Cognition and Motivation - Forging An Interdisciplinary Perspective (2012)
Cognition and Motivation - Forging An Interdisciplinary Perspective (2012)
This collection examines the many internal and external factors affecting cognitive
processes. Editor Shulamith Kreitler brings together a wide range of international
contributors to produce an outstanding assessment of recent research in the field.
The contributions go beyond the standard approach of examining the effects of
motivation and emotion to consider the contextual factors that may influence
cognition. These broad and varied factors include personality, genetics, mental
health, biological evolution, culture, and social context. By contextualizing cog-
nition, this volume draws out the practical applications of theoretical cognitive
research and brings separate areas of scholarship into meaningful dialogue.
Edited by
Shulamith Kreitler
Tel Aviv University
cambridge university press
Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town,
Singapore, São Paulo, Delhi, Mexico City
A catalog record for this publication is available from the British Library.
Cambridge University Press has no responsibility for the persistence or accuracy of URLs
for external or third-party Internet Web sites referred to in this publication and does not
guarantee that any content on such Web sites is, or will remain, accurate or appropriate.
This book is dedicated to the memory of Hans Kreitler (1916–1993),
my late husband, who accompanied me with love and inspiration
for many years along the road of cognitive and motivational
explorations in science and life
Contents
Introduction 1
Shulamith Kreitler
vii
viii Contents
Index 483
Contributors
xi
xii Contributors
from Harvard in 1941, has helped to shape the fields of cognitive, develop-
mental, and linguistic psychology.
Chi-yue Chiu is a professor of Management and Marketing at the Nanyang
Business School, Nanyang Technological University, in Singapore. Dr. Chiu
is also a specially appointed researcher at the Institute of Sociology, Chinese
Academy of Social Sciences, and Research Director of the Institute on Asian
Consumer Insight. He received his doctorate in social psychology from
Columbia University.
Karl Edlinger is a curator in the Department of History of Science at the
Vienna Natural History Museum. His doctoral research focused on the struc-
ture and function of sensory organs in Cephalaspidea, marine gastropod
mollusks. Dr. Edlinger’s current research involves systemic studies of issues
in mollusks, evolution, and organism theory.
Anastasia Efklides is a professor of Experimental and Cognitive Psychology
at Aristotle University of Thessaloniki, Greece. Her research interests include
cognition and meta-cognition, particularly in relation to motivation and self-
control. Dr. Efklides is the recipient of several major awards, including a com-
mendation for Outstanding Career Contribution to Educational Psychology
from the International Association of Applied Psychology and the 2011
Oevre Award from the European Association for Research on Learning and
Instruction.
Michael W. Eysenck is Professorial Fellow at Roehampton University at
London. Dr. Eysenck was a professor of Psychology at Royal Holloway
University from 1987 to 2009 and has published widely in the areas of cogni-
tive psychology and anxiety and cognition.
Evridiki Fioratou is a research Fellow at the Multidisciplinary Assessment
of Technology Centre for Healthcare at the University of Nottingham. She
received her doctorate in psychology at Lancaster University. Dr. Fioratou is
an experimental and applied cognitive psychologist, whose work focuses on
problem solving, insight and learning, as well as decision making and diag-
nostic processes in healthcare contexts.
Dida Fleisig is a lecturer in the College of Management and Academic Studies
at Tel Aviv University, Israel. She received her doctorate in cognitive psychol-
ogy from Tel Aviv University and currently performs research in the areas of
judgment, decision making, and overconfidence.
Eva Gatarik is a research associate at the University of Applied Sciences
Upper Austria, Steyr. She previously worked as a research assistant at the
Contributors xiii
psychology from the Claremont Graduate School and has published widely
on the subject of creativity. Professor Runco is the founder of the Creativity
Research Journal, a Fellow of the American Psychological Association, and
the President of Creativity Testing Services. He is the recipient of honors
including a Spencer Foundation Research Grant and the Early Scholar Award
from the National Association for Gifted Children.
Anna Sheveland is a doctoral candidate at the University of Maryland,
College Park. Her research interests include motivated cognition, epistemic
authority, political ideology, and terrorism.
Dorothy G. Singer is a retired senior research scientist in the Department of
Psychology at Yale University. Dr. Singer is co-director of the Yale University
Family Television Research and Consultation Center, affiliated with the
Zigler Center for Child Development and Public Policy, and a Fellow of the
American Psychological Association. Her research and publications focus
on early childhood development, television effects on youth, and parent
training in imaginative play. She received the 2006 Distinguished Alumni
Award from Columbia University Teachers College and the 2009 Award
for Distinguished Lifetime Contributions to Media Psychology from the
American Psychological Association.
Jerome L. Singer is Professor Emeritus of Psychology at Yale University and a
Fellow of the American Psychological Association. His research focuses on the
psychology of imagination and daydreaming, and he has published widely on
the subjects of thought processes, imagery, personality, psychotherapy, chil-
dren’s play, and the effects of television. Dr. Singer is the recipient of the 2008
Rudolf Arnheim Award for Distinguished Contributions to the Psychology of
Aesthetics, Creativity, and the Arts and the 2009 Paul Farnsworth Award for
Lifetime Contribution and Service, both from the American Psychological
Association.
Jeff Stewart is an independent scholar living in rural Maine. His 2006 doc-
toral dissertation at Harvard was entitled “The Development of Consciousness
from Affective Sources.” He is currently finishing a book on consciousness
and the self.
Ola Svenson is a researcher at Decision Research, Oregon, and Professor
Emeritus at Stockholm University. He received his doctorate from Stockholm
University in psychophysics and measurement theory and has conducted
research on cognition and decision making, pioneering process perspective,
and the think-aloud method in behavioral decision research. His applied
xvi Contributors
research includes studies of traffic safety, risk analysis, risk perception, and
nuclear safety. Dr. Svenson founded the European Group for Process Tracing
of Decision Making and is the recipient of the U.S. Society for Risk Analysis
1997 European Distinguished Achievement Award.
Nicole Szesny is a clinical psychologist and research assistant at the Max
Planck Institute for Psychiatry in Munich. She received her doctorate in psy-
chology at the University of Munich in 2011. Dr. Szesny’s research interests
include cognition and neurobiological markers in depression.
Wendy Wan is an associate professor of Business Management at Sun Yat Sen
University. She received her doctorate in social and personality psychology
from the University of Hong Kong. Her current research examines cultural
effects on consumer culture and conflict-related behavior.
Kineret Weissler is a doctoral candidate studying olfactory perception at
Tel Aviv University and the Weitzman Institute of Research. Her research
uses the framework of the cognitive orientation theory of motivation devel-
oped by Shulamith and Hans Kreitler. Weissler was employed by the Israeli
ministry of health until 2012.
Manfred Wimmer is a lecturer at the Institute for Scientific Theory and
Research at the University of Vienna, as well as a docent and free research
collaborator at the Konrad Lorenz Institute. His research interests include the
biological origins and sociocultural dynamics of emotions, and both inter-
and transdisciplinary approaches to cognition research.
Dan Zakay is a professor of Psychology at Tel Aviv University, from which
he received his undergraduate and graduate degrees. His research focuses on
fundamental issues in cognitive psychology and its applications in fields such
as transportation safety and national and community resilience. Professor
Zakay founded and directs the graduate program in Organizational Behavior
at the Interdisciplinary Center Herzliya and is the 2011 recipient of the EMET
Prize in Psychology.
Edward F. Zigler is Sterling Professor of Psychology, Emeritus, at Yale
University. He received his doctorate in clinical psychology from the
University of Texas, Austin, in 1958, joining the Yale faculty the following year.
Professor Zigler founded and is Director Emeritus of Yale’s Edward Zigler
Center in Child Development and Social Policy, one of the first centers in the
United States to combine training in developmental science and social policy
construction. He is one of the founders of applied developmental psychology
and has played a significant role in education reform, including advocacy for
Contributors xvii
Jerome Bruner
xix
xx Foreword
Shulamith Kreitler
I love knowing. My heart loves to know and so my heart tells my brain to do every-
thing necessary in order to know and it happens.
(Jonathan Kreitler, age 5 yrs.)
1
2 Introduction
to account for those effects. Both theories assume that there is an impor-
tant distinction between performance effectiveness and processing efficiency
reflecting the relationship between performance effectiveness and use of
processing resources. In addition, attentional control theory assumes that
anxiety impairs two major executive functions involving inhibitory and shift-
ing processes, respectively. The chapter provides a detailed discussion of the
research in recent years concerned with testing aspects of these theories, out-
lining future research directions.
Chapter 6 (by Stewart & Panksepp) delves into the biological foundations
of affective systems that serve as sources for both cognition and motivation.
Motivation is derived from core emotional command systems in the mam-
malian brain. Central to the different emotional command systems is that
of SEEKING, a spontaneous generator of neurobiological events that goad
the animal toward exploration. The eagerness and expectancy corresponding
to this exploratory/investigative foraging drive are massively integrated by
brain dopamine activity into a coherent BrainMind state called SEEKING
that helps establish the neural conditions for appetitive learning for all kinds
of rewards, including the urge to PLAY. SEEKING remains central through-
out life, promoting enthusiasm for learning and living, is critical for a life well
lived, but can also be led to excesses, in the form of addictions.
Chapter 7 (by Wimmer) deals with the organic origins and evolution
of motivation, emotion, and cognition. The major assumptions are that in
early periods of phylogenetic development, cognition, emotion, and motiva-
tion have been closely bound together, without ever losing their interactive
dynamics, and that cognitive functions even on the highest levels are always
closely tied to their emotional and motivational substructures. Thus, each
analysis of the evolution of cognition has to consider the evolution of emo-
tion/motivation. This transdisciplinary approach is supported by data from
classical ethology and developmental psychology as well as by investigations
of the symbolic abilities of human beings.
Chapter 8 (by Au, Wan, & Chiu) complements the phylogenic approach by
focusing on the social and cultural context of cognition. The authors define
culture as a network of procedural and declarative knowledge, shared among
a collection of interconnected individuals. If a knowledge item is activated
(i.e., when it is cognitively accessible to the individual and applicable to the
context), it can affect subsequent judgments and behaviors. Cultural differ-
ences in judgments and behaviors reflect cultural differences (a) in the specific
knowledge items available in the culture or (b) in the prevalence of situational
cues that render a certain subset of knowledge items chronically accessible to
members of a culture. Situational and individual difference factors (e.g., need
6 Introduction
for firm answers, need to belong, cognitive load, or mortality salience) that
increase individuals’ reliance on culture to provide quick and widely accepted
answers tend to enlarge cultural differences in judgment and behavior.
The next three chapters are devoted to more purely physiological aspects.
Chapter 9 (by K. Edlinger) addresses the confluence of evolutionary and cul-
tural developments as an epistemologically active vector. Human beings, and
in particular perception and cognition, result from a long evolutionary pro-
cess shared by all species. In Darwinian theories, evolution of organisms and
their abilities are considered as outcomes of adaptation. The shortcoming of
these approaches is that they lack a consistent theory of organisms, viewed as
mosaic-like arrangements of characteristics. In contrast, the theory of organ-
ismic constructions, grounded in constructive realism, considers organisms
as mechanical constructions constantly engaged in converting energy, func-
tioning in accordance with internal needs. Organisms are not blueprints of
their environment. Their prime qualities are dynamics, autonomy, and spon-
taneity. Cognition is an activity of autonomous entities, actively construct-
ing their own realities in accordance with special internal needs. This view
corresponds also to medicine and applies to the functioning of the nervous
system, characterizing the organism’s relations with the environment, espe-
cially perception and cognition.
Chapter 10 (by W. Johnson) explores the issue of what and how genes affect
cognition. In particular, the chapter addresses the problem of the paradox
between the claims that cognition is heritable but that genes do not con-
trol our thoughts. The author reviews the history of the paradox since the
development of Mendel’s ideas of genetic transmission across generations
and Darwin’s theory of evolution, and describes the Modern Synthesis that
underlies current ideas of genetics and evolutionary biology. The Synthesis
has been used to develop the common measures of genetic influences on
human cognition. The likely common violations of the assumptions underly-
ing these measures have implications for understanding genetic influences on
cognition. Also, issues involved in identifying the specific genes that contrib-
ute to cognition are discussed.
Chapter 11 (by N. Jaušovec & K. Jaušovec) addresses the issue of the rela-
tionship between brain functioning and cognition. It describes the brain
and techniques for studying its function and structure, referring to the the-
ories about the interactions. Following this introduction, it focuses on the
relationship between intelligence and brain activation patterns in response
to the performance of cognitive tasks employing many different demands.
Further, it presents recent neuroscientific research of emotional intelligence,
creative thinking, and individual differences in personality traits as well as
Introduction 7
person works on the task, so that there is consistency and coherence in the
person’s actions and updating of person characteristics. Metacognition relates
cognition and affect and motivates control of cognition and effort/affect as
well as attributions about competence in co-regulation and other regulation
in collaborative learning.
Chapter 19 (by Panther) shows that motivation is a crucial concept in lin-
guistic theorizing. In particular, a case is made for the relative motivation
of grammatical structure by conceptual and pragmatic factors. For purposes
of illustration, a case study on English question tags is presented, and it is
shown that their form is motivated, although not predictable, by factors
such as communicative function, metonymic principles, inferencing within
speech–act scenarios, and economy of coding. Tags are found in many other
languages than English, but what kinds of tags appear in a specific language
cannot be predicted.
Chapter 20 (by Zigler) deals with the role of motivation in regard to cog-
nitive functioning of individuals at the extremes of the IQ curve – the men-
tally challenged and the gifted. The motivational factors are, in both cases,
environmental circumstances, such as educational opportunities, family
support, and encouragement in the workplace; personality and behavioral
tendencies, such as outerdirectedness or innerdirectedness, responsiveness
to tangible or intangible rewards, positive or negative reactions to others; and
cognitive-motivational determinants, such as beliefs referring to motivation-
ally orienting themes in regard to cognitive performance. Despite differences
in the specific nature of these factors, their joint impact affects the level of
cognitive performance in the two groups.
Chapter 21 (by Singer & Singer) deals with reflective self-awareness, day-
dreaming, anticipatory fantasy, and planning, relating such consciousness to
more general cognition, theories of emotionality (e.g., Mandler, Baars, and
Tomkins), motivation as reflected in Klinger’s current concerns studies, and
exploring its origin in the imaginative play of children as well as its implica-
tions for theory of mind and heightened self-awareness. Further, research is
presented about ongoing consciousness in adults on the basis of signal detec-
tion experiments, natural occurring thought, and concepts of a self. Findings
based on brain-imaging methods have supported the psychological experi-
mentation by demonstrating a brain-default network that becomes active
when external stimuli processing is reduced. The implications of these studies
for understanding not only retrospective thought but also planning, imagina-
tion, aesthetic, and scientific creativity are indicated.
Chapter 22 (by Runco & McGarva) concludes the book with a focus on
creativity. In the last decades, the study of creativity has grown dramatically,
10 Introduction
reflecting the recognition that it affects not only the arts but all forms of
innovation and entrepreneurship in the sciences, technology, and education.
Runco approaches the field by considering the who, what, where, when, why,
and how of creativity, focusing mainly on the why. The chapter explores what
that means, that creativity is motivated or is the result of particular motives –
both extrinsic and intrinsic – from various theoretical perspectives (i.e., the
Freudian, humanistic, behavioral, psychoeconomic theory, and theory of
personal creativity).
Each of the chapters is independent of other chapters, and represents the
authors’ view with respect to the discussed subject matter as a whole as well as
their own special view of the theme, addressing theories, methodologies, and
empirical findings. In most cases, no specific studies are presented in detail.
The presentation is inclusive, relying on empirical material as examples dem-
onstrating theoretical constructs, conclusions, and implications.
The chapters in each of the parts of the book separately and in the two parts
together as a whole complement each other and are designed to constitute the
groundwork of an integrative and coherent foundation for forging a recon-
ceptualization of cognition in the context of motivation and beyond.
The explorations of cognition in the multiple motivational contexts may
promote the emergence of a new approach to cognition that will highlight
its pivotal role in psychology, nurtured by the new unfolding interactions
between the motivations and performance, needs and emotions, genetics and
learning, thinking and feeling, internal and external environments, and last
but not least between physiology and psychology. Only the future can tell
whether this growing and enriched ecological environment for cognition will
result in a second cognitive revolution in psychology.
This introduction would not be complete without expressing the deep
appreciation and gratitude of the editor to the authors of the diverse chapters
who have contributed of their expertise, knowledge, and extraordinary abili-
ties and insights to each of the chapters, which constitute real steps forward
along the broadening road of exploration and expanding role of cognitive
sciences as a whole and cognition in particular. In particular, I would like to
mention the special contribution of Ann Renninger, whose insights, coopera-
tion, and support all along in diverse forms have served as a source of inspira-
tion and great help in completing the project of this book.
This book would not have been produced without the continuous sup-
port of the editors of Cambridge University Press, whose encouragement,
patience, and belief in the goal have been a major motivational force in regard
to the present cognitive project.
Introduction 11
References
Baldwin, J. M. (1911). The individual and society. Or psychology and sociology. Boston:
Richard G. Badger.
Baltes, P. B., & Staudinger, U. M. (Eds.) (1996). Interactive minds: Life-span perspectives
on the social foundation of cognition. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Dewey, J. (1913). Interest and effort in education. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
James, W. (1890). The principles of psychology (Vols. 1 & 2). New York: Holt.
Kreitler, S., & Kreitler, H. (1990). The cognitive foundations of personality traits. New
York: Plenum.
Power, M., & Dalgleish, T. (2008). Cognition and emotion: From order to disorder (2nd
ed.). Hove and New York: Psychology Press.
Renninger, K. A., Hidi, S., & Krapp, A. (1992). The role of interest in learning and devel-
opment. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Saklofske, D., & Zeidner, M. (Eds.) (1995). International handbook of personality and
intelligence. New York: Plenum.
Shizgal, P. (1999). Motivation. In R. A. Wilson & F. C. Keil (Eds.), The MIT Encyclopedia
of the Cognitive Sciences (pp. 566–568). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
Sorrentino, R. M., & Higgins, E. T. (Eds.) (1986). The handbook of motivation and cogni-
tion: Foundations of social behavior. New York: Guilford.
Part I
15
16 Kruglanski & Sheveland
phenomena. On the one hand, the need for closure should induce a general
tendency toward abstraction because of the desire of individuals with high
need for closure for stable knowledge that transcends the specific situation.
However, abstract judgments about positive out-group and negative in-group
behaviors should run counter to the tendency for individuals with high need
for closure to display in-group favoritism (insofar as the in-group is typi-
cally the provider of stable knowledge). This then is one case in which the
need for a nonspecific closure is in conflict with the need for a specific clo-
sure (implying an in-group bias). The resultant tendencies toward abstract-
ness and concreteness work in concert as far as judgment of positive in-group
and negative out-group behaviors are concerned, and are in conflict (hence
possibly canceling each other out) as far as negative in-group and positive
out-group behaviors are concerned. Consistent with this prediction, Webster
et al. (1997) found that high (vs. low) need-for-closure participants exposed
to positive in-group or negative out-group behaviors described such behav-
iors more abstractly. However, as predicted, high and low need-for-closure
participants did not differ on the abstractness of their descriptions of negative
in-group or positive out-group behaviors.
Persuasion. Research by Kruglanski, Webster, and Klem (1993) explored
the conditions under which the need for closure may increase or decrease
individuals’ susceptibility to persuasion. To do this, participants were pre-
sented with information about a legal case, allowed time to process the infor-
mation, and later engaged in a discussion with a partner (fellow “juror”) in
order to reach a verdict in the case. When participants were given complete
information about the case, including legal analysis suggesting the appropri-
ate verdict, individuals high (vs. low) on the need for closure were less likely
to be persuaded by their fellow juror (who argued for the opposite verdict).
However, when individuals with high need for closure were given incomplete
information lacking the legal analysis, they were more likely to be persuaded
by their fellow juror than their counterparts with low need for closure. In
short, individuals high (vs. low) on the need for closure tend to resist per-
suasion attempts when they have formed a crystallized opinion about a topic
on which they may freeze, but tend to change their attitudes when presented
with persuasive appeals when they lack an opinion about the topic.
Empathy. Webster-Nelson, Klein, and Irvin (2003) found that, because
individuals with high need for closure tend to “freeze” on their own perspec-
tive, they are less able to empathize with their interaction partners, espe-
cially when those are dissimilar from themselves. In the Webster-Nelson et
al. (2003) study, the need for closure was manipulated via an induction of
mental fatigue. In a similar vein, using a dispositional measure of the need
22 Kruglanski & Sheveland
for closure, Shteynberg et al. (2008) found that high (vs. low) scorers were
less sensitive to injustice done to their teammate by the experimenter (i.e.,
perceived the experimenter as less unfair). Finally, using a referential task
paradigm, Richter and Kruglanski (1999) found that individuals with high
(vs. low) dispositional need for closure tended less to implement an effective
“audience design.” They tended less to “tune” their messages to their inter-
locutors’ unique attributes; as a consequence, their communications were less
effectively decoded by their recipients.
Negotiation behavior. To test the effect of the need for closure in the domain
of negotiation behavior, DeDreu, Koole, and Oldersma (1999) measured par-
ticipants’ dispositional need for closure and then (after a 30 min. delay) had
them engage in a task in which they operated as sellers and interacted with
presumed buyers (actually simulated by computer-programmed responses).
The participant’s (seller’s) task was to negotiate the terms of the sale, includ-
ing delivery time, price, and form of payment. Each of these was associated
with rewards for the participant in the form of chances in a lottery such that
greater profit for the seller was associated with higher chances of winning.
Participants engaged in six rounds of negotiations, beginning with the buyer.
The buyers’ responses were pre-programmed to remain at a moderate level,
conceding slightly more at each round. To manipulate the focal point to which
participants might adjust their negotiations, they were either told that previ-
ous participants had received 11,000 points (high focal point), 3,000 points
(low focal point), or simply that the range of possible points extended from
0 to 14,000 (no focal point).
Three dependent measures were assessed. First, prior to the start of the
negotiations, participants were asked to indicate the minimum amount they
would be willing to accept in the negotiation. Second, participants’ concessions
in the task were determined by the decrease in the amount of points partici-
pants demanded from the first to the last rounds of negotiation (with greater
numbers indicating a larger concession). After the six trials (in which most
participants did not reach an agreement), participants completed a self-report
measure of the extent to which they thought systematically during the task.
The results indicated that individuals with high (vs. low) dispositional need
for closure tended more to adhere to anchor values. That is, they determined
the minimal profits they themselves would accept according to the alleged
profits attained by others in the task. When no focal point was provided, par-
ticipants with high versus low need for closure did not differ in the minimal
value they expressed their willingness to accept. In addition, participants with
high (vs. low) need for closure made smaller concessions to their negotiation
partners and engaged in less systematic information processing.
Epistemic Motivations 23
Group Phenomena
The foregoing findings exemplify need for closure effects on a variety of
intrapersonal and interpersonal phenomena (for an extensive review see
Kruglanski, 2004). Extensive research also examined the effects of the clo-
sure motivation on groups, including the group centrism syndrome described
next.
Group Centrism. Some people are more group-oriented than others, and
most people are more group-oriented in some situations than in others.
Kruglanski et al. (2006) introduced the concept of group centrism, defined
by the degree to which individuals strive to enhance the “groupness” of their
collectivity. Groupness, in turn, has been defined by a firm, consensually
supported shared reality (Hardin & Higgins, 1996), unperturbed by dissents
and disagreements. Although reality sharing has been regarded as the defin-
ing essence of groupness (e.g., Bar-Tal, 1990, 2000), its attainment may be
facilitated by several aspects of group interaction enhanced by the need for
closure. At the initial phases of group formation, this can involve members’
attempts to arrive at a speedy consensus by exerting uniformity pressures on
each other, as demonstrated in a series of studies by DeGrada et al. (1999).
To further test the influence of need for closure on the group
decision-making process, Pierro et al. (2003) engaged participants in a group
task after participants’ need for closure had been assessed, several months
earlier. Participants were divided into groups based on their need-for-closure
scores, with some groups containing high need-for-closure individuals and
others individuals low on need for closure. Each group was composed of four
individuals, role-playing managers in a corporation. The group’s goal was to
determine which of the company’s employees should be given a cash award
for their work performance. Each “manager” represented a candidate nom-
inated by this manager’s department. The dependent measures included the
asymmetry of speaking time (seizing and holding the floor), perceptions of
each participant’s influence over the group, and each member’s style assessed
on the laissez fair-autocratic dimension.
24 Kruglanski & Sheveland
Notes
1. This view is consistent with philosophical conceptions of scientific knowledge,
arguably the most evolved and substantiated variety of knowledge, as perennially
conjectural and potentially subject to refutations (Popper, 1963).
2. In a recent paper, Roets, Van Hiel, Cornelis, and Soetens (2008) argued that in addition
to exerting a direct motivational effect similar to that of dispositional need for closure,
situational manipulations of need for closure (via time pressure or noise) exert an effect
on cognitive capacity as well manifesting itself in deteriorated task performance.
References
Andersen, S. M., & Cole, S. (1990). Do I know you?: The role of significant others in gen-
eral social perception. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 59, 384–399.
Andersen, S. M., Glassman, N. S., Chen, S., & Cole, S. W. (1995). Transference in social
perception: The role of chronic accessibility in significant-other representation.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 69, 41–57.
28 Kruglanski & Sheveland
Jost, J. T., Glaser, J., Kruglanski, A. W. & Sullaway, F. J. (2003). Political conservatism as
motivated social cognition. Psychological Bulletin, 129, 339–375.
Kosic, A., Kruglanski, A. W., Pierro, A., & Mannetti, L. (2004). Social cognition of immi-
grants’ acculturation: Effects of the need for closure and the reference group at
entry. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 86, 1–18.
Kruglanski, A. W. (1989). Lay Epistemics and Human Knowledge: Cognitive and
Motivational Bases. New York: Plenum.
(1996). Motivated social cognition: Principles of the interface. In E. T. Higgins & A.
W. Kruglanski (Eds.), Social psychology: Handbook of basic principles. New York:
Guilford Press.
(2004). The psychology of closed-mindedness. New York: Psychology Press.
Kruglanski, A. W., Dechesne, M., Orehek, E., & Pierro, A. (2009) Three decades of lay
epistemics: The why, how and who of knowledge formation. European Review of
Psychology, 20, 146–191.
Kruglanski, A. W., & Freund, T. (1983). The freezing and un-freezing of lay-inferences:
Effects on impressional primacy, ethnic stereotyping and numerical anchoring.
Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 19, 448–468.
Kruglanski, A. W., Orehek, E., Dechesne, M., & Pierro, A. (2010). Lay epistemic the-
ory: Motivational, cognitive, and social aspects of knowledge formation. Social and
Personality Psychology Compass, 4, 939–950.
Kruglanski, A. W., Pierro, A., Higgins, E. T., & Capozza, D. (2007). “On the move” or
“staying put”: Locomotion, need for closure and reactions to organizational change.
Journal of Applied Social Psychology, 37, 1305–1340.
Kruglanski, A. W., Pierro, A., Mannetti, L., & De Grada, E. (2006). Groups as episte-
mic providers: Need for closure and the unfolding of group-centrism. Psychological
Review, 113, 84–100.
Kruglanski, A. W., Pierro, A., Mannetti, L., Erb, H. P., & Chun, W. Y. (2007). On the param-
eters of human judgment. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, 39, 255–303.
Kruglanski, A. W., Shah, J. Y. Pierro, A., & Mannetti, L. (2002). When similarity breeds
content: Need for closure and the allure of homogeneous and self-resembling
groups. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 83, 648–662.
Kruglanski, A. W., & Webster, D. M. (1991). Group members’ reactions to opinion devi-
ates and conformists at varying degrees of proximity to decision deadline and of
environmental noise. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 61, 212–225.
(1996). Motivated closing of the mind: “Seizing” and “freezing.” Psychological Review,
103, 263–283.
Kruglanski, A. W., Webster, D. M., & Klem, A. (1993). Motivated resistance and open-
ness to persuasion in the presence or absence of prior information. Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology, 65, 861–876.
Kunda, Z., & Sinclair, L. (1999). Motivated reasoning with stereotypes: Activation, appli-
cation and inhibition. Psychological Inquiry, 10, 12–22.
Livi, S. (2003). Il bisogno di chiusura cognitiva e la transmissione delle norme nei piccoli
gruppi [The need for cognitive closure and normtransmission in small groups].
Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Universitá di Roma, La Sapienza.
Orehek, E., Fishman, S., Dechesne, M., Doosje, B., Kruglanski, A., Cole, A. P., & Jackson,
T. (2008). Certainty quest and the societal response to terrorism. Unpublished
30 Kruglanski & Sheveland
Pierro, A., & Kruglanski, A. W. (2005). Revised Need for Cognitive Closure scale.
Unpublished manuscript, Universitá di Roma, La Sapienza.
(2008). “Seizing and Freezing” on a significant-person schema: Need for closure
and the transference effect in social judgment. Personality and Social Psychology
Bulletin, 34, 1492–1503.
Pierro, A., Mannetti, L., DeGrada, E., Livi, S., & Kruglanski, A. W. (2003). Autocracy
bias in groups under need for closure. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin,
29, 405–417.
Popper, K. (1963). Conjectures and refutations: The growth of scientific knowledge.
London: Routledge.
Richter, L., & Kruglanski, A. W. (1999). Motivated search for common ground: Need
for closure effects on audience design in interpersonal communication. Personality
and Social Psychology Bulletin, 25, 1101–1114.
Roets, A., & van Hiel, A. (2006). Need for closure relations with authoritarianism, con-
servative beliefs and racism: The impact of urgency and permanence tendencies.
Psychological Belgica, 46, 235–252.
(2007). Separating ability from need: Clarifying the Dimensional structure of the
Need For Closure Scale. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 33, 266–280.
(2008). Why some hate to dilly-dally and others do not: The arousal-invoking capac-
ity of decision-making for low and high scoring need for closure individuals. Social
Cognition, 26, 259–272.
Roets, A., Van Hiel, A., Cornelis, I., & Soetens, B. (2008). Determinants of task perfor-
mance and invested effort: A need for closure by relative cognitive capacity interac-
tion analysis. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 34, 779–792.
Rubini, M., & Kruglanski, A. W. (1997). Brief encounters ending in estrangement:
Motivated language-use and interpersonaI rapport. Journal of Personality and
Social Psychology, 12, 1047–1060.
Semin, G. R., & Fiedler, K. (1991). The linguistic category model, its bases, applica-
tions and range. In W. Stroebe & M. Hewstone (Eds.), European Review of Social
Psychology (Vol. 2, pp. 1–30). Chichester: Wiley.
Shah, J. Y., Kruglanski, A.W., & Thompson, E. P. (1998). Membership has its (epistemic)
rewards: Need for closure effects on ingroup bias. Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology, 75, 383–393.
Shteynberg, G., Gelfand, M., Imai, L., Mayer, D., & Bell, C. (2008). Unpublished data.
University of Maryland, College Park.
Tetlock, P. E. (1992). The impact of accountability on judgment and choice: Toward a
social contingency model. In L. Berkowitz (Ed.), Advances in Experimental Social
Psychology (Vol. 25, pp. 331–376). New York: Academic Press.
Van Hiel, A., Pandelaere, M., & Duriez, B. (2004). The impact of need for closure on
conservative beliefs and racism: Differential mediation by authoritarian submis-
sion and authoritarian dominance. Personality and Social Psychology bulletin, 30,
824–837.
Webster, D. M., & Kruglanski, A. W. (1994). Individual differences in need for cognitive
closure. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 67, 1049–1062.
(1998). Cognitive and social consequences of the need for cognitive closure. European
Review of Social Psychology, 8, 133–173.
Epistemic Motivations 31
Webster, D. M., Kruglanski, A. W., & Pattison, D. A. (1997). Motivated language use
in intergroup contexts: Need-for-closure effects on the linguistic intergroup bias.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 72, 1122–1131.
Webster, D. M., Richter, L., & Kruglanski, A. W. (1996). On leaping to conclusions
when feeling tired: Mental fatigue effects on impressional primacy. Journal of
Experimental Social Psychology, 32, 181–195.
Webster-Nelson, D., Klein, C. F., & Irvin, J. E. (2003). Motivational antecedents of empa-
thy: Inhibiting effects of fatigue. Basic and Applied Social Psychology, 8, 133–173.
2
Shulamith Kreitler
32
The Structure and Dynamics of Cognitive Orientation 33
more likely that the involvement of cognition in the different domains and
functions of the organism is pervasive, and most probably in both directions;
that is, it affects the different processes and is also affected by them. This
assumption is the first of several that guide this chapter.
The second assumption is that motivation is a major factor affecting the
contents and processes of cognition. This statement may seem trivial were it
not for the implicit prevalent assumption that cognition simply takes place,
similar to digestion and breathing in the physical domain. Because cognition
fulfills a basic role concerning the organism and survival in general, it is pos-
sible that part of the motivation for cognition is automatic or built-in, as in
the case of physical functions. However, as cognition consumes so much of
the time and energy resources of the organism, the so-called apparent auto-
matic motivation does not cover the whole of the motivational role for cogni-
tion. Hence, it is likely that motivation for cognition is complex in the sense
that it includes several components or levels. External or internal triggers
may be important constituents of motivation for specific behaviors, but they
are implemented in the course of development by further layers of motiva-
tion, represented by cognitively shaped beliefs, supported by personality dis-
positions and emotional tendencies.
The third assumption is that cognition is a major constituent of motiva-
tion. This holds regarding behavior in general, emotions, and even physiolog-
ical processes, at least those involved in physical health or diseases. As will be
shown later (see The Cognitive Orientation Model: General Description), the
assumption about the cognitive nature of motivation holds regarding behav-
iors of all kinds – habitual and non-habitual; normal and psychopathologi-
cal; motoric or emotional. Furthermore, it holds regarding different kinds of
individuals – young (at least down to the age of 3–4 years) or old (over 90);
normal or psychopathological; and most important of all, regardless of the
intellectual level of the person – individuals with normal intelligence as well
as those at the lower tail of the IQ curve (see the chapter by Zigler in this
book).
The fourth and final assumption is that cognition functions in terms of cog-
nitive acts. This assumption highlights the similarity in motivational effects
between cognition and other behavioral domains. A cognitive act denotes an
organized sequence of steps including some starting point, the major part of
the action, and some concluding point. Examples of cognitive acts are mak-
ing a plan, recalling something specific, making a decision, solving a certain
problem, answering a question, making an act of analysis, drawing a con-
clusion from a set of data, categorizing an array of inputs, choosing one of
two strategies, or deciphering a code. Thus, in case of planning, the starting
34 Kreitler
point of the cognitive act would be a question such as, “How do we go about
it,” and the end point would be some kind of plan. In the case of decipher-
ing a code, the starting point would be a question such as, “What does this
mean,” and the endpoint of the act would be the transcription of the code or
statement of the message in an understandable form or a conclusion, such
as, “I am sorry, I failed to decipher the code.” A cognitive act may also be
called mental action, and resembles what Piaget called an operation (Piaget
& Inhelder, 1973). It is not unlike any other act that an organism performs,
the difference being that the components of the act are cognitive in nature –
namely, cognitive contents and processes, as distinct from motoric or phys-
iological components. Cognitive contents are items of information, denoted
for example by nouns or verbs (e.g., table, to go) and their combinations (e.g.,
in the form of sentences or images). Cognitive processes are specific changes
in cognitive contents resulting in transformations in terms of function, loca-
tion, combinations, and so forth (e.g., the combination “the table is here” is
changed into “the table is broken” or is replaced by “the table is a piece of
furniture”). It should further be noted that cognitive acts are not necessarily
conscious, nor under voluntary control, although some parts of them may be
accessible to awareness. The major point is that cognitive acts are not identical
with the underlying cognitive contents and processes of which they consist.
The distinction between the cognitive act and its constituents is important
in the context of motivation because motivation, as commonly conceived in
psychology, refers to cognitive acts but not to the constituent processes. The
same holds concerning motor acts, for example. Here too, motivation affects
the act of moving from one room to the next, but not the kind of muscles,
joints, or blood vessels that are involved in the implementation of the act of
movement.
incentive and goal theories deal mainly with the second question; instinct
theories and habit-formation theories deal mainly with the third question;
and feedback theories with the fourth.
In the present context, motivation for cognition will be dealt with from
the point of view of the theory of cognitive orientation (CO). The particular
advantages of this theory for cognition are that it is a comprehensive theory
of motivation regarding cognition; it enables prediction of cognitive acts; and
despite being a cognitive-motivational approach, it does not assume rational-
ity, realism, reasonableness, conscious decision making, and voluntary con-
trol of the cognitive proceedings. Another important advantage of the CO
approach is that it enables a systematic change and improvement of cognitive
acts (Kreitler & Kreitler, 1990a; Zakay, Bar El, & Kreitler, 1984).
A major thesis of the CO theory is that any act, cognitive or other, is a func-
tion of a motivational disposition and a behavioral program that implements
it. The motivational disposition consists of a cluster of beliefs, whereas the
behavioral program consists of cognitive contents and processes structured
in sequences, schemes, strategies, or heuristics. For describing the formation
of the motivational disposition and behavioral programs, we will apply the
system of meaning that provides a presentation of a comprehensive set of
cognitive contents and processes – namely, the meaning variables. The mean-
ing variables and their combinations into patterns also provide access for
the influence of personality traits and emotions on cognitive performance.
Finally, the enactment of the cognitive acts is dependent on the atmosphere
of the overall cognitive environment, including mental sets and states of
consciousness.
Meaning is a concept that plays a major role in the CO theory. Meaning is
defined as a pattern of cognitive contents (e.g., a color, an emotion) focused
on some input (e.g., a stimulus, an object) that is expressed verbally or nonver-
bally, and forms together with the input or subject a meaning unit (Kreitler &
Kreitler, 1990b). Examples of meaning units are “The sea – is made of water,”
“Law – a social institution.” In a given context, meaning consists of one or more
meaning units, each of which may be characterized in terms of the contents
(e.g., causes, sensory qualities) assigned to the subject (viz. referent) and rela-
tions between it and the subject (e.g., its directness, generality). Meaning vari-
ables characterize the contents or the relations between the contents and the
subject (e.g., causes or actions characterize the contents; conjunctions or met-
aphors characterize the relations of the contents to the subject) (see Table 2.1).
Thus, meaning variables characterize both the contents and the process of its
generation. Meaning assignment proceeds by assigning to a subject one or
different kinds of contents. Meaning includes the more interpersonal part as
36 Kreitler
Table 2.1. Major Variables of the Meaning System: The Meaning Variables
well as the more personal-subjective part, and may vary in contents, struc-
ture, variety, and complexity. The various phases of progression from the
input stimulation to the output of behavior consist of different kinds of elab-
oration of meanings.
INPUT
What is the input?
What action?
4 types of beliefs:
Cog. Orientation
Cluster
Behavioral Intent
How to perform
action?
Behavioral Output
Program (Behavior)
Self I Factual
Goals I Desired
Motivational Disposition
[Behavioral Intent]
Beliefs about Goals
General Beliefs
Figure 2.3. The vector of the four belief types representing the motivational disposition.
intents when there are two CO clusters (intent conflict); the retrieval of an
almost complete CO cluster on the basis of past recurrences of similar situ-
ations; the formation of incomplete clusters due to the paucity of beliefs of a
certain type; or the formation of an inoperable cluster due to the inclusion of
as-if beliefs in one or more belief types that may orient toward daydreaming.
The fourth stage is initiated by the formation of the behavioral intent, and
is focused on the question “How will I do it?” The answer is in the form of a
behavioral program; namely, a hierarchically structured sequence of instruc-
tions governing the performance of the act, including both the more general
strategy as well as the more specific tactics. Different programs are involved
in executing an overt molar act, a cognitive act, an emotional response, a
daydreamed act, conflict resolution, and so forth. There are four major
kinds of programs: (1) Innately determined programs (e.g., those control-
ling reflexes). (2) Programs determined both innately and through learning
The Structure and Dynamics of Cognitive Orientation 41
Key-words
the underlying meanings and do not directly evoke associations to the behav-
ior or cognitive act.
Thus, a CO questionnaire mirrors the prediction matrix (see Figure 2.5). It
usually consists of four parts presented together in random order, each repre-
senting one of the four types of beliefs. Each part contains, in random order,
beliefs referring to the different themes. The participant is requested to check
on a four-point scale the degree to which each belief seems true (or correct)
to him/her. A CO questionnaire is examined for its psychometric properties,
including reliability and validity, before it is ready for application.
It is evident that for every kind of behavior it is necessary to construct a
particular CO questionnaire. This in itself is the “bad news.” However, the
“good news” is that a single CO questionnaire may predict a broad range of
relevant behaviors, for instance, the CO questionnaire of curiosity yielded
significant predictions of 14 different curiosity behaviors (Kreitler & Kreitler,
1994b).
The prediction procedure generated by the CO theory has provided a great
number of significant predictions of actual cognitive and other behaviors, of
many different kinds and from different domains, in participants of different
ages and intelligence levels, even cognitively challenged individuals. Notably,
the procedure does not enable the participants to tailor their responses so that
they would or would not correspond to their behaviors because it is impossible
The Structure and Dynamics of Cognitive Orientation 45
2)
3)
n)
to unravel the kind of involved behavior from the statements in the CO ques-
tionnaire. Further advantages of the prediction procedure are that applying it
does not require any special mind-set, preparation, intention, or even average
intelligence on the part of the participants. Additionally, success in predicting
does not depend on involving any further criteria or constructs or assump-
tions or the creation of particular conditions regarding any behavior.
performed for changing beliefs of the four types relevant for curiosity. The
training led to the expected increases in the level of curiosity behaviors in the
children whose CO of curiosity was raised (Kreitler, Kreitler, & Boas, 1976).
Finally, the CO of memory includes themes such as the centrality of inner
life, investing in oneself, the importance and value of a mass of information,
dealing with the past as a source of stability, conserving ones’ possessions,
continuity in development, and life as an organized structure rather than a
random set of points. High scorers on the CO of memory performed better
on various memory tests, verbal and nonverbal, than the low scorers. Notably,
this was observed in samples of undergraduates as well as in people over 65
(Kreitler & Kreitler, 1990b).
CO questionnaires for types of thinking. Types of thinking refer to structur-
ally and motivationally defined kinds of thinking that direct the activation of
cognition along specific lines. We will deal with creativity, inventiveness, and
intuitive thinking.
The CO questionnaire of creativity (Casakin & Kreitler, 2010; Kreitler &
Casakin, 2009). This questionnaire refers to 79 themes, which form the fol-
lowing 11 groupings: (1) self-development (investing, promoting, and guarding
oneself); (2) emphasis on the inner world (identifying, knowing, developing,
and expressing one’s thinking, feeling, and imagination); (3) inner-directedness
(emphasis on one’s desires, will, and decision; self-confidence in one’s ability
to succeed); (4) contribution to society (concern with contributing some-
thing meaningful to the community or society even if it does not involve
personal advancement); (5) awareness of one’s own uniqueness as an individ-
ual (emphasis on oneself as an individual unique in one’s talents and way of
perceiving, behaving, and being, not necessarily due to nonconformity); (6)
freedom in acting (need to act in line with rules and regulations set by oneself
rather than by others); (7) restricted openness to the environment (readiness
and need to absorb from the environment knowledge and inspiration coupled
with resistance to being overwhelmed and harmed by too much openness);
(8) acting under conditions of uncertainty (readiness to act under condi-
tions of uncertainty concerning the results, with no control over the circum-
stances, a tendency which may resemble risk-taking); (9) demanding from
oneself (demanding from oneself effort, perseverance, giving up comfort,
and readiness for total investment despite difficulties and even failures); (10)
self-expression (concern with using one’s talents and expressing oneself with
authenticity and characteristically); (11) nonfunctionality (readiness to act
even if functionality is not clearly evident from the start). The eleven group-
ings form two factors, confirmed in several different samples. The first factor
represents the themes focused on the self – its uniqueness, development, and
48 Kreitler
spent on average in playing chess and learning to play chess as well as the
level of expertise in the game itself, as evaluated by expert observers (Kreitler
& Margaliot, in press).
The CO questionnaires for cognitive styles. Cognitive styles are preferred or
habitual ways of performing various cognitive processes or acts. Some cog-
nitive styles are closer to habits (e.g., scanning, leveling versus sharpening);
others appear to be closer to personality traits (e.g., intolerance of ambigu-
ity, field independence). The CO of rigidity includes themes such as fear of
punishment, limited possibilities for doing things, trying harder or giving up
when a task gets difficult, and keeping track of one’s responses. Children with
IQs lower than 70 scoring high on the CO of rigidity persevered more in their
responses and were less likely to change their responses when required than
the low scorers (Kreitler & Kreitler, 1988a; see also Chapter 20 in this book).
Intolerance of ambiguity is one of the oldest cognitive styles or cognitive
traits. The themes of the CO of intolerance of ambiguity include, for example,
acceptance of authority, clear demarcation of domains, avoidance multiplic-
ity in favor of homogeneity, internal control, and avoidance of changes. High
scorers had a shorter reaction time before identifying ambiguous figures or
colors (Kreitler, Maguen, & Kreitler, 1975).
Chaotic thinking is one of the most recent cognitive styles. The CO of cha-
otic thinking includes themes such as acceptance of inconsistency, preference
for complexity, preference for ambiguities, avoidance of direct confrontation
with difficulties, trying not to miss opportunities, and being aware regard-
ing the environment. In tasks of planning, high scorers in the CO of cha-
otic thinking as compared with low scorers produced more different plans
and considered in each plan a greater variety of aspects, including consider-
ation for personal needs of involved individuals; in tasks of model building,
they produced more complex models, considering imaginary eventualities
(Kreitler, & Margaliot, in press).
the cognitive scene led to the following findings as compared with the dom-
inance of the interpersonally-shared mode: identifying embedded figures is
faster and with fewer errors; gestalt completion is faster; there are more asso-
ciations, especially personal associations; judging emotional expressions on
faces is faster and with fewer errors; visual memory is better; understanding
of poetry is better; art preferences in the visual arts change in the direction
of the expressionistic and symbolists art works; scores on creativity tests are
higher; reaction time of response to neutral stimuli is slower; judging validity
of syllogisms is poorer; indices of emotional control and reality testing on the
Rorschach test are poorer; accuracy of size estimations and size comparisons
of lines and circles is poorer. (Kreitler, Kreitler, & Wanounou, 1987–1988).
Because the modes of meaning were correlated with and led to so many
different and variegated cognitive effects and in addition to other effects (e.g.,
self-image, emotions), it seemed justified to consider the changes in the cog-
nitive system as representing states of consciousness.
Further studies showed that other configurations of meaning variables also
led to pervasive results in cognitive performance, although of a different kind
than those obtained by means of the meaning modes. In these studies, the
experimental induction did not focus on the meaning variables but on attitu-
dinal approaches (abstract or concrete approach) or emotional states (anger
or joy). Each of these inductions produced specific changes in the meaning
variables dominating the cognitive scene. These changes in the dominant
meaning variables were responsible for changes in cognitive performance.
For example, the induction of the concrete approach led to the salience of
the meaning variables relating to the concrete aspects of objects (e.g., sensory
qualities, material, weight, size, location) and to weakening of the meaning
variables relating to more abstract features (e.g., superordinate categories,
subclasses). Accordingly, the judgments of the subjects about severity of situ-
ations were more limited in scope and reflected consideration of fewer rele-
vant aspects (Rotstein, 2010).
The conclusion supported by these preliminary studies is that the state of
the cognitive system at a given time – which may be called state of conscious-
ness – plays a role in codetermining the cognitive output. However, it is still
unclear at present in which ways the state of the cognitive system affects the
output. One way may be assumed to be through cognitive programs. This is
likely because these programs depend on meaning variables (see Table 2.1)
and the state of the cognitive system consists in the differential salience of
meaning variables.
Another possibility would be that the state of the cognitive system also
affects the salience of different CO clusters. It could be the case that in a
The Structure and Dynamics of Cognitive Orientation 55
Cognitive Cognitive
Types Acts
Specific
Cognitive Act
Cognitive
function Cognitive Programs
Cognitive Cognitive
Domains Styles
one deals with recurrent acts. For many cognitive acts, there are already CO
questionnaires that may be freely used. Concerning the cognitive program, it is
mostly only necessary to check its availability by questioning or observation.
In the studies in which both the CO clusters of cognitive acts and the avail-
ability of cognitive programs were considered, it turned out that the rela-
tive weight of these two factors are approximately equal (Kreitler & Casakin,
2009; Kreitler & Kreitler, 1987a, 1987b).
In addition to predicting cognitive acts, the CO approach provides the the-
oretical and methodological means for changing cognitive performance by
focusing on the relevant CO clusters, cognitive programs, and state of con-
sciousness (Kreitler, 2009a; Kreitler & Kreitler, 1990a). A major role of the CO
model of cognitive functioning is to serve as a platform and framework for
further studies that will continue to clarify and improve the existing approach
and discover new venues and perspectives for the exploration of cognition.
References
Altshuller, G. (1984). Creativity as an exact science. New York: Gordon & Breach.
Anderson, J. R. (1993). Problem solving and learning. American Psychologist, 48, 35–44.
Bechara, A. (2004). The role of emotion in decision-making: Evidence from neurologi-
cal patients with orbitofrontal damage. Brain and Cognition, 55, 30–40.
Casakin, H., & Kreitler, S. (2010). Motivation for creativity in architectural design:
Differences between architects and engineers. International Journal of Technology
and Design Education, 20, 477–493.
Casakin, H., & Kreitler, S. (in press). Studying design problem solving through the the-
ory of meaning. In S. Helie (Ed.), The psychology of problem solving: An interdisci-
plinary approach. Hauppauge, New York: Nova Publishers.
Csíkszentmihályi, M. (1998). Creativity: Flow and the psychology of discovery and inven-
tion. New York: Harper Perennial.
Damasio, A. (1994). Descartes’ error. New York: Putnam’s Sons.
Geary, D. C. (2005). Origin of mind: Evolution of brain, cognition, and general intelli-
gence. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.
Greenspan, P. (2004). Practical reasoning and emotion. In A. Mele & P. Rawling (Eds.),
The Oxford handbook of rationality (pp. 206–221). Oxford, UK: Oxford University
Press.
Isen, A. M. (2004). Some perspectives on positive feelings and emotions: Positive affect
facilitates thinking and problem solving. In A. S. R. Manstead, N. Frijda, & A.
Fischer (Eds.), Feelings and emotions: The Amsterdam symposium. Studies in emo-
tion and social interaction (pp. 263–281). New York: Cambridge University Press.
Kreitler, S. (1999). Consciousness and meaning. In J. Singer & P. Salovey (Eds.), At play
in the fields of consciousness: Essays in honor of Jerome L. Singer (pp. 175–206).
Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
(2001). Psychological perspective on virtual reality. In A. Riegel, M. F. Peschl, K. Edlinger,
G. Fleck, & W. Feigl (Eds.), Virtual reality: Cognitive foundations, technological issues
and philosophical implications (pp. 33–44). Frankfurt, Germany: Peter Lang.
The Structure and Dynamics of Cognitive Orientation 59
Naqvi, N., Shiv, B., & Bechara, A. (2006). The role of emotion in decision making: A
cognitive neuroscience perspective. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 15,
260–264.
Newell, A., & Simon, H. A. (1972). Human problem solving. Englewood Cliffs, NJ:
Prentice-Hall.
Nurymberg, K., Kreitler, S., & Weissler, K. (1996). The cognitive orientation of com-
pliance in short and long-term type 2 diabetic patients. Patient Education and
Counseling, 29, 25–39.
Piaget, J., & Inhelder, B. (1973). Memory and intelligence. New York: Basic Books.
Polya, G. (1957). How to solve it (2nd ed.). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Richter, R. (2003). Cognitive aspects of creativity. Unpublished master’s thesis, Tel-Aviv
University.
Roth, G., & Wullimann, M. F. (2001). Brain evolution and cognition. New York: Wiley.
Rotstein, Y. (2010). The impact of transformations in state of consciousness on changes in
judgments and evaluations. Unpublished Master’s Thesis, Tel-Aviv University.
Sternberg, R. J., & Frensch, P. A. (Eds.), (1991). Complex problem solving: Principles and
mechanisms (pp. 159–183). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Tipton, R. M., & Riebsame, W. E. (1987). Beliefs about smoking and health: their mea-
surement and relationship to smoking behavior. Addictive Behaviors, 12, 217–223.
Westhoff, K., & Halbach-Suarez, C. (1989). Cognitive orientation and the prediction
of decisions in a medical examination context. European Journal of Personality, 3,
31–71.
Yiend, J. (2010). The effects of emotion on attention: A review of attentional processing
of emotional information. Cognition and Emotion, 24, 3–47.
Zakay, D., Bar-El, Z., & Kreitler, S. (1984). Cognitive orientation and changing the impul-
sivity of children. British Journal of Educational Psychology, 54, 40–50.
3
Situational Press
One of the barriers to traditional investigation of the relations between per-
sonality and cognitive traits is a mismatch between the context for these two
domains. As noted by Cronbach (1949), personality traits are considered an
individual’s needs and orientation in the context of typical behaviors. That is,
personality traits are less likely to be manifest in behaviors when the individual
62
Personality and Cognition 63
cognition interact, in both the short-term and over the course of develop-
ment and maturation.
In contrast, one can also consider personality traits in a maximal perfor-
mance context. For example, an individual’s level of introversion/extrover-
sion describes that individual’s preference for being in social situations, but
it does not inherently describe the individual’s capability of performing in
social situations when there is a strong situational press. Many introverts are
quite unhappy when forced to give a presentation to a large audience, but are
nonetheless capable of performing well under such circumstances. Very little
research has been conducted in this area (Willerman, Turner, & Peterson,
1976), but it is possible that individual differences in personality traits set a
zone of tolerable problemiticity for particular kinds of situations. An individ-
ual who is highly extroverted may be able to work in isolation for an hour or
two, but perhaps no longer without needing a break to interact with others;
an individual who is highly introverted may be able to function well at a party
for a similar amount of time, but as time increases, remaining at the party
may become more and more aversive for the individual. It is also possible
that there are individual differences in the flexibility to adapt to situations
where the situational press works in ways that are counter to the individual’s
baseline preferences.
Trait Complexes
As individuals reach early adulthood, we tend to see greater coherence in a
plethora of affective, cognitive, and conative traits. In a meta-analysis of per-
sonality trait, intellectual ability, and vocational interest relations, Ackerman
and Heggestad (1997) found at least four broad sets of traits that had sig-
nificant degrees of overlap, namely: Social, Intellectual/Cultural, Clerical/
Conventional, and Science/Math. The Social trait complex is represented by
the relatively high correlations between measures of Extroversion and both
Enterprising and Social vocational interest themes. The Intellectual/Cultural
trait complex is represented by the overlap among crystallized intellectual
abilities (e.g., verbal abilities and domain knowledge). The personality trait
complex is represented by the overlap of openness to experience and artis-
tic and investigative vocational interest themes. The Clerical/Conventional
66 Ackerman
skills in math. The most plausible framework for such developmental influ-
ences is that the profiles of affective, cognitive, and conative traits develop
in a manner where there are multiple feedback loops and cross-influences.
Furthermore, on a day-to-day basis, the influences are likely to take place
at such a low level that they do not even pervade conscious attention. By
the time an individual reaches adolescence, however, these profiles are surely
noticeable in terms of how that person interacts with his/her environment,
whether at school, home, or with his/her peers.
Closing Thoughts
Affect and cognition have traditionally been considered relatively independent
areas of inquiry, and as a consequence, implicitly considered to be relatively
independent in their operations. In fact, it is quite common to see personal-
ity traits referred to in the literature as “non-ability traits.” In the context of
research from the last two decades, this label should be seen as misleading at
best. Cognitive activities involve a complex interplay of intellectual processes
and personality processes, such as when one is attempting to memorize new
names of people met at a party, trying to think of someone who will make an
ideal match for other members of a dinner party, or deciding what to do for a
vacation. Our likes and dislikes have an essential affective component that is
often mediated by our abilities and cognitive styles associated with our daily
problem solving.
Similarly, individual differences in personality traits affect the individual’s
orientation toward or away from various stimuli for further cognitive pro-
cessing. People who are high in neuroticism, for example, appear to devote
substantial cognitive attention toward parsing situations in search of person-
ally threatening stimuli (Matthews & Deary, 1998). How we code situations or
even evaluate the situational press of a particular environment also involves
both affective and cognitive processes. Some individuals will interpret a situa-
tion as having less environmental press than others, and may behave in a way
that is more typical for them than others who interpret the environmental
press as allowing little flexibility for behavior. An employee who shows up late
for the first day of work might represent someone who either has miscoded
the strength of the situation or who has a much lower level of conscientious-
ness than other employees who arrive on time or early to work. This pattern
is reflected in the so-called honeymoon effect described by Helmreich, Sawin,
and Carsrud (1986). That is, personality traits may not be highly related to
job performance and other job-related behaviors – such as citizenship behav-
iors – early in job tenure, but with additional time in the job, personality traits
become significantly correlated with job performance and other job-related
behaviors.
In the final analysis, although there is clearly justification for considering
personality and cognition as important domains in their own right, there are
various points of interaction and interplay that occur between an individual’s
preferences, desires, and modes of addressing the world, on the one hand,
and their cognitive processes and skills, on the other hand. The correlations
between personality traits and cognitive abilities are significant, but not espe-
cially large in magnitude. These correlations, however, mask two important
Personality and Cognition 73
aspects of the larger picture. First, there is a mismatch between the condi-
tions of assessment for personality (typical behaviors) and cognitive ability
(maximal performance). Second, personality differences are most frequently
influential, when there are relatively low levels of environmental press. When
these considerations are taken into account, the correlations found between
personality traits and cognitive-ability measures suggest that even in the
maximal performance situations of cognitive-ability testing personality traits
have an influence, whether it is in the testing situation itself or more a result
of an accumulated set of the individual’s experiences.
References
Ackerman, P. L. (1996). A theory of adult intellectual development: process, personality,
interests, and knowledge. Intelligence, 22, 229–259.
(1997). Personality, self-concept, interests, and intelligence: Which construct doesn’t
fit? Journal of Personality, 65(2), 171–204.
(2003). Aptitude complexes and trait complexes. Educational Psychologist, 38, 85–93.
(2006). Personality, trait complexes, and adult intelligence. In A. Eliasz, S. Hampson,
& B. de Raad (Eds.), Advances in personality, Volume II (pp. 91–112). New York:
Psychology Press.
Ackerman, P. L., & Beier, M. E. (2006). Determinants of domain knowledge and inde-
pendent study learning in an adult sample. Journal of Educational Psychology, 98,
366–381.
Ackerman, P. L., Beier, M. B., & Bowen, K. R. (2002). What we really know about our
abilities and our knowledge. Personality and Individual Differences, 34, 587–605.
Ackerman, P. L., & Heggestad, E. D. (1997). Intelligence, personality, and interests:
Evidence for overlapping traits. Psychological Bulletin, 121, 219–245.
Ackerman, P. L., & Wolman, S. D. (2007). Determinants and validity of self-estimates
of abilities and self-concept measures. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Applied,
13, 57–78.
Beier, M. E., & Ackerman, P. L. (2001). Current events knowledge in adults: An investi-
gation of age, intelligence and non-ability determinants. Psychology and Aging, 16,
615–628.
Carstensen, L. L. (1998). A life-span approach to social motivation. In J. Heckhausen &
C. S. Dweck (Eds.), Motivation and self-regulation across the life span (pp. 341–364).
New York: Cambridge University Press.
Cattell, R. B. (1971). Abilities: their structure, growth, and action. NY: Houghton Mifflin Co.
Chamarro-Premuzic, T., & Furnham, A. (2008). Personality, intelligence and approaches
to learning as predictors of academic performance. Personality and Individual
Differences, 44, 1596–1603.
Chamorro-Premuzic, T., Furnham, A., & Moutafi, J. (2004). The relationship between
estimated and psychometric personality and intelligence scores. Journal of Research
in Personality, 38, 505–513.
Cronbach, L. J. (1949). Essentials of psychological testing (1st edition). New York: Harper
& Brothers.
74 Ackerman
Demetriou, A., Kyriakides, L., & Avraamidou, C. (2003). The missing link in the rela-
tions between intelligence and personality. Journal of Research in Personality, 37,
547–581.
Harris, J. A., Vernon, P. A., & Jang, K. L. (2007). Rated personality and measured intelli-
gence in young twin children. Personality and Individual Differences, 42, 75–86.
Helmreich, R. L., Sawin, L. L., & Carsrud, A. L. (1986). The honeymoon effect in job per-
formance: Temporal increases in the predictive power of achievement motivation.
Journal of Applied Psychology, 71, 185–188.
Holland, J. L. (1959). A theory of vocational choice. Journal of Counseling Psychology, 6
(1), 35–45.
Horn, J. L. (1989). Cognitive diversity: A framework of learning. In P. L. Ackerman, R.
J. Sternberg, & R. Glaser (Eds.), Learning and individual differences. Advances in
theory and research (pp. 61–116). New York: W. H. Freeman.
Humphreys, M. S., & Revelle, W. (1984). Personality, motivation, and performance: A
theory of the relationship between individual differences and information process-
ing. Psychological Review, 91, 153–184.
Jones, C. J., & Meredith, W. (1996). Patterns of personality changes across the life span.
Psychology and Aging, 11, 57–65.
Judge, T. A., Heller, D., & Mount, M. K. (2002). Five-factor model of personality and job
satisfaction: A meta-analysis. Journal of Applied Psychology, 87, 530–541.
Kanfer, R., & Ackerman, P. L. (2000). Individual differences in work motivation: Further
explorations of a trait framework. Applied Psychology: An International Review, 49
(3), 469–481.
(2004). Aging, adult development and work motivation. Academy of Management
Review, 29 (3), 440–458.
Kant, I. (1790). Critique of judgment. Translated by Werner S. Pluhar. Indianapolis, IN:
Hackett Publishing Co.
Marsh, H. W., Trautwein, U., Ludtke, O., Koller, O., & Baumert, J. (2005). Academic
self-concept, interest, grades, and standardized test scores: Reciprocal effect mod-
els of causal ordering. Child Development, 76, 397–416.
Matthews, G., & Deary, I. J. (1998). Personality traits. NY: Cambridge University Press.
McDougall, W. (1933). The energies of man: A study of the fundamentals of dynamic psy-
chology. New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons.
Murphy, S. T., & Zajonc, R. B. (1993). Affect, cognition, and awareness: Affective prim-
ing with optimal and suboptimal stimulus exposures. Journal of Personality and
Social Psychology, 64, 723–739.
Revelle, W., Humphreys, M. S., Simon, L., & Gilliland, K. (1980). The interactive effect
of personality, time of day, and caffeine: A test of the arousal model. Journal of
Experimental Psychology: General, 109, 1–31.
Rushton, J. P., Brainerd, C. J., & Pressley, M. (1983). Behavioral development and con-
struct validity: The principle of aggregation. Psychological Bulletin, 94, 18–38.
Sarason, S. B. (1959). Test anxiety. Journal of the National Education Association, 48 (8),
26–27.
Shavelson, R. J., Hubner, J. J., & Stanton, G. C. (1976). Self-concept: Validation of con-
struct interpretations. Review of Educational Research, 46, 407–441.
Sullivan, B. A., & Hansen, J-I. C. (2004). Mapping associations between interests and
personality: Toward a conceptual understanding of individual differences in voca-
tional behavior. Journal of Counseling Psychology, 51, 287–298.
Personality and Cognition 75
Tokar, D. M., & Subich, L. M. (1997). Relative contributions of congruence and personal-
ity dimensions to job satisfaction. Journal of Vocational Behavior, 50, 482–491.
Willerman, L., Turner, R. G., & Peterson, M. (1976). A comparison of the predic-
tive validity of typical and maximal personality measures. Journal of Research in
Personality, 10, 482–492.
4
Introduction
The fundamental interrelation between the rational and emotional elements
of human nature has been discussed since the old Greek philosophers Plato
and Aristotle. Although Plato’s theory of mind was essentially dualist, assum-
ing an earthly body that is inhabited by a divine soul, Aristotle proposed
a functionalist model of the mind. Plato’s idea that affect is a dangerous,
invasive force subverting rational thinking has recurred in many theories
throughout the ages. In his psychodynamic model, Freud, for example, sug-
gested that the Id has to be dominated by the ego (Lyons, 2008). The view
that emotion is also an essential component in cognition and behaviour has
emerged through advances in our understanding of emotion and social cog-
nition and their underlying neurobiological substrates (e.g., Adolphs, 2002,
2009; Ochsner & Gross, 2005; Pessoa, 2008; Van Overwalle, 2009). This
renewed interest in the relationship between cognition and emotion has led
to the development of innovative interdisciplinary research approaches in
this field.
The main aim of this review is to identify normal and pathological con-
ditions in which cognition, emotion, and motivation can dissociate and act
independently of each other as well as conditions in which they are associated
and interact. Neurobiological, neuropsychological, and psychopathological
evidence supports a concept of functional segregation for these modalities,
albeit there is evidence suggesting in certain contexts that emotion and moti-
vation modulate – that is, enhance or impair, cognition, and emotion may
even dominate cognition (e.g., Clore & Palmer, 2009). Rather, it appears that
cognition serves as a tool that is used by the emotional and motivational sys-
tems. Thus, cognitive processes are always embedded in emotional and moti-
vational contexts. It is, therefore, the interplay between cognition, emotion,
76
Cognition in the Context of Psychopathology 77
2009). For the integration of cognition, emotion, and motivation, the lateral
prefrontal cortex appears crucial, whereas other prefrontal cortical areas
(orbitofrontal, ventromedial, anterior cingulate areas) are strongly involved
in affective function (Pessoa, 2008).
It is commonly assumed that only the ‘objective’ information about objects –
or in social situations, about persons – determines our attitudes towards and
judgments about them. One’s evaluations, however, are also based on infor-
mation from one’s own affective states and reactions. Especially in social
situations, the feelings that are elicited in us by other people are the crucial
factor in the evaluation of other people (Clore & Huntsinger, 2007). Although
knowing and feeling are intrinsically intertwined, there are methods to exam-
ine cognition and emotion separately through experimental control of one
or the other (Clore & Palmer, 2009). Interestingly, experimentally induced
mood states demonstrate differential effects of different affective conditions
on cognitive processing of stimuli (Westermann et al., 1996). Differences in
positive and negative mood have been found in regard to decision making,
memory, information processing, and attention (Ashby, Isen, & Turken, 1999;
Clore & Huntsinger, 2007).
Interestingly, patterns of emotion function differentially in different peri-
ods of development and influence cognition and behaviour associated with
different forms of psychopathology (Izard et al., 2002). There are individual
differences in the motivation to approach or avoid emotion-inducing situa-
tions. This motivation is known as ‘need for affect’ (Maio & Esses, 2001), and
depends on cognitive processes (information processing and attention allo-
cation subserving the need for cognition; inhibition and activation of behav-
ioural responses), emotional processes (e.g., affect intensity, affect sensitivity),
and personality traits. In addition, individual differences in the need for affect
and social behaviour may be explained by individual differences in emotional
development, because feedback between cognition and emotion may gen-
erate, maintain, and reconfigure representations of emotional events. This
interaction between cognition and emotion also subserves self-organisation
of individual developmental paths through periods of stability and change,
thus stabilising the whole system and guaranteeing an emotional equilibrium
(Lewis, 1995).
Despite empirical evidence that cognition and emotion belong to different
brain systems and that many brain areas may be conceptualised as either cog-
nitive or affective, it is important to stress that both cognition and emotion
are intimately intertwined and dependent on each other. Pessoa (2008) sug-
gested that complex cognitive-emotional actions have their basis in ‘dynamic
coalitions’ of brain networks that possess a high degree of connectivity.
80 Zihl, Szesny, & Nickel
orbitofrontal injury (Namiki et al., 2008) and in cases with traumatic dif-
fuse axonal brain injury (Green, Turner, & Thompson, 2004). Brain-injured
subjects suffering from executive dysfunction may benefit less from remedia-
tion of emotion recognition deficits (McDonald, Bornhofen, & Hunt, 2009).
Interestingly, subjects with retrograde amnesia may nevertheless be able
to recollect (pleasant) emotional events from their lives. Medial temporal
structures, but not the hippocampus, appear crucial for emotional autobio-
graphical memory, indicating dissociation between the long-term storage of
semantic (i.e., cognitive) contents and that of emotional contents (Buchanan,
Tranel, & Adolphs, 2005).
Patients with cerebrovascular or traumatic (right-sided) brain injury may
show impairments in recognising affective information from the face, voice,
bodily movement, and posture (Bornhofen & McDonald, 2008; Charbonneau
et al., 2003; Kucharska-Pietura et al., 2003), which may persistently interfere
with successful negotiation of social interactions (Ietswaart et al., 2008). In
addition, controlling and modulating vocal affect as well as comprehension
and expression of affective sentences (prosody) may also be impaired, and
may contribute to impaired communication competence and poor social out-
come (Marquardt, Rios-Brown, & Richburg, 2001; Watts & Douglas, 2006;
Wildgruber et al., 2006; Zupan et al., 2009). Interestingly, face perception,
the use of context cues, and semantic knowledge can be affected at the same
time the perception of linguistic specifications of prosody is relatively spared,
indicating a dissociation between cognition (face processing capacities and
semantic knowledge) and recognition of emotion from prosody and facial
expression (Croker & McDonald, 2005; Green et al., 2004; Pell, 1998).
Impairments of emotional and social behaviour are typically observed after
frontal lobe injury. It can be explained by defective or lost stimulus-reinforcer
associations, inaccurate evaluation of stimuli signifying reward or punish-
ment in a social context, and failures to translate emotional and social infor-
mation into task- and context-appropriate action patterns. These functional
impairments arise from impaired perception and interpretation of social and
emotional stimuli, inadequate hypotheses about the social environment, and
inadequate selection of emotional and social actions. Consequently, patients
may show deficient social judgements and decision making; social and per-
haps also cognitive inflexibility; lack of self-monitoring, particularly in social
situations; and deficient goal-directed behaviour, including apathy, disinhibi-
tion, task impersistence, and general disorganisation (Hornak, Rolls, & Wade,
1996; Rankin, 2007; Vecera & Rizzo, 2004).
Depression. According to the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental
Disorders (DSM-IV), depression is a mental disorder that is characterised by
Cognition in the Context of Psychopathology 83
low mood, loss of interest, feelings of guilt, low self-worth, disturbed sleep and
appetite, listlessness, and cognitive dysfunctions independent of its origin as
a result of head injury or as an entity on its own (APA, 1994). In depression,
there is evidence for associations as well as dissociations between cognitive
and emotional dysfunctions. Patients may exhibit affective and cognitive dys-
functions, but cognitive impairments may also persist even after improve-
ment of depressive symptomatology (Frasch et al., 2009; Landro, Stiles, &
Sletvold, 2001; Majer et al., 2004; Reppermund et al., 2007; Reppermund et
al., 2009). Yet, there is also evidence in these studies for preserved cognition
in the presence of depressive symptomatology. Because these differential pat-
terns can hardly be explained by a lack of motivation, it may be speculated
whether these two patterns of dysfunction represent two distinct subgroups.
However, irrespective of the presence of cognitive dysfunction, all patients
complain of more or less pronounced difficulties with attention, memory, and
executive function. This indicates that self-perception of patient’s cognitive
capacities does not always match with the objectively assessed cognitive sta-
tus, indicating that at the level of awareness, there seems to be no dissociation
between (self-perceived) cognitive performance and emotional dysfunc-
tion. Impairments of cognitive functions have been found in a wide range
of cognitive domains (e.g., episodic memory, learning, attention, and exec-
utive functions) (Austin, Mitchell, & Goodwin, 2001; Bearden et al., 2006;
Stordal et al., 2004; Zihl, Groen, & Brunnauer, 1998). Reduced motivation
in depression is known to impair cognitive performance, possibly because
task-specific self-efficacy and enhancement of task-focused attention fail to
increase performance level (Scheurich et al., 2008). The impact of severity
and subtype of depression on cognitive dysfunction as well as the influence
of age, comorbid disorders, and persistence of these impairments after recov-
ery are still unclear (Austin et al., 2001; Castaneda et al., 2008; Majer et al.,
2004; Reppermund et al., 2009). However, cognitive deficits might persist
longer than the period of illness, yet this seems to be true for all depressive
sub-diagnoses (Neu, Kiesslinger, Schlattmann, & Reischies, 2001).
There is preliminary evidence that particularly executive dysfunction in
depression may represent a risk factor for relapse (Dunkin et al., 2000; Majer
et al., 2004; Simons et al., 2009), indicating that recovery of emotion regu-
lation and mood may not be sufficient for gaining and stabilising emotional
equilibrium. Multiple sources of evidence support the view that depression
is associated with frontal lobe dysfunction (Harrison, 2002; Lesser & Chung,
2007). This view would also explain the associative patterns of cognitive and
emotional dysfunction as well as the dissociations between the two domains;
differing degrees of dysfunction in prefrontal regions can result in more
84 Zihl, Szesny, & Nickel
regional frontal lobe syndromes (Duffy & Campbell, 2002). In a more recent
paper, Dichter, Felder and Smoski (2009) reported a double dissociation of
prefrontal responses in subjects with unipolar depression to the contexts in
which the target events were embedded. In a neutral context, they found a
hypoactivation of prefrontal structures, which is consistent with findings in
normal subjects. In contrast, cognitive control stimuli embedded in a sad
context revealed a greater activation of prefrontal structures in the depressed
group than in normal subjects. This result could be interpreted as a greater
cognitive effort that is required in depression for disengaging from the sad
images in order to respond to the target stimuli. Depressed subjects may also
show increased processing of negative stimuli and/or diminished processing of
positive verbal and visual stimuli, which is paralleled by corresponding brain
activation patterns, albeit this finding may only apply to specific subgroups
(Canli et al., 2004; Surguladze et al., 2004). These alterations may explain
impaired interpersonal functioning in depression, although the mode of pre-
sentation of emotional stimuli (e.g., facial expressions) may be crucial; when
dynamic facial expressions are used, subjects with depression may perform
like normal subjects (Kan et al., 2004). Thus, in a depressive state, additional
visual-social information may be required for proper processing and inter-
pretation (i.e., visual cortical areas can enhance emotion processing) (Schultz
& Pilz, 2009). Yet, because this enhancement effect also depends on attention
allocation to stimuli, the inability to accurately recognise subtle facial emo-
tional signals may be understood as a perceptual bias towards high arousal
emotions (Csukly et al., 2009). In bipolar disorders, emotion perception and
affect generation deficits have been reported in association with impaired
executive function (cognitive control and regulation), suggesting that the
variations in mood can be explained partly in terms of specific impairments
in the cognitive control of emotion (Green, Cahill, & Malhi, 2007).
A summary of the observations on the pathology of cognition and emo-
tion after acquired brain injury and in depression shows that there is convinc-
ing empirical evidence for the association as well as for the dissociation of
symptoms. Furthermore, negative emotions can lower functional recovery
after brain injury and positive emotions can enhance recovery. In depres-
sion, cognitive dysfunction may increase the risk for relapse. Thus, emo-
tion definitely can modulate cognition. Yet, cognition subserves emotion in
regaining and maintaining individual self-organisation in periods of change
(e.g., after highly challenging life events, brain injury, or in depression) and
may thus constitute a protective factor. Cognition may therefore be consid-
ered as a tool for planning, executing, and monitoring adaptation to chal-
lenging conditions and thus for developing and improving coping strategies
Cognition in the Context of Psychopathology 85
(Ochsner & Gross, 2005). Emotion may elicit, maintain (via motivation), and
reinforce such cognitive activities unless successful tools for coping are devel-
oped and tested, and also found useful for transfer. Cognition, emotion, and
motivation are also engaged in the evaluation of the usefulness of such coping
strategies, either concerning their feasibility, accuracy, and speed (cognition)
or concerning their positive and negative value for an individual in terms of
the specific personal significance of the coping strategy and its effect on one’s
own behaviour and that of others. The resulting emotional and cognitive
adaptation is important for improving and maintaining self-regulated emo-
tional control based on various feedbacks between cognitive and emotional
components of the coping strategy. These feedbacks can then generate, main-
tain, and reconfigure the representation of the adaptation to the challeng-
ing task as cognitive and emotional events or as a cognitive-emotional event.
Emotional regulation involves the initiation of new or at least adapted (i.e.,
adequate) emotional responses and inhibition of inappropriate responses.
In conditions of reduced deployment of attentional resources, emotional
information is prioritised and receives privileged access to attention and
awareness (so-called emotional attention), which enhances processing of
emotional signals (Vuilleumier, 2005). For developing and using coping strat-
egies in emotion regulation, personality traits also come into play, as they
are known to influence cognitive activities (e.g., Connor-Smith & Flachsbart,
2007). Personality traits can thus enhance (viz. openness), impede, or at least
bias (viz. neuroticism) the development and selection of environment- and
task-related adaptation strategies. As Bienvenu et al. (2004) have shown, low
assertiveness and high openness to feelings are associated with major depres-
sive disorder; neuroticism is related to its acuity. It seems, therefore, that
personality traits exert their main influence on cognition via the domain of
emotion, which becomes manifest particularly in psychopathological states
such as depression.
In conclusion, cognition and emotion seem to represent two separable but
intensively and reciprocally interacting functional systems, which can modu-
late each other positively and negatively. As a rule, they cooperate when devel-
oping, testing, and selecting strategies for coping with challenging events and
tasks as well as for maintaining emotional stability over time.
References
Adolphs, R. (2002). Neural systems for recognizing emotion. Current Opinion in
Neurobiology, 12, 169–177.
(2003). Cognitive neuroscience of human social behaviour. Nature Reviews
Neuroscience, 4, 165–178.
(2009). The social brain: Neural basis of social knowledge. Annual Review of
Psychology, 60, 693–716.
Adolphs, R., & Tranel, D. (2004). Impaired judgments of sadness but not happiness fol-
lowing bilateral amygdala damage. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 16, 453–462.
Adolphs, R., Tranel, D., & Damasio, A. R. (2003). Dissociable neural systems for recog-
nizing emotions. Brain and Cognition, 52, 61–69.
APA (1994). Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders, 4th Edition, (DSM-IV).
Washington, DC : American Psychiatric Association.
APA Dictionary (2007). Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.
Ashby, F. G., Isen, A. M., & Turken, U. (1999). A neuropsychological theory of positive
affect and its influence on cognition. Psychological Review, 106, 529–550.
Austin, M. P., Mitchell, P., & Goodwin, G. M. (2001). Cognitive deficits in depression –
Possible implications for functional neuropathology. British Journal of Psychiatry,
178, 200–206.
Barbas, H. (2000). Connections underlying the synthesis of cognition, memory, and
emotion in primate prefrontal cortices. Brain Research Bulletin, 52, 319–330.
Baumeister, R. F., Vohs, K. D., Dewall, C. N., & Zhang, L. Q. (2007). How emotion
shapes behavior: Feedback, anticipation, and reflection, rather than direct causa-
tion. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 11, 167–203.
Bearden, C. E., Glahn, D. C., Monkul, E. S., Barrett, J., Najt, P., Villarreal, V., & Soares, J.
C. (2006). Patterns of memory impairment in bipolar disorder and unipolar major
depression. Psychiatry Research, 142, 139–150.
Bienvenu, O. J., Samuels, J. F., Costa, P. T., Reti, I. M., Eaton, W. W., & Nestadt, G.
(2004). Anxiety and depressive disorders and the five-factor model of personality:
A higher- and lower-order personality trait investigation in a community sample.
Depression and Anxiety, 20, 92–97.
Bornhofen, C., & McDonald, S. (2008). Emotion perception deficits following traumatic
brain injury: A review of the evidence and rationale for intervention. Journal of the
International Neuropsychological Society, 14, 511–525.
Brodaty, H., Sachdev, P. S., Withall, A., Altendorf, A., Valenzuela, M. J., & Lorentz, L. (2005).
Frequency and clinical, neuropsychological and neuroimaging correlates of apathy
following stroke – The Sydney Stroke Study. Psychological Medicine, 35, 1707–1716.
90 Zihl, Szesny, & Nickel
Buchanan, T. W., Tranel, D., & Adolphs, R. (2005). Emotional autobiographical memo-
ries in amnesic patients with medial temporal lobe damage. Journal of Neuroscience,
25, 3151–3160.
Canli, T., Sivers, H., Thomason, M. E., Whitfield-Gabrieli, S., Gabrieli, J. D., & Gotlib, I.
H. (2004). Brain activation to emotional words in depressed vs. healthy subjects.
Neuroreport, 15, 2585–2588.
Castaneda, A. E., Suvisaari, J., Marttunen, M., Perälä, J., Saarni, S. I., Alto-Setälä, T. A. H.,
Koskinen, S., Lonnquits, J., & Tuulio-Henriksson, A. (2008). Cognitive function-
ing in a population-based sample of young adults with a history of non-psychotic
unipolar depressive disorders without psychiatric comorbidity. Journal of Affective
Disorders, 110, 36–45.
Charbonneau, S., Scherzer, B. P., Aspirot, D., & Cohen, H. (2003). Perception and pro-
duction of facial and prosodic emotions by chronic CVA patients. Neuropsychologia,
41, 605–613.
Chaytor, N., Temkin, N., Machamer, J., & Dikmen, S. (2007). The ecological validity
of neuropsychological assessment and the role of depressive symptoms in moder-
ate to severe traumatic brain injury. Journal of the International Neuropsychological
Society, 13, 377–385.
Clark, L., Iversen, S. D., & Goodwin, G. M. (2002). Sustained attention deficit in bipolar
disorder. British Journal of Psychiatry, 180, 313–319.
Clore, G. L., & Huntsinger, J. R. (2007). How emotions inform judgment and regulate
thought. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 11, 393–399.
Clore, G. L., & Palmer, J. (2009). Affective guidance of intelligent agents: How emotion
controls cognition. Cognitive Systems Research, 10, 21–30.
Compton, R. J. (2003). The interface between emotion and attention: a review of evi-
dence from psychology and neuroscience. Behavioral & Cognitive Neuroscience
Reviews 2, 115–129.
Connor-Smith, J. K., & Flachsbart, C. (2007). Relations between personality and coping:
A meta-analysis. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 93, 1080–1107.
Croker, V., & McDonald, S. (2005). Recognition of emotion from facial expression fol-
lowing traumatic brain injury. Brain Injury, 19, 787–799.
Csukly, G., Czobor, P., Szily, E., Takacs, B., & Simon, L. (2009). Facial expression recog-
nition in depressed subjects: the impact of intensity level and arousal dimension.
Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 197, 98–103.
Delgado, M. R. (2007). Reward-related responses in the human striatum. Annals of the
New York Academy of Sciences, 1104, 70–88.
Dichter, G. S., Felder, J. N., & Smoski, M. J. (2009). Affective context interferes with cog-
nitive control in unipolar depression: An fMRI investigation. Journal of Affective
Disorders, 114, 131–142.
Dosenbach, N. U., Fair, D. A., Cohen, A. L., Schlaggar, B. L., & Petersen, S. E. (2008). A
dual-networks architecture of top-down control. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 12,
99–105.
Dubrovsky, B. (1995). Fundamental neuroscience and the classification of psychiatric
disorders. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 19, 511–518.
Duffy, J. D., & Campbell, J. J. (2002). Regional prefrontal syndromes: a theoretical and
clinical overview. In D. T. Stuss & R. T. Knight (Eds.), Principles of frontal lobe func-
tion (pp. 113–123). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Cognition in the Context of Psychopathology 91
Dunkin, J. J., Leuchter, A. F., Cook, I. A., Kasl-Godley, J. E., Abrams, M., &
Rosenberg-Thompson, S. (2000). Executive dysfunction predicts nonresponse to
fluoxetine in major depression. Journal of Affective Disorders, 60, 13–23.
Enge, S., Fleischhauer, M., Brocke, B., & Strobel, A. (2008). Neurophysiological mea-
sures of involuntary and voluntary attention allocation and dispositional dif-
ferences in need for cognition. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 34,
862–874.
Frasch, K., Bullacher, C., Jaeger, M., Kilian, R., Rink, M., Wittek, R., Becker, T., &
Neurmann, N. U. (2009). Effects of symptom reduction and psychotropic medica-
tion on cognitive impairment in depression. Psychopathology, 42, 59–66.
Garety, P. A., Bebbington, P., Fowler, D., Freeman, D., & Kuipers, E. (2007). Implications
for neurobiological research of cognitive models of psychosis: a theoretical paper.
Psychological Medicine, 37, 1377–1391.
Gottlieb, J., Balan, P., Oristaglio, J., & Suzuki, M. (2009). Parietal control of attentional
guidance: the significance of sensory, motivational and motor factors. Neurobiology
of Learning & Memory, 91, 121–128.
Grady, C. L., & Keightley, M. L. (2002). Studies of altered social cognition in neuropsychi-
atric disorders using functional neuroimaging. Canadian Journal of Psychiatry, 47,
327–336.
Green, M. J., Cahill, C. M., & Malhi, G. S. (2007). The cognitive and neurophysiological
basis of emotion dysregulation in bipolar disorder. Journal of Affective Disorders,
103, 29–42.
Green, R. E., Turner, G. R., & Thompson, W. F. (2004). Deficits in facial emotion percep-
tion in adults with recent traumatic brain injury. Neuropsychologia, 42, 133–141.
Harrison, P. J. (2002). The neuropathology of primary mood disorders. Brain, 125,
1428–1449.
Herbener, E. S., Song, W., Khine, T. T., & Sweeney, J. A. (2008). What aspects of emo-
tional functioning are impaired in schizophrenia? Schizophrenia Research, 98,
239–246.
Hornak, J., Rolls, E., & Wade, D. (1996). Face and voice expression identification in
patients with emotional and behavioural changes following ventral frontal lobe
damage. Neuropsychologia, 34, 247–261.
Ietswaart, M., Milders, M., Crawford, J. R., Currie, D., & Scott, C. L. (2008).
Longitudinal aspects of emotion recognition in patients with traumatic brain
injury. Neuropsychologia, 46, 148–159.
Izard, C. E., Fine, S., Mostow, A., Trentacosta, C., & Campbell, J. (2002). Emotion
processes in normal and abnormal development and preventive intervention.
Development and Psychopathology, 14, 761–787.
Jimura, K., Locke, H. S., & Braver, T. S. (2010). Prefrontal cortex mediation of cogni-
tive enhancement in rewarding motivational contexts. Proceedings of the National
Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 107, 8871–8876.
Jorge, R. E., Robinson, R. G., Moser, D., Tateno, A., Crespo-Facorro, B., & Arndt, S.
(2004). Major depression following traumatic brain injury. Archives of General
Psychiatry, 61, 42–50.
Jorge, R. E., Robinson, R. G., Starkstein, S. E., & Arndt, S. V. (1994). Influence of major
depression on 1-year outcome in patients with traumatic brain injury. Journal of
Neurosurgery, 81, 726–733.
92 Zihl, Szesny, & Nickel
Taylor, S. F., & Liberzon, I. (2007). Neural correlates of emotion regulation in psychopa-
thology. Trends in Cognitive Science, 11, 413–418.
Tonks, J., Slater, A., Frampton, I., Wall, S. E., Yates, P., & Williams, W. H. (2009).
The development of emotion and empathy skills after childhood brain injury.
Developmental Medicine and Child Neurology, 51, 8–16.
Tonks, J., Williams, W. H., Frampton, I., Yates, P., Wall, S. E., & Slater, A. (2008).
Reading emotions after childhood brain injury: Case series evidence of dissocia-
tion between cognitive abilities and emotional expression processing skills. Brain
Injury, 22, 325–332.
Van Overwalle, F. (2009). Social Cognition and the Brain: A Meta-Analysis. Human
Brain Mapping, 30, 829–858.
Vecera, S. P., & Rizzo, M. (2004). What are you looking at? Impaired ‘social attention’
following frontal-lobe damage. Neuropsychologia, 42, 1657–1665.
Vuilleumier, P. (2005). How brains beware: neural mechanisms of emotional attention.
Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 9, 585–594.
Watts, A. J., & Douglas, J. M. (2006). Interpreting facial expression and communication
competence following severe traumatic brain injury. Aphasiology, 20, 707–722.
Westermann, R., Spies, K., Stahl, G., & Hesse, F. W. (1996). Relative effectiveness and
validity of mood induction procedures: A meta-analysis. European Journal of Social
Psychology, 26, 557–580.
WHO (1993). The ICD-10 Classification of Mental and Behavioral Disorders. Diagnostic
Criteria for Research. Geneva: World Health Organization.
Wildgruber, D., Ackermann, H., Kreifelts, B., & Ethofer T. (2006). Cerebral processing
of linguistic and emotional prosody: fMRI studies. Progress in Brain Research, 156,
249–268.
Wildgruber, D., Riecker, A., Hertrich, I., Erb, M., Grodd, W., Ethofer, T., & Ackermann,
H. (2005). Identification of emotional intonation evaluated by fMRI. Neuroimage,
24, 1233–1241.
Zihl, J., Groen, G., & Brunnauer, A. (1998). Cognitive deficits in schizophrenia and affec-
tive disorders: evidence for a final common pathway disorder. Acta Psychiatrica
Scandinavica, 97, 351–357.
Zupan, B., Neumann, D., Babbage, D. R., & Willer, B. (2009). The importance of vocal
affect to bimodal processing of emotion: Implications for individuals with trau-
matic brain injury. Journal of Communication Disorders, 42, 1–17.
5
Introduction
This chapter is concerned mainly with the effects of individual differences
in anxiety as a personality dimension on various kinds of cognitive perfor-
mance. More specifically, the emphasis will be on trait anxiety (a dimension
relating to general susceptibility to anxiety) and test anxiety (a dimension
relating to susceptibility to anxiety specifically in test situations). Not surpris-
ingly, there is typically a negative association or correlation between anxi-
ety and performance. For example, Hembree (1988) reviewed hundreds of
studies and found that the mean correlation between anxiety and aptitude or
achievement was −0.29. There are obvious issues here concerning the direc-
tion of causality: does anxiety impair performance or does poor performance
create anxiety? The evidence from intervention studies strongly suggests that
much of the association occurs because anxiety impairs performance. For
example, Schwarzer (1990) reviewed the findings from 137 intervention stud-
ies. Participants who received treatment for test anxiety had higher scores
on test performance and grade point average than participants in placebo or
waiting list groups.
There is another issue that needs to be addressed at this point. In addition
to the causality issue, there is an additional problem of interpretation with
studies, in which it is found that individuals scoring high in trait or test anx-
iety perform significantly worse than those scoring low. There is typically a
moderate correlation between trait measures of anxiety and state measures
(assessing current levels of anxiety). Accordingly, the findings may reflect the
direct influence of trait or test anxiety on performance or the influence may
be indirect via state anxiety. Surprisingly, this issue has been addressed in rel-
atively few studies, so it is not possible to adjudicate between these two pos-
sibilities. However, it would be useful in future research to use experimental
96
The Impact of Anxiety on Cognitive Performance 97
designs including low and high stress conditions to clarify the respective roles
of trait and state anxiety in affecting performance.
postdating that review, but will also include some of the most important ear-
lier research.
Working Memory
According to processing efficiency theory, anxiety is associated with worry,
and worry utilises some of the processing resources of the working memory
system. The assumption that worry requires working-memory capacity was
tested by Hayes, Hirsch, and Mathews (2008). They asked high and low wor-
riers to think about a current worry or a positive personally relevant topic
when attempting to press keys in a random order. High levels of performance
on this task require considerable use of the resources of working memory.
The key finding was that high worriers performed worse than low worriers
on the random key-press task only when engaged in worry. The implication
is that worry consumes some of the available attentional resources of working
memory and thus impairs task performance.
Evidence that the anxiety reduces the available capacity of working mem-
ory was reported by Derakshan and Eysenck (1998). They used a load par-
adigm, in which participants performed a primary task concurrently with
a secondary or load task that imposed low or high demands on working
memory capacity. The primary task involved simple reasoning, and the main
dependent variable was response latency on this task. There was no difference
between the low- and high-anxious groups on this measure when the second-
ary task imposed low demands on working memory capacity. However, the
adverse effