Joseph Raz - Notes On Value and Objectivity
Joseph Raz - Notes On Value and Objectivity
Joseph Raz - Notes On Value and Objectivity
Edited by
Brian Leiter
University of Texas, Austin
CAMBRIDGE
UNIVERSITY PRESS
CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS
Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore, Sao Paulo
Published in the United States of America by Cambridge University Press, New York
www.cambridge.org
Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9780521554305
A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library
Contributors page IX
Acknowledgments xi
Introduction 1
BRIAN LEITER
Legal Interpretation, Objectivity, and Morality 12
DAVID O. BRINK
Objectivity, Morality, and Adjudication 66
BRIAN LEITER
Objectivity Fit for Law 99
GERALD J. POSTEMA
Objective Values: Does Metaethics Rest on a Mistake? 144
SIGRUN SVAVARSDOTTIR
Notes on Value and Objectivity 194
JOSEPH RAZ
Embracing Objectivity in Ethics 234
PHILIP PETTIT
Pathetic Ethics 287
DAVID SOSA
Bibliography 331
Index 351
5
Notes on Value and Objectivity
JOSEPH RAZ
A. Introduction
It is natural that we should be interested in the nature of objectivity in general
and in the objectivity or otherwise of practical thought in particular. In one of
its senses objectivity is a precondition of knowledge. It also demarcates a type
of thought1 that is importantly different from others.
In this chapter our interest is in one way in which various types of thought
differ. They are subject to different disciplines. Suppose, for example, that I say
"I will be a good teacher" and you tell me: "But you have tried and failed for
years," "I may reply by saying: "So what? That does not stop me from
daydreaming," a response that is inappropriate if the thought expresses a belief.
This is but one example of one aspect of what I called the different
"disciplines" to which a thought or the holding of a thought can be subjected, a
difference that marks the distinction between classes of thoughts and of ways
of holding them. These disciplines determine whether my thought and yours,
which have the same content, belong to the same type.
Of some thoughts, for example, it is possible to say, "They were mistaken,"
whereas of others this is inappropriate. A closely connected mark is that having
or holding some thoughts can constitute knowledge. I mean that the fact I think
that a general election was held in Italy yesterday is part of what makes it true
that I know that a general election took place in Italy yesterday.
We mark this distinction between classes of thoughts that can constitute
knowledge and can be mistaken and those that cannot by calling the first
objective and the others subjective. When we ask whether practical thought is
objective or subjective we are asking whether it is subject to one type of
discipline or another. So the inquiry is natural and important. In the first part of
I am grateful to Peter Hacker and especially to Brian Leiter for comments on an earlier draft.
Notes on Value and Objectivity 195
the chapter ("The Long Route") I will say something in general about the way
we can characterize and explain objectivity in abstract terms. Parts II and III
attempt to allay certain doubts about the objectivity of practical thought. Part II
deals with the fact that practical concepts are parochial and not universally
accessible to all. Part III deals with the social dependence of practical concepts.
in general. We may also have to enter into the morass of determining what
propositions are about. And there are further difficulties in store.
David Wiggins seems to sidestep these problems when he says that "A
subject matter is objective (or relates to an objective reality) if and only if there
are questions about it (and enough questions about it) that admit of answers
that are substantially true — simply and plainly true."5 The qualification "sub-
stantially true" puts us on our guard, however. It would seem that in order to
gain an understanding of objectivity we need to resolve issues concerning
various kinds of truths.6
Trying to sidestep these issues as well I suggested at the beginning of this
article that a domain is objective if it is capable of being the object of knowl-
edge, if propositions that belong to it can state what one knows, thoughts that
belong to it can manifest what one knows. If only true propositions can be
known, and only true thoughts can express one's knowledge, domains are
objective in this sense only if thoughts, propositions, and statements that be-
long to them can be true or false. But problems are to be found here too. If there
can be aspects of reality that it is logically impossible for us (but who are "us"?
The human race? Or all agents capable of knowing something? Or each one of
us?) to know anything about, then while the objectivity of a domain is a
precondition of knowledge, the reverse is not the case. We cannot say that a
domain is objective only if it can express knowledge, that is, express what is
knowable. There may be (objective domains of) propositions that state how
things are regarding matters of which it is impossible to have any knowledge.
This is one reason why I will not try to define domain-objectivity or to give
necessary and sufficient conditions for the objectivity of domains. Rather I will
attempt to elucidate the notion by considering a number of conditions that
partially characterize it.
While the epistemic and domain senses of objectivity are obviously interre-
lated, they differ in important respects. When judging someone or some opin-
ions to be epistemically objective (or lacking objectivity), one presupposes that
the matter which is so judged is domain-objective. In other words, domain-
objectivity marks the fact that we are dealing with a domain about which one
can be objective in the epistemic sense, and statements that are domain-
objective are those that can also be epistemically objective.
One way in which the two clusters of senses differ is in the responsibility7 of
people who are or are not, or whose opinions are or are not, objective in the
various senses. People should be epistemically objective and their opinions
should not be epistemically subjective. They are responsible for failing to be as
they should, for such failures are due to biases and other distortions of their
cognitive functioning for which people are held responsible. Their responsibil-
ity for their failures of epistemic objectivity does not assume that knowledge is
a good that they should pursue. It only means that they should not form
198 JOSEPH RAZ
judgments that are tainted by bias. Even though in some of its variants noted
above epistemic responsibility is a matter of ability rather than performance, it
is an ability the presence or lack of which can only be established by perfor-
mance. Hence those who lack it are those who are lacking in performance.8
The only responsibility that can arise if an area of inquiry or judgments
about it are domain-subjective is responsibility for failure to realize that the
domain is subjective. There can be, of course, no responsibility for these
matters or judgments being subjective. This is just how things are. Nor for that
matter can people be responsible for treating matters subjectively in these
cases, for there is nothing else they can properly do.
It is crucial to notice that in no sense is objectivity identified with truth,
though in all of them it is related more or less indirectly to truth. Thoughts that
are objective can be the subject of knowledge, and they are expressed in
propositions that can be true or false (or correct or incorrect). People who are
epistemically objective judges of certain matters are not free from error in
those matters. They are merely free from errors arising out of biases and an
emotionally blinkered inability to respond to the evidence and evaluate it.
Statements and opinions that are epistemically objective are those that are
neither reached nor sustained through biases of this kind. But obviously they
can be false or mistaken for other reasons. Epistemic objectivity is closely
associated with rationality. It is a condition of being a rational judge of certain
matters that one is epistemically objective regarding them. Being objective is
not, however, sufficient to make one a rational judge. Various inabilities may
undermine one's rationality that do not arise out of bias but are a result of
cognitive incompetence, hastiness, and like defects that do not undermine
one's objectivity.
is, only if the fact that I think that things are so and so does not constitute their
being so and so (some self-referential thoughts are the exception).9
context. And (b) they allow that there can be reasons of an appropriate kind,
that is, reasons whose existence makes such beliefs true.
