiently one tries, in accordance with the strictest rules of
scholarship, to reconstruct an “‘event’”—the quintessential form of histor-
ical ‘“‘fact”—that event derives its significance only from a total history
external to the event and independently defined. The temporal structure
of this type of history consists of a series of discontinuities described in the
mode of continuity: such is the classic substance of narrative.
History of the non événementielle kind rejects narrative—at least this
literary type of narrative—as its primary concern is to define problems.
Borrowing from the contemporary social sciences such as demography,
geography, and sociology, it has renewed and redefined the scope of
historical inquiry. First, it isolates the various levels of historical reality in
order to focus on a small number of them, or ona single one, and describe
them (or it) as systematically as possible, that is, separately. That is why it
constructs historical ‘‘facts” that differ on two counts from those of
“event-oriented”’ history: in most cases, they lie outside the classic field
of major political changes, and they are defined no longer by their
uniqueness but by the possibility of their being compared with earlier and
later phenomena. A “fact” is no longer an event chosen because it
coincides with a high point in a history whose ‘meaning’ has been
determined beforehand, but a phenomenon chosen and constructed on
the basis of its recurrent character, which makes it comparable to other
phenomena of the same kind over a given period. Documents and “‘facts”’
no longer exist independently but in relation to the series that precedes
and follows them; it is their relative value that becomes objective and not
their relation to an elusive “true” substance. By the same token, new
topics and methods have been developed. Historical corpora are by
definition so diverse that the historian can assemble them according to his
preferences and skills and deal with them from an economic, demo-
graphic, sociological, ethnological, or linguistic point of view.
But there is no such thing as an innocent methodology. By his new
approach, the historian has changed the nature of the problems tradi-
tionally dealt with by his discipline. The unique and noncomparable
phenomenon cannot be handled by such a methodology, and the special-
ist of intellectual biography will not find it satisfactory, either. Nor will
the historian of antiquity, who lacks and probably always will lack the
serial data indispensable for a systematic quantitative treatment.
Moreover, history that relies on serial data concentrates on a particular
type of source, of problem, and above all of temporality. The sources
History and Ethnology 73
A Dual Tradition
The absence of history from the educational system, and thus its non-
existence as a school discipline, in early modern Europe is due to the fact
that it simply did not exist as a discipline at all. It was torn between two
intellectual activities that ignored or even scorned each other: erudition
and philosophy. The first was in the hands of the antiquarii, also known in
old French texts as antiquaires, that is, specialists of things ancient and,
naturally, of antiquity—men who confined themselves to a narrow,
esoteric, and recondite area of knowledge and who were proficient in
dead languages. This tradition gave birth, not to history in the
nineteenth-century sense of the word, but to the notion of historical facts
as the building blocks of history.
This old tradition, whose roots go back to the Renaissance, was not
originally a critical tradition.' It did not deal with Scripture but with
Greco-Roman antiquity, in which sixteenth-century Europe passionately
sought a new identity. However, the antiquarians’ interest in antiquity
did not stem from a desire to rewrite the history of that period. The
ancients had already written it, and who could improve on Thucydides,
Livy, or Tacitus? The task of the “moderns” was simply to comment on
ancient historians, to work in their margins. That was the meaning of
belles-lettres. Alternatively, when they wanted to escape this mirror game
they would write Roman (or Greek) ‘‘antiquities,” not “histories.”’ But
these “‘antiquities’”’ were themselves doubly marginal with respect to the
royal way of history: they described nonliterary sources, and they ex-
humed coins, stones, inscriptions, and portions of monuments—the ran-
First published as ‘“‘La Naissance de l’histoire,” H-Histoire, no. 1 (March 1979), 11-41.
dig
78 Seventeenth- and Eighteenth-century Culture
classicism: “For a long time the author wondered whether this work
should not be entitled Mémoires, which is certainly the title that would
suit it best, both because of the manner of its composition and because of
the purpose for which it was compiled. The title of Annales has also been
envisaged, because in fact the work follows as much as possible the
sequence of periods and is even divided almost always according to year;
moreover, a plain and unadorned style, such as will be found here, seems
more suited to annals than to history. Nevertheless, the title of History
was finally adopted as it is the one requiring the least justification,
because it is the simplest, and because all narrative is in a sense a History.
But the readers are asked to consider the title only in that sense of the
word, and not to expect to find an ordered history here. The author never
contemplated writing a history of that sort, and he would like to make it
clear that he has always regarded such an undertaking as exceedingly
difficult in itself and far beyond the scope of whatever talent and knowl-
edge he may possess.’”
One might, however, infer from this excessive display of modesty that the
gap between historians and antiquarians was narrowing. On the contrary,
eighteenth-century French culture widened the gap by creating a vogue
for ‘‘philosophical history,” which drew away from antiquarian research,
an activity it disdained.
Actually, it was the very advances in this research that backfired on it
in the late seventeenth and early eighteenth centuries. Antiquarian re-
search had criticized some traditional historical beliefs, for instance by
debunking miracles, reducing the number of Christian martyrs, and
revamping biblical chronology. As a consequence, rationalist individual-
ism systematically challenged the very notion of historical fact. Bayle
devoted an entire dictionary, from A to Z, to the destruction of the
historical foundations of religious beliefs, but all he left to the rational
individual was uncertainties. Fontenelle bluntly observed that it was
impossible to write truthful history: ‘We have been so accustomed during
our childhood to Greek fables that when we have become capable of
reasoning, it does not occur to us to find them as astonishing as they really
are. But if we shake off our habitual ways, we cannot help being fright-
ened at the realization that the entire ancient history of a people is merely
a heap of fantasies, dreams, and absurdities. Is it possible that all this
could have been passed off as true? Why would it have been presented to
us as false? How could men have been fond of blatant and ridiculous
falsehoods, and why should they have stopped being fond of them?”
But, above all, this historical defeatism was rooted in an obsession
with modernity, that is, with the present. European elites had lived since
The Birth of History in France 81
antiquity, and the model of a moral narrative in the manner of Livy. But
history subsumed not only the techniques and achievements of the ars
antiquaria—chronology, paleography, archaeology, and so on—but also
the inventory of space, that is the activity that preceded geography and
was known as “travel.” For the non-European societies, scattered across
the surface of the earth and gradually described by travelers, also tes-
tified, in their own way, to history: the “savage” was man in his infancy.
Space and time thus provided complementary perspectives for the de-
veloping study of evolution. And it is on the basis of this epistemological
connivance that, in the later reforms of the French educational system,
geography and history moved forward in stride and as if intertwined.
But in the eighteenth century, the ill-defined state of history as a field is
sufficient proof of the extent to which the study of the past was still far
from being a school discipline: if history was not taught, it is because it
was not yet a teachable subject.
The two types of intellectual activity that composed history were too
foreign to each other to constitute a homogenous discipline. Erudition
was both too uncertain and too scholarly an art to be taught in the
classroom. It was indulged in by gentlemen and by a narrow circle of
specialists who discussed their discoveries far from even a cultivated
public. How could one teach numismatics in primary or secondary
school? As for philosophical history, it attracted many readers but repre-
sented too modern a genre, in every sense of the word modern, for it not
to be, educationally speaking, a dangerous product. In the eighteenth
century, it was still too recent a creation for its legitimacy to be recog-
nized. Thus, it did not command the respect normally associated with
subjects taught at school. Above all, philosophical history ran counter to
the classical tradition, in which history was no more than an annex to
belles-lettres, in other words, a fine story modeled on Livy or Tacitus.
The Jesuit secondary schools (colléges) remained faithful to their late
sixteenth-century charter, in which the model of antiquity constituted the
cultural identity of Europe. Students learned history—apart from sacred
history—only in the margins of Cicero.
There had been and still were exceptions to this rule. The elementary
schools of Port-Royal turned history into a core discipline to which part of
the daily schedule had to be devoted. But these schools were ephem-
eral—they were closed when Louis XIV persecuted the “Messieurs” of
Port-Royal—and strictly elitist, since they took in only the children of the
Jansenist upper bourgeoisie. The Port-Royal example, therefore, illus-
trates the exceptional rather than the regular presence of history in school
curricula. The Oratorians, too, later regretted not having made enough
room for history in their schools. And the military academies founded by
the monarchy in the third quarter of the century, with a view to training
professional soldiers, tried to include history in their curriculum. But,
until the expulsion of the Jesuits from the kingdom, in 1762, it was their
The Birth of History in France 83
colléges that set the pace for secondary education. Although they re-
mained conservative in their curricula—introducing Cartesianism, for
example, only in the eighteenth century—it would be wrong to think that
they were particularly ‘“reactionary.” The universities of the same
period—especially the University of Paris—were still far more insensitive
to the shifting boundaries of intellectual fields. At the end of the eigh-
teenth century, the professors of rhetoric of the faculty of liberal arts in
Paris found nothing to change in their traditional blend: a smattering of
ancient history tacked onto sacrosanct Latin discourse.
The fact remains that the expulsion of the Jesuits signaled the begin-
ning of a vast intellectual debate over the nation’s educational system.
The celebrated Jesuit schools, bereft of their teachers, were placed under
the control of the Parlement of Paris, whose task was now to fill them with
new professors and new ideas. Hence a flowering of educational schemes,
the most famous being the one put forward by La Chalotais. In a report of
1768, the president, Rolland d’Erceville, tried to make a synthesis of
these schemes. This was, in a sense, a Jansenist revenge, for the eigh-
teenth-century parlementaires had never really accepted the condemna-
tion of Jansenism by Rome, and they relished the political aspects of what
had been a rare example of resistance to Louis XIV’s absolute authority.
Thus, it was also a revenge for history, which had been held in such high
esteem at Port-Royal. But, for the parlementaires, the most detestable
feature of the Society of Jesus was the fact that it was a foreign order,
alien to the kingdom and totally in the hands of the pope. The par-
lementaires wanted a “‘national’” educational system controlled by the
state. This upper nobility of the robe, a passionately Gallican group,
expressed in its own manner and in its own cultural terms the strong
upsurge of a feeling of national identity rooted in a very distant past.
These men wanted school curricula to include not history in general so
much as the history of France, for it was this history that guaranteed the
original contract between the nation and its king and was the depository
of an imprescriptible tradition.
Actually, if one looks at the French secondary schools revamped at the
end of the ancien régime, one finds that history had made occasional
inroads into the curricula. At the celebrated Collège Louis-le-Grand on
the Montagne Sainte-Geneviéve in Paris, a compulsory half hour of
history on “days off, Sundays, and holidays” was introduced in 1769. A
number of historical topics were set as subject matter for “exercises,” the
public contests held on days off with the aim of testing the pupils’
expository and reasoning skills. In 1772, an exercise at the collége of
Arras was conducted in order to demonstrate that ‘‘the study of the
history of France in particular can alone impress in the lawyer’s mind the
true principles of our government.” In Lille, French history was included
in the curriculum itself, beginning with the class of troisiéme, during
which Gaul, the Germanic invasions, and the first two dynasties (Mero-
84 Seventeenth- and Eighteenth-century Culture
reasoning, and the glorification of national identity did not square with a
scientistic vision of the universe—a vision within which that identity
constituted a sort of irreducible residue. The other explanation involves
political ideology: the French revolutionaries did not regard their action
as taking place within a narrow, national framework. In its struggle for
liberty and equality, Jacobin and Thermidorean France constituted the
vanguard of mankind itself. Even when its armies ransomed conquered
countries, revolutionary France never abandoned the concept of univer-
sal democracy. Last, and perhaps not least, what was revolutionary
France to do with the nation’s interminable past, which belonged to the
monarchy and to feudalism? The Revolution was associated only very
briefly with the notion of a restoration of a golden age in the relationship
between the monarchy and the nation. All the ideas about a popular
contract, original rights, and a primitive constitution vanished as soon as
the Revolution displayed its true colors. It was the Revolution itself that
marked the starting point, established the original contract and constitu-
tion, and founded a new national history by wresting the French from
their past. Since the Revolution cut French history in half, why did it have
to recount that damnable part that belonged to its enemies? But the other
part was still too short to constitute a past; it was only the celebration of
origins.
Thus, for the French revolutionaries, history was not a genealogy, as it
was to be for nationalist ideologies of the nineteenth century. Instead, it
provided a universal reference chart against which the excellence and
supreme rationality of the French experience could be measured. The
French Revolution saw history as a laboratory for social science and as
the agent responsible for organizing the materials for that science—not as
a form of knowledge in its own right, built around the chronological study
of the nation’s annals. Consequently, the French Revolution bequeathed
no enduring doctrine of history to posterity. The notion of “social sci-
ence” lived on in the work of Saint-Simon and Auguste Comte but as a
marginal, illegitimate, and suspect current in our culture. The encyclo-
pedist concept was already obsolescent under the Directory, and it never
passed into the educational system. As for national history—the prime
area for the emergence of history as a discipline and for its legitimation as
a school subject—the French Revolution turned it into a battlefield for an
intellectual civil war. The French during the nineteenth century were a
people who could cherish only one-half of their history: who could not
love the Revolution without despising the ancien régime, nor love the
ancien régime without despising the Revolution.
Thus, history became an all the more burning educational problem and
issue as its development—both epistemological and institutional—led it
88 Seventeenth- and Eighteenth-century Culture
at last, after nearly a century, was the French Revolution in power. That
Republic, a provisional entity that nevertheless proved relatively long-
lived, represented a conservative authority governing in the name of
revolutionary values.
Once the English had been driven out, our France emerged.
But, in this France, the central figure was the man in whom
Joan of Arc put her hopes: the king. Because of the very fact
that he had united his kingdom and reconquered it from the
enemy, he, so to speak, concentrated all of France in his
person. And here is what pupils must be clearly told: by the
fifteenth century, when there were no more powerful vassals,
when Louis XI had annexed the last great independent prov-
inces, and when the communes had been disorganized by the
king’s agents and ruined by war, the king was no longer a
suzerain and protector; he was a master.
But beware! The following warning was crucial for future citizens:
the history of France a choice topic was not only its particular value but its
universal value. It took a hundred years for Mably and Condorcet to be
united through the agency of the republican school system.
The other facet of this analysis would consist in looking at why and how
this consensus has since broken down, especially after the Second World
War, under both internal and external pressure—resulting from the
evolution of historiography and of the social sciences in general and from
the end of European ascendancy in the world. Although, or because,
school syllabi always live on long after the circumstances that explain
their birth have disappeared, there is a general awareness today that the
teaching of history in France once again needs to be reexamined. And
perhaps the first step, before putting forward any proposals, would be to
understand what has come undone in the past hundred years. But one
must understand beforehand the various elements of the total picture.
One must first journey back through time. The following are what seem
to me to be the main stages of the journey.
In order to become a school discipline, history has had to undergo
several changes, so as to constitute an intellectually autonomous, socially
necessary, and technically teachable field of knowledge. For history, by
nature, lacks a particular object (since everything is ‘‘historical’’), an
autonomous language (since history is narrative), and assignable limits
(since it exists everywhere and nowhere). It is, therefore, particularly
hard to conceive history as a discipline, and all the more so as a school
discipline. Either it is not teachable or else it is taught—as was the case for
many centuries—as an appendage to classical letters. Even when it
became a school “subject,” its boundaries were laid down with painstak-
ing care, out of fear that the pupil would be lost in the ocean of “‘historical
facts” and fail to learn the language or method of history.
Since the seventeenth century, history’s progress toward autonomy
has followed two parallel and consequently independent tracks. Philo-
sophical history won the battle of the ‘““modern”’ against the “‘ancient”’
and eventually developed, thanks to Condorcet and the Idéologues, a
doctrine of progress. For its part, the ars antiquaria—from Port-Royal to
the Benedictines of Saint-Maur via the Académie des Inscriptions—
constructed a method for locating and evaluating historical facts. But in
the absence of a French Gibbon, the Enlightenment never united the two
learned traditions. It bequeathed to the Revolution and to the nineteenth
century a secularized discourse on universal history, along with a set of
distinct techniques and descriptive forms of knowledge—chronology,
paleography, travel, and so on.
It was these dissociated traditions that the nineteenth century thor-
oughly reshaped and redefined in order to produce, at the beginning of
the Third Republic, the history taught to French youth. Reshaping
meant, first of all, excluding. The age of classicism had shown the way by
beginning to place outside history certain sectors of the vast spectacle
98 Seventeenth- and Eighteenth-century Culture
For the historian, the book is always a perplexing object. Wrapped in its
title as if in a timeless definition, the book is forever enclosed, and yet it
never ceases to take on successive meanings. Although it is the product
par excellence of individual effort, it presupposes a community of lan-
guage and a complex system of social connections. It is doubly myste-
rious—as an invention and as a familiar object. Indeed, the study of the
book crystallizes all the difficulties of the historian’s craft: the passage
from the individual to the collective, the relation between the intellectual
and the social, time’s judgments on time, the measure of innovation and
inertia. Even though it has accumulated so many layers of criticism,
human writing is far from having been deciphered in terms of history.
For the past century and a half, traditional literary scholarship has
been tracking down the secrets of the book on two levels: internally,
through the study of the texts themselves, and externally, through the
biographical approach. Thus, traditional literary scholarship has been led
to make assumptions about social and collective phenomena on the basis
of evidence about individuals. It is precisely this approach that the
historian would like to reverse. Not that he is obliged to settle beforehand
the old debates about collective versus individual behavior or infrastruc-
ture versus superstructure. But the historian’s raison d’étre is to integrate
accidental phenomena into a quantitative and intelligible framework. He
must therefore isolate—in the extraordinarily bewildering mass of
99
100 Seventeenth- and Eighteenth-century Culture
As luck would have it, the historian of the printed book in the eigh-
teenth century has a series of highly valuable quantitative sources at his
disposal: the records of the royal book-control bureau, the Administra-
tion de la Librairie, recently unearthed by Robert Estivals.* By the
Renaissance, the French monarchy had secured control of the kingdom’s
literary output. It kept a careful record of printed matter at the Chancel-
lerie, which delivered printing licenses, and at the Dépôt Légal, which
registered published books. This extremely thorough and complex
bureaucratic accounting of book production has the posthumous advan-
tage of making it possible to conduct surveys on a very large scale and
thus to improve on later, incomplete bibliographies. It also offers the
historian a more sophisticated perspective: the relation between a society
and its own literary works. In this respect, the eighteenth century is an
ideal period for study.
In actual fact, the French monarchy under Louis XV and Louis XVI
was not the crude force of repression and censorship described a pos-
teriori by the revolutionary liberation movement. Not that it is inaccu-
rate, in a certain sense, to regard the Age of Enlightenment as a long
struggle between the forces of intellectual innovation and those of con-
servative resistance. But the role of inquisitor devolved primarily, not on
the central government, but on the Parlements, which happened at the
same time to be the staunch adversaries of the royal bureaucracy. The
king of France allowed more books to be published than the Sorbonne or
the great magistrates would bear, as is shown by the crisis over the
Encyclopédie. The truth is that the monarchic state, which put
Book Licensing and Book Production 101
Malesherbes in charge of the book trade for twelve crucial years as the
first directeur général de la librairie, followed prevailing trends more than
it directed them. The monarchy was not only very sensitive to pressures
from civil society but receptive to contemporary ideas and to the concept
of a more rational government. In short, it had become both weaker and
more modern. This change puts into clearer perspective the official
sources one can use to study the control of ideas. The technical and social
value of these sources makes them a rather exceptional document pro-
duced by a society on the subject of its own writings.
Most of this society’s literary output can be inventoried, since each
work had to be granted a printing license by the chancelier. But even
books that were refused a license were recorded on the register of
requests, and these victims of censorship do not elude our general count.
Traditionally, there were two types of licenses: priviléges and permissions
du Sceau. The first, which was costlier,’ also gave the applicant a monop-
oly on the work for a specified period. The second was not exclusive, but
it saved the expense of a privilége. Both licenses were public and were
explicitly mentioned in the books concerned; they were tantamount to
government decrees. The book-trade code (Code de la Librairie) of 1723
restated this procedure, which was more than a century old. Both types of
licenses were revocable, temporary, and renewable. When his privilége
expired, the printer who wanted to keep his monopoly or reissue a work
had to ask for a renewal or an extension of his privilége. The new license
was recorded in the same register and is, thus, a likely indication of the
work’s success.
The tendency for printing licenses to be renewed was a boon for
Parisian libraires (publisher-booksellers), who were in closer contact
than their provincial colleagues with the authorities and with authors. It
also fueled a long controversy in the eighteenth century. Provincial
libraires were opposed not to licenses but to their renewal. In a famous
text, Diderot came out in favor of the Parisian libraires in the name of
property rights.‘ This debate, from which the modern notion of copyright
gradually emerged, was resolved on 30 August 1777 by Louis XVI, who
issued a series of important decrees. Henceforth, an author who secured
a license in his own name and sold his work himself could hand down to
his heirs a perpetual copyright for his work. But the transfer of the
manuscript to a third party reduced the copyright to a life annuity, for the
license granted to the libraire was valid only during the author’s lifetime.
(However, a ten-year minimum was stipulated if the author died within
ten years of the issue date.) This marked the end of the renewal of
privilèges, and these renewals ceased to appear in our registers.
In addition, the 1777 decrees seem to have led to a new type of permit,
which did not bear the stamp of the Grand Sceau: the permission simple.
The Manuel de l’auteur et du libraire of 1777 does not mention it, while
the Almanach de la librairie of 1778 gives the following definition: ‘The
102 Seventeenth- and Eighteenth-century Culture
permission simple gives no other right than that of publishing a work for
which no license exists or for which the license has expired, under the
provisions of the Council’s decree of 30 August 1777 on licenses. Permis-
sions simples are issued with the simple signature of M. le Directeur
Général [de la Librairie].
“Any libraire or printer in any town can obtain a permit of this kind,
but he must have it recorded within two months on the registers of the
Chambre Syndicale [de la Librairie—the libraires’ guild] in the arron-
dissement corresponding to his place of residence, otherwise his permit
will be null and void.”
Thus, the decrees of 1777, by placing more books out of copyright,
made it easier to reprint them, especially for provincial libraires. How-
ever, these books slip through our survey, since the requests for permis-
sions simples were handled not by the Chancellerie but by the directeur
général alone.
Another type of printing license also appeared in the eighteenth
century: the permission tacite (‘‘tacit permit”). The best comment on it
was made by Malesherbes, in his fifth Mémoire sur les problèmes de la
librairie, written in 1759. First he discusses its origins: ““As the tendency
to publish on all sorts of subjects has become more widespread, and as
private individuals, particularly the powerful, have also become more
sensitive to being mentioned in print, circumstances have arisen in which
the authorities have not dared to grant public permission to publish a
book, and in which, nevertheless, they have felt that it would be impossi-
ble to forbid it. This is how the first tacit permits originated. . . .”
Malesherbes added that they had been on the increase “for the past thirty
years,” but in 1788 he wrote that he did not know when they had begun.°
His predecessor as supervisor of the book trade, the comte d’Argenson,
who had been chief of police during the Regency and had been, since his
very birth, familiar ‘‘with all the secrets of government,” had always
resorted to tacit permits. “I think,” Malesherbes added, ‘‘that they began
at about the time of Louis XIV’s death.” But the fact remained that they
were illegal—under the laws then in force—because they were not public:
“The only difference between these illegal permits and the others is that
they are not handled by the Sceau and that the public does not see the
censor’s name. This practice was probably introduced to give libraires
and authors some token authorization while protecting censors from
complaints by hostile [i.e. unsuccessful] applicants. But a record of these
permits is kept and the censor at fault is not immune from the rigors of
official punishment.”
These records are indeed preserved in the manuscript division of the
Bibliothèque Nationale under the title ‘Registre des livres d’impression
étrangère présentés à Monseigneur le Chancelier pour la permission de
débiter.” The first volume begins in 1718, but the series kept its fictitious
title until 1772 in order to conceal the illegal character of the new practice
Book Licensing and Book Production 103
by presenting these works as imports. The tacit royal license was confined
to the distribution of the book in question; officials refused to accept any
responsibility with regard to the act of printing. For the same reasons, a
great many eighteenth-century works printed in Paris by tacit permission
listed Amsterdam, London, Geneva, or even Peking as place of publica-
tion. It is only in 1772 that the registers of these licenses were labeled as
what they really were: an interesting sign that the royal bureaucracy was
no longer afraid of its own past and its own laws.
But, by the early eighteenth century, at the cost of a falsehood collec-
tively agreed upon, the bureaucracy authorized and kept count of a
literature that it itself designated as bearing the stamp of presumed
nonconformism. The state accepted this literature as inevitable, that is, as
the expression of a social and intellectual current that could no longer be
repressed but only channeled. When in 1758 the weight of scandal led the
chancelier to revoke the license for the Encyclopédie by government
decree, Malesherbes got around the difficulty by issuing a tacit permit.
But, more generally, authors or libraires who were seeking to avoid
difficulties and reduce costs or who were speculating on the diminishing
resistance of the authorities bypassed the administrative channel of the
Sceau Public de la Chancellerie; they contented themselves with asking
for a gesture of tolerance whose only guarantee lay in a consensus
between public opinion and government. Among these somewhat sus-
pect new titles, whose character was not concealed from the censor,
manuscripts formed the largest but—as Diderot noted—not the only
group: ““One must distinguish two sorts of titles appearing by tacit per-
mission alone: the first are the work of foreign authors and have already
been published outside the kingdom; the second are the work of authors
living in France and are in manuscript or have been published under
spurious titles.’
Thus, there is a qualitative difference between the two major series of
records relating to applications for printing licenses. In the eighteenth
century itself, an external dividing line was drawn between two types of
literature—a partition that is valuable for the historian, since it indicates
the origin of the defenses put up by a society against its own culture. This
aspect alone would be a sufficient justification for maintaining that divid-
ing line and thus for studying priviléges and tacit permits separately. But
the quantitative analysis of these sources confirms the need for this
methodological approach.’
Between 1723—the opening date for the registers, following a gap
between 1716 and 1723—and 1789, one finds 31,716 works submitted for
a privilège or permission du Sceau. This figure is higher than the one given
by R. Estivals, because he counts only published books, not licenses. The
fact is that libraires or printers would sometimes include several books in
a request for a single privilège or permission du Sceau.* Actually, the same
is true for tacit permits, but there are far fewer works covered by this
104 Seventeenth- and Eighteenth-century Culture
series for the whole century: only 12,610, or just over a third of the
number of books in the first series.
This numerical gap is essentially due to the chronological difference
between the two sources. Even though they dated from the Regency,
tacit permits did not flourish in earnest before the 1750s. The practice did
not become widespread until Malesherbes was appointed to the Direc-
tion Générale de la Librairie in 1751. The first register of tacit permits
(1718-47) lists a total of 713 books over thirty years, that is, a very low
average of 24 a year. The second register (December 1750-March
1760)—which, no less than the first one, is impossible to analyze on a
yearly basis—includes 714 titles for a period of nine years and four
months, that is, 126 a year. This almost decennial average is in itself only
the starting point of a rising trend, since the next two registers reveal a
very rapid increase in the annual average: 156 books a year between
March 1760 and October 1763; 396 between October 1763 and November
1766. From 1767 on, the sources make it possible to calculate annual
figures showing that there were nearly as many requests for tacit permits
as for standard licenses (see chart).
While the two trends converged from the late 1760s on, only the
second trend presents features enabling internal comparisons to be made
from the beginning of the century onward, because of the relative stabil-
ity of the annual figures. The yearly average for the period from 1723 to
1789 was 463 books; the figure works out to 456 before 1750 and 469 from
1750 to 1789. There is no trace here of the discontinuity that characterizes
the registers of tacit permits. Thus, one cannot combine the evidence for
two administrative practices that are not comparable, for one was an
institutionalized tradition, and the other, which was for long time un-
avowed and unavowable, did not flourish before the 1760s.
Moreover, the problem remains of determining if and how, in earlier
decades, the hundreds of titles a year belonging to a category officially
recognized only later were actually printed. In his fourth Mémoire sur les
problèmes la librairie, which can be dated to early 1759, Malesherbes
noted that ‘over the past thirty years the use of tacit permits has become
almost as widespread as that of public licenses.” “Over the past thirty
years”? Since the 1730s? The statement is surprising if one compares it
with the huge disparity in the annual figures revealed by the two series of
licensing records spanning the first half of the century. Yet it is difficult to
reject this statement out of hand, coming as it does from a man who was
ideally placed to know. One can assume both that the statement was
exaggerated’ and that nevertheless, during this period, a considerable
number of books were granted permits so “‘tacit’’ as to leave no written
trace. Indeed, Malesherbes himself implied as much in his fifth Mémoire
sur les problèmes de la librairie, quoted earlier, when, having distin-
guished between tacit permits and simple acts of tolerance of which no
trace remained, he added, “The first tacit permits to be granted were no
Book Licensing and Book Production 105
doubt of this sort; similar permits are sometimes still given, owing to the
lack of well-established principles enabling the censor to regard himself
as immune from reproach. But true tacit permissions differ considerably
from these acts of tolerance or perhaps of connivance.”
Thus, it is probable that until the 1750s a wide variety of illegal
literature—distinct, however, from clandestine literature proper, hunted
down by the royal police—was simply tolerated by the authorities, with-
out our being able to find a written trace of it in the licensing registers.
An example dating from the midcentury shows the extent of juris-
prudential uncertainty surrounding the matter. In 1748, Montesquieu
had L’Esprit des lois printed in Geneva without an author’s name. Its
immediate impact in France indicates how widely it was distributed. Both
the Jesuits, in the Mémoires de Trévoux, and the Jansenists, in the
Nouvelles ecclésiastiques, devoted two articles to it the following year.
The Jansenist journal, which fulminated against the book, concluded its
second article, dated 16 October 1749, by openly accusing the authorities:
“Orders will be given for the executioner to burn the Nouvelles ecclésias-
tiques, whose sole and perpetual aim is to confirm men in the possession
of truths that make both a true Christian and a faithful subject of the king;
and permission will be granted for the sale of a disgraceful work that
teaches men to regard virtue as a useless principle for a monarchy, and all
religions, even the true religion, as political issues, as being solely the
product of climate, etc. May we be allowed to say so: is not one act a
punishment for the other?” In August 1750 the Sorbonne intervened in
its turn to make up post eventum for the official clearance that had not
been requested for the work. The Sorbonne suggested a certain number
of cuts, which Montesquieu refused by appealing to public opinion: “‘All
of Europe has read my book, and everyone agrees that it was impossible
to tell whether I preferred republican government or monarchical gov-
ernment... .’’ Actually, if Malesherbes is to be believed,” Montesquieu’s
book, in its original form, obtained a tacit permit that immediately paved
the way for numerous reprints, none of which bear any traces of the
Sorbonne’s demands.
The very complexity of this example shows that it is hard to assess the
precise bibliographical value of the two series of licensing records de-
scribed above. As comparisons cannot be made with the two most readily
available sources—the Dépôt Légal, which is less exhaustive, or the
alphabetical author catalog of the Bibliothéque Nationale, which does
not list anonymous titles—the simplest procedure is to summarize the
contents of the two registers in order to point out what they do not
contain.
1. The registers of privilèges and permissions du Sceau contain three
sorts of applications. The largest category concerns new manuscripts. But
before the decrees of 1777, which put an end to the need to apply for
106 Seventeenth- and Eighteenth-century Culture
BELLES-LETTRES
1793 books 2728 books 2285 books Re books 821 books 724 books
12 unidentified 72 unidentified 49 unidentified ~ - Miscellanies
100 % ye Almanacs
> Journals
< Humor
Orators
Poetry
Grammar
Philology
Belles-lettres
ar Dictionaries
0 nai 1723-27 1750-54 1784-88
Various
rio LESS 00S: = = Specialized arts
e Liberal arts
=
aed -
Politics
Sciences
20
Philosophy
(Novels)
Belles-lettres
Grammar
Dictionaries
0 1750-59 1770-74 1780-84
1750-59 1770-74 1780-84
100 %; Specialized arts
Various + =
Mechanical arts
Liberal arts
TACIT PERMITS
PEN
Politics
Sciences
\
Philosophy
100
80
Tacit
permits
Sciences
71] and arts
20
Politics
1720 30 40 50 60 70 80 88
108 Seventeenth- and Eighteenth-century Culture
One can also reverse the question: What sort of publication bypassed
applications for printing permits, whether public or tacit? Basically, three
categories of books.
No doubt the least important one includes a share of provincial pub-
lications. In the eighteenth century, most new books published in the
provinces with official permission seem to be works of local interest—
items commissioned by local government bodies, bishoprics, courts of
justice, academies, or universities. That, at least, is the conclusion drawn
from Madeleine Ventre’s study of the Languedoc,” and her data seem to
correspond to what we know about the rapid decline in provincial pub-
lishing as early as the seventeenth century.
Actually, in the eighteenth century, a considerable number of provin-
cial libraires and printers had taken to dealing directly with the central
government, especially for matters that did not concern official orders
from local authorities. The prevailing trend was toward centralization,
and the appropriate habits were spreading. But the fact that our registers
contain few applications for licenses from the provinces substantiates and
justifies in retrospect the endless complaints by eighteenth-century pro-
vincial libraires against their Parisian colleagues, who exercised a dual
110 Seventeenth- and Eighteenth-century Culture
hegemony over the book market owing to the renewal of their licenses
(which prolonged their monopoly of previously published books) and
owing to the proximity of most authors (which gave them a monopoly of
new titles). The example of the Languedoc shows that the decrees of 1777
gave a small stimulus to provincial publishing without seriously threaten-
ing Parisian ascendancy.
In practice, a Parisian libraire would be deprived of a manuscript only
if the author, fearing even the censorship of tacit permits, preferred the
circuitous route of having his book printed in the provinces or abroad and
deposited at the Chambre Syndicale. But even in this case the work
would be mentioned in the registers of tacit permits under the heading of
“books introduced through the Chambre.” Thus, the Parisian and cen-
tralized character of the sources concerning official control of the book
trade is probably not a major drawback, at least for the eighteenth
century.
The two other categories of missing books pose a far greater problem
for an exhaustive census of eighteenth-century publications. First, some
books were simply tolerated by the police without ever being mentioned
in official documents. ‘I do not know,’’ wrote Malesherbes, who dis-
cussed these publications at length, “what to call these sorts of licenses,
which have become common practice. Strictly speaking, they are only
assurances of impunity.” It was, for example, an authorization of this
kind that Montesquieu’s Paris publisher claims to have obtained—prior
to any tacit permit—from the comte d’Argenson for L’Esprit des lois as
early as the beginning of 1749.”
We have seen that the very graph of the number of requests for tacit
permits is a sufficient indication of the extent of this practice before
Malesherbes took office. But, conversely, the increase in tacit permits
from 1751 onward strongly suggests that the first directeur général suc-
ceeded in establishing as a standard administrative practice the doctrine
he described to the dauphin in 1759, when he asserted that he knew ‘‘only
one way of enforcing prohibitions, namely, to enact as few of them as
possible.” One can also observe that his successors remained faithful to
his doctrine.
However, it is unlikely that simple tolerance disappeared altogether.
Too many anecdotes testify to the contrary, and in 1761 Malesherbes
himself found no other solution than to allow Rousseau’s Emile to
circulate at its own risk, without being able to grant it a tacit permit. But
when one considers the spread of tacit permits from the 1760s onward and
when one observes that Restif de la Bretonne and Mirabeau requested
and obtained them, one can assume that this practice very largely re-
placed the secret acts of tolerance of the first half of the century.
Nevertheless, the Parlements and the clergy continued to threaten
even authorized books with scandal and legal prosecution. They intimi-
dated not only authors but also censors and royal officials. It is their
Book Licensing and Book Production 111
pressure that explains to a great extent the existence of the last category
of books to elude our grasp—those that enjoyed no permission or toler-
ance whatsoever and, whether printed in France or (as was more often
the case) abroad, were quite simply clandestine. Police records and legal
sources for the history of the book trade under the ancien régime" are so
scattered that it is virtually impossible to make a count of such books.
Thus, by definition, they fall outside the scope of the present study.”
All the same, by using the applications for priviléges and tacit permits,
we have been able to count up slightly more than 44,000 book titles. This
is a considerable figure if one compares it, for example, with the 25,000
titles published in Paris during the sixteenth century (according to Lucien
Febvre and Henri-Jean Martin), even if it is true that we are dealing with
requests for publication and not with the published books themselves.
But we have seen how the statistical value of this count is unevenly
distributed: nearly 13,000 licensed books up to 1750, and only a few
hundred tacit permits. Thus, it is above all on the strength of the 30,000
works dating from the second half of the eighteenth century that the
sources studied here accurately reflect their titles and provide a realistic
census of the publications of their period.
Let us imagine for a moment that all these books could be placed in a
library arranged in a temporal sequence—a doubly fictive library, in that
successive reprints would stand alongside never-published manuscripts
and in that no cultured individual in the eighteenth century would have
deprived himself of the major works published abroad and banned in
France. But this imaginary library remains to a great extent, as we have
seen, that of an entire society. It is richer and more representative than
the partial bibliographies compiled late in the century. We have tried to
reconstruct it according to subject by means of chronological samplings.
Works have been classified according to eighteenth-century criteria.
The Bibliothéque Nationale contains a wealth of inventories of eigh-
teenth-century private libraries, in which books are arranged according
to the five major categories in use at the time: (1) theology and religion,
(2) law and jurisprudence, (3) history, (4) sciences and arts, and
(5) belles-lettres. Moreover, bibliographical manuals such as those of
Durcy de Noinville or Cels-Martin provide detailed information on the
guidelines for such inventories, thus making our own classification easier.
The following is the scheme adopted here:"
3. Novels
4. Correspondence”
D. Orators
E. Humor
F. Journals and periodicals
G. Almanacs*
H. Miscellanies
belongs to category IV. A very small number of titles raise the problem of
whether form or content should be the criterion. For example, should Le
Bonheur, a poem by Helvetius, come under the heading of “‘poetry”’ or
“ethics”? In all these cases we have been guided by eighteenth-century
criteria: the theme for Rousseau’s Discours was suggested by a resident
member of the Classe de Morale of the Académie de Dijon, and most
contemporary libraries classified the work under “ethics.” In the catalog
of Malesherbes’s library, Le Bonheur is listed under ‘ethics and morals,”
an extremely rare exception to the tyranny of nomenclature—a product
of classical aesthetics—which quite often manifested itself by the juxta-
position of a genre label to the title.
The slowness of identification procedures for these books naturally
made it impossible to classify all the 45,000 works mentioned. In order to
eliminate annual fluctuations and attempt to measure the general trend,
we have made three five-year samplings (1723-27, 1750-54, and 1784-
88), each involving some 2,000 works, in the registers of privilèges. The
registers of tacit permits, which can be used from 1750 on, have also been
divided into three periods: the first isa ten-year period (1750-59), so as to
obtain a reasonable number of books; the other two are five-year periods
(1770-74 and 1784-88). All the figures have been converted into percent-
ages to allow for comparisons. In absolute terms these figures represent
highly diverse units—since nothing is more different from one book than
another book—but in relative terms they are quite comparable, if indeed
reckoning in large numbers eliminates similar disparities within each time
period.
especially important area of sciences and arts: it was their volume and
above all their degree of ‘“‘nobility,” more than their special character,
that justified their being classified separately.
The privilége registers of 1723-27 point to the great social importance
of sciences, arts, and belles-lettres, all of which together represent nearly
half the total. Within the “sciences and arts” category, ethics and
metaphysics predominate in philosophy, and medicine dominates the
sciences. The “‘liberal arts,’’ consisting mainly of music, have a crushing
numerical superiority over agriculture and mechanical arts, which retain
the stigma of manual activities. Apart from the abrégés de paix perpetu-
elle, almost all “political” books consisted of manuals of commercial
practice.
In belles-lettres, classical aestheticism still prevailed: many grammar
and philology books perpetuated and taught the science and rules of
noble language. “Poetry,” in the wide sense of the word, was by far the
largest category, bearing witness to the persistence of the main classical
genres: verse, drama, and correspondence. There were also many books
in Greek and even more in Latin. But one can already note the relative
importance of novels, which were more common than verse compositions
and tragedies.
Such, then, were the broad bibliographical outlines of a great tradi-
tional classical culture in the early eighteenth century and the balance
between its various elements. One can proceed to a comparison with the
two samplings for the 1750s and the late eighteenth century based on the
privilége registers alone.
of the manual tradition of a preindustrial world that did not have much to
teach it. Instead, the Enlightenment sought to raise these arts to the level
of the style noble and to include them—in the name of universality—in a
hedonistic utopia. The cities of happiness depicted by Ledoux are
perhaps more significant than the famous plates of the Encyclopédie.
half the titles in this category. Naturally, we are dealing with the crisis of
the ancien régime—that is, the short-term crisis, for if one looks at the
1784-88 period year by year, one finds a fairly constant proportion of
books in the sciences and arts, while the percentage of these books that
were devoted to politics rose sharply from 1787 onward, specifically after
the Assembly of Notables in February, which triggered the spate of
revolutionary literature. A similar but opposite phenomenon no doubt
explains the relatively shrinking volume of political books between 1770
and 1774 in comparison with the 1750s: the early 1770s were the period of
the Triumvirate, the last great attempt at neoabsolutist government by a
king of France. At any rate, the percentage for “politics” rose suddenly in
1774 with the death of Louis XV, Turgot’s liberalization, and the return
of the Parlements. Thus, the registers of tacit permits not only confirm
the exuberance of science and art so deeply characteristic of the Enlight-
enment; they also record the shorter-term variations of this phe-
nomenon, which reflect the turning points charted by traditional history.
Hence the greater instability and the more marked character of per-
centages within the category. The most revealing perspective is obtained
by adding philosophical and political works together; their proportionate
volumes vary, but they have many internal connections in that the philo-
sophical category is dominated by the moral works of contemporary
philosophers. Indeed, it is not the twentieth century but precisely the
eighteenth century—with Abbé Baudeau—that invented the expression
“moral and political sciences.”’ One can thus measure their numerical
superiority over conventional sciences, a superiority that does not appear
in the public priviléges. The tacit permits forcefully demonstrate the
upsurge of interest in a wide range of social issues. However, certain
features are common to both sets of sources: the predominance of medi-
cine in the scientific category,“ the relative importance of agronomy, and
the infinitesimal percentage of works dealing with mechanical arts.
Toward the middle and end of the century, history seems to have
represented a percentage of tacit permits very close to its share of
privilèges. It is hard to explain the intervening drop during the 1770-74
period. However, an examination of the titles clearly shows that the
historical works submitted for tacit approval were of a slightly different
character from those listed in the privilége records: alongside genuine
historical narratives, one can observe an increase in historical
documentary literature, especially in more or less authentic memoirs of
more or less famous figures of the past. The term memoirs is in itself a
sufficient indication of the ambiguity and novelistic overtones of this
genre. During the eighteenth century, which novelized history and his-
toricized the novel, heated discussions took place about the similarity
between the two genres.
Moreover, the novel, a perennial suspect for classical aesthetics, was
taking shelter behind history. For this was one of the means it had
Book Licensing and Book Production 121
Manuscripts
Priviléges Tacit Permits Mornet
1741-45 74 18 205
1751-55 123 195 199
122 Seventeenth- and Eighteenth-century Culture
The soundings we have carrried out confirm the basic features of the
two sources—features emphasized in all contemporary accounts: without
tacit permits, the book-licensing records of the ancien régime would give
no indication of the fascination exercised by the novel over French
society at large. But, without the public licenses, these records would
obliterate all trace of the Latin culture and traditional aesthetics on which
every eighteenth-century generation—even that of the Revolution—was
brought up.
These two radically divergent series are valuable for the historian. Not
only do they help to mark the boundary between innovation and tradi-
tion, but, by assembling at the outset the conditions for their contradic-
tory development, they appear as complementary at the end of the
process. The proportions differ, but the trends are identical.
The persistence of legal works indicates the vitality of a political
society engendered by the great royal jurists. This continuity points both
to the proliferation of private interests and to the yearning for the
abstract and univocal arbitration of legal codes. The persistence of books
on history is as ambiguous to interpret as history itself, which in the
eighteenth century was, all at the same time, a conventional form of
recitation, an undiscriminating form of curiosity about time and space,
and an awakening of national consciousness. The Age of Enlightenment
Book Licensing and Book Production 123
125
126 Seventeenth- and Eighteenth-century Culture
that in the eighteenth century the same history could be written from
contradictory points of view—all it took was the demands of immediate
circumstance for that history to become overladen with unexpected signi-
ficance.
As observers of their own times, Boulainvilliers and Mably were
struck by the debasement of political freedom. What they regarded as the
most decisive development of their age was, however, stubbornly over-
looked by men around them whose task was to understand the present.
The intendants, for example, were supposed to describe conditions in
France, but their reports, which were filled with references to royal
rights, were silent about the rights of the French. “They do not conceive,
or refuse to conceive, of any principle of government other than the
despotism of a prince and his ministers,! wrote Boulainvilliers indig-
nantly, having resolved there and then to condemn the authorities. As for
Mably, he was distressed to read a history of France by Pére Daniel:
“From Clovis to our times,’’ Père Daniel led his reader on “‘as if he were
dealing with the very same monarchy.’” Only those who took the present
for granted could display such peace of mind; but a present experienced
in such a manner was, of necessity, unintelligible. Only dissatisfaction
with the present could give meaning to the past.
For both Boulainvilliers and Mably, the present in all its features
bespoke the abuses of despotic kingship, while contemporary observers
did not even seem aware of the fact. This twofold diagnosis lay at the
heart of the two authors’ pursuit of history, which they regarded as a
necessity. So similar was their need for history that Mably had to resist
those of his friends who wanted him to title his observations Histoire de
notre gouvernement. Histoire de l’Ancien Gouvernement de la France is
what Boulainvilliers had called his great work a half century earlier—a
telling sign that the two men shared an identical belief in history as a
meditation on the origins of power and as a remedy for fascination with
the present.
To confess to such beliefs was obviously to break with the providential-
ist view of history. Boulainvilliers did so more forcefully than Mably,
because for him the model of Bossuet, however repulsive (“one of the
most shameful demonstrations of the indignity of our time’’),*’ was also
closer and more constraining. Boulainvilliers still felt it necessary, before
undertaking a historical project, to state that God may have given man
natural wisdom without controlling the use man would make of it. “He
has abandoned the world to our contest”: this strong statement, which
emancipated history from metaphysics, opens the A brégé d’ Histoire uni-
verselle, written around 1700 for his children. Fifty years later, Mably did
not regard this laissez-passer—this laissez-penser—as indispensable,
even as a rhetorical precaution.
There was still another kind of history from which the very logic of
their undertaking diverted them: the history of princes written for
princes. Nevertheless, in keeping with tradition, Boulainvilliers wrote
128 Seventeenth- and Eighteenth-century Culture
history primers for the duke of Burgundy and Mably for the infante of
Parma. But neither author remained faithful to the content or tone of this
type of history, designed for a traditional purpose. Erudite minutiae
concerning ‘“‘idle and lazy kings who contributed nothing to human
happiness’’* seemed superfluous to both. There should be no trace of
sycophancy in a work aimed at being thoroughly critical. As a revenge on
despotism, history could bring monarchs before its tribunal. Mézeray and
Pére Daniel, for their part, had been gripped by panic when popes and
kings appeared on the stage. But their pusillanimity was precisely a
telling sign of what their work was worth.
Neither Mably nor Boulainvilliers wanted to break with erudite his-
tory—another variety of history for which tradition provided a model.
Following the teachings of Bayle, they still regarded history as a con-
tinuing effort to correct errors. But this demanding form of history,
requiring vast quantities of archives and preoccupied with checking facts,
was wholly dependent on the present. It was the present that guided the
historian in the necessary selection of events from the abundant stores of
the past. It was in the name of the present that the two authors disdained
the “‘succession of feats of arms and wars,” “quirks,” and “‘prejudice,” in
order to focus on the crucial issues: the source of authority, the extent and
limits of power, the rules of government in France, and, lastly, the
“principles” that determined the entire sequence of events leading up to
the detestable present.
For both Boulainvilliers and Mably recounted a process of deteriora-
tion. Theirs was a history of how ‘“‘self-evident principles” were worn
down, adulterated, and transformed beyond recognition. The history of
France was a story of decay. Boulainvilliers made the point in his empiri-
cal and realistic way by excusing himself—when, for example, he had to
discuss “‘the most unpleasant reign in the history of France,’ that of
Charles VI—for having to dwell so often on the disgrace of the state.
Mably described the same situation with the more tragic accents of a man
who viewed all of history as a decline. “History is an almost unbroken
succession of miseries, disasters, and calamities.’’’ What was there to be
gained from such a black tale? Mably and Boulainvilliers shared a some-
what intermittent belief in the pedagogic value of misfortune.
Yet the true value of history did not lie in these negative lessons, but in
giving prominence to a continuous transformation, in which the past was
constantly present in the present. Mably and Boulainvilliers—unlike
Voltaire—firmly believed in history as a process of perpetual change.
Neither thought it possible to divide the flow of time into periods that
would constitute strongly individualized and relatively autonomous
wholes. Thus, their history, which linked interminable transformations to
one another and displayed the ubiquitous role of differences, was both a
war machine against centralizing government and a remedy for the
doctrines of centralization and fixity. Its peculiar virtue was that it en-
abled the historian, thanks to the well-established connections between
Mably and Boulainvilliers 129
contract to France. It alone turned the French people into a free nation.
Everything had already been said in the late seventeenth century with the
words free nation.
History was thus the repository of the greatness of origins and the
secret of usurpations. It constituted a purely immanent reference system
that substituted for the unfolding of a providential plan. But Boulainvil-
liers used history to justify a ‘‘discourse on inequality” that was exactly
the opposite of Mably’s.
Yet for the comte de Boulainvilliers—and this once again proves how
much of an eighteenth-century man he was—men were originally free
and equal in rights. The problem for this intellectual so obsessed with his
noble status was, therefore, how to interpret and justify the traditional
social hierarchy according to the values of a cultural world already
dominated by the Enlightenment—that is, a world cut off from any
transcendental reference point and suffused with the concept of natural
equality among individuals. The task of history, in this cultural setting
marked by the notion of natural equality, was to explain the emergence of
inequality, the product of a conquest that turned the victors into nobles
and the vanquished into non-nobles. But Boulainvilliers did not stop
there, for history could undo what it had wrought. Race was the element
that would preserve history’s achievement. The original distinction be-
tween statuses, which was by and large accidental, became a necessity
when perpetuated through the blood. Thus, far from being archaic, the
concept of “‘race,”’ as Louis Dumont has suggested, seems to have been
linked to the birth of egalitarian ideology. Indeed, this concept made it
possible to replace the old organicist justification of inequality with a
historico-biological theory that was not only compatible with “natural”
equality but allowed the notion of equality to be integrated into an
inegalitarian construct. Nobles were different from (that is, superior to)
commoners, but all nobles were equal among themselves. Equality was a
basic element in Boulainvilliers’s vision of the nobility, and it was what
made him so different from Saint-Simon, obsessed with the preeminence
of dukes and peers.
For Boulainvilliers, the military caste created in the wake of the
conquest was a society of equals. He never failed to stress that among the
free conquerors who had come from Germany, ‘‘the now-prevalent dis-
tinctions based on titles were totally unknown.” But this egalitarian
society was also a closed society. While conquest conferred a rank then
perpetuated through the blood, nothing else could confer it in its place—
not even, and least of all, royal favor. Boulainvilliers was therefore intent
on emphasizing the closed character of the nobility (the idea of estab-
lishing once and for all a general inventory of noble families of the realm
was another aspect of that intention)" and the strict equality prevailing
within that exclusive group.
Mably and Boulainvilliers 133
was used during the Enlightenment and the Revolution. He criticized the
church and scholasticism, as well as the crass manners and the ignorance
of his time. He hailed the sixteenth-century Renaissance of arts and
letters’—an uncommon periodization in histories of France of this epoch
and in eighteenth-century culture in general.
In truth, what Boulainvilliers sought to give back to a nobility that had
so completely forgotten its origins as to be unable to define itself was the
awareness of its own existence. The fact was that the nobility would
nearly have lost that awareness were it not for the greed of commoners.
The “inordinate passion” of the latter for ‘“‘entering the nobility by royal
patent” still kept alive within the nobility the feeling of corporate iden-
tity, with its dual aspect of exclusion and equality. Boulainvilliers
dreamed of a less external basis. But the feudal regime that provided him
with the model was simply an ideal type of the relationship between civil
society and the king of France. This ideal type presented two features: a
society founded on inequality of status and on equality within each status;
the independence of nobles from the king, conceived as primus inter
pares.
Mably’s problem was quite different. Like Boulainvilliers, he postu-
lated a primitive state of equality, rooted in “a nature that had no
enclosed fields.” But he was not out to legitimize at any price a metaphys-
ically unacceptable social hierarchy, for he regarded it, in any case, as
having no genuine historical foundation. On the contrary, Mably de-
veloped a radical critique of heredity. He was challenging the concept not
as applied to kings alone, but as applied to all of mankind. As long as
vassals were granted personal distinctions, all was well in Mably’s history:
nobility was not transmitted through the blood, the children of the
nobility remained in the common class of citizens, and there was a single
order with two classes. History went wrong when these two classes (which
were constantly disintegrating and being rebuilt according to individual
talent and virtue) were turned into fixed orders. Mably’s villain was not
Philip the Fair, but Clothar II, who, by establishing hereditary benefices,
introduced a privileged order into the nation.
This order at once became the mortal enemy of equality—if only by
the fascination it exerted on the third estate, which it prevented from
having a sense of its own corporate identity (one can observe here the
complete reversal of Boulainvilliers’s thesis). Mably dated its birth to a
still remote period. But his basic aim was nevertheless to demonstrate
that the nobility had not always existed, thereby depriving the privileged
order of the prestige of an original state. This point was so crucial for
Mably that, in order to prove it, he did not hesitate to challenge the
authority of Montesquieu and to call to the rescue—only once, it is
true—the arguments of the opposite camp, that of Abbé Dubos: “I do
not imagine that Monsieur le Président de Montesquieu believes that
nations had noblemen from the start.” Thus, Mably found no trace of
Mably and Boulainvilliers 135
political feudalism in the origins of the nation. In his borrowings from the
germanistes, what counted for Mably was the structure of the ‘‘old gov-
ernment.’’ A king who was more of a captain than a monarch and who
commanded soldiers far more than he ruled subjects; a collegial executive
power exercised by the king and the notables in council; a legislative
power in the hands of a general assembly, the Champ de Mars—these
were the basic features of Mably’s system.
One must add to it a vision of the conquest borrowed from Montes-
quieu, halfway between the absurd idyll of the relations between Gauls
and Franks imagined by Dubos and the watertight separation imposed by
Boulainvilliers. For Mably, as for Montesquieu, the vanquished, having
been freed from the Roman imperium, rallied to their conqueror. Mably
saw this rallying less as an effect of habit than as the result of a voluntary,
conscious, and public choice—a solemn declaration, an oath. Official
renunciation of Roman law was the price that the Gauls had to pay in
order to “‘begin to enjoy the same prerogatives,” to obtain the same legal
settlements as the victorious Franks, and finally—the obvious triumph of
assimilation!—to be admitted to the Champs de Mars.
Thus, Mably rejected inequality on two counts: it was neither the
product of race (since, unlike Montesquieu, he did not believe in the
existence of an original Frankish nobility) nor the fruit of conquest (since,
unlike Boulainvilliers, Mably postulated the intermingling of the victors
and the vanquished). Inequality was a perversion, the first link in a long
chain of vices. It stimulated the growth of private wealth, the loss of
attachment to freedom, and—worst of all!—irregular attendance at the
Champs de Mars. In Mably’s view, therefore, the only possible founda-
tion for society was equality.
But one must be clear about the exact nature of equality as Mably saw
it. Mably did not believe, any more than Boulainvilliers did, in an
undiscriminating form of equality, whose model was once again provided
by despotism: “The closer one gets to despotism, the more social ranks
become indistinguishable.”’'* Mably—who also invoked the authority of
Montesquieu—inherited from Boulainvilliers the notion of a farsighted
despotism that saw things from too far and too high to perceive any
differences. But Mably did not advocate the type of equality that would
be fatal to dependency, for “‘only in Turkey or some other despotic state
can one believe that the subordination necessary in society is incompati-
ble with equality.”
This time the aim was therefore to reestablish inequality within an
egalitarian system, and Mably did his best to devise such a scheme.
Actually, a few adjustments were enough to make inequality tolerable.
Could one preserve inequality of wealth? The Swiss example showed that
wise sumptuary laws succeeded in preventing the anarchic proliferation
of wealth. Could one admit the inequality of power? Yes, if it were based
on competence, that is, if one claimed power less as a sovereign than as a
136 Seventeenth- and Eighteenth-century Culture
Thus, Mably’s great innovation was not the reversal of the concept of
nobiliary liberalism—what one might call his democratic version of Ger-
manism—but its extension to include the third estate alongside the clergy
and the nobles in the nation’s assemblies. Mably also linked the ideal of
equality to the preservation of ‘“ranks.” This linkage—which, inciden-
tally, shows how risky it would be to oppose the liberal current and the
democratic current in the eighteenth century—could be achieved,
according to Mably, thanks to a legislation devised as a harmonious
system.
Indeed, the idea that is new in Mably, and that one would look for in
vain in Boulainvilliers, is that of harmony. The organicist metaphor is
obviously useless in describing a society split between victors all enjoying
equality through privilege and vanquished all equal in servitude. How-
ever, the metaphor is indispensable to a pluralist notion of the body
social. It guarantees the dignity of each section of society (‘‘each class of
citizens understands that it can be happy without oppressing the others’’)
and insures that they will take part in the effort to reach a common
goal—the “public good’—which can be attained providing there is a
general acceptance of a hierarchy of social functions. That is why, for
Mably, the most admirable sovereign in the history of France was Charle-
magne, the orchestrator of harmony, the mediator who brought social
orders closer together and made them forget their old quarrels. The work
of the ideal legislator is to hold the balance between the various orders—a
balance that “‘is today the only imaginable equality among men.” Conse-
quently, the legislator’s task is easier when there are more orders: they
balance each other out and, in addition, it is a finer achievement to make
them all contribute to common happiness. Four orders are better than
three, and five better than four. Such multiplicity would therefore,
according to Mably’s wish, mean the triumph of harmonious plurality,
which he regarded as the ultimate constituent factor of the nation.
Thus, the discussion on the history of France was one of the liveliest
features of eighteenth-century French culture, because it was rooted in
civil society’s drive toward power and in the search for a legitimacy
intended not as a substitution—since absolutism was a usurpation—but
as a restoration. Boulainvilliers and Mably represent two decisive mo-
ments in the debate, for they were writing respectively the nobiliary
version and the roturier version of the same history, that of the nation.
What separates them is important as far as their opinions are concerned:
Boulainvilliers was an exclusionist aristocrat, while Mably brought the
third estate back into the national fold. But in other respects their
differences were virtually negligible. Both authors joined in the social
demand for a liberalization of the regime—a demand for which the
nobility, at the end of Louis XIV’s reign, acted as a natural spokesman.
Above all, both authors were writing what was intellectually the same
138 Seventeenth- and Eighteenth-century Culture
history, built on the same institutions, and enacted by the same cast.
Their concept of “nation” enabled them to deal simultaneously with the
social and the national dimensions, unlike their nineteenth-century suc-
cessors, who restricted their vision to the national dimension alone. By
combining the social sphere and the national sphere, Boulainvilliers and
Mably wedded society to its own myth.
In the years immediately preceding the French Revolution, the histor-
ical theme of nationhood acquired a particularly momentous political
significance. It occurs very often in the prerevolutionary pamphlets pub-
lished between the Assembly of Notables and the opening of the Estates
General (late 1787—April 1789). These pamphlets, most of which were
anonymous, testify to the spread of the Boulainvilliers-Mably version of
French history among the educated classes of the eighteenth century.
They contain many references to the origins and history of the nation.
In these improvised writings, so closely connected to contemporary
events, such references present the advantage of making the political
demands quite explicit; they also show the extent of the triumph of
Mably’s ‘‘democratic”” thesis over-Boulainvilliers’s aristocratic thesis in
public opinion. When one of these pamphlets defends the orders of
society as one of the building blocks of the monarchy, it is in the name of
tradition or of the Constitution, never in the name of race. Far from being
a possible foundation for a new legitimacy that would have benefited the
nobility, the notion of race was used as an argument against the nobles in
Sieyés’s Qu'est-ce que le Tiers Etat? ,in which he advocated sending back
“into the forests of Franconia all the families that cling to the absurd
pretention of being issued from the race of conquerors and of having
inherited their rights.”
In actual fact, “Germanic liberties” had become the mythical heritage
of the entire nation, now waging the decisive battle for the restoration of
those liberties. The centerpiece of this construct was the king-and-nation
dyad—two powers that were not defined by a conflict but were the two
indispensable elements of legitimate public authority. Their theoretical
definition was not contradictory but complementary. The king, enjoying
a historical right attested by filiation, embodied the state. The nation was
both a historical and a mythical human community—a depository of the
social contract, a general will whose origins were shrouded in the mists of
time, a promise of fidelity to those origins. Between king and nation there
existed an apparent relationship of subordination, which was actually a
binding obligation to cooperate. The king was the head of the nation, but
his rule was legitimate only if he respected the rights and laws of the
nation.
When he did not respect them, it was because nefarious elements
thwarted that cooperation. The culprits were either ministerial despo-
tism, as had been the case since Richelieu, or usurpation by the nobility,
as during the feudal period. Thus, the battle waged during the years from
Mably and Boulainvilliers 139
140
Gibbon’s History 141
The ideas of the moderns were given their definitive form for the
eighteenth century in d’Alembert’s Discours préliminaire and Condor-
cet’s Esquisse d'un tableau historique des progrès de l’esprit humain. In
them we find that ‘‘civilization” was a process before it was a state; its
purpose was to make “civil,” to “‘police” the uncivilized. The word
civilization itself, which dates from this period in both French and En-
glish, was invented to express this drive of enlightened society toward
what ought to be, the conviction of being on the right road, the certitude
that the future was in fact infinite and that history had a purpose.
But, in many respects, Gibbon wrote a history very different from
others of his century; his history was at once more “‘ancient”’ and more
“modern”: more ancient because Gibbon was a professional antiquarian
and familiar with the learned and the scholarly societies of Europe in the
seventeenth century, into whose proceedings his mastery of French per-
mitted him easy access; more modern because he integrated this erudi-
tion with the art of retelling the past and, in so doing, invented the
historical panorama that was to become so important in the romantic era.
Gibbon was somewhere between Tillemont and Renan, but this ‘“‘some-
where” constituted more than just the philosophical consensus of the
Enlightenment; it was also an original vision of the past and present in
Europe.
His own biography already reveals some of this vision in the studious,
retiring years in Lausanne undertaken by an English gentleman who had
tasted the charms of the salons of Paris and London. For, on the banks of
Lake Geneva, in those Franco-German confines that were so crucial for
the transformations of European culture, Gibbon saw only a retreat
where he could continue his work. A place of exile in his youth, Switzer-
land became a shelter in his maturity. By choosing Switzerland, he
avoided belonging to any of the nations of Europe and thus signified that
his only loyalties lay with his two universal homelands: historical erudi-
tion—that most international of cultures—and Rome, the mother of
Europe. The revelation of 15 October 1764 had given a meaning to his life
amounting almost to a religious conversion. Freud entered Rome only
after he had already become Freud and was ready to confront the classical
studies of his youth, which constituted at the same time the world of the
gentile. But Gibbon did not become Gibbon until that day in October
when he trod “with a proud foot upon the ruins of the Forum.” He
received from Rome more than his idea of civilization; he received from it
his cultural identity.
Between Rome and Gibbon lay the same link that connected the
European intellectuals of the Renaissance to antiquity. It was a romance,
complete with the same delight in discovery and the same freshness and
joy in the recapture of lost secrets. Yet, since the Renaissance, education
had put Rome into everyone’s store of knowledge: the Latin and history
that one learned from Cicero and Tacitus continued to be the basis of the
142 Seventeenth- and Eighteenth-century Culture
period in the history of the world, during which the condition of the
human race was most happy and prosperous.’” It was a unique moment,
which did not fit into any general concept of historical change.
This view of second-century Rome as representing a privileged mo-
ment in human history was impossible to integrate into a linear view of
humanity’s progress, such as the one Condorcet wrote later on (1793).
But such a conception was typical of cyclical histories, according to which
civilization had no purpose toward which the cumulative progress of
mankind was heading but rather consisted of a series of intermittent
“happy and prosperous” periods. In this conception, second-century
Rome represented the crowning of history’s most splendid cycle—and to
such a degree that the hope Gibbon assigned to eighteenth-century
Europe was not to surpass this model and the values it bore but to
constitute a less fragile vessel for them.
It is difficult to determine very precisely or securely the reasons behind
Gibbon’s worshipful admiration for the Empire. Nowhere does he pre-
sent a systematic description of Roman civilization. He is so permeated
with the idea of its superiority that he feels no need to discuss the reasons
for it nor to take stock of its elements. The famous judgment from
chapter 3 of the Decline and Fall quoted above, regarding the excep-
tionally happy state of humanity during the Antonine period, is sup-
ported only by some rather brief justifications relating to the virtue and
wisdom of the emperors who came after the civil unrest in the first
century. The loss of freedoms—those famous Roman freedoms that
nourished so many of the century’s books—was more than compensated
by the exercise of an equally enlightened despotism.
Gibbon was, in fact, indifferent to the political philosophy that so
excited many of his contemporaries. He wrote, as did his masters in
antiquity—Thucydides, Cicero, and Tacitus—moral history. For a period
to be great, it was necessary, but also sufficient, for it to have produced a
certain kind of man. The emperors of the second century were his
exempla; they were at once a culture and a moral.
Nevertheless—and not surprisingly—Gibbon’s history of Rome is also
a history of Gibbon. The cult of the Antonines reflected the views the
historian held toward his own present. In this respect, Gibbon was an
entirely original writer. He did not, as did the men of the Renaissance,
have to rediscover Rome beneath the medieval sediment, for that work
had been done for him. But neither did he believe, as did the artists and
men of letters of the seventeenth century, that Rome could truly be
imitated. He was already too much of a historian, in the nineteenth-
century sense of the word, not to conceive of history as flux, never
representing the same situations—or the same successes—twice. The
cycles of civilization that history presented were not comparable, and
they were transient. The Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire is
dominated throughout by the romantic notion of the uniqueness and
144 Seventeenth- and Eighteenth-century Culture
the extended Roman frontiers (though a few pages later he points out
that northern Europe, once a stronghold of barbarians, had little by little
been civilized).
The comparison, in fact, comes out in favor of eighteenth-century
Europe. Gibbon lists the elements militating in favor of a relative stability
for the civilization it has attained—its geographic extent, its national
diversity, its mastery of the art of war, the undeniable distinction of its
inventions and basic technology—and in the end he even advances the
idea of a continuous progress of humanity “‘since the first discovery of the
arts.” But it was still the case that Europe’s civilization, even if it was
probably indestructible, remained subject to the challenge of the “‘savage
nations of the globe.” It could be seriously threatened, forced to retreat,
to become expatriated ‘“‘in the American world.” In a century that had
witnessed a rapid acceleration in the Europeanization of the globe, a
phenomenon that had characterized history everywhere since the Ren-
aissance, Gibbon discussed the reverse hypothesis drawn from the Ro-
man example. It was not that he thought it likely, but that his concept of
civilization already included a threatening reversal, a permanent exterior
menace—the savage world.
Savage or barbarian? Generally speaking, the Enlightenment distin-
guished between these two terms by defining them as two different steps
in the evolution toward civilization. The Encyclopédie (1751) still con-
fused them, however, for in it ‘“‘savages” were described as ‘“‘barbaric
people who live without laws, without government, without religion, and
who have no fixed habitation.”’ But it then adds, ‘There is this difference
between savages and barbarians, namely, that the first form scattered
little nations that have no desire to unite, whereas the barbarians often
unite, and this happens when a chief submits to one of the others. Natural
liberty is the sole concern of government among savages; along with this
liberty, nature and climate are almost the sole forces that prevail among
them. Occupied by hunting or pastoral life, they do not burden them-
selves with religious observances and do not make their religion a basis
for organizing their lives.”
Some time later, the Dictionnaire of Trévoux (1771), although it
followed the Encyclopédie very closely, took pains not to use the term
barbarian as a synonym for savage. The latter term “‘is also used for those
people who wander in the forests, without fixed habitation, without laws,
without government, and almost without religion.” Thus, the two dic-
tionaries agree with Montesquieu in distinguishing between savages and
barbarians by stating that the first “live scattered about, retreating into
the forests and the mountains, without uniting, while the second often
unite and sometimes live under a chief to whom they have submitted.”
Ferguson (1767) writes that the savage, in America, has neither property
nor government nor judges, while the barbarian, in Europe, had property
and obeyed a chief.’ De Pauw (1768) clearly distinguished different stages
146 Seventeenth- and Eighteenth-century Culture
Decline and Fall. The first revolved around the external confrontation
between Rome and the barbarians, the second around the internal disin-
tegration of the Empire at the hands of the Christians. It is a Rome
weakened by “the spirit of Christianity,” we might say, borrowing from
Montesquieu, that is finally conquered by the barbarian invasions. And
the real victor, as the history of both the Eastern and Western Middle
Ages shows, was Christianity.
This is perhaps the reason—or the existential impulse—that led Gib-
bon to write, not a panorama of Roman civilization, but an account only
of its fall. Of course, like his contemporaries, Gibbon was sensitive to the
transience of history’s great successes, but this feeling hardly justified his
having extended his account as far as the fifteenth century! If he wished to
encompass the entire Middle Ages into the fall of Rome and under what
was, in that context, a very strange title, it was because Christianity’s
history fascinated him as much as, perhaps even more than, that of
Rome. He invested his account with his hatred, not of the Christian faith,
but of the church, the priests, and monks; he committed to it his struggle
against intolerance and fanaticism; he deployed for the purpose the
whole anticlerical tradition of the French Enlightenment.
He was too good a historian, however, to say—and he never did
say—that the Christianity of the established churches for which he pro-
fessed no love was a form of ‘“‘barbarism.”’ On the contrary, he seized
every opportunity to show how Christianity was in fact the important
reconstructive principle of his historical world—the Europe built upon
the debris of the Roman Empire. On the one hand, he wanted to express,
through the three-dimensional historical space in which civilization, bar-
barism, and Christianity evolved, his preference for a pre-Christian civi-
lization rather than a Christianized barbarism. But, on the other hand, he
constantly—and more radically—showed that what motivated his
worship of Rome, its values, its “‘spirit,’’ and its moral figures was the
existence of a civilization in its chemically pure state—and that meant
without the Church.
ALU OR
ae we 4.6 ee
oR a
=
SAUTER
Le
ars
ios tr fee La
*
D in : cues
the 2 TES a
|4
DEMOCRACY
| |
F4
Fe
From Savage Man to Historical Man:
The American Experience in
Eighteenth-Century French Culture
The misfortune of the savage was sometimes equated simply with his
backwardness. Such was the view expressed by travelers who, in provid-
ing the reader with accounts of the mores of distant peoples, were seeking
Originally delivered as a lecture in October 1976 at the William L. Clements Library, Ann
Arbor, Michigan. First published in French in La Révolution américaine et l'Europe,
proceedings of the Colloques Internationaux du Centre National de la Recherche Scienti-
fique, no. 577, Paris-Toulouse, 21-25 February 1978 (Paris: Editions du CNRS, 1979),
93-105; reprinted in Annales: économies, sociétés, civilisations, July-August 1978, 729-39.
This study, as will be seen, is greatly indebted to two classic works: Bernard Fay, L'Esprit
révolutionnaire en France et aux Etats-Unis (Paris, 1924); and D. Echeverria, Mirage in the
West: A History of the French Image of American Society to 1815 (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1957). My analysis is an attempt to modify the conclusions reached by
these two authors, but it is based very largely on the material they have provided.
153
154 America and the Idea of Democracy
Is it not surprising that the only men found on one half of the
globe should be beardless, devoid of intelligence, contami-
nated by venereal disease (for syphilis, which Europe calls the
French disease, has become the American disease), and so
fallen from the human state as to be incapable of being disci-
plined—which is the complement of stupidity? The fondness
that Americans have always displayed, and still display, for
savage life proves that they hate the laws of society and the
constraints of education, which, by taming the most intemper-
ate passions, are alone capable of raising man above the
animals. . . .”
epic. But the agrarian idyll of the American smallholder was considerably
more than an additional variant of the old theme of natural happiness.
Far from being a sort of exotic reference lost in space—that is, harking
back to a very ancient past—it inaugurated a new historical epoch and
constituted a promise. The union of the thirteen colonies represented “‘an
unforgettable moment in the annals of the universe. This moment can be
regarded as a rebirth of nature, as a new gift it has bestowed on the Old
World, as a second creation; for everything we see today bears the stamp
of youth and is only just unfolding.’”’
Thus, America was a new origin of humanity, but a thoroughly histor-
ical origin, since it was contemporary. This logical paradox was possible
because the American homo novus brought about a radical change in
European man—a rebirth at once geographical and cultural. It was
geographical because it was initially a consequence of the availability of
space, in contrast to the ‘‘overcrowding” of European societies, but it was
especially a consequence of man’s return to the earth, the mother of
moral and civic virtues. Crévecceur’s American foreshadows Robespierre
and Saint-Just’s “patriot,” who also owned a parcel of his homeland’s
soil. Landownership and agriculture enabled man to be at one with
nature and with history. Indeed, the man of the “frontier,” living on the
outer limit of cultivated land, was for Crévecceur a sort of transitional,
ambiguous figure, caught between the virtues of new man and the two
sources of corruption threatening those virtues: the European heritage of
violence, conveyed by every newcomer, and contamination by the savage
state, which wrested the settler from agriculture and drew him toward
hunting.
For only educated and enlightened men could fully enjoy the blessings
of space and land. The United States was doubly fortunate in having been
peopled by European dissenters, fleeing from intolerance, prejudice, and
persecution, and in having been born precisely in a later age, enlightened
by science and philosophy. Far from being, like the Europeans, burdened
with and corrupted by the weight of the past, Americans were predis-
posed by that very past to rid themselves of its inertia, since they were the
first to have fought and escaped its violence. Their relationship to history
was in the nature of a rebirth, in which their late appearance on the
American scene made them benefit fully from the progress of knowledge
and reason. It is this shortcut that brought them back to the state of
nature, which, instead of acting as an abstract reference, thus became a
historical period, the rebirth of society on a rational basis. Provided it
remained faithful to this exceptional origin, America was destined to be
the central laboratory for human history. It was thus to America, and not
to Greece and Rome, that the “‘learned men” of Europe were invited to
turn in order to acquire new knowledge—that is, to the “primeval germ
... of an enlightened and new people,” since it is “more enjoyable to find
160 America and the Idea of Democracy
oneself at the origin of things than at a sad review of the fragments of the
past.”
In this happy history, what was the role of the two figures excluded
from the new society, the Negro and the Indian? The Negro was either
happy under the patriarchal authority of a good master or on his way to
emancipation. He had no real existence in a world built on equality;
indeed, there was almost no conceptual room for him. The Indian played
an ambiguous but crucial role. On the one hand, as a primitive, he
bestowed nature’s blessing on the settlers. While de Pauw had regarded
the settler as being trapped in the brutish state of savages, for Crèvecœur,
on the contrary, the settler imitated their simple and natural virtues. On
the other hand, although the Indian was untainted by European corrup-
tion, he embodied a society inferior to that of the settlers: Indian society
was fragile and unenlightened; it was based on hunting and had no
agriculture, arts, or sciences. Europe represented history without nature.
The Indian embodied nature without history. Only the American recon-
ciled the two principles.
Therein lies the secret, in my view, of the assimilation of the ‘ Amer-
ican dream” into French culture. Before the outbreak of the French
Revolution, which acted as the focal point for the belief in a new begin-
ning—a regeneration, as the French were to put it—of mankind, it was
American independence that crystallized the idea of a history-as-origin,
by means of which society would once again conform to nature and
reason. That is the deep connection between the two revolutions. The
idea of revolution in its 1789 sense originated for the French in the birth of
the United States.
But this link also explains precisely why the French Revolution put an
end to the “American dream” in French opinion. Not that America
ceased to exist as a political and philosophical point of reference. The
American example was still cited in revolutionary speeches and newspa-
pers, particularly in connection with constitutional problems. A system-
atic study’ would probably show that references to America were specifi-
cally made by the girondins, and in particular by Brissot and Condorcet,
who remainded faithful to their youthful passion. But that the ‘ American
discourse” should have been a feature of the most cosmopolitan intellec-
tual and political family of the Revolution—the only family, in fact, with
any “international” character at all—already indicates that this discourse
had become quite alien, if not suspect, to a great many actors in the
French drama, from the members of the Constituent Assembly to the
montagnards. |
The reason is that from 1789 on, the French had their own dream,
From Savage Man to Historical Man 161
which made a substitute unnecessary. From the very onset of the Revolu-
tion, they were obsessed with their own example, narcissistically fasci-
nated by their own history. If one reads the countless pamphlets that
flooded the old kingdom between 1787 and 1789 or if one examines the
interminable and monotonous evidence of the cahiers de doléances, one
will find few references indeed to foreign examples. Tocqueville, who was
well versed in this literature, had understood the phenomenon:
We shall never relinquish our rights, but we shall not use them
to excess. We shall not forget that the French are not a new
people just emerged from the depth of the forest to form an
association, but a great society of twenty-five million men—a
society intent on strengthening the ties that exist between all
its parts, and on regenerating the kingdom, a kingdom for
which the principles of genuine monarchy will always be
sacred."
But as the Revolution unfolded, entering into conflict with the Catho-
lic church, waging war on the kings of Europe, and sending Louis XVI to
his death, it became an expression of the French people’s rejection of
their own history. There are two reasons why the Jacobin break with—or
eradication of—the nation’s past was incompatible with an admiration of
the American example. First, Jacobinism was predicated on a total
psychological and ideological commitment to the French Revolution,
now the sole embodiment of liberty and equality, of the great beginning
of human emancipation. There was no room in Jacobin thinking for two
pilot nations. Second, the secret of social happiness rediscovered by
France was no longer thought of as a gift of nature but as the stake in a
domestic and international conflict. In America, equality and indepen-
dence resulted from consensus. In revolutionary France, they were seen
as the outcome of a long and bloody conflict. This, it seems to me, is
where the two myths of origins parted ways and made the political and
cultural life of the two nations so alien to each other after several years of
considerably fraternal relations. Furthermore, from 1793 on, it is what I
would call the “conflictual messianism”’ of French Jacobinism that, in its
turn, had an impact on American politics via the Republicans. However,
Jacobinism failed to constitute an effective ideological model for Amer-
ica, for the two experiences had become as remote from each other as the
physical distance that lay between them.
combination of these habits with the ideas and prejudices dating from the
earliest origins.’ There follows this crucial passage:
Thus, the United States came once again under the common-law
jurisdiction of history. The American Revolution was subject to the same
erosion of principle by passion as the French Revolution had been, and it
became the object of the same disenchantment. Whatever advantage still
accrued to America was due solely to geography and chance.
In order to complete his demonstration, Volney also had to demolish
the last American myth: that of a harmonious and happy savage state,
enshrined in the natural order before the institution of property. In short,
Volney had to exorcise Rousseau. He did so in one of the very few
fragments of this part of his book that he actually wrote. These fragments
were published as appendixes to the Tableau under the title Observations
générales sur les Indiens ou Sauvages de l’Amérique du Nord. Volney’s
savage no longer played the leading role on the philosophical stage where
the natural order and civilization confronted each other. Although, as in
Rousseau, the savage predated the creation of property, he ceased to be
an abstract entity a la Rousseau and became the object of empirical
observation. Volney’s savage embodied not a principle but a historical
society, whose weakness lay precisely in its having predated property and
agriculture; consequently, it was vulnerable to the slightest contact with
“civilization.”’ The savage was neither a utopian creature, as in Rous-
seau, nor a foil, as in de Pauw. Savagery was a primitive society, a
still-rudimentary history, destined—condemned, even—to become civi-
lized through the introduction of property. Thus, it was one of the several
elements in American history, but a secondary element, set for assimila-
tion or destruction, and subject to the merciless law of development.
Savagery had been removed from the poetic world of origins and re-
turned to the prosaic world of social life. By losing its ‘savages,’ America
was all the more thoroughly reabsorbed into the ordinary flow of history.
By achronological coincidence, at almost the same time, or just a short
while earlier, the greatest of all French writers went—or pretended to
have gone—on the same journey as Volney. Actually, it is of little
importance that the itinerary was for the most part invented, for
Chateaubriand introduced America, not into French philosophy or poli-
166 America and the Idea of Democracy
tics, but into French literature—and with what a stir! Atala and René—
together with Les Natchez, published later but cast in the same mold—
revolutionized the novel and aesthetic sensibility. Admittedly,
Chateaubriand incorporated traditional descriptive elements such as the
good savage, the antithesis between savagery and civilization, and the
luxuriance of nature; but he added the feeling that Europe would never
again move out of its confines, that it was a prisoner of its past, and that
the American dream of happiness lay beyond its grasp. Of all the imagi-
nary travelers in search of the new man, René was the first to experience
the burden of time and the impossibility of casting off the old man. France
under the Consulate shared in this feeling. All it discovered in the
American forest was the “‘genius of Christianity’ —its own past.
Thus, between 1780 and 1800—twenty years during which French
history moved at such a rapid pace—the American dream shifted from
revolutionary messianism to social science and met its death in literature.
The myth of a reborn humanity at last faithful to its origins—a myth so
enduring in American culture—did not survive in France after the Jaco-
bin experience. The French replaced it by the myth of an egalitarian
nation, composed of both peasants and soldiers, a nation engaged in an
endless battle to deliver mankind from an invincible past. I do not feel
that, since this period, the two nations have ever again experienced the
ephemeral sense of cultural community that had brought them so close
together for ten or fifteen years. That is perhaps why these ten or fifteen
years are being celebrated with such loquaciousness and such solemnity.
Deep ties are generally silent.
The Conceptual System of
“Democracy in America”
167
168 America and the Idea of Democracy
before his departure.’ Moreover, this letter mentions only the incidental
reasons connected with the 1830 revolution—an event that placed the two
applicants for the mission, as scions of legitimist families, in a “difficult
position.” Besides, even if one were to accept this type of “diplomatic”
explanation, why America? Many other countries could satisfy the
curiosity of two friends and provide a legitimate excuse for their absence.
At the time, the young American republic represented the ideal for an
intellectual orientation quite alien to the tradition in which the two young
aristocrats had been brought up: the orientation of the liberal opposition
under the Restoration—liberals of every hue, freemasons, and republi-
cans, all assembled in a pro-American camp under the symbolic aegis of
La Fayette.’ But it is true that Beaumont was distantly related to La
Fayette and that in family circles the young Alexis had met former
“Americans” such as Chateaubriand, Hyde de Neuville—the agent of
princes during the Revolution, former ambassador to Washington, and
close friend of the comte Hervé—and Monseigneur de Cheverus,
archbishop of Bordeaux and former bishop of Boston.
If Tocqueville and Beaumont were searching for the secret of free
institutions, they could have gone to study them in countries less radically
alien to their tradition and more spontaneously dear to their hearts—
Switzerland and England in particular. But Switzerland, according to
classic political theory, was considered a republic only in consequence of
its smallness; England, then regarded as being on the verge of collapse,
was not, in any case, a democracy. However, Tocqueville did visit En-
gland in later years, and his correspondence from the pre-1830 period,
even as he was attending with passionate interest Guizot’s course at the
Sorbonne, shows his concern with the comparative history of France and
England.® Why, then, America?
To this question, at least, there is an answer provided by Tocqueville
himself, well after his return, in a letter of January 1835 to his friend
Kergorlay, written just after the publication of the first volume of Democ-
racy in America.’ Tocqueville begins by stating that, since the march
toward equality is inevitable, the central problem of the age is to deter-
mine whether equality is compatible with freedom; he adds:
nections between the principle that governed societies and the type of
political system that could issue from it, but he never regarded those
connections as inevitable.
Thus, Tocqueville constantly combined two types of analysis and two
types of beliefs. In his reasoning, he juxtaposed a logic of typology—
based on the opposition between aristocracy and democracy—and a logic
of evolution, based on the inevitable triumph of democracy. As for his
general world view, he compensated for his rational acceptance of
democracy by fighting for the values that were inseparable from the
aristocratic world, freedom foremost. His entire life, from an early age,
revolved around this problem—a blend of theory and experience—or
around this theory of family experience, which constantly combined facts
with values, conceptual richness and exhaustive documentation with
political convictions.
If the visit to America was already implicit in this exploration, it was
because America provided the young, systematically minded aristocrat
with an existential and conceptual laboratory. A homeland founded on
the negation of the nobility (a country, therefore, where Tocqueville
himself could not have existed), America offered the example of a
chemically pure experiment in democracy. Tocqueville used this discov-
ery—truly a brilliant one in its simplicity and boldness—to verify and
elaborate on an idea. He must have had a premonition, when he set sail,
of the great secret that he later shared with Comte Molé on his return
from his second visit to England in 1835, in a letter that belatedly answers
the question of 1831, Why America?
Thus, America was the ideal site for analyzing in vivo the democratic
principle at work, that is, the risks it involved and the advantages it
offered to freedom. As for the European nations, they stood midway
between aristocracy and democracy; they were torn by the conflict be-
tween two principles and two worlds and often prey to the extreme form
of democracy represented by revolution. The American example did not
constitute Europe’s future—which was necessarily different—but it gave
Democracy in America 173
Europe some basis for conceiving its future so as to ensure the most
favorable conditions and the least number of obstacles to freedom.
Tocqueville was prepared to resign himself to the end of the nobility,
provided the aristocratic legacy of freedom were capable of surviving the
democratic age.
Actually, in order to understand the close connection that exists
between Tocqueville’s visit to America and his analysis of France, one
can also look directly at Democracy in America, which is entirely aimed at
a comparison between America and Europe. The most explicit text on
this point is the end of chapter 9 of part 2 of volume 1. Tocqueville begins
by examining the importance of laws and mores in preserving American
democracy, as opposed to what he calls the ‘material causes,” that is, the
specific features of the New World and the advantages it offers to man in
his relation to geographical space. Tocqueville is confronted with a classic
problem—perhaps the central problem—of social sciences: how to iso-
late the role and influence of a variable or of a limited set of variables on a
complex process. That he was well aware of the difficulty is proved by his
attempt to find a point of comparison in a country situated outside the
American continent, and therefore deprived of the geographical advan-
tages inseparable from America, yet possessing comparable laws and
mores. However, he cannot find any such country. He draws the conclu-
sion that, in the absence of objects of comparison, “we . . . can only
hazard opinions.’’”
This is a typical passage in that it illustrates Tocqueville’s fundamental
mode of reasoning and demonstration: the comparative method. Having
found one or more ideas as explanatory hypotheses for a phenomenon he
was attempting to elucidate, Tocqueville tested them on various
‘“grounds.” When he could not’find relevant grounds for the problem at
hand, he ‘“‘hazarded opinions’’—that is, to his mind, indemonstrable and,
at best, plausible propositions. And America represents one of the poles
of the intellectual two-way journey that forms the fabric of his entire
book.
But, as always in the human sciences, there were no terms capable of
being compared rigorously. Not only was Europe deprived of the
“physical advantages” enjoyed by the Anglo-Americans but its historical
traits made it radically different from the New World. Tocqueville cites
Europe’s large population, its big cities, its armies, and its ‘““complicated
politics.” These legacies would be enough to prevent a transfer of the
laws of American democracy to Europe, since these laws would clash
with other mores, other ideas, and other religious beliefs. For Tocque-
ville, who never clearly distinguished between facts and values, the
United States did not constitute for Europe either a conceptually compa-
rable experience or a model to be followed. For “‘one can imagine a
democratic nation organized in a different way from the American
people.”
174 America and the Idea of Democracy
But these institutions, these traditions, and even religion itself had
disappeared or were withering away, to be replaced by a society in which
classes were less and less differentiated, individuals increasingly alike and
isolated from one another, and public opinion ever more malleable and
indistinct.
the political meaning of the term democracy, and vice versa, according to
which one of these two conceptual levels he is exploring.
Socially and culturally, American provides him with an example of
pure democracy and of a government derived from this pure democracy.
In both respects, America is an anti-Europe, with no aristocratic inheri-
tance, no legacy of absolutism, and no revolutionary passions. Instead, it
has a tradition of local community freedom. Because of all these features,
mutatis mutandis, America is a crucial topic for Europeans to reflect
upon.
these connections, since he goes from the chapter on the “‘social state” to
the famous and very detailed description of the American political sys-
tem. But the connections can be found in chapter 9 of part 2 of volume 1
and also in Tocqueville’s travel notes, which testify to the fact that the
elements of his explanation were already in place by 1831. For Tocque-
ville, what has preserved American political democracy, after historical
circumstances gave it birth, is not only a fidelity to origins but something
resembling a state of mind, so widespread and so deeply rooted that one
can call it “national mores.” It is this factor that is responsible, day after
day, for maintaining society’s independence and its preeminence over
politics.
First, religion plays an admirable regulatory role in two ways: by what
it prescribes and what it forbids. While Catholicism, according to
Tocqueville, encourages equality and obedience (except when Catholi-
cism is separated from the state, in which case it acquires new characteris-
tics), Protestantism, especially in its sectarian and pluralist form, encour-
ages equality and independence. American religion is made of a set of
republican varieties of Christianity. But religion also sets limits on what
can be known to—and transformed by—man; hence, American boldness
is tempered by a sort of collective moderation. By preventing citizens
from “imagining certain things,” religion acts as an obstacle, in other
words (in words that Tocqueville does not use), to the revolutionary
spirit, which is the negation of democracy in the name of democracy.
Tocqueville wondered about this paradox all his life without ever fully
mastering its breathtaking implications; but, in America, religious con-
sensus had destroyed its attractiveness.
Another key factor in the independence of American society was its
high level of culture. Here Tocqueville parts company with Montesquieu:
the mainspring of republics is not virtue but instruction, by which
Tocqueville means the democratization of knowledge, particularly in
political matters. Speculating on the “thousand reasons that make repub-
lican freedom tolerable in the United States,” he wrote in his travel
notebooks:
There is one major reason that towers over all the others and,
after one has enumerated all of them, carries the day. The
American people taken as a whole are not only the most
enlightened in the world but—and I consider this a far more
important advantage—the people with the most advanced
education in practical politics. It is this truth, in which I
strongly believe, that arouses in me the only hope I have for
the future happiness of Europe.”
Despite their lack of refinement, the vulgarity of their manners, and their
obsession with money, the American people were, for the French aristo-
180 America and the Idea of Democracy
crat, the most civilized on earth. Tocqueville thus measured the worth of
the human investment that America represented—with eighteen centu-
ries of European history behind it. America was a nation of town dwellers
out to conquer nature, bypassing the unending curse of the peasant
condition in Europe. The pioneer was the unlikely breed between the
height of civilization and the height of savagery—the quintessence of
history and the quintessence of nature. Tocqueville’s travel notebooks
contain some unforgettably beautiful passages on this theme,” but he
used only a small portion of them in his book.
It is this high degree of civilization that supplied the Union—setting
aside the South, undermined from within by slavery—with one of the
basic ingredients in democratic mores: uniformity. Tocqueville, in his
notes, admits to being surprised by this feature of American life. Accus-
tomed as he was to observing differences of ‘“‘several centuries” between
the provinces—or parts of provinces—of European nations, he expected
to find an all the greater disparity within the New World as it was still
being colonized and ought to have presented, according to the locality,
‘‘an image of society at every age . .. from the wealthy urban patrician to
the desert savage.’ But Tocqueville observed the opposite. As the
Americans who were settling on the ‘frontier’ came not directly from
Europe but from the oldest settled territories, they had already been
exposed to the spirit of equality and subjected to the uniformization of
tastes and mores. “You will find the same man you left behind in the
streets of New York in the almost inaccessible wilderness: same clothing,
same attitude, same language, same habits, same pleasures.’’* Tocque-
ville did not believe, as Michel Chevalier did,” that the frontier consti-
tuted a third America, after that of Puritan businessmen and that of
slaveholding planters. The Saint-Simonian’s criteria were economic,
while Tocqueville’s were moral and cultural.
Actually, in analyzing the West and the American spirit in general (for
the West merely reveals its quintessence), he borrows—albeit with some
modifications—a concept dating from the previous century: ‘“‘civiliza-
tion.” Like the eighteenth-century philosophers, Tocqueville uses it to
refer to a set of cultural features that make societies both more regulated
and more active; but, unlike Voltaire, he does not regard it as the upper
ridge of a succession of cycles or, like Condorcet, as the terminus of a
linear progress. He wrests the concept from history—an undefinable
vector, another name for Providence—and incorporates it into his own
intellectual system. For Tocqueville, “civilization” is the particular form
of social activity that democracy, in its free state, makes available to all
citizens. By the same token, this definition allows him to relativize the
field of his analysis and to confine the benefits of civilization to the
European stock of mankind. Hence the well-known passage on the
genocide of the Indians, a passage that I cannot resist quoting at length,
not because its tone corresponds to present-day attitudes, but because it
Democracy in America 181
needs, or, after the formation of society, when the individuals that
compose it are sufficiently enlightened and sufficiently independent of
their passions (or law-abiding, which amounts to the same) to do without
government. In a later passage,” he distinguishes two clearly separate
“social states”: “In the first, the people are sufficiently enlightened and
they find themselves in sufficiently favorable circumstances for them to be
able to govern themselves. Here society acts upon itself. In the second, a
power external to society acts upon it, forcing it to march along a given
path.” America, of course, fits the first description—that of a self-
administered society. It offers the example not only of what could be
called ‘‘pure democracy,” but also, up to a point, of ‘pure society,” with
politics excluded.
Naturally, my analysis goes too far, since a great portion of the first
volume of Democracy in America is devoted to a description of the
American political system. But it does serve to emphasize Tocqueville’s
intellectual approval of political democracy, despite what he regards as its
‘‘excesses.”” Political democracy, which provides for the freedom and
responsibility of citizens through administrative decentralization (which
Tocqueville is careful to distinguish, as we know, from governmental
decentralization), basically embodies the advantages of an aristocratic
political system while increasing the number of its beneficiaries. Conse-
quently, the problem, on both the administrative and the governmental
levels, is to compare the advantages and drawbacks of the two systems,
one in the hands of society as a whole, the other controlled by a heredi-
tary elite. This fascinating and justly famous part of the book is of little
import here, in that it is informed throughout, explicitly and implicitly, by
the conceptual opposition described above. What makes these chapters
interesting is the exceptional thoroughness with which Tocqueville ex-
plores this contrast from every angle, using American institutions as the
basic example; but he does not modify the central structure of the
dichotomy.
However, there is one chapter in the first volume of Democracy in
America—the last chapter—in which he is compelled to abandon his
conceptual “‘core.” In the extraordinary chapter 10 of part 2, he specifi-
cally leaves American ‘‘democracy” aside in order to examine the future
of what he calls the “three races” that inhabit the United States, namely,
the Anglo-Americans, the Indians, and the Negroes. Hence, Tocqueville
feels obliged, for once, to discard his analytical system, which has no
relevance to the two marginalized “‘races’—Indians and Negroes—the
two peoples who by definition are not ‘“‘democratic’’; and, as their exis-
tence is not without consequence on the future of the Union, this future
itself is not entirely contained in the prognosis concerning democracy.
Curiously enough, and almost regretfully, Tocqueville adds to the list of
subjects left aside by his type of analysis ‘the commercial activity prevail-
ing in the Union” and its importance for the future, as if his task were to
Democracy in America 183
desires and struggles. This expiains why Tocqueville shifts so often from
equality as a dominant social state (that is, as a norm) to equality as a
passion (that is, as both a feeling and an ideology). One could almost say
that the democratic social state is characterized more by the passions it
engenders than by their fulfillment, since actual equality of conditions is
never achieved but always yearned for. “When inequality is the general
rule in society, the greatest inequalities attract no attention. When every-
thing is more or less level, the slightest variation is noticed. Hence the
more equal men are, the more insatiable will be their longing for
equality.’”*!
In other words, this genuine equality—an avowed but elusive aim, a
reference to a norm but also an object of desire—is subdivided into a host
of partial attempts to establish social differences. Tocqueville understood
that the belief in equality as a value does not eliminate what he calls
“private individual pride,” that is, the passion for distinguishing oneself
from others. On the contrary, the belief in equality intensifies this pas-
sion, while modifying and increasing its scope. The tendency to “‘distin-
guish”’ oneself is all the more legitimate as classes are less defined by
custom or law, as is the case in aristocracies. In addition, democracy
increases the number of signs of differentiation because, by making
conditions equal, and even more by making citizens uniform, it gives
added value to the slightest advantage; and, by increasing social mobility,
it replaces traditional hierarchies with recent and temporary privileges,
conspicuously displayed by their beneficiaries while they enjoy them.
There is in Democracy in America (particularly in chapters 14 and 16 of
part 3 of volume 2) an outline of a theory of how equality breeds symbolic
inequality and how this process gives rise to the restlessness and envy that
are the sentiments characteristic of democracies.
Nevertheless, Tocqueville believes that this inherent instability is com-
pensated by certain factors enabling the system to function in harmony.
First, there is religion, which he regards as a key element of the social
consensus and as a protection for ‘‘democratic” citizens against the
inordinate pretense to know everything and thus to change everything.
But there is also a built-in corrective, hidden within the very desire for
equality and the passion for social promotion: in a democratic state,
where careers are relatively slow and where individuals have become
used to making a daily effort to climb up the social ladder step by step,
there is a tendency for desires to become commensurate with means, and
ambitions with chances. Tocqueville was the first to discover this basic
law of modern societies, according to which men internalize by their
desire only a probable future, in the statistical sense of the term. They
look forward only to what can happen to them, thus avoiding both
exaggerated ambitions and insurmountable disappointments.
Moreover, it is the absence of these correctives for equality that
characterizes an intermediate social state between aristocracy and
Democracy in America 189
racy” stem the intellectual traits, the mental habits, and the mores of the
Americans. This proposition is partly tautological, since the definition of
democracy includes equality as a norm and as a passion. But Tocqueville
manages to compose variations of almost infinite subtlety and richness on
this proposition, in that his aim is to rework his central definition un-
ceasingly by examining its correlates.
Thus, it is not of the greatest importance, in my view, that the plan of
the admirable second volume has only the appearances of rigor; that the
SHC
distinction between ‘“‘ideas,’”’ “sentiments,” and ‘‘mores”’ is often de-
batable; that even within each of the parts, especially the third, the
arrangement of topics is not very logical. What does matter is the extraor-
dinary congruence between America as an object of study and the defini-
tion of democracy that Tocqueville uses in order to explore it. By virtue
of their origins, at once recent and homogeneous, their social state, and
their political institutions, the Americans fulfill the requirements for a
laboratory experiment in democracy. The assertion that every aspect of
their life is a consequence of democracy is a convenient expository device
for saying that every feature of America can be understood by reference
to a social consensus on equality. The association of new men for the
purpose of exploiting a virgin territory—an association with no other
historical foundation than this common belief—provided Tocqueville
with a field of study providentially suited to his conceptual genius, which
was both profound and simple.
Profound and simple: a comparison with Marx“ will perhaps enable us
to add a final word of explanation concerning these predicates.
Marx’s concepts, in every period of his intellectual development, are
never simple. They are reworkings of concepts inherited from German
philosophy or borrowed from English political economy; they owe noth-
ing to Marx’s subjective experience and almost everything to his reflec-
tion on the reflections of others. In contrast, Tocqueville’s system is
founded not on an intellectual construct but on a self-evident empirical
notion transposed to the abstract level, where it is defined as the irreversi-
ble progress of equality. This notion becomes the centerpiece of Tocque-
ville’s analysis, which aims at deducing its consequences.
Marx delves behind the equality proclaimed by the French Revolu-
tion, a value that has become the source of social legitimacy in the West.
He unmasks and denounces actual inequality, the contradiction between
facts and values. He writes a genealogy of the cause of this contradiction,
a cause that he locates on the economic level and in the social relations
arising from the production of wealth. Equality becomes no more than an
ideological lie, or a higher goal that cannot be achieved without the
destruction of capitalism. This dichotomy destroys all the features of
Tocquevillian equality, that is, equality as a social norm and as a passion.
Marx is interested in the workings of economic life and in the connections
between economics and society. Tocqueville explores the relation be-
194 America and the Idea of Democracy
tween the social principle and human behavior: by bringing his analysis to
bear on the motives of the individual and collective action of his contem-
poraries, Tocqueville has no need to reduce the political sphere to
another order of reality that is supposed to underlie and determine it. He
thus breaks with the obsessive search for the foundations of society so
characteristic of the eighteenth century and of Marx, who in this respect is
the heir to that century. Tocqueville deliberately focuses on what lies
“‘downstream’’: he regards the founding principle as a sort of historical
datum that is both evident and impossible to reduce to a causal demon-
stration; what counts is to deduce its consequences on social life. For
Marx, freedom lies in the abolition of surplus value; for Tocqueville, in
the intelligent handling of the belief in equality.
In this sense, Marx’s thought is infinitely more complex; it approaches
politics only through a series of mediations (in which, as it turns out,
Marx gets lost). But, in another sense, Tocqueville’s ‘“‘simplicity” goes
deeper. Despite appearances, Marx’s entire system is directed toward the
realization of the promises of equality. In denouncing inequality through
the analysis of capitalist social relations, he rediscovers equality in the
guise of the historical necessity of socialism but never ceases to regard it
as the basic value of the social compact. He criticizes the capitalist version
of equality only the better to demonstrate that it must act once more as a
founding principle for history, through the new departure represented by
revolution. Tocqueville, on the contrary, does not internalize equality as
a value: he is an aristocrat. But he does observe the fact that equality has
become the legitimating principle of modern societies, and he tries to
measure this phenomenon. By using a method that is both spatially and
temporally comparative, he confers a relative value to equality as a
legitimating principle and a new belief that must be compared to older
principles and beliefs in order for its immense impact to be appreciated.
Tocqueville is thus the first to view modernity in an anthropological
perspective.
Paradoxically, the ‘“‘simpler’ his thought and the less bookish his
theory, the more the two—thought and theory—are directly fed by a
contemporaneous psychological experience and the more they enable
experience to be dissociated from its conceptualization. Tocqueville went
from the aristocratic world to the democratic world, and it is this very
passage that constitutes the thread—and the anguish—of his life. With a
foot in each world, he regards as a self-evident truth that equality is only
one of the modes of social life. It is out of his archaic existential position
that he constructs his modern conceptual inquiry.
Marx’s thought, on the contrary, aims at a totally scientific investiga-
tion into the most hidden sources of inequality, which it unmasks under
the misleading disguise of a free contract between equal individuals. But
the more it tries to be scientific, independent of contemporary experi-
ence, and intent on discovering reality under the mask of ideology, the
Democracy in America 195
For any traveler in modern America, the most glaring phenomenon is the
urban crisis. It has hit hardest in the oldest industrialized areas of the
United States—the Northeast and the Great Lakes—the areas that are
the most traditional symbols of America’s success. These chosen lands of
democracy, affluence, and individual promotion have become the sites of
collective revolt and hopeless poverty. Yesterday, they embodied the
nation’s promise; today, the frailty of basic values and principles: equal
opportunity, individual success, free enterprise, and liberty.
It all began when the blacks, driven from the South by farm mecha-
nization, migrated to the North, where they were attracted by industrial
wages. This movement dates from just after the First World War, but it
assumed massive proportions only during and after the Second World
War. The great American cities had grown in the nineteenth century,
thanks to European immigrants, who contributed to their expansion,
their construction, and their rising prosperity. By the mid-twentieth
century, these cities were in the hands of the only peasants in American
history: the blacks who had lived in the old plantation economy.
The blacks have indeed settled in the inner cities. For a European
accustomed to the gloomy housing complexes of working-class suburbs
and the concentration of wealth in the inner cities, it is extraordinary to
observe the reverse phenomenon in the United States: the poor, that is,
the blacks, in the heart of the city, surrounded by a vast middle-class area
within a radius of twenty, thirty, or fifty kilometers. What is extraordi-
nary is not that blacks and whites cannot live together. After all, the
urban history of Europe also involves the separation of rich neighbor-
hoods and poor neighborhoods and even, more recently, the ethnic
197
198 America and the Idea of Democracy
I have assembled in the last part of this book four studies on modern
Jewish history, three of which have been published in a different form by
Le Nouvel Observateur (the fourth, “Israel, Zionism, and the Diaspora,”
is here published for the first time).
The first of these studies is devoted to the Jewish problem in modern
French history; the second is a presentation for the French public of the
work of the Israeli historian Gershom Scholem; the third deals with the
relations between the French Left and Israel. The third essay is the only
one to have appeared more or less in its present form in Le Nouvel
Observateur (15 May 1978). The first two have been somewhat revised
and rewritten.
References to the original articles are given in the notes. I should like
to take the opportunity of thanking my friend Jean Daniel for having
published them in the first place and for allowing me to use them in this
book.
209
Ltée fe eliascd fs ei ir
couch
sae FAN 9.1 sop
; eG, Ÿ :
rane
KA eave nr27 Samet von anitaee
H LE _
The history of French Jews has been affected by the repercussions of its
characteristic feature: the willingness to submit to Jacobin assimilation.
The reason why this history has been so unobtrusive is that it was also
almost pointless. Since the French Revolution, the Jews were a part of
French history. Even if the Right denied them this title to joint ownership
of the French patrimony, the Jews had chosen to receive at least precar-
ious tenure rights to it from the liberals. What was the use, then, of
dwelling on the factors that made them a distinctive category of citizens?
In this respect, the increase over the past few years in the number of
works on the history of the French Jewish community from 1789 to today
is the sign of a major change, many of the reasons for which are obvious.
First, the impact of the war, which has taken several forms: the Vichy
persecutions, the existence of an officially anti-Semitic French govern-
ment, and the massacre of Jewish refugees from Germany and eastern
Europe have reactivated the residue of bad conscience inseparable from
any successful assimilation. And then there was Israel, the unlikely and
tragic victory of the destitute Jews scorned by the French consistories, the
survivors par excellence of the Holocaust, the outcasts of Europe pro-
moted to the central role in Jewish history, the proletarians of the
community who had become its national flag.
I am writing as if this were an exclusively Jewish history. Of course, it is
also our history, that of the gentile French, and it is not a particularly
glorious one. But it derives its true weight and universal value from the
way the Jews experienced it, suffered from it, acted on it, and interpreted
it. The French Left has been all too prone to deal only with the outer
First published in Le Nouvel Observateur, 5 April 1976, 17 September 1979, and 28 April
1981.
211
212 Aspects of Modern Jewish History
aspect of the Jewish question, even with the best possible intentions
(which was not always the case), even when trying to reduce it to anti-
Semitism, and especially when treating it as a capitalist diversion. Now
that the Jews have gained a national history, that of the French Jews—
which seemed frozen, withdrawn, and dependent—is stirring again. For a
fairly long time, the history of French Jews has fluctuated according to the
variations of our “‘thermometer’’: is it not time we looked at theirs?
First, I should like to take this opportunity to pay tribute to a series of
books that are an honor to postwar French publishing. The “Diaspora”
series, edited by Roger Errera, is precisely an expression of the renewed
interest in Jewish history in France. It has brought to the attention of the
French public a first-rate collection of authors and books, such as Ger-
shom Scholem’s admirable Messianisme juif (The Messianic Idea in Juda-
ism). On a less fundamental but no less valuable level, this series also
aims at providing a survey of modern French Judaism.
Patrick Girard’s book concerns the oldest period, 1789 to 1860.' While
it does not contain any new information on the history of French Jews
between these two dates, it gives an excellent summary of their progress
from revolutionary emancipation to gradual integration into French soci-
ety. The tremendous impulse of liberal universalism marked the con-
tribution of the Revolution to the Jewish question. By granting full
citizenship first to the Sephardic Jews of Bordeaux and of the Comtat
Venaissin (1790), then to the Jews of Alsace (1791), the Revolution
brought these old ghetto communities back into the mainstream of his-
tory. The Revolution offered them the historical model of French “‘re-
generation”; and the consequent substitution of a politically oriented
form of messianism for traditional values became a key factor in the
fragmentation of the old Jewish communities. No Jew had an ancien
régime to mourn. All Jews responded to both the most modern idea and
the oldest idea introduced by the new regime: the rights of the citizen and
the right to participate in a just undertaking.
Yet this ‘‘assimilation” was to take half a century, owing to the
persistence of traditional French attitudes, first in the form of popular
anti-Semitism during the Terror, then in the policy of the Empire. Napo-
leon reversed the Revolution’s perspective on the Jews. Whereas revolu-
tionary emancipation had consisted in replacing their religious status by a
political status, Napoleon, in convening the Great Sanhedrin—that is,
the notables of the Jewish community—in 1807, made their French
citizenship conditional on a religious pact with the Christians.
What the revolutionaries had regarded as the cause of the moral decay
of the Jews became for the emperor the guarantee of their good conduct.
This renewed focus on religious identity explains the confiscation of some
of the benefits acquired by the Jews through the Revolution. In particu-
lar, it explains the “infamous decree”’ of 1808, which reestablished the
juridical inferiority of Jews before the courts, with the exception of the
Jews and French Democracy 213
Jews of Paris and Bordeaux (but, at the time, the Alsatian Jews, against
whom the decree was directed, were by far the largest community).
The decree did not survive the fall of the Empire for very long. The
July Monarchy definitively granted the Jews equal status in law and
recognition of their denominational rights, by creating a budget for the
Jewish religious establishment. French Jews, now legally assimilated,
entered a relatively happy phase of their history as a dynamic community
of bourgeois, of shopkeepers and artisans dominated by eminently suc-
cessful bankers and professionals. This community was increasingly
urban, Parisian, and—in short—bourgeois in character, cemented by a
secularized complex of traditional religious beliefs, by a strong minority
feeling, and by a deep attachment to France’s liberal image.
Was it an ‘assimilated’? community? Patrick Girard’s whole book is
centered on this basic question. In his view, assimilation is a dynamic
process “in which individuals belonging to a community with a distinctive
way of life attempted to formulate a doctrine combining a very old
religious heritage with the values of the surrounding society, values
intended to justify the preservation of an identity reduced to its denomi-
national aspect.” This somewhat weighty vocabulary, nonetheless useful
for its relative precision, expresses a positive judgment on the cultural
crossbreeding arising from the encounter between the Jewish tradition
and Western liberalism.
The author feels no idealized regret for the old, closed community. He
does not project on these mid-nineteenth-century French Jews the catas-
trophes of the twentieth century. Surprisingly, for such a young man (he
was born in 1950), he does not detest the ‘“‘middle-of-the-road” Judaism
of moderate and prudent notables, who preserved traditional practices in
the privacy of family life while adapting themselves to the modern world
in their professional and public life. He admires them for having handled
so skillfully the intercommunity tensions between the orthodox, who
rallied round L’Univers israélite, and the liberals, who published the
Archives israélites.
In both camps, French Jews had become israélites. This was their way
of saying that they were no longer Jews like those of the eastern Euro-
pean ghettos but that they nevertheless remained Jews in their attach-
ment to a past and a religion. These ‘‘assimilated” communities, products
of the encounter between Judaism and the French Revolution, were not
national communities, but neither did they mark the end of Judaism.
They represent a phase of its history that was “just as Jewish and collec-
tive as other [phases].”
This analysis echoes—without ever saying so explicitly—a fun-
damental debate in Jewish historiography and particularly a book in the
same series, published in 1973; the book of a Canadian professor,
Michael Marrus, devoted to French Jews during the Dreyfus affair.* The
two authors, while following each other chronologically, do not have the
214 Aspects of Modern Jewish History
In actual fact, the French anti-Semites did not advocate forced emigra-
tion. Very few Jews managed to leave the occupied zone between 1940
and 1942. Apart from internment, a fate reserved for foreigners, the aim
was to set up a special status, an idea borrowed from the monarchic
tradition and from the Action Frangaise. A second-class citizenship
within the bounds of the law was to be defined for French Jews. This was
the purpose of the decree of 18 October 1940, drafted by the minister of
justice of the first Laval government, Raphaél Alibert, former member of
the Conseil d’Etat and a faithful disciple of Maurras. But this decree,
which barred Jews from the civil service, was reinforced on 14 June 1941
by a new statute, extending the ban to the professions and to business;
this was the work of the commissaire général aux questions juives under
the Darlan government, Xavier Vallat. And what a highly typical figure
Vallat was: a right-thinking member of parliament under the Third
Republic, a former teacher in the Catholic school system who had be-
come a professional war veteran after the First World War, a Catholic
monarchist who had made the rounds of all the right-wing parties; not a
fascist, even less a germanophile, but simply a symbol of a milieu and a
culture that had finally taken its revenge on democracy. Professing an
anti-Semitism “‘in the national interest” for which he was actually at-
tacked by Parisian “collaborators,” Xavier Vallat was the perfect
embodiment of something worse than Vichy’s submissiveness: its duplic-
ity. On every level, he pushed anti-Semitic policy further than the Ger-
mans were asking, but in the name of his convictions against theirs. He
cloaked the unequal bargaining with the victor, which was both Vichy’s
principle and its excuse, with the domestic flag of French nationalism.
Thus, he was able to stake out an original position for himself in the
process whereby Vichy outrivaled the Nazis in their own policies.
But the most surprising feature in Paxton and Marrus’s merciless
description is not the existence of anti-Semitic ministers or doctrines at
Vichy, nor the relative passivity of public opinion, dazed by a defeat as
sweeping as that of June 1940. After all, this type of policy, this brand of
minister, and this spineless acquiescence of public opinion can ultimately
be explained by the Nazi victory and the state of French politics. What is
more surprising, and frightening, is the absence of any reaction on the
part of the civil servants who enacted all these measures, prosecutions,
and confiscations. The Conseil d’Etat examined the statutes concerning
Jews as if they were ordinary laws. Law professors demonstrated their
validity and novelty. The prefects enforced them. The police carried out
orders. Never, nowhere, did an official resign or even protest! The entire
French administrative machinery obeyed the new ministers as if they
derived their authority from the people in the normal way.
All these officials had served republican France. Their behavior can-
not easily be accounted for either by invoking their prewar attitudes (as in
218 Aspects of Modern Jewish History
the case of Alibert or Vallat) or by the all too easy recourse to the oldest
exorcistic myth of Catholic France (as in the case of the average French-
man). This sinister history nevertheless seems to demonstrate two things:
first, that what one can call the French elites of the period were much
more imbued with deep and lively anti-Semitic feelings than one would
be led to believe by the number of far-right deputies in the 1928, 1932,
and 1936 parliaments; second, that the incantatory recourse to the Jewish
plot or poison was perhaps more vital to bourgeois France than to
grass-roots France, in that the defeat provided the first with a twofold
revenge for the Dreyfus affair and for the Léon Blum government, while
the second was not asking for that much. Consequently, this recourse was
more a technique for conquering power and public opinion than an active
ideological and emotional act of communion. Of the two classical poles of
anti-Semitism, Vichy embodied manipulation far more than preaching.
This feature, it seems to me, gives it a distinctive—and, moreover,
particularly vile—character in the annals of this inexhaustible passion.
The next period is better known and tragically simple. In late 1941 and
early 1942, when Hitler decided to exterminate the Jews and inaugurated
the policy of deportation to the East, a policy extended to France in June,
Vichy’s “independence”’ in anti-Semitic matters came to an end. Dar-
quier de Pellepoix, the racketeering hoodlum, replaced Xavier Vallat,
the Catholic member of parliament. A card-index census of the Jewish
population was patiently put together by French civil servants and police
between 1940 and 1942. It became the matrix for the deportation of Jews,
which began with the massive roundup of the Velodrome d’Hiver (indoor
sports stadium) on 16 and 17 July 1942, carried out by 9,000 French
policemen. In its camps, Vichy held in reserve thousands of other foreign
Jews, whom Laval gradually handed over, on request. By the end of
1944, slightly more than 75,000 Jews (out of 300,000) had been deported
from France to the concentration camps located on former Polish terri-
tory. Some 2,500 returned.
Thus, from the autumn of 1942 on, the mechanism of wholesale
deportation continued on its lethal course, with the help of the censuses,
identity checks, and internments carried out by the French authorities. In
February 1943, in the southern zone, a series of arrests of foreign Jews
second in magnitude only to the July and August 1942 roundups was
carried out exclusively by the French police. Yet, as the liberation
approached, this task was assumed by the German police, with the help,
it is true, of the Milice. This is probably one of the reasons why the
deportation figures for 1943 and 1944 are lower than those for 1942, when
all the resources of the French police were at the Germans’ disposal.
Some 33,500 Jews were deported in 1943 and 1944 as against 42,500 in
1942 alone.
Unfortunately the relative decline in these sinister figures does not
mean that the Vichy government had finally taken a stand against Ger-
Jews and French Democracy 219
man policy. Paxton and Marrus cite only two examples of genuine
opposition. The first dates from the spring of 1942, when Vichy refused to
extend the obligation to wear the yellow star to the Jews of the still-
unoccupied zone; the second dates from the summer of 1943, when
Pétain resisted pressures to ‘‘denaturalize”’ recently naturalized Jews (by
virtue of a law of 1937) and to add to the categories of ‘“‘deportable”’ Jews.
But neither of these refusals led Vichy to protest against the deportation
of Jews or to withdraw its consent and support for the measures that
brought it into effect. The deportation of foreign Jews, or of French Jews
arrested for having violated the legal restrictions imposed on them,
ceased only with the liberation of the country.
Finally, what can one say about the balance sheet? A classic argument
in favor of the thesis that Vichy was a “‘shield” is that three-quarters of the
Jewish community living in France in 1939 survived; moreover, it is
known that the overwhelming majority of the 75,000 Jews deported from
France to the camps where they were exterminated was composed of
foreign Jews. And this dismal distinction, borrowed from Vichy, still
serves as its posthumous justification. In reality, the argument would
have a demonstrative value—within its own anti-Semitic logic—only if it
could be accompanied by proofs showing that the Vichy government
actively protected French Jews from deportation after having persecuted
them by its laws. But these proofs do not exist, and no one has ever been
able to produce any. Furthermore, Paxton and Marrus show that there is
no link between the number of surviving Jews and the various policies of
occupied or satellite countries. The tragically essential factor in the
extermination of the Jews, and in its magnitude in each European state,
was the means implemented by the Nazis for that purpose.
Thus, one cannot give Vichy policy the credit for what was actually due
to circumstance. If three-quarters of the French Jewish community suc-
ceeded in escaping deportation and genocide, it was owing to a shortage
of manpower in the German police operating in France and to the
possibilities for shelter both in the Italian occupation zone and in rural
France. Public opinion in these areas became increasingly sensitive to the
Jewish plight as the prospect of Nazi defeat became clearer and the
Service du Travail Obligatoire simultaneously deported greater numbers
of workers to Germany. But none of this is attributable to a determina-
tion or to a policy—even at a clandestine level—of the Laval government.
As far as Vichy’s action proper is concerned, the historian can only
document its original and autonomous contribution to Nazi anti-
Semitism, particularly between 1940 and 1942, and its objective contribu-
tion to extermination, through its own concentration camps, its police,
and the assistance it provided the Germans in their roundups, particularly
in connection with the foreign Jews who took refuge in France between
the wars.
The evidence marshaled by Paxton and Marrus thus leads the reader
220 Aspects of Modern Jewish History
Since the war and the inglorious disappearance of the Vichy regime,
my generation especially remembers having lived through a period
haunted by the return from the camps—a return that also meant the
discovery of the camps. But the taboo that consequently weighed on
anti-Semitism also led to a somewhat furtive burial of the Jewish ques-
tion. A spontaneous conspiracy of silence, as it were, was hatched to
exorcise this specter. Gentiles tried not to think of it, and Jews carried a
secret too heavy and too peculiar to talk about.
But this uneasy equilibrium between a guilty conscience and the
willingness to efface was upset ten or fifteen years ago. The generation
that reached twenty at the end of the 1960s—Jews and Gentiles alike—
rediscovered the Jewish problem. To understand how and why this
occurred, one can start with the family photograph taken in 1979 by two
journalists, Harris and Sédouy.* From this collection of interviews con-
ducted by them in all the milieus of French Jewry, only a single common
feature emerges: anxiety. No doubt this is an age-old trait, but, in the
midst of the apparently reassuring uniformity of our prosperous society,
itis more alive, more entrenched, and more varied than ever. And what if
France were to become once again a country where Jews could not live?
This question is always latent in the answers given in the interviews; it is
even implicitly voiced by French Jews who have “always” been assimi-
lated.
This patent erosion of the democratic certainties of assimilation can be
clearly explained by certain structural reasons. French Jewry (600,000 to
700,000 French Jews) is a population replenished by a recent influx of
North African immigrants, whose arrival has modified the balances
within the community. The assimilated bourgeoisie is less predominant
Jews and French Democracy 221
among the North African Jews, and the assimilationist creed is not
necessarily accompanied by the abandonment of religious practices and
traditional ways of life. Consequently, the face of French Jewry has
changed and become more visibly Jewish. This greater capacity to assume
the particular Jewish heritage (even in its secularized form, that is, as a set
of habits more social than cultural in nature) poses novel problems for all
French intellectual traditions, both left-wing and right-wing. To under-
stand this, one can listen to Rabbi Guedj expressing regret—in the
unlikely setting of Sarcelles—for the secular environment of Constantine
and answering the question “‘Is it possible to live in a country without
espousing its dominant philosophy and its way of life?” in the following
words: “Tell me, please, what is the dominant philosophy in France
today? I cannot go along with those who think like that. That’s how
Nazism started... .”
The thoroughgoing renewal of French Jewry was marked by two major
and equally destabilizing events (if one takes assimilation as a reference
point): the Holocaust and the birth of the state of Israel. The first
exterminated nearly all the eastern European Jews who had recently
immigrated into France. The role of the Vichy authorities also struck a
deep blow at the belief of assimilated Jews in the safety of their own
destiny. It showed them that even in France, a hundred and fifty years
after the Revolution, their future was not settled forever.
On top of that, after the war, came the birth of Israel and, twenty years
later, the Six Day War, which seems to have played a crucial role in
crystallizing the attitude of French Jews toward the new state. French
Jewry, no longer so assured of being able to stake everything on demo-
cratic assimilation, could at least refer to a new image and at most count
on the help of a new homeland. Through innumerable channels, Zionism
transformed the Jewish consciousness in the Diaspora by confronting it,
on the strength of Zionism’s own historical success, with a series of
ultimatum-questions that, in accordance with the nature of Zionism, led
from the religious sphere to the national sphere. At the same time, the
international dimension of Israel’s existence led the Diaspora communi-
ties to establish forms of solidarity that are probably in turn transforming
anti-Semitism into a worldwide phenomenon, in an unprecedented form
and on an unprecedented scale.
Hence the new tremors in Franco-Jewish identity that one can discern
in the interviews assembled by Harris and Sédouy. Thirty-five years after
the war, one can measure the impact of a twofold evolution: on the
gentile side, the ban on anti-Semitism imposed when death-camp survi-
vors returned is gradually weakening, not because it has disappeared
from living memory, but because the young generations do not have that
memory; and, on the Jewish side, the community is much more willing
today than before or just after the war to assert and accept its distinctive-
ness, as regards its special ties with Israel, its traditional way of life, its
222 Aspects of Modern Jewish History
But this notion, which should mark the starting point of any discussion of
the topic, is where Fabre-Luce leaves off. Taking up the idea of assimila-
tion precisely where the Jewish community has left it, he turns it into a
sort of no-man’s-land protected from Christian anti-Semitism and Jewish
proselytism. Assimilation becomes an abstract, unreal zone where pas-
sions are extinct and anxiety has vanished because only the author’s
limpid ideas prevail. In the typically French realm of blind intelligence,
Alfred Fabre-Luce finds a refuge from the historical density of a problem
that he finds more shocking than intriguing.
His idea is to propose to French Jews a sort of pact that would define a
minimal consensus, which both parties would endeavor to maintain: the
gentile French would act to prevent the rebirth of anti-Semitism as a way
of drawing attention away from national difficulties, and French Jews
would abide by a sort of code of good conduct, characterized by the
abandonment of cultural proselytism and Zionist militancy. In this cu-
rious deal, two concrete clauses could serve as guarantees: the search for
a common position of the French on the Middle East and the establish-
ment of a “‘good”’ version of the history of Vichy.
The mind boggles at these chapter headings. The first belongs to the
realm of wishful thinking—an idea that is unworkable in practice and,
moreover, not very interesting in the abstract. But the second is more
revealing of Fabre-Luce’s polemical obstinacy: he wants to rewrite the
history of Vichy.
Indeed, the bulk of his short book is devoted to an analysis of Vichy, a
crucial period in the relationship of Jews with France, especially if one
focuses exclusively on assimilation. For Fabre-Luce, there is a Jewish
version of the history of Vichy, characterized by an emphasis on the
purely French responsibility for the persecutions. Curiously, the pro-
tagonist in this enterprise is the American professor Robert Paxton (a
Gentile, and rather of the southern aristocratic sort). I shall not dwell on
this curious assertion, since Fabre-Luce knows that, naturally, one finds
Gentiles in every Jewish lobby. But what I find bizarre, and even some-
what disturbing, in this type of historiographical analysis, is the suspicion
that there exists a Jewish determination to produce and circulate a history
of Vichy that is contrary to the truth and serves the interests of an
avenging minority.
I have no objection—far from it—to discussing the editing of Le
Chagrin et la Pitié or certain excessively systematic allegations made by
Paxton. But what seems less admissible to me is to pin the same yellow
star on Ophiils, Paxton, Stanley Hoffmann, and Léon Poliakov, whom
Fabre-Luce regards as a lobby of historians and film makers entrusted
with the task of ‘‘presenting to the French the history of their war years
through a Jewish prism.” Indiscriminate amalgamations seldom proceed
from a form of thinking that is not somewhat crude. In this instance, the
224 Aspects of Modern Jewish History
225
226 Aspects of Modern Jewish History
As if to round out the story and give the example of family the
pedagogic simplicity of an ancient tragedy, Gershom Scholem had three
brothers. Two of them sided with his father, and one of these two was
even more German—in fact, an outspoken German nationalist. The
fourth brother, in contrast, soon joined the Social-Democratic party,
became a Communist member of parliament after the war, was expelled
from the party as a Trotskyite in 1927, and died at Buchenwald at the
hands of the Nazis precisely for having been a Communist member of
parliament. Thus, the Scholem children entered the twentieth century
each under his own flag: assimilation, revolution, and Zionism. Of the
three options for solving the famous “‘Jewish question” that accompanied
their childhood, the third seemed at the time the most outlandish and the
most shaky; it alone was to withstand the century.
Moreover, Gershom Scholem’s books continually explore this variety
of Zionism, for it represents not just a youthful awakening but the central
question of a lifetime. It was less a political commitment than a moral
choice. The young Scholem was motivated not by the desire to build a
Jewish state but by the refusal of the duplicity inherent in the daily
existence of the Jewish bourgeoisie in Germany. Basically, it is the very
same feeling that led one of his brothers—as if by chance, the only one
with whom he had close ties—toward revolution and socialism. Admit-
tedly, it is hard to explain what drove one brother to Marxism and
Leninism, the other to study with a professor of Hebrew and to take
Talmud courses: such are the mysteries of individual existence. But if one
accepts the idea that their contradictory choices had a common origin,
one cannot help observing that the choice of the future historian was
better suited to the problem at hand than that of the future Communist
deputy of the Reichstag. The first wanted to identify the elements and
sources of the problem, while the second sought to eliminate its very
terms and thus began by negating them.
In this respect, the Zionism of the young Gershom Scholem, because it
was a postassimilation Zionism, a return and not just a breach or a vision
of the future, was inseparable from the central paradox of the entire
movement—from the chemical process that produced national ideas
from religious ideas, modernity from archaism. In the Zionist movement
to which its youth rallied at the turn of the century despite their rabbis’
hostility, the ghetto Jewry of eastern Europe saw only its new, secular,
modern, socialist, and nationalist aspects—Zionism as a break with the
past. In contrast, because he was the rebel child of a historical Jewish
experience rooted in the cult of modernity and in the repression of
tradition, Scholem knew in advance that the Jewish national movement
conveyed, took hold of, and revitalized an age-old cultural heritage
through the agency of modern political categories. What the Jews have in
common—and what provides the least unsatisfactory explanation for
their extraordinary survival and their national ambition to return to
Gershom Scholem and Jewish History 227
As long as Israel was only the reflection of Jewish destiny, that is, of
Jewish suffering, it was not hard for the Left to love Israel. Indeed, the
Left saw the new state as the embodiment of its traditional conception of
the Jewish problem as the sign of capitalist injustice, of the Jews as the
exemplary victims of a system, and of Jewish distinctness as the obverse
of persecution. The Second World War and the Holocaust brought this
feeling to a peak—a feeling theorized by Sartre: what “‘coagulated” the
Jewish problem was the anti-Semitic hatred displayed by Christian
Europe; the men and women who in those years were settling in their new
homeland could not be colonizers, since they were wanderers, survivors
of the tragedy in the camps. Even this dignity was not enough to preserve
them from suffering, since they were being rejected from shore to shore
by their new persecutors: the British. In fact, the French Left had not yet
learned to hate colonizers, whom it was often fond of regarding as the
overseas exporters of its own values. It felt far more guilty about the
plight of the Jews than about Arab or Vietnamese suffering.
This democratic universalism, so popular and yet so sectarian in the
immediate aftermath of the war, was dealt a heavy blow by the decol-
onization wars. Once again, the force and legitimacy of nationalism
became manifest, in their simplest and yet most conceptually elusive
aspects. A new Left began to define itself with reference to this struggle,
which was helping to put an end to Jacobin Europocentrism. The new
Left gradually exerted its pressure on the two great traditional parties by
waging intellectual guerrilla warfare on the outskirts of the Communist
party and by provoking a definitive split within the Section Francaise de
230
Israel and the French Left 231
234
Israel, Zionism, and the Diaspora 235
life to be abandoned. The first vision was that of Herzl, for Zionism was
born in western Europe, specifically in Austria, where the Jewish com-
munity had made brilliant progress in the nineteenth century but where
anti-Semitism, too, had flared up violently. Lueger, the leader of the
Christian Social party—the man whose anti-Semitic diatribes fed the
young Hitler—was elected mayor of Vienna in 1897. The fact is that
Jewish assimilation had apparently provoked a rejective reaction in the
body social. Through Theodore Herzl, the Zionist dream emerged in this
society at the crossroads of democratic progress and resistance to that
progress. Like many memorable ideas or great events, it was predicated
on a revolution made of expectations, a revolution thwarted by the
counterrevolutionary force of reality.
Thus, the starting point of Zionism was both the success and the failure
of assimilation. The success, since Herzl belonged to a completely secu-
larized milieu that was cut off from the Jewish tradition. He was the
perfect representative of the intelligentsia integrated into German cul-
ture since the Enlightenment—a milieu whose fundamental belief was
that democracy was the necessary and sufficient condition for emancipa-
tion. But, at the same time, Herzl witnessed the failure of this central
creed, since the development of a new anti-Semitism within democratic
culture, in Austria, Germany, and France, proved to him that his youth-
ful convictions were mistaken. Thus, “‘assimilated’’ Jews were the first to
understand that democracy did not solve the Jewish problem, as all of
enlightened Europe had believed since the French Revolution. And it
was a “modern” anti-Semitism, born of democracy, that triggered Zion-
ism. By founding a national state and a homogeneous Jewish society,
Zionism aimed at enabling modern Judaism to lead a collective existence
modeled on European nations and yet in opposition to them, or at least to
the ideology of individual Jewish assimilation that they professed.
It is probable that Austro-German Jewry was the only branch of
European Jewry whose intellectual sensibility at the time made it a
suitable breeding ground for the Zionist idea: it was sufficiently inte-
grated into modern culture (unlike the traditionalist eastern European
ghettos) to adopt the idea of nationality and yet close enough to its origins
(unlike the French-style embourgeoisé varieties of Jewry) to preserve a
connection, if not with a religious belief, at least with the idea of a
separate culture. But, as evidenced by the episode of Herzl’s temporary
endorsement of the West African compromise as a substitute for
Jerusalem,’ that connection is easier to define in negative terms, as a
consequence of anti-Semitic rejection, than in positive terms, as a taking
into account of the cultural heritage.
Unlike that of Herzl, the second vision of the European Jew that
contributed a contrario to the birth of Zionism was not informed by the
need to put an end to anti-Semitism or by the impossibility of assimila-
tion. It was centered not on the external aspect of the Jewish problem,
236 Aspects of Modern Jewish History
eked out an existence in the shadow of the Turkish pashas, into the stake
of a battle between two messianic movements. More generally, as far as
Israel is concerned, the emphasis on biblical origins turned religion into a
cofounder of the state, inseparable from public authority. Religion has
made Israeli society a hostage to a conservative rabbinate, despite the
deliberately modernist aims of that society’s founders.
But it is probably the relationship between Israel and the Diaspora
that provides the best insight into the Israelis’ curious relation to the
Jewish past. It is true that the converse analysis is no less interesting and
that the attitude of Diaspora Jews toward Israel is composed of varying
degrees of love and hatred, from which a guilty conscience is never
absent. The very existence of Israel has transformed the general condi-
tion of Diaspora Jews owing to the way they are perceived by Gentiles;
yet these Diaspora Jews have remained in the Diaspora. At the other
end, Israel’s vision of the Diaspora is most often centered either on the
early-twentieth-century eastern European ghettos or on the Nazi
tragedy—that is, on the negation of the new Jewish farmer and soldier.
Occasionally, one can even discern a certain anti-intellectualism in this
spontaneous reconstruction of the past as a foil. Furthermore, as in the
early days of Zionism, the unfortunate and endangered Diaspora is only
an instrument or a source of recruitment: its fate is to become assimilated
or to enlist. While awaiting the inevitable outcome, Israel contributes to
the process by propagating a vision of the Diaspora’s natural submission
to Israel as its potential state. Having normalized the Jewish destiny
within its borders, Israel expects the same to happen to Judaism as a
whole. Because it has altered the image of Judaism the world over, Israel
assumes that it has unified Judaism from every point of view and thus no
longer feels the need to be aware of its diversity. Hence, geographical
space confronts Israel with the same enigmas and the same impasses as
historical time, and for the same reasons: the Jewish nation, whatever the
intentions or beliefs of Zionism, is not ‘‘like the others.”
Indeed, a modification of this vision could well be the first step toward
the general reappraisal of Zionism that everyone in Israel regards as a
necessity. To begin with, a very simple observation: aside from its ex-
traordinary historical achievement, Zionism has not realized its chief
objective, which was to bring all of the Jewish people together in Pales-
tine. Immigration has virtually ceased, and Israel’s population growth is
now solely dependent on its domestic birthrate. The annual migratory
balance is actually negative: this is a sign of the relatively high emigration
rate, but the phenomenon is hard to evaluate since the Israelis who leave
their country present their departure as a temporary absence. Emigration
apparently involves both the poorest social strata and the professions
(doctors, lawyers, and engineers): in both cases, the American dream
remains the natural pole of attraction. This phenomenon, which is quite
“normal”—and, moreover, easy to understand in a country where wages
Israel, Zionism, and the Diaspora 241
are relatively low, taxes very high, and military service interminable—has
become, no less understandably, the object of anxious concern in a
country founded on the law of return. Apart from its statistical impact,
emigration is a vivid sign of the psychological limits of the Zionist idea.
In fact, these limits have never ceased to exert a constraining effect,
since, from the very outset, at the turn of the century, emigration to
America was infinitely greater than the aliyah to Jerusalem; but these
constraints had been masked both by the spectacular triumph of the
creation of the state of Israel and by the massive immigration tragically
engendered by Hitler’s genocide. Today, more than thirty years after the
birth of Israel, no Zionist leader can seriously base a policy on the
assumption that Israel will absorb the entire Diaspora. The Diaspora
Jews, if they were supposed to have come, would already be there.
Russian Jews will perhaps continue to emigrate to Israel, since the Israeli
visa is the only one that allows them to leave the Soviet Union. However,
these immigrants will be few and far between, and there is no guarantee,
as experience has shown, that they will settle easily or definitively in
Israel. Barring an unpredictable catastrophe in the United States or
western Europe, Zionism does not solve the problem of the Diaspora. It
is condemned to coexist with the Diaspora.
The simplest way of rethinking Zionism, on the basis of what it has
accomplished and what it has become, would probably be to take into
account the abandonment of a universal solution to the Jewish problem—
an abandonment that is evident in the facts. Like all great historical
movements, Zionism has not fulfilled all the predictions of its founders or
achieved all the desired results. However, if one compares the degree to
which Zionism has carried out its initial project with the degree to which
other great ideas that have mobilized mankind in the twentieth century
have carried out theirs, Zionism does not come out too badly: all the
more reason to limit its scope and objectives according to the historical
tasks imposed on it by circumstances, while preserving its fidelity to the
spirit of its founders. Paradoxically, this redefinition implies both the
secularization of the state and the restitution to the Jewish people of its
entire past. It is by emancipating the national feeling from the historical
shortcut between the Bible and the founding of Israel that one will spare
it from the temptation of a debased form of messianism. In this respect,
Israel’s relation with the Diaspora constitutes a test.
AA hotel
Veo marca Ge Cee é
ar aR wi ALT Le
Mr malt, Préfet aS
"PEN \ar PRESS L
| Dre DU 2e
Li Le ALES PR
é… MATE Ayo des
ve CRD rien *des
23: | bret eae
mia te et ar ù
IV | oi
arr oes pee F4
. a ine
NOTES:
Introduction
Chapter 1
1. Raymond Aron, Trois essais sur l’âge industriel (Paris: Plon, 1966).
2. See Raymond Aron’s article on Sartre’s Critique de la raison dialectique in Le Figaro
littéraire (19 October 1964).
3. In Esprit (November 1963).
4. See Edmund Leach, “‘Genesis as Myth,” Discovery (May 1962); idem, ‘The Legit-
imacy of Solomon,” Archives européennes de sociologie (1966); idem, ‘Claude Lévi-
Strauss, Anthropologist and Philosopher,” New Left Review (1966).
Chapter 2
243
244 Notes to pages 44-84
Chapter 3
Chapter 4
Chapter 5
is the first grade of elementary school, sixiéme the first grade of secondary school, premiére
(formerly classe de rhétorique) and classe de philosophie (or terminale) the last two years of
secondary school. Before the Revolution, collèges was the general term for secondary
schools. After the Revolution, the secondary schools were divided into /ycées and collèges,
the former ranking somewhat above the latter.—TRans. ]
4. This information on the Collége de Juilly is taken from a recent and as yet unpub-
lished dissertation by Etienne Broglin, “De l’Académie royale à l’institution: le Collège de
Juilly, 1745-1828” (University of Paris, 1978).
5. The major speeches on education policy by the members of the revolutionary
assemblies can be found in C. Hippeau, L’Instruction publique en France pendant la
Révolution (1881). For more details, see J. Guillaume, ed., Procés-verbaux du Comité
d'Instruction publique de la Convention nationale, 6 vols. (Paris: Imprimerie Nationale,
1890-1907).
Chapter 6
1. The example has been given in this field by the work of L. Febvre and H.-J. Martin,
L’Apparition du livre, L’Evolution de l’humanité, 49 (Paris: Albin Michel, 1958).
2. R. Estivals, “La Statistique bibliographique de la France sous la monarchie au
XVIIIe siècle” (unpublished dissertation, University of Paris, 1962); idem, Le Dépôt légal
sous l’Ancien Régime de 1537 à 1791 (Paris: M. Rivière, 1961).
3. The verso of the last leaf of Bibliothèque Nationale Ms. Fr. 22 001 lists the following
fees: privilège général, 101 livres and 2 sous; permission for six years, 61 livres and 18 sous;
permission for three years, 30 livres.
4. Diderot, Lettre sur le commerce de la librairie, reprinted as Lettre sur la liberté de la
presse, ed. J. Proust (Paris: Editions Sociales, 1963).
5. Malesherbes, Mémoire sur la liberté de la presse (1788).
6. Diderot, Lettre.
7. The registers for printing license requests used as the basic source for this study are
the following:
Priviléges et permissions du Sceau
Ms. Fr. 21 995 1723-28
Ms. Fr. 21 996 1728-38
Ms. Fr. 21 997 1738-50
Ms. Fr. 21 998 1750-60
Ms. Fr. 21 999 1760-63
Ms. Fr. 22 000 1763-68
Ms. Fr. 22 001 1768-74
Ms. Fr. 22 002 1774-84
Ms. Fr. 21 978 1784-89
Permissions tacites
Ms. Fr. 21 990 1718-46
Ms. Fr. 21 994 1750-60
Ms. Fr. 21 992 1760-63
Ms. Fr. 21 991 1763-66
Ms: Er. 21,993 1766-72
Ms. Fr. 21 983 1772-82 (first occurrence of the
title permissions tacites)
Ms. Fr. 21 986 1782-88
Ms. Fr. 22 003 1788-89 (This last register of requests for tacit permits has been
mistakenly listed in the Bibliothèque Nationale manu-
script catalog among the privilège registers.)
246 Notes to pages 103-112
8. The itemized count of several books included in the same request for a privilége
generally presents no problems. Prints and engravings, often submitted in very great
numbers in a single request, have not been included in our census. However, bishoprics
often applied for a single privilège for a whole series of liturgical or devotional handbooks,
of which a summary list would be provided: breviaries, diurnals, missals, antiphonaries,
directories, and so on. In this case alone, it has been impossible to distinguish between
licenses and books. We have therefore adopted the method of counting arbitrarily as one
book the set of diocesan handbooks (usages), which artificially reduces their number.
9. Malesherbes did write in his fifth Mémoire sur les problèmes de la librairie that tacit
permits ‘‘have multiplied to the point of being today as common as public licenses.”
10. Malesherbes makes this statement in his Mémoire sur la liberté de la presse of 1788.
Moreover, a letter from the Parisian libraires (publisher-booksellers) Huart and Moreau to
Montesquieu, dated 8 January 1749, cites the rumor that L'Esprit des lois had been granted
a tacit permit. This fact cannot be verified on our registers, which are missing from late 1746
to late 1750.
11. After 1778, the “books entered via the Chambre Syndicale” no longer appear on the
registers of requests, but only in the listings of tacit permits.
12. Madeleine Ventre, L’Imprimerie et la librairie en Languedoc au dernier siècle de
l’Ancien Régime, 1700-1789 (Paris and The Hague: Mouton, 1958).
13. Letter from Huart to Montesquieu, March 1749.
14. Most of which are to be found in the manuscript division of the Bibliothèque
Nationale and in the Bibliothèque de l’Arsenal.
15. Forbidden books escape our census, but the book-licensing records invariably
preserve the traces of the most significant among them: Emile and Le Contrat social, for
example, spawned a long series of commentaries, which testify to their social impact.
16. This classification has been prepared with the help of Daniel Roche.
17. The division into five major categories is attested by the practices followed in library
catalogs. See for ex. Louis Desgraves, ed., Catalogue de la bibliothèque de Montesquieu
(Geneva: Droz, 1954); “Catalogue des bibliothèques des parlementaires parisiens,” in
François Bluche, Les Magistrats du Parlement de Paris au XVIIIe siècle, 1715-1771 (Paris:
Les Belles Lettres, 1960), 291; Durcy de Noinville, Dissertation sur les bibliothèques (Paris,
1758), Bibl. Nat. call no. Q. 3507; J.-M. Cels-Martin, Coup d'œil éclairé d’une bibliothèque
(Paris, 1773), Bibl. Nat. call no. Q. 5346.
18. See library catalogs such as Catalogue des livres de feu Monsieur le Maréchal de
Lautrec (Paris, 1762), Bibl. Nat. call no. Q. 8138; see also references in note 17 and esp.
Cels-Martin, Coup d'œil. We have classified under this heading the Histories of the Old and
New Testaments, the Lives of Jesus Christ, and similar works, for they all deal with biblical
or sacred history as distinct from ecclesiastical history.
19. See references in note 18.
20. The division of theological works into Catholic and non-Catholic (orthodox and
heterodox) was practiced in public libraries. See the “Catalogue général de la Bibliothèque
du Roi” (1739-42), reprinted in /ntroduction au catalogue général auteurs of the Biblio-
thèque Nationale (1897). This section naturally includes sermonizing, polemical, catechis-
tic, ascetic, and mystical theologians. See Cels-Martin, Coup d'œil.
21. The “liturgy” category appears in the bibliographical guides mentioned above,
where it includes devotional and catechistic literature.
22 See noted,
23. See Cels-Martin, Coup d'œil; Catalogue Montesquieu; Catalogue de la bibliothèque
Malesherbes (1797), Bibl. Nat. call no. 8° INV. Q. 9128; Catalogue Lautrec.
24. See M. Camus, Lettre sur la profession d'avocat, avec un catalogue raisonné des
livres de droit qu’il est le plus utile d’acquérir et de connaitre; Catalogue Malesherbes, vol. 2;
Cels-Martin, Coup d'œil.
25. Biographies and memoirs of famous men, literary history, history of theater,
heraldry, archaeology, and so forth, have been classified under “ancillary sciences [of
history]’’ (III.B.3). See Cels-Martin, Coup d'œil; Catalogue Malesherbes.
Notes to pages 112-121 247
26. See Catalogue de la Bibliothèque du Roi (1688) s.v. histoire ecclésiastique; Cels-
Martin, Coup d'œil, s.v. histoire sacrée; Catalogue Lautrec. In all of these works and
catalogs, geographical studies are grouped together with historical works.
27. See note 17: certain authors equate this category with philosophy, by virtue of the
tradition that philosophia comprehendit artes et scientias. For ex., Formey, Conseils pour
former une bibliothèque peu nombreuse mais choisie. However, in the catalog of books
belonging to M. Augry, a lawyer in Vendôme (Bibl. Nat. call no. Q. 3026), the entire
category is included under the heading “mathematics.” Pedagogical works are listed here
under “‘ethics.’” Theodicy, ontology, anthropology, magic, and cabalistic literature have
been classified under “‘metaphysics.”’ The science of navigation is classified here, in accord-
ance with Cels-Martin, under astronomy; alchemy under “‘chemistry.”’
28. Cels-Martin, Coup d'œil; Catalogue Lautrec; Catalogue Malesherbes.
29. The distinction between physical, mathematical, and natural sciences can be found
in Cels-Martin, Coup d'œil; Catalogue Lautrec; Catalogue Malesherbes. See also the Encyc-
lopédie, vol. 1, “Système figuré des connaissances humaines.”
30. Includes works on government, politics, commerce, and finance. See Catalogue
Malesherbes; Encyclopédie méthodique (1784), s.v. art; on political economics, see Cels-
Martin, Coup d'œil.
31. Catalogue de la Bibliothèque du Roi (1688) Catalogue Malesherbes; Cels-Martin,
Coup d'œil, Formey, Conseils; Maïeul de Chaudon, Bibliothèque d’un homme de goût
(Paris, 1772-77), Bibl. Nat. call no. 5340-41 and Q. 5542-45; Almanach de la librairie
(1781).
32. Music, painting, sculpture, drawing, etching, dance, architecture, art of warfare,
epistolary art, decoration; see Cels-Martin, Coup d'œil.
33. Cels-Martin, Coup d'œil; Encyclopédie, vol. 1, “Système figuré”; Catalogue
Malesherbes. Wood, silk, gems, iron, copper, clocks, wool, pyrotechnics, fire, and so on.
34. See note 17. Sports and pastimes.
35. Belles-lettres: see note 17. Essays, criticism, rhetoric, and so on, have been clas-
sified under “grammar and philology” (V.B), in accordance with Cels-Martin.
36. See note 17.
37. Formey, Conseils; Maieul de Chaudon, Bibliothéque.
38. Formey, Conseils; Maïeul de Chaudon, Bibliothèque; Cels-Martin, Coup d’eil;
Catalogue de la Bibliothèque du Roi (1688); Catalogue Malesherbes; Catalogue Lautrec.
39. The assistance of my friends and colleagues Jean-Louis Flandrin and Daniel Roche
has been invaluable in helping me to identify a great number of these books.
40. As explained in note 8, collections of diocesan handbooks (usages) have been
counted in this category as single units—an arbitrary but unavoidable choice.
41. This phenomenon is the chief explanation for the relative decrease in the number of
“poetry” books between 1784 and 1788.
42. Daniel Mornet, Les Origines intellectuelles de la Révolution française (Paris, 1932).
43. This share is all the larger as the three samplings, for the sake of consistency and
comparability, have not taken into account the “books entered via the Chambre Syndi-
cale”’—a category mentioned only between 1767 and 1778. These already printed books,
sent in from the provinces and abroad, cover a wider range of genres than the manuscripts
deliberately submitted for tacit permits.
44. In accordance with the criteria of the time, we have listed under ‘‘medicine,”’ in the
tacit-permits category, the abundant polemical literature of the 1780s concerning Mesmer’s
theory of animal magnetism. More generally, the bibliographical grid scatters among
different headings (metaphysics, chemistry, medicine) a basically homogeneous occultist
philosophy whose importance in the late-eighteenth century is well known.
45. We have excluded from these percentages the short popular novels published by the
Bibliothèque Bleue and other specialized libraires.
46. Jean-Jacques Rousseau, La Nouvelle Héloise, ed. Daniel Mornet (Paris, 1923),
vol. 1.
47. The Bibliothéque universelle de romans is a good instrument for identification.
248 Notes to pages 122-130
48. The manuscript registers of book licenses make it possible to reexamine certain
problems in literary history, such as the one raised by Georges May—in a remarkable work
(Le dilemme du roman au XVIIIe siècle: étude sur les rapports du roman et de la critique,
1715-1761 [Paris, 1963])—concerning the ban on novels imposed by Chancelier d’Agues-
seau in 1738. Citing the bibliography compiled by S. Paul Jones for the first half of the
eighteenth century (A List of French Prose Fiction, New York, 1939), May rests his
argument on the paucity of new novels published in Paris in 1738. According to May, only
six novels appeared, of which one, in fact (Essai sur la nécessité et les moyens de plaire, by
Paradis de Moncrif), is essentially a moral treatise followed, it is true, by a tale. But an
examination of the registers of printing-license requests shows that between 20 February
1737—the date given by May as that of the enactment of the ban—and the end of 1738, the
number of new, authorized novels was considerably greater. Admittedly, during the same
period, the censors turned down some twenty novels, including both new titles and reprints.
Chapter 7
having bred the false and ridiculous argument of those who say that Hugh Capet handed
over his land, fiefs, and real estate to his new subjects to reward them for having made him
king. From this argument a most abominable conclusion has been drawn, namely, that all
property belongs to the king, and that he is entitled to leave to his subjects whatever part of
it he pleases.”’
13. In the “Dissertation abrégée sur les premiers Français et leur origine,” which
concludes the Essais sur la noblesse de France (Amsterdam, 1732), Boulainvilliers goes so
far as to reassure those whom despotism has ennobled: ‘“‘As for the new nobles and the
anoblis, they have nothing to fear from our undertaking. Our views are summary, simple,
and innocent. They never descend explicitly to an examination of particular cases. Such
persons can therefore peacefully enjoy their metamorphosis.”
14. Mably, De la Législation.
15. Boulainvilliers, “Mémoire pour la construction d’un nobiliaire général,” Ecole
Supérieure de la Guerre (Paris), Ms. 25-26: “The old nobility has no means for guaran-
teeing its status; some of these nobles have lost their patents and charters in the course of
foreign and civil wars, and, with the exception of those families whose names remain in
history, they are left with only partial evidence, which is bound to perish through an infinity
of accidents.” Moreover, Boulainvilliers makes his purpose quite clear: ‘“‘the old nobility
[must be able to] distinguish itself from the new nobility, the nobility granted by individual
patent or consecutive to the ownership of certain offices. . . .”
16. Boulainvilliers, Histoire.
17. Boulainvilliers, Abrégé de l'Histoire de France (The Hague: Gesse et Néaulme,
1733): ‘‘Belles-lettres, after languishing for a long time, buried under the bad taste of earlier
centuries, reemerged in this century in all their brilliance... .”
18. Mably, Observations sur l'Histoire de France (Geneva: Par la Compagnie des
Libraires, 1765).
19. Mably, De la Législation.
20. Mably, De l’étude de |’Histoire: Mably cites the case of certain Swiss cantons as an
example of this ingenious arrangement.
21. Mably, Entretiens de Phocion (Amsterdam, 1763).
22. This is the solution Mably advocates in De la Législation: ‘The nobility must have a
patrimony that it cannot increase; on no account must the nobility be allowed to possess land
or inheritances intended for another order of citizens. . . .”
Chapter 8
Chapter 9
1. 2 vols. (1768-69).
2. Ibid., 2:176.
3. J.-P. Brissot, Examen critique des voyages dans l'Amérique septentrionale de M. le
marquis de Chastellux (Paris, 1786).
4. Ibid., 105-6.
5. Mazzei, Recherches historiques et politiques sur les Etats-Unis de l'Amérique septen-
trionale ... , 4 vols. (Paris, 1788).
6. Crévecceur, Lettres d’un cultivateur américain (Paris, 1784). [Retranslated here from
the French edition: the passages quoted do not correspond precisely to the original English
text.—TRANS. ]
7. Ibid., ‘‘deuxième lettre.”
8. Ibid.
9. This study is in progress, thanks to the able survey of parliamentary speeches of the
French revolutionary period being conducted by Mme Edna Lemay, maitre-assistant at the
Ecole des Hautes Etudes en Sciences Sociales.
10. Tocqueville, L’Ancien Régime et la Révolution (Paris: Gallimard, 1953), vol. 2,
chap. 7: 131-32.
11. Reprint of Le Moniteur, 1:142.
12. Letter quoted in Gilbert Chinard, Volney et l'Amérique d’après des documents
inédits (Baltimore and Paris, 1923), 63-66.
13. Volney, Tableau du climat et du sol des Etats-Unis (Paris, 1883), preface. The
quotations that follow are also taken from the preface.
Chapter 10
1. The fundamental work on Tocqueville’s journey to the United States is still that of G.
W. Pierson, Tocqueville and Beaumont in America (New York: Oxford University Press,
1938).
2. Tocqueville and Beaumont’s plan for a fact-finding visit was set out in Note sur le
système pénitentiaire et sur la mission confiée par Monsieur le Ministre de l'Intérieur à MM.
Gustave de Beaumont et Alexis de Tocqueville (1831). Their findings were published in 1833.
A second, two-volume edition appeared in 1836, with a long introduction: Du système
pénitentiaire aux Etats-Unis et de son application en France, suivi d'un appendice sur les
colonies pénales et de notes statistiques. A third edition, expanded to include Tocqueville’s
legislative work on the penitentiary problem, was published in 1845.
3. Correspondance d’Alexis de Tocqueville et de Gustave de Beaumont (Œuvres com-
plètes, 8), 1:105-6.
4. René Rémond, Les Etats-Unis devant l'opinion française, 2 vols. (Paris: Armand
Colin, 1962), esp. vol. 2, chap. 7.
5. André Jardin, “L’ Amérique et les Américains vus par Tocqueville,’ H-Histoire, no.
4 (March 1980): 227—-40.
6. See esp. Tocqueville’s letter to Gustave de Beaumont of 5 October 1828 (Corres-
pondance Tocqueville-Beaumont, 1: 47-71).
7. Correspondance d’Alexis de Tocqueville et de Louis de Kergorlay (Œuvres complètes,
13), 1:373-75.
8. Actually, Saint-Beuve attributes this statement to “a very judicious and very respect-
able person,” adding a commentary of his own: ‘consequently, [Tocqueville’s] thoughts
were sometimes shallow.” See Sainte-Beuve, Causeries du lundi, 3rd ed., vol. 15.
9. H. de Tocqueville, Histoire philosophique du régne de Louis XV, 2 vols. (Paris,
1847).
Notes to pages 170-193 251
Chapter 12
Chapter 13
253
254 Index
Erceville, Rolland d,’ 83 Gibbon, Edward, 81, 88, 97; The De-
Errera, Roger, 212 cline and Fall of the Roman Empire,
Erudition, 77-82, 128 140-49
Esprit des lois, L’ (Montesquieu), 105, Girard, Patrick, 212-14
110, 164 Girondins, 157, 160
Esquisse d'un tableau historique des pro- Glorious Revolution, 90
grès de l'esprit humain (Condorcet), Goths, 147
141 Goubert, Pierre, 52
Essai (Montesquieu), 142 Great Sanhedrin, 212
Estivals, Robert, 100, 103 Greece, ancient: America versus, 158,
Ethnology, 7-8, 17-18, 29-39, 68-74 159; and history, 55, 77, 92; Mably
Event, historical, 11-12, 49, 51, 55-57, on, 129
71-72 Guedj, Rabbi, 221
Guizot, François, 28, 168, 190; and
history in France, 88-91, 96, 98
Fabre-Luce, Alfred, 222-24
Family, and urban crisis, 198
Fanon, Frantz, 29 Haam, Ahad, 237, 239
Fascism, 28, 35 Haganah, 237
Febvre, Lucien, 1-4, 111 Harris, André, 220-22
Ferguson, Adam, 145 Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, 34, 37
Feudalism, 133-35 Helvetius, Claude-Adrien, 109, 114
Fidélité et Utopie (Scholem), 227 Henriade (Voltaire), 108
Fleury, André-Hercule de, 108 Henry II of France, 47
Fonds Séguier, 46-47 Henry IV of France, 46
Fontenelle, Bernard Le Bovier, Sieur Herzl, Theodore, 225, 235-37
de, 80 Histoire critique du Vieux Testament
Ford, Gerald, 205 (Simon), 78
Fortoul, 90 Histoire de l'Ancien Gouvernement de la
Foucault, Michel, 34-35 France (Boulainvilliers), 127
Franklin, Benjamin, 155 Histoire des empereurs (Tillemont),
Franks, 129, 131, 135, 147 79-80
French Revolution, 27-28, 30, 46, 131; History, definitions of: histoire des men-
and American Revolution, 157-60, talités, 15-18, 64-65; histoire
164-65; and Enlightenment, 123; and événementielle, 48-49, 71-72; narra-
Jews, 211, 215, 235, 239; Lavisse on, tive, 8-9, 54-56; political, 9; serial,
93-94; Lévi-Strauss on, 33-34; Marx 42, 58, 73; ‘‘total,”” 5-6, 67, 70
on, 193; and nationhood, 125, Hitler, Adolf, 70, 215-18, 231, 235-41
138-39; and teaching of history, 85- passim
98; and Tocqueville, 169-71, 185-86, Hoffman, Stanley, 223
195-96; and two types of history, Holocaust, 211, 221, 230, 232-33,
10-11 238-41
Fréres des Ecoles Chrétiennes, 84 Hundred Years’ War, 93
Freud, Sigmund, 20, 32, 64, 141 Hugo, Victor, 27-28
Fronde, 34, 125 Humanism, 69, 142
Fustel de Coulanges, Numa-Denis, 91 Hyde de Neuville, Jean-Guillaume,
Baron, 168
Garaudy, 37
Garibaldi, Giuseppe, 237 Ideologies, end of, 27-31
Gaullism, 27, 31, 232 Idéologues, 86-87, 97, 162-63
Gauls, 130, 135 India, 7
Genesis, Book of, 36 “Instructions” (Lavisse), 92, 94
Geography, 72, 82, 85, 115 Irgun, 237
Germanic tribes, 129-38, 146-47 Islam, 29, 148, 227, 239-40
256 Index
Israel, 23, 211; and French Jews, Lévi-Strauss, Claude, 22, 30-39, 73; La
221-22; and French Left, 230-33; and Pensée sauvage, 31-36
Scholem, 228-29; and Zionism, Libraires, 101-22
234-41 Lindsay, John, 200
Livy, 77, 78, 82
Jabotinsky, Vladimir, 237 Louis Philippe, 89-90, 185
Jacobins, 30, 96, 166, 230, 231; and Louis XI of France, 93
American Revolution, 162; tradition Louis XIII of France, 47
of, and French Jews, 211, 221 Louis XIV of France, 7, 81, 102, 140,
Jacquerie, 46-47 163, 170; and nobility, 126, 137;
Jansenists, 82-83, 105, 114, 117, 119 and Port-Royal, 82, 83; and Voltaire,
Jefferson, Thomas, 158 55, 69
Jews, Judaism, 22-23, 207-41; and Louis XV of France, 100, 120, 169-70
blacks in America, 205 Louis XVI of France, 100, 101
Jivaro, 34-35 Louis XVIII of France, 88
Johnson, Lyndon, 201, 203 Lueger, Karl, 235
July Monarchy: development of history Luria, Isaac, 227
during, 89-91, 96, 98; and equality,
185; Jews under, 213, 214 Mabillon, Jean, 79
Mably, Gabriel Bonnet de, 97, 109,
125-39, 146-47
Kant, Immanuel, 36
Malesherbes, Chrétien-Guillaume de
Kapital, Das (Marx), 35
Lamoignon de, 100-110, 114
Kennedy, John F., 203
Malthus, Thomas, 51, 62
Kergorlay, Louis de, 168, 170
Manchester, 71
Klatzkin, Jacob, 236-37
Manuel de l'auteur et du libraire, 101
Kriegel, Annie, 215
Marriage: age at, 61-65; Tocqueville
Kriegel, Maurice, 222
on, 186-87
Marrus, Michael, 213-20
Labrousse, Ernest, 45 Martin, Henri-Jean, 111
La Chalotais, Louis René de Caradeuc Marx, Karl, 28, 70, 71, 233, 238;
de, 83 Das Kapital, 35; Lévi-Strauss com-
La Fayette, marquis de, 157, 168 pared with, 32, 36; Sartre compared
Lakanal, Joseph, 86 with, 34; Tocqueville compared with,
Languedoc, 50-51, 109-10 171-72, 192-96
La Popeliniére, 69 Marxism, 3, 4, 16, 20, 46, 57, 123; of
La Rochefoucauld, 162 French intellectuals, 27-39; and
La Rochelle, Drieu, 28 Israel, 230-33
Laslett, Peter, 17 Maurras, Charles, 28, 217
Laval, Pierre, 218-19 Mauss, Marcel, 31
Lavisse, Ernest, 92-94, 96 May, Georges, 122
Lazare, Bernard, 214, 227 Mazzei, 158
Leach, Edmund, 36 Mazzini, Giuseppe, 237
Le Bossu, René, 115 Mémoires de Trévoux, 105
Legon inaugurale (Lévi-Strauss), 33 Mémoires pour servir à l'histoire ecclé-
Ledoux, Claude-Nicolas, 119 siastique (Tillemont), 79
Lefebvre, Georges, 11 Mémoire sur les problèmes de la librairie
Lenin, 28, 29, 37 (Malesherbes), 102, 104
Lenôtre, Georges, 19 Mentalités, 15-18, 64-65
Le Roy Ladurie, Emmanuel, 3, Messianisme juif (Scholem), 212
50-51, 62 Mézeray, François Eudes de, 128
Lettres de Madame de Maintenon, 108-9 Michelet, Jules, 89-91, 98
Lettres sur l'Amérique du Nord (Cheva- Mirabeau, 110, 157, 161
lier), 178 Molé, Louis-Mathieu, Comte, 172
Index 257
D * En .
€ 7
reas QE 1e
'
To (arr Re «
L TT CE
perty vs
==
zs
D. LA d te
» en
| A
=. .
: Coque.
mA
Tr
ve
e D.
SRE
ÈS
à
sepsnree
sectgeeecti=
cé > Te +
frà yee $2 SFIS
<: i
Sterne SS: RS, ase Der Pise
=e
PARIS 3 NS:
+
Foie orme
ES: nier es AE
SE DR easasrso te LE
HE
HAE FEDEIRE HSE
=
SRE
BUS
HSE
Eat
Peat ettees ee
ae
HR
He
RITES
re
ERNST RER
LT:
FE
a
de
ost Gesen ee
FE
RES