Stern 1936
Stern 1936
Stern 1936
"pure" theory of law any more than other philosophers before him.18
But this failure, taken in itself, would not impair the value of his theories.
As stated by Mr. Jones:17 ". . . if in justifying the supremacy of inter-
national law by reference to ethical and political postulates, Kelsen, like
Austin in his digression into Utilitarianism, leaves his chosen path of
logical deduction, this at least may be said—that without his ideal of
an international community, international law would never have come
into existence."
Kelsen's conception of a unitary legal system, headed by international
law, has been criticized both often and sharply. Even though many
would be inclined to accept a monistic legal theory, the fact cannot be
overlooked that, according to Kelsen's own statement, the choice of inter-
national law as the hypothetical fundamental norm is purely arbitrary.
It has been said of Kelsen's reasoning18 that it "seems to fly in the face
of the facts of the present day." But only the future can tell whether or
not Kelsen idealized the present international status.
It remains to consider Kelsen's deontological conception. As purist,
Kelsen believes that he has eliminated the ideological element from his
legal theory. He is led to his deontological conception by his Neo-Kantian
schooling, and his views are a reaction to a time in which insistence on
rights was usual and in which duties to the community were neglected,
or even, as in international life, denied. Kelsen turns from a conception
which over-emphasizes rights to a theory which considers duties, obliga-
tions, as primary norms, and authorizations (Berechtigungen) as second-
ary norms. From a purely logical point of view, these secondary norms
are even irrelevant for Kelsen's theory. One may raise the question
whether a legal system which balances rights and duties would not be of
greater service.
Thus, a relativist approach to the questions involved might force one
to question Kelsen's success as positivist, to discard his purism as well as
his deontological conception, and to refer his monistic conception of the
world order to the field of political speculation. Nevertheless, the author
of the Reine Rechtslehre must be credited with at least one achievement.
With the irresistible force of exact logical reasoning, he analyzes weak
points in present-day juristic conceptions and thus contributes to steady
advancement in legal philosophical thinking.
W. B. STERN.
Johns Hopkins University.
16
See Karl Bergbohm, Jurisprudenz und Rechtsphilosophie (1882), Vol. 1, p. 279-
17
Loc. cit., p. 19.
18
J. Walter Jones, loc. cit., p. 13.