Two further important conditions derive from Bernard Williams's discus-
sion of the absolute conception of reality (about which more will be said
below). In advancing the absolute conception Williams was concerned with the
conditions for the possibility of knowledge. His discussion is therefore relevant
to objectivity understood as a mark of domains of thoughts that could con-
stitute knowledge. Williams introduces the discussion by saying: "If knowl-
edge is what it claims to be, then it is knowledge of a reality which exists
independently of that knowledge. . . . Knowledge is of what is there any-
way. "ll This thought yields the condition of objectivity which can be formu-
lated as follows:
objectivity, for it does not yield a comprehensive set of conditions, the satisfac-
tion of which is necessary and sufficient for a domain to be objective, and that
provide an adequate explanation of objectivity beyond the need for further
refinement and adjustment. Any set of conditions, however successful they
may be in answering the questions and concerns that led to their formulation,
will need to be refined as new problems emerge. It is in principle impossible to
circumvent the long route by providing a set of necessary and sufficient condi-
tions that will never call for revision and refinement and from which all the
other necessary features of objectivity can be deduced. It is not possible to
argue for this impossibility here. It depends, first, on the fact that propositions
are open to somewhat different interpretations, that they are all inherently
vague and therefore, even if true, may call for further refinement to meet the
needs of new puzzles and hitherto unexplored questions.17 It depends, second,
on the ever-present possibility that new questions will emerge forcing us to
notice and articulate new conditions of objectivity. Perhaps the following could
serve as an example of another condition that does not follow from the above
and that may illustrate how more and more may emerge with emerging reasons
to think of them:
they constitute beliefs, that to hold such thoughts is to have certain beliefs, and
that means that these thoughts can be true or false and that holding them can in
principle amount to knowledge. This shows, the argument proceeds, that
whether they are objective cannot just be a matter of how we treat them. It is a
question of what the world really is like, a question about how things are in the
world.
Here is my problem: Domains of thought are objective, I suggested at the
outset, only if they are subject to disciplines that make them capable of con-
stituting knowledge, and so on. The charge against the way I explained this
route to an explanation of objectivity was that it led to an articulation of what
we take to be the conditions of knowledge, rather than what really are the
conditions of knowledge. It may seem that the only way to justify my position
is to deny that the two can differ. But that would imply that we cannot be wrong
about the conditions of knowledge, which seems too strong a claim. In fact it is
not needed. All I need to argue for is that, necessarily, our knowledge or
understanding of the conditions of objectivity depends on our knowledge or
understanding of the conditions of knowledge. If our knowledge or under-
standing of one of these concepts is imperfect so is our knowledge or under-
standing of the other.
Whether our thoughts are true or not is immaterial to their objective charac-
ter, but they must, among other things, be capable of being true or false, of
bearing a truth-value. Therefore, they cannot amount to knowledge unless they
are about how things are anyway, about the world as it is independently of
these thoughts. That means (given that the character of domains of thought
depends on the disciplines to which we subject them) that they cannot be about
reality unless we treat them as about how things are independently of thought
about them.
As so far stated, these considerations do not show more than that satisfying
the conditions spelled out above, and others derived in like manner, is neces-
sary for a domain of thought to be objective. But their implications reach
further:
First, it is not the case that this approach allows that what is objective is "up
to us." That would mean that we can choose whether to regard matters of taste
or morality as objective. But the account I suggested has no such consequence.
Second, notice that these conditions do more than point to surface syntacti-
cal features, for example, that the thoughts are expressed in indicative sen-
tences, allow embedding, et cetera. They assume the practices that Wright
regards as underlying what he calls "the minimalist" account of truth.20
Wright's account has convinced some writers that nothing of substance de-
pends on allowing that propositions and utterances can be true or false, given
the minimalist account of truth.21 The condition of relevance, however, takes
my explanation of objectivity beyond the conditions that, according to Wright,
have to be satisfied for a truth predicate to apply to a domain.
Notes on Value and Objectivity 203
so. Someone who does not know anything at all about what may count as
evidence in favor of the proposition that Gubaidulina is a great composer, or
that this chair is not comfortable, or that Everest is the highest mountain on
earth, does not really know what it is to be a composer or a mountain, and so
forth. If upon hearing the claim that Gubaidulina is a great composer someone
replies, "Oh yes? Does she eat fish?" then, barring a peculiar sense of humor,
his remarks reveal that he has not understood what he was told. Such misunder-
standings are often used in popular humor to expose the ignorance and pretense
of social climbers. Examples like this would show that part of understanding
any concept is having some grasp of what counts as relevant evidence showing
that it applies or does not apply.
At the same time, the fact that one thing or another is evidence for the
existence of something, or for its possession of some property, tells us some-
thing about the nature of these existences: material things are those whose
existence and properties can be established one way, mathematical objects and
properties are those that are established in very different ways, et cetera. In
sum, the relevance conditions straddle the divide between the semantic, epis-
temic, and metaphysical. It requires more than knowledge of connections
among concepts. It requires knowledge of the way things are in the world is
relevant to the application of concepts.
The interdependence of the different aspects (semantic, metaphysical, and
epistemic) reveals itself in the way arguments regarding problem cases pro-
ceed. There is a striking correlation between those philosophers who think that
there are "Non-Naturalistic" moral properties and those who believes that
moral predicates refer to such properties. Mackie is the only philosopher who
believes that moral predicates refer to nonnatural properties, but that there are
no such properties, nor can there be. Apart from him, those who believe that
moral statements are "semantically objective" also believe that there are moral
properties, and — some argue — since there are no nonnatural properties, moral
properties must be natural properties. Those who believe that there are no
moral properties opt for a noncognitive interpretation of moral utterances and
so on. The same is true regarding secondary qualities. Even Mackie does not
offer an error theory of secondary qualities or of mathematical properties. In all
these cases one's view of the nature of the properties that exist and one's view
of the semantics of the relevant range of predicates go hand in hand. They are
interdependent and, needless to say, so are the relevant evidential criteria. That
is why I claimed that domain-objectivity combines semantic, epistemic, and
metaphysical criteria.
The interdependence of the semantic and metaphysical is recognized and
explained by Crispin Wright. He argues that, if one believes, as error theorists
like Mackie and Field do, that even though propositions asserting the existence
of ethical (or mathematical or other) properties are false, we need not radically
change our use of them for they serve some other valid purpose, then one has to
Notes on Value and Objectivity 205
explain why not accepting that truth in that domain is constituted by serving
that purpose. In his words: "why insist on construing truth for moral discourse
in terms which motivate a charge of global error, rather than explicate it in
terms of the satisfaction of the putative subsidiary norm [what I called "the
valuable purpose"], whatever it is? The question may have a good answer. . . .
But I do not know of promising argument in that direction."24 That is the sort of
consideration that led me to claim that domain-objectivity combines semantic,
epistemic, and metaphysical criteria.
In spite of these points doubts are likely to linger. While not being conserva-
tive, the criteria I mentioned are all in some sense internal to the ways we treat
thoughts in the domain in question. Is there no possibility that a domain will
meet these criteria and yet fail to be objective simply because of how things
are? In principle the answer is affirmative. Since the long route deals with
problems as they are encountered, and denies the feasibility of producing a
definitive list of necessary and sufficient conditions for objectivity, the (epis-
temic) possibility that factors may emerge that defeat the objectivity of do-
mains of thought that meet the above conditions cannot be ruled out. All we
can do is examine specific doubts regarding the objectivity of practical
thought. The rest of this chapter consists in dispelling two specific sources of
such doubt that have attracted considerable attention.
impossible for us to understand. By the same token, many of our interests were
beyond the reach of people in previous generations, and so were the concepts
mastery of which depends on understanding these interests.
The impossibility of acquiring concepts that presuppose interests remote
from those we have and that do not yet exist (and therefore cannot be mastered
or discovered by simulation) is sufficient to show that practically all concepts
that can be acquired only by people who understand some nonuniversal inter-
ests are parochial concepts. Regarding all of them, there was a time when they
were beyond the reach of people living at that time. There is, however, yet
another type of limitation on people's ability in principle to master such con-
cepts: habituation and simulation are demanding and relatively slow processes.
You often have to immerse yourself in an alien culture, understand its con-
cerns, religious and other beliefs, come to understand how people normally
react in many (to them normal) situations, share —at least in imagination-their
hopes, fears, and aspirations. All these factors mean that even if there is no
interest-dependent concept one cannot acquire, it is in principle possible for
any person to master only a relatively small number of such concepts and
hence, given the length and diversity of human history, impossible in principle
for anyone living today to master more than a fraction of the interest-dependent
concepts that pertain to different human societies now, or did in the past, even
if we leave aside the future.25
If interest-related concepts are parochial, so are evaluative or normative
concepts, for they are all interest-related (not, of course, in "serving" the
interests of the agent, but in the fact that mastery of the concept requires
understanding some interests or others). This is evident when we consider
relatively specific, so called thick, concepts, like the excellence of an opera or a
novel. But the same is true of our abstract normative concepts such as those
designated by the terms "duty," "obligation," "ought," "a right," "valuable,"
"good," "beautiful," "person," "happiness," "pleasure." The history of these
terms, and the attempt to find terms of comparable meaning in other languages,
show how their meaning mutated over time and how different languages differ
in their abstract normative vocabulary. It is reasonable to conclude that abstract
normative concepts too are parochial.
Doubts have been cast on the objectivity of parochial concepts, on the
possibility of knowledge that depends on their possession and cannot be refor-
mulated without their use. I will examine some grounds for such doubts.
distinction, which differs from any I have mentioned so far. "A view or form of
thought is more objective than another if it relies less on the specifics of the
individual's makeup and position in the world, or on the character of the
particular type of creature he is." 26 In other words, Nagel calls a view or
thought subjective if it essentially depends on employing parochial concepts
for its expression. The greater its dependence on parochial concepts the more
subjective it is.
For Nagel "objectivity is a method of understanding."27 It seems to be a
method of understanding reality with different aspects of reality being under-
stood depending on the degree of objectivity attained in the method of under-
standing them: "We may think of reality as a set of concentric spheres, progres-
sively revealed as we detach gradually from the contingencies of the self"
{Nowhere, 5). This sentence may suggest that the more objective our method of
understanding the more of reality we come to know and understand. But this is
not Nagel's meaning, or at least it is only part of his meaning. While some
aspects of reality reveal themselves only as they are objectively investigated,
others are lost except when understood through subjective methods. "The
attempt to give a complete account of the world in objective terms . . . inevita-
bly leads to false reductions or to outright denial that certain patently real
phenomena exist at all" {Nowhere, 7). In particular, "[t]he subjectivity of
consciousness is an irreducible feature of reality" (ibid.), which presumably
means that it can only be fully known and understood with the use of subjective
methods, including the use of parochial concepts. Nagel seems to think that
only the mental requires parochial concepts for its understanding.
Although there is a connection between objectivity and reality — only the supposition
that we and our appearances [this seems to mean here: how things appear to us, not how
we appear to others — JR] are part of a larger reality makes it reasonable to seek
understanding by stepping back from the appearances in this way — still not all reality is
better understood the more objectively it is viewed. Appearance and perspective are
essential parts of what there is, and in some respects they are best understood from a less
detached standpoint. Realism underlines the claims of objectivity and detachment, but it
supports them only up to a point. {Nowhere, 4)
But how can we know that no other aspect of reality requires parochial
concepts for its understanding? Perhaps the thought is that since the mental is
subjective it requires subjective concepts for its understanding. But that
thought is guilty of the fallacy of equivocation: Thought is subjective in the
psychological sense that means simply that it is mental. The "method of sub-
jectivity" as a method of knowledge does not mean knowing in a way which
involves mental states, dispositions, or capacities. All knowing involves the
mental in these ways, be it knowledge obtained by more or less objective
methods. "The method of subjectivity" means knowledge that can only be
obtained by the use of parochial concepts. To avoid equivocation the thought
208 JOSEPH RAZ
should be: parochial concepts, and thoughts involving them, can only be under-
stood with the use of parochial concepts. That amounts to claiming that paro-
chial concepts cannot be eliminated. If they are necessary for knowledge of
certain matters, then those matters cannot be known "objectively." That would
not justify the conclusion that only the mental can be understood by the use of
parochial concepts.
Perhaps I am wrong to identify Nagel's understanding of the objective/
subjective distinction with reliance on and the use of concepts that are more or
less parochial? Perhaps all he means is that the mental can be understood only
with the use of psychological concepts? He certainly believes the latter, but that
is not all he is claiming.
The more objective our understanding the more detached it is from our
specific situation, specific capacities, et cetera. To quote Nagel again: the more
objective the thought the less it relies "on the specifics of the individual's
makeup and position in the world, or on the character of the particular type of
creature he is." These specifics constitute what he calls the special perspective
of that creature. Objective knowledge, like any other knowledge, is obtained
within that perspective, but it does not rely on it. It can be shared by people
whose perspectives are different. Subjective knowledge cannot be shared in
this way. It is available only to those who share the same perspective.
My suggestion is that perspectives can be identified by the range of con-
cepts that those who inhabit them can possess. This does not exhaust the
differences between perspectives, but the others follow from the inability of
those who inhabit a perspective to possess certain concepts. The possession of
concepts, let us remind ourselves, involves certain mental abilities, certain
perceptual abilities, and certain experiences. For example, inability to master
mathematical concepts makes one incapable of possessing a whole range of
scientific concepts, the lack of sight makes the understanding of color concepts
incomplete, and those who never desired anything cannot understand what it is
to want something.
So the more objective knowledge is the less does its possession presuppose.
It presupposes fewer common mental abilities, fewer common perceptual abil-
ities, and fewer common experiences. If that is so we can understand why
knowledge of the nature of thought is more objective than knowledge of the
nature of Christianity. To understand the nature of thought one needs to have
the capacity for thought, but other things being equal, this capacity is available
to anyone capable of thinking. These may include Martians, automata, and
others, besides humans. Knowledge of Christianity requires concepts such as
salvation, redemption, and love that need not be available to all who are
capable of knowledge. Hence it is more subjective.
This line of thought can explain some aspects of Nagel's position. But it
does not seem to explain some of its basic tenets. First, it does not explain why
all knowledge of the mental is more subjective. Since only people with a
Notes on Value and Objectivity 209
mental life are capable of knowledge none is excluded from the perspective
that involves at least some mental concepts. Second, it does not explain why
only the mental defies complete objectivity. It does not answer the question:
Why should we assume that there are no aspects of reality that can be known or
understood only by creatures with specific capacities and experiences, that are
incompatible with the capacities needed to understand other aspects of reality?
Nagel seems bereft of an argument which will limit his "subjective method" of
knowledge to the mental only.28
Can we really distinguish between some concepts or propositions which figure in the
conception of the world without observers, and others that do not? Are not all our
concepts ours . . . ? Of course; but there is no suggestion that we should try to describe a
world without ourselves using any concepts, or without using concepts which we,
human beings, can understand. The suggestion is that there are possible descriptions of
the world using concepts which are not peculiarly ours, and not peculiarly relative to our
experience. Such a description would be that which would be arrived at, as C. S. Peirce
put it, if scientific enquiry continued long enough; it is the content of that "final opinion"
which Peirce believed that enquiry would inevitably converge upon, a final opinion . . .
independent not indeed of thought in general, but of all that is arbitrary and individual in
thought.29
The scientific representation of the material world can be the point of convergence of
the Peircean enquirer precisely because it does not have among its concepts any which
reflect merely a local interest, taste or sensory peculiarity. . . . This extended conception
would then be that absolute conception of reality.30
And Williams contrasts this view with that of a critic who maintains that
"scientific theories are a cultural product which it would be senseless to sup-
pose could be freed from local relativities."31
The motivating concern leading to the priority condition seems to be the
need to establish the credentials of our knowledge claims and of our concepts.
We need to know that through our concepts we can understand the world as it is
independently of us, that our thoughts are no mere shadows cast by our own
concepts. Therefore, any view or thought that claims to be knowledge must
meet a test that is concept-independent, or — given the impossibility of thought
without concepts — that is at least independent of any concepts that are not
accessible to everyone. That test is the Peirceian convergence of all those who
210 JOSEPH RAZ
them from becoming aware of certain aspects of the world that can be known
only by those who have that capacity. It does not show that those who have
those senses are not able through them to perceive how things really are, thus
acquiring (perceptual) knowledge the others lack.39
Clearly some concepts have no use in formulating any true thoughts about
how things are (other than about what use people made of those concepts). The
credentials of concepts are not beyond question. But I doubt that parochial
concepts need more defense than nonparochial ones. "Ether," "alkahest," and
other scientific or pseudoscientific concepts, nonparochial if any are, fail the
test. They are no help in acquiring knowledge. Some of these concepts are
empirically empty. Others are conceptually incoherent or inconsistent with
basic scientific laws.
Nonparochial concepts, because they are in principle accessible to all, have
one obvious advantage. When they can be used to test parochial concepts and
parochial epistemic principles, then they can be used to test whether those
parochial concepts and principles are free of local biases. Such taints will be
exposed once the concepts and principles that incorporate them are judged by
principles that are accessible to people not blinkered by those interests, and
whose vision is not distorted by the peculiarities of any specific perceptual
capacity or alleged capacity.
It does not follow that all parochial concepts or principles can be thoroughly
tested in this way. Moreover, pointing out this advantage is very different from
giving nonparochial concepts and principles special priority, a special status
among the conditions for the possibility of knowledge.40
It seems to me that the thought that they could play such a criterial role is a
mutation of a Cartesian ideal. Not that Williams's absolute conception involves
a commitment to self-evident knowledge, but it is committed to the thesis that
the objectivity of thought is underpinned by an epistemic principle stating that
under ideal conditions knowledge is undisputed and clear for all to see. Two
ideas combine here, one explicit and one implicit: The first is that under ideal
conditions there will not be any deep disagreement. (If a disagreement occurs it
will be quickly resolved —by looking at the evidence as it were). The second is
that in the ideal conditions epistemic tests will not lead us astray. In the real
world, it is acknowledged, we are at the mercy of epistemic luck. We may often
be epistemically justified, indeed required, to accept beliefs that are in fact
false. But under ideal conditions this will not happen.
These ideal conditions may never be realized, but only an epistemology that
subjects itself to this test, that accepts that what is true will be recognized as
such under ideal conditions, can underpin a claim to objectivity. Only domains
of thought that can stand this test (i.e., that out of the thoughts which belong to
them, under ideal conditions competent inquirers will necessarily converge and
accept the same thoughts and reject the same thoughts) are domains of objec-
tive thought. While we acknowledge, the thought is, that in real life we are at
Notes on Value and Objectivity 213
things really are in the world. They do so by claiming that knowledge must be
anchored in the universal, in those concepts all can have and those claims of
knowledge round which all competent inquirers will converge in ideal condi-
tions. By replying that the worry is illusory, that by exploring the preconditions
of our concepts of knowledge and truth we are willy-nilly exploring features of
reality I was navigating a middle course. On the one hand is the Scylla of
denying that the nature of reality, knowledge, truth, and objectivity are just
what is revealed through use of the concepts we happen to have of them, and
requiring some absolute test satisfaction of which by a concept or a principle
guarantees that they reach to reality "as it really is." 41 Against this is the
Charybdis that denies that we can ever have any concepts of reality, knowl-
edge, or truth different from those we happen to have, or that the nature of
reality or knowledge can be different from what these concepts (our concepts
of them) reveal. Our concepts are what we measure by. A thought that is not a
thought (i.e., does not conform to our concept of a thought) is not a thought.
Knowledge that is not knowledge (i.e., not an instance of our concept of
knowledge) is not knowledge.
The middle road allows that our concepts can be subjected to rational
evaluation, which may lead to revision. But it denies that the evaluation is in
the light of any absolute test, like the tests of convergence. We judge our
concepts in light of our concepts and beliefs. While it is necessary that in
general they will be vindicated, some of them, some aspects of even the most
basic of them, may turn out to be incoherent or unsustainable, given whatever
else we know. If we are lucky we improve our understanding of reality and of
knowledge. But we do not do so by satisfying one or several master tests.
Similarly, some of our epistemic procedures may be misguided. What is taken
to be good or adequate evidence for a class of conclusions may turn out to be
inadequate. Considerations taken to be good reasons for certain positions may
be irrelevant, or confused, or just insufficient to justify them.
The history of the practice of science provides examples of how epistemic
standards change, often in the light of rational reflection and criticism, but
without any master test that is held constant and governs the changes. Various
people have suspected that concepts such as the divine, the supernatural, time
travel, miracle, action at a distance, beauty are not all that they seem to be.
Arguments have been put forward to show that their use has to be abandoned
because they are incoherent, or that they have to be reformed in some funda-
mental ways.
If that is so then even the necessary features of our concepts of objectivity
and knowledge may stand in need of revision and can be revised through
reasoning that follows the long route. To deny that is to assume that while the
use of these concepts can reveal difficulties with concepts like "beauty," that
pressure is one-sided: Our concept of "beauty" comes under pressure for being
in tension with the presuppositions of knowledge, but our concept of knowl-
Notes on Value and Objectivity 215
edge is not under pressure for being in conflict with necessary features of
"beauty." But there is no reason to think that. So long as we remain holistic in
our approach to the clarification of the structures of thought the possibility of a
need to revise our notions of knowledge and truth remains.42 I am not saying
that they need revising, only that it is possible that they do.
To acknowledge this possibility is to acknowledge the possibility that there
are preconditions for anything being true or false, or capable of being known,
which are not reflected in our concepts, that is, our concepts as they are.
Therefore, the long route is not "purely internal" and self-vindicating. I con-
clude that it may be that the long route is all we need.
As doubts about the objectivity of this or that domain arise we inquire a n d -
if successful — we establish conditions that settle the issue one way or another.
In other words we need a focus for an inquiry. The focus establishes which
results might be relevant and helpful. There is no way of producing an exhaus-
tive list of such conditions, for we can never anticipate all the doubts that can
arise concerning the objectivity of this or that domain.
Put it another way: there is no interesting comprehensive theory of objec-
tivity. But there can be fruitful inquiries into the objectivity of one area or
another when specific doubts arise regarding their status.
view. It does not follow from the idea that knowledge is of what is there
anyway.
Williams's condition fares no better if it is narrowed down to saying that
knowledge must be of a reality that exists independently of any thoughts or
beliefs about its existence. The example of the chess club refutes this condition
as well, since the existence of the club depends on some people believing (or
having believed) that it exists.
Objects of knowledge can sometimes even depend on the agent's own prior
thoughts and experiences. The motivation for the condition of independence,
namely, that knowledge is of what is there anyway, does not justify the blanket
exclusion of all cases of this kind. For example, yesterday the chairperson of
the chess club may have passed a regulation binding on the club. Its existence
and content depend on his intentions in passing it. They also depend on his
beliefs about what he was doing, that is, his belief that he is making a rule for
the club. There is nothing in that to disqualify him from having knowledge of
the existence or content of rules he made any more than there is reason to deny
that other people can have that knowledge. Moreover, his knowledge of the
regulation is not knowledge of his own thoughts and intentions. It is knowledge
of a rule of the club. Nor need it derive from his memory of his own thoughts.
He may have forgotten that it is his regulation, and learn about it from col-
leagues. He, like anyone else, can have knowledge of the regulations of the
club. The underlying rationale of the independence condition does not warrant
Williams's claim that if knowledge is to be of what is there anyway it must be
independent of what is there in virtue of people's or the agent's own thoughts
and experiences. The objectivity of no domain of thought depends on this
condition.
But is not that conclusion premature? It may be thought that while in
general views and thoughts about matters whose existence depends on psycho-
logical or social facts are objective, there is a special case against the objec-
tivity of evaluative thought arising out of its possible dependence on social
facts. If it turns out—it may be argued-that if value propositions are capable of
being true or false then their truth-value depends on social facts, then norma-
tive or evaluative thought cannot be objective.
This particular objection to the objectivity of practical thought concentrates
on what I called the relevance condition. Practical thought appears to meet the
other conditions we canvassed. The real doubt about its objectivity is: does it
meet the relevance condition? Are there grounds that are not merely persuasive
but logically relevant to the confirmation or discontinuation of any practical
thought? The most promising attempt to provide an affirmative answer relies
on the use of thick concepts. But thick concepts seem to depend on a shared
culture with its shared acceptance of various values. Hence it seems that the
thick concept solution to the problem of the relevance condition makes the
truth of evaluative propositions depend on the social facts of shared views.
Notes on Value and Objectivity 217
This is where the objection is directed: if it turns out that if practical proposi-
tions are true or false they are so in virtue of social facts, then they are not
capable of being either true or false.
The objection is a serious one. Thick concepts are indeed crucial to any
attempt to establish the objectivity of practical thought and its conformity with
the relevance condition. Consider the sort of reasons people give in support of
such propositions: Simon should be respected because he acted with great
dignity. Sarah deserves promotion for she solved a complicated problem with
subtlety and ingenuity. Robin acted well; he kept his head under pressure and
showed cool judgment and discrimination in handling his boss. This is a great
film: it is easy to understand without being trivial, and it combines humor and
wisdom. Typically just about all our evaluative reasoning is saturated with
thick concepts of a variety of kinds. Both conclusions and reasons for them are
typically expressed by the use of thick evaluative concepts. An account of the
relevant reasons that support or undermine evaluative or normative proposi-
tions will largely consist in an explanation of the relations between thick
concepts. But, and that is where the objection starts, mastery of thick concepts
depends on shared understandings and shared judgments. These shared judg-
ments both enable us to understand the meaning of thick evaluative terms, and
incline us to accept the legitimacy of their use. There is no independent way of
validating the legitimacy of the use of thick concepts. Hence, the validity of
evaluative propositions, if it depends on thick concepts, depends on shared
understandings and judgments, that is, on social facts. The truth or correctness
of value propositions cannot, however, depend on social facts. Such depen-
dence will make value judgments contingent, for the facts they depend on are
contingent, and arbitrary, for whether or not one has cogent reasons to accept
them will depend on the evaluatively arbitrary fact of one's membership in one
culture or another. Worst of all, if the truth conditions of evaluative proposi-
tions are contingent social facts, then they cannot be normative; they are
merely statements of those facts whose existence renders them true.
Since the normative cannot depend on social facts it cannot depend on thick
concepts, and given the absence of any other plausible account of the way
practical thought meets the relevance condition, we must conclude that it lacks
objectivity.
and values and practices that are conditions for access to such good or values.
On the one hand, it is possible that values and goods are created or maintained
in existence by social practices and the shared beliefs and understandings that
are part of them. I will call practices that bring into existence goods or values,
or sustain them in existence, sustaining practices. On the other hand, it is
possible that shared understandings affect not the existence of values and
goods, but our ability to learn of them and perhaps to benefit from them. Such
practices control access to the values and goods concerned. Quite likely the
social dependence of values and goods takes many and varied forms. I will
briefly delineate four fairly typical types of case, starting with the closest to
dependence of value on practice.
The type of good or social meaning I have in mind here may differ from local
goods in degree only, but a difference there is: Take a game, for example,
chess, with the goods that playing it makes possible (being good at chess, being
a good chess tactician, ingenious at the end game, etc.). Chess was created at a
particular time. It makes no sense to think of it as having existed from the
creation of the world and only discovered at a certain time. It was invented,
created, and developed, not discovered. So it too is socially created or socially
constituted, and like all socially created goods and meanings it has an origin in
time, and its existence is contingent rather than necessary. It could not have
been invented. But in one respect chess is unlike manners. Once invented it is
with us forever. Of course it can be forgotten. Times may come when no one
will know what chess is, no one will know how to play it. Some games that
used to be played by people during the flowering of Maya civilization in the
Yucatan, for example, are lost to us. But that is mere loss of knowledge, loss of
access to a good. We can rediscover how to play these games. There is a sense
in which once the game is invented it remains in existence for ever, or at least
for as long as it is logically possible for it to be (if lost) rediscovered.46
Many other goods belong to this kind. Think of New York Jewish humor.
Enjoying it, being good at telling good New York Jewish jokes and witticisms,
or being able to display that sense of humor in one's conversation is valuable
and admirable. Like chess, New York Jewish humor and other goods of this
kind are generated by a particular culture and did not exist beforehand. This
sense of humor developed and emerged during a particular period in the history
of New York. It did not exist as a timeless form of humor to be discovered by
New York Jews in the nineteenth or twentieth century. Like all socially con-
stituted goods, New York Jewish humor enjoys a contingent existence. It might
not have come into existence. But, unlike fashion and like chess, once it has
been developed it remains in existence forever (or for as long as it can be -
should it be lost — rediscovered). It is quite likely that times will come when
people will not understand this form of humor. It also likely that a time will
come when there will be no one around capable of understanding it. But these
are contingent facts, which do not limit the possibility that it will be re-
discovered. What goes for New York Jewish humor goes for classical ballet,
the novel, opera, and a large number of other goods that are culturally con-
stituted in similar ways.
220 JOSEPH RAZ
Wherein lies the difference between the two categories of socially created
goods? In the possibility of enjoying them outside the cultures that bred and
sustained them. Suppose you discover a game that has long been forgotten or a
form of music no longer practiced in your culture. It is in principle possible to
discover what they were, to come to understand them and the cultures that
sustained them. That would involve understanding what was good in them.
Once one understands those goods one can enjoy them, one can engage in them
in the right way, bringing one the intrinsic benefits that they brought people in
the cultures where they were practiced. Naturally this requires further condi-
tions, one needs to be good at games, have willing partners to play with, be
musical, et cetera. But in principle those goods though created and practiced in
one culture can be enjoyed by people in other cultures, even by individuals who
live in cultures where the game or form of music did not take root. Not so with
regard to local goods. While we can learn and appreciate the fashions or
manners of previous times or faraway places, we cannot enjoy their benefits
unless they become the fashions and manners of our society.47
1. People cannot be blamed for not being guided by values they could not
know about.
222 JOSEPH RAZ
seal of approval of game theory. Moreover, it may be thought that with conven-
tional goods the explanation for what is good about this mode of conduct, or
dress, et cetera, is clear: it is good because that is how people generally behave,
how they dress, and so on. This is, however, at best only part of the explana-
tion.53 The rest has to account for the reason for conforming to the conven-
tional norm. We understand conventions only when we understand the good
they are thought to achieve and whether they in fact lead to good or ill.
The values served by conventional goods explain what, if anything, is good
in the conventions and enable us to distinguish between good and bad conven-
tions. I emphasize this point for it shows that the explanation of the goodness of
any good or valuable thing or option has to be relatively independent of the
social practices that create that good. Only thus can we acknowledge that social
conditions can also lead to bad practices, which will be mistakenly taken by
their participants as good ones. In "Moral Change and Social Relativism"54 I
suggested a different argument to the same effect, namely, that the inherent
intelligibility of values means that they have to be somewhat independent of
social practices. The two arguments are two aspects of the same thought.
These arguments do not show that normative properties are not socially
created. They show that they are not all conventional, and that their normative
nature must be explained normatively and cannot be explained in nonnorma-
tive terms. But there can be social practices or other social phenomena that can
only be identified in normative terms, and such social practices can be said to
give rise to new normative properties consistently with the arguments above.
We learn that not all goods are socially created not from the argument above
but by examining the nature of the various goods (as was sketched in the
previous section). The preceding argument is meant to show that even if all
goods are socially created (and they are not) it does not follow that the reasons
that explain why they are good, what makes them good, consist in an appeal to
the fact that the relevant social practices exist. They must consist in pointing to
good-making properties of the social practices concerned.
These remarks may lead to the opposite objection, namely, that socially
created goods are not socially created at all. The goods involved in them are
timeless, only the ways they are realized are local. But while that may be true
of some instances, it is not generally true. For example, observing rules of
polite behavior tends to make one feel comfortable in social situations and
facilitates interaction with others. That good is neither conventional nor so-
cially created. It is timeless. But to say this is to abstract from the differences
between different societies and different codes of good behavior. The abstract
value of facilitating interactions may be the correct value to apply to the
situation, yet it leaves out information that only a concrete and localized
description of the good of polite behavior in one or another social setting can
convey. Concrete socially created values must be subsumed under abstract
universal values, or they will be unintelligible. But they are no "mere" in-
Notes on Value and Objectivity 225
stantiations of universal values. They are distinctive specific goods, which can
be enjoyed only if created by social practices.55
with the objectivity of evaluative thought. For, the objector points out, many
conflicting evaluative thoughts have equal credentials. Therefore, none of
them can be correct or true. The argument is not merely that they cannot be
known to be correct or true. That would have been the case had there been
nonrelational grounds establishing one rather than the other which people
cannot, not even in principle, come to know.57 But, according to the objector's
argument, the failure is not of ability to know. There are no such grounds,
therefore there is nothing to know.
Much has been written about the coherence of the incommensurability
claim that underlies the objection. I will put such doubts to one side. The
objection is also vulnerable on other grounds. It relies heavily on the inability
to explain the concepts of one culture, or system of thought, using those of
another. But how important is this limitation? The argument is often discussed
as revolving not on the relations between concepts belonging to two different
systems of thought, but on the relation between the meanings of terms in two
languages. In the development of languages, however, new terms are often
added whose meaning cannot be precisely explained using the other terms of
the language. We learn their meaning in part through use, and by ostension, and
only in part by locating their meaning relative to that of other words.58 We do
the same when we encounter concepts in a foreign culture. Words are added to
the language often borrowed from the other language, whose meaning is
learned not exclusively through explanation, but by ostension, and through
habituation to aspects of the alien culture that they signify.
There is little doubt that often we fail to understand concepts embedded in a
culture or system of thought that is alien to us. But is there any reason to think
that even given favorable conditions we could not master them? That they
cannot be exhaustively or satisfactorily explained using our concepts does not
establish that conclusion, for we can learn them directly, by being exposed to
their use, rather than through translation. Sometimes we could do so by actu-
ally living in the alien society; at other times it is possible to learn their
meaning by learning about that society and reconstructing in imagination, or
simulation, its ways and beliefs.
To claim that members of one culture cannot in any way come to understand
the concepts of another amounts to the implausible claim that people have the
capacity to acquire the concepts of one culture only. Once they have done so
their conceptual capacity is exhausted or perhaps blocked. This seems an
implausible supposition.
I can think of only one possible reason for it. Complete understanding of a
concept — and it is important to remember that understanding is a matter of
degree — involves knowing its relations with all the concepts one understands.
Take, for example, the relation "being incompatible with." One does not under-
stand what it is to be blue if one does not know that it excludes being red, nor
what it is to be just if one does not know that it excludes being unfair. It follows
Notes on Value and Objectivity 227
that in a way the more concepts one has already acquired the more difficult it is
for one to acquire new ones, for one would have to understand whether they are
or are not compatible with those one has already mastered. Could it not there-
fore be the case that for this reason those who mastered the concepts of our
culture cannot understand those of ancient alien civilizations? Our inability to
understand their concepts is no sign of reduced mental ability. Rather, to
understand their concepts we have to know the degree to which they are
compatible with ours. Members of those ancient civilizations themselves did
not have that knowledge. Since they did not know our concepts they did not
have to know how our concepts relate to theirs in order to understand theirs. We
do, and this is why we cannot understand their concepts.
At this point the argument that systems of thought are incommensurate
because their concepts are not mutually translatable has been abandoned in
favor of the assertion that systems of thought are incommensurate because no
one can master the concepts of more than one of them. The new contention is,
however, implausible. It flies in the face of the evidence. There were and are
people who inhabited more than one culture and understood both. It also
overlooks the fact that our own culture contains concepts derived from
different systems of thought, which have not merged together. While some of
us do not have use for concepts such as grace, sacred, blessed, prayer, and
others, for the most part we manage to understand them, when we try. Finally,
the conclusion exaggerates the conceptual insularity of different cultures. To be
sure there are many culture-specific concepts, that is, concepts that evolved in
one culture and have no parallels in others. But they are embedded in a
conceptual framework that includes many concepts bridging the cultural gap or
having at least near relatives in other cultures. It seems safe to dismiss the
thesis that no person can master concepts of more than one culture and, with it,
the thesis that there are past or present cultures whose concepts cannot in
principle be understood by us. 59
It may be worth pointing out that the considerations I advanced here are
consistent with the view expressed in Part II about the essentially local charac-
ter of evaluative concepts, or of many of them, and of the nonexistence of a
Peirceian ideal condition from which everything can be known. There I was
arguing that it is impossible, even if only because of the impossibility of
knowing the future, for anyone to master all the evaluative concepts. Here, I
argued that there is no general reason to think that no one can come to know
and understand more than one of the existing systems of thought. This conclu-
sion can be reinforced to the effect that no past or present human culture and its
concepts are beyond the comprehension of people for whom it is an alien
culture. There are no human cultural islands that cannot be understood by
anyone other than their members.
At this point one may be tempted to resuscitate the challenge to the objec-
tivity of evaluative thought, while abandoning the conceptual incommen-
228 JOSEPH RAZ
surability thesis. One may argue that (1) all justification is internal to a system
of thought, and that (2) there is no way of adjudicating between beliefs belong-
ing to different systems of thought, and since (3) some beliefs belonging to
different systems of thought are incompatible and cannot both be true, on pain
of contradiction, it follows that no beliefs are true. As before, this argument
presupposes (1) that evaluative beliefs are true only if there are reasons that
explain how it is that they are true, and (2) that evaluative reasons are in
principle available to people, though not necessarily to everyone. For reasons
we cannot explore here these seem reasonable assumptions.
This challenge to the objectivity of evaluative thought is ill-founded. It is
true that all justifications are relative: they are all addressed to an actual or
potential audience, addressing the doubts of that audience and relying on what
that audience accepts. The relativity ofjustifications is itself a result both of the
parochial character of (many) evaluative concepts and of the path dependence
of epistemic justifications. So long as all the different justifications are consis-
tent, that relativity does not undermine the objectivity of evaluative thought.
Nor does it follow from the relativity of justification that there is no way of
adjudicating between incompatible thoughts or beliefs.
More generally I suspect that not infrequently the sense that incompatible
evaluative propositions have equal credentials and therefore neither can be true
results from a failure to distinguish two types of incompatibility. Two evalua-
tive propositions can be (1) inconsistent with each other, or they can (2)
express values, virtues, or ideals that cannot both be realized in the life of a
single person. The second kind of incompatibility does not undermine the
objectivity of evaluative thought. It merely leads to value pluralism.
The first kind of incompatibility is relevant to the debate on objectivity.
Given the two presuppositions I accepted it must be the case that only one of
two inconsistent propositions can be adequately supported by reasons. But we
have to distinguish epistemic from constitutive reasons (though they may
overlap). Two people can have adequate epistemic reasons for accepting each
of two inconsistent propositions. These could be as banal as that different
people, whose judgment they have good reason to trust but whose beliefs are
inconsistent with each other, have advised them. Even constitutive reasons can
conflict as there may be something to be said for both sides of an evaluative
dispute (constitutive reasons are often prima facie). But evaluative proposi-
tions and their negations cannot both enjoy adequate or completely vindicatory
support by reason. None of the considerations I canvassed in this article sug-
gest that inconsistent evaluative propositions do enjoy adequate or vindicatory
support by reasons.
This has been a long and mostly negative discussion. There may be reasons
for rejecting the objectivity of evaluative thought. I offered various consider-
ations to show that many arguments offered as justifying such rejection do not
succeed in doing so. The constructive contribution of my arguments is in
Notes on Value and Objectivity 229
Notes
1. Unless otherwise indicated, when referring to what people think, I have in mind the
thought (or thought-content) rather than the act or activity of thinking.
2. Bear in mind that it would be odd actually to talk of people's impartiality unless someone
challenged it or unless the circumstances of the action invite doubts about it.
At the hands of some contractarian or constructivist philosophers impartiality extends
in another direction as well: in matters of ethics what impartial judges accept is thereby
made true. But I will not explore the contractarian uses of the notion.
3. Though nothing much depends on the way domains are demarcated. The criteria of
objectivity determine whether a domain is objective or not, whichever way it is carved.
4. For example, Marmor, "Three Concepts of Objectivity" in A. Marmor (ed.), Law and
Interpretation (Oxford: Clarendon, 1995).
5. D. Wiggins, "Objective and Subjective in Ethics, with Two Postscripts About Truth" in
B. Hooker (ed.), Truth in Ethics (Oxford: Blackwell, 1996), p. 36.
6. Wiggins's own view is explained in "What Would Be a Substantive Theory of Truth?" in
Z. van Straaten (ed.), Philosophical Subjects: Essays Presented to P. F. Strawson (Ox-
ford: Oxford University Press, 1980).
7. Responsibility, rather than more narrowly moral responsibility.
8. Whether this applies to epistemic objectivity in all its variants is open to doubt. Perhaps
the capacity to be epistemically objective (one version of epistemic objectivity noted
above) is an exception. The question whether or not one is responsible for not being
objective in that sense involves considerations of aspects of responsibility that cannot be
pursued here.
9. And this may account for the tendency to classify them as subjective.
10. Some would make this the first and most important condition of objectivity. One way of
formulating it is: A domain is objective if thoughts belonging to it deal with matters about
which there are propositions that are true or false (or correct or incorrect, or more or less
correct or incorrect). I state the condition in this way, rather than by saying that those
thoughts express propositions that are true or false, in order to allow for the possibility of
thoughts that are objective, and belong to an objective domain, but express propositions
that are neither true nor false.
11. B. Williams, Descartes (London: Harvester, 1978), p. 64.
12. I am using a realist mode of expression ("about a reality") in a weak sense, in which we
could say of arithmetical propositions that they are about numbers and their relations,
without being committed to Platonism about numbers. This weak sense is explained in
the second half of the independence condition.
13. In "What Would Be a Substantive Theory of Truth?" (Philosphical Subjects), Wiggins
suggests as a mark of truth that a statement's being true or not is independent of any
230 JOSEPH RAZ
particular subject's means of appraising its truth-value. This goes beyond the indepen-
dence condition. Practical or evaluative thought does not conform with this condition
under some natural interpretations of it, but is objective. Some of the discussion in the
sequel bears on the reasons for rejecting Wiggins's condition.
14. Many would claim — Williams observes — that we are now familiar with the situation of
doing with less than an absolute conception, and can, as modern persons and unlike the
ambitious or complacent thinkers of earlier centuries, operate with a picture of the world
that at the reflexive level we can recognize to be thoroughly relative to our language, our
conceptual scheme — most generally, to our situation. But it is doubtful to what extent we
really can operate with such a picture, and doubtful whether such views do not implicitly
rely, in their self-understanding, on some presumed absolute conception, a framework
within which our situation can be comprehensively related to other possible situations.
{Descartes, p. 68.) We should agree that the notion of "relative reality" does not make
much sense. There is no interesting sense in which something can be the case relative to
us, but not be the case relative to others, unless, as Williams observes, such claims
presuppose a common frame of reference.
15. Such an isolationist position seems to be endorsed by Dworkin in "Objectivity and Truth:
You'd Better Believe It," Philosophy & Public Affairs 25 (1996), p. 87.
16. It is not clear whether as formulated by Williams the condition would rule out perspec-
tivalist accounts of truth or of reality that are not self-contradictory. For a claim that there
can be coherent perspectivalism see S. D. Hales, "A Consistent Relativism," Mind 106
(1997):33.
17. This also explains why there is safety in numbers. The more criteria we have the firmer
our grasp of the concept, for cumulatively they eliminate the possibility of misunder-
standings relative to known questions. On the other hand they open up more possibilities
of hitherto unthought of questions regarding which they are vague and need refinement.
18. Cf. B. Williams, "Truth in Ethics" in Hooker (ed.), Truth in Ethics, p. 25. (Note that this
example merely illustrates the possibility of additional, logically independent, condi-
tions. It does not illustrate any puzzles they may be called for to dispel). My espousal of
the long route is in line with Dworkin's position in "Objectivity and Truth." There he
warns against taking it for granted that conditions for the objectivity of one domain (say
relating to material objects) apply also to all other domains (say that which relates to
mathematics or to values).
19. This objection is based on claims endorsed by several philosophers, including Dummett,
Wiggins, Williams, and Crispin Wright in Truth and Objectivity (Cambridge, Mass.:
Harvard University Press, 1992).
20. Truth and Objectivity, chaps. 1 and 2.
21. Cf, for example, B. Williams, "Truth in Ethics," pp. 19—20 and elsewhere.
22. In the sense with which the phrase was introduced by J. Mackie in Chapter 1 of Ethics:
Inventing Right and Wrong (London: Penguin, 1977).
23. For example, Marmor, "Three Concepts of Objectivity," and Pettit and Leiter in the
present volume.
24. "Truth in Ethics," in Truth in Ethics, p. 3. It may be that Wright's argument here is the
argument Dworkin tries to make in his "Objectivity and Truth: You'd Better Believe It."
25. Given that mastery of concepts is a matter of degree, everything I say in the text has to be
modulated to allow, e.g., for a more imperfect mastery of a greater number of concepts.
26. The View From Nowhere (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986), p. 5. He also says
Notes on Value and Objectivity 231
that, "To acquire a more objective understanding of some aspect of life or the world, we
step back from our initial view of it and form a new conception which has that view and
its relation to the world as its object. In other words we place ourselves in the world that is
to be understood" (ibid., p.4). Here Nagel seems to be saying that a belief about the world
is more subjective than a belief about my having a belief about the world. But my beliefs
about the content of the theory of quantum mechanics are not more subjective than my
belief that I have certain beliefs about quantum mechanics. They are simply different. I
will assume that the quotation above is simply an unhappy formulation of the idea I
quoted in the main text.
27. Ibid., p. 4.
28. This issue is relevant to the standing of perceptually dependent properties, e.g., color
properties, and I will not pursue it here.
29. From "A Critical Review of Berkeley's Idealism," in Charles S. Peirce, Selected Writings
(Values in a World of Chance), ed. Philip P. Wiener (New York: Dover, 1966), p. 82;
Descartes, p. 244.
30. Ibid., p. 245.
31. Ibid., p. 248.
32. See H. Putnam, "Bernard Williams and the Absolute Conception of the World" in
Renewing Philosophy (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1992), p. 80, and J.
McDowell, "Aesthetic Value, Objectivity, and the Fabric of the World" in E. Schaper
(ed.), Pleasure, Preference, and Value (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983),
P . i.
33. Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy (London: Fontana Press/Collins 1985), p. 140.
34. Ibid.
35. It is illuminatingly discussed by Wright in Truth and Objectivity, e.g., pp. 88—94.
36. C. Wright's condition of cognitive command {Truth and Objectivity, pp. 92-93)
disregards the existence of rational underdetermination in its assertion that a discourse
exhibits cognitive command only if all disagreements can be explained by "divergent
input." On pp. 95ff, Wright has an interesting discussion of the related topic of the degree
to which reason can be permissive only, but he does not fully adjust his conclusions to
allow for its insights.
37. "Objectivity and the Science-Ethics Distinction," in Putnam, Realism with a Human
Face (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1990).
38. For a critique of the absolute conception that argues that science too needs perspectival
concepts, see Putnam, "Objectivity and the Science-Ethics Distinction." Note that to
establish his case Putnam has to show not only that different systems of representations
can be used in science, but also that they employ what I call parochial concepts.
39. There may or may not be reasons to think that some perceptual concepts, those designat-
ing the so-called secondary qualities, designate relational properties of things. For exam-
ple, there may or may not be reason to think that they designate how things when
observed strike the observer, rather than how they are when not observed. Williams
advances some arguments to that effect, and their examination is irrelevant to my argu-
ment here. The only relevant point is that the fact that perceptual concepts are local is not
such an argument.
40. This is one of the points made by McDowell, "Aesthetic Value, Objectivity, and the
Fabric of the World."
41. It may be worth noting that the rejection of this option is not just an endorsement of the
232 JOSEPH RAZ
"Neurath's boat" understanding of the pursuit of knowledge. Those who accept that we
must start from here, i.e., from the beliefs we happen to have, can be wedded to an ideal
convergence test or some other test of the kind here rejected.
42. Perhaps it is helpful to warn here that this reference to a holistic approach is not an
endorsement of an epistemic approach based on coherence in any shape or form. I have
explained some of the reasons for this in Ethics in the Public Domain (Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1994), essay 13: "The Relevance of Coherence."
43. Williams, Descartes, p. 64
44. I am assuming a club which is not legally incorporated.
45. They will also be crude in not drawing some elementary distinctions. I will refer to
goods, values, valuables, norms, considerations which determine that an action is right or
wrong, etc., without trying to distinguish between them. For present purposes such
distinctions are immaterial. Furthermore, I will use examples, implying that they are
examples of genuine goods, or values. Their purpose is to illustrate abstract general
points. It is not my suggestion that everything that is endorsed by a local culture is good
for that reason, and the examples can be substituted with others by those who doubt their
credentials. Finally, I will consider only beliefs about intrinsic goods and will avoid any
reference to instrumental goods.
46. It is true that chess may be forgotten and then be reinvented rather than rediscovered.
That would be the case if its reemergence is independent of knowledge of its previous
existence. But this seems to be consistent with my claim: So long as it can be re-
discovered there is something to rediscover.
47. Two qualifications do not erode the contrast I draw in the text. First, there are "deviant"
ways of enjoying local goods in alien cultures: it could, e.g., mark one as an eccentric.
Similarly, there is usually a whole network of meaning associated with all goods —
socially constituted or not — which is lost when they are moved from one context to
another. Playing chess in seventeenth-century Paris invokes different meanings than
playing in Washington Square in New York City today.
48. I will call any good, norm, or value that is not socially constituted "universal," even
though it may not be strictly universal, as its existence may be conditioned by other
factors.
49. See generally, P. M. S. Hacker, Appearance and Reality (Oxford: Blackwell, 1988).
50. See my discussion of the universality of value in "Moral Change and Social Relativism,"
in E. F. Paul et al. (eds), Cultural Pluralism and Moral Knowledge (Cambridge: Cam-
bridge University Press, 1994). Among other things I discuss there the possibility of
applying judgements that presuppose responsibility, to people, their life, character or
actions, by values that were not created until a later time. In the present discussion I
ignore that possibility.
51. I present a simplified and inaccurate norm, to avoid complicated substantive moral
issues.
52. See "Thick Concepts and the Social Connections."
53. At best for, as was noted in discussing local goods, typically a single conventional
standard provides an opportunity for a variety of goods, some of which depend not on
conformity but on deviation from it (e.g., the good of being an unconventional person, or
one with a strong individual taste).
54. In Cultural Pluralism and Moral Knowledge.
Notes on Value and Objectivity 233
55. I have argued this and some other points made in the current section and the next one in
"Moral Change and Social Relativism."
56. My formulation of the objection is not meant to capture the precise argument of any
writer, though it borrows from points advanced by a number of philosophers. For exam-
ple, some aspects of such a view were elaborated by A. Maclntyre in his Gifford lectures.
Davidson's "On the Very Idea of a Conceptual Scheme" is the best-known attempt to
refute such views. But see Hacker, Appearance and Reality.
57. The argument presupposes, correctly, that evaluative beliefs are not about brute facts.
What value things have is an intelligible matter. Necessarily if something has a value in
one way or another then there are reasons which explain this fact.
58. The Oxford English Dictionary defines "nerd" as "An insignificant or contemptible
person, one who is conventional, affected, or studious; a 'square', a 'swot.'" Surely this
misses out a lot that is essential to the understanding of the term in contemporary,
especially American culture. The OED instances the following (from an ad in the New
York Times, 1978): "The nerdiest nerds on TV are really smart cookies," a quote made
mysterious rather than explained by their definition.
59. This remark is confined to cultures of creatures who share our perceptual capacities and
emotional make-up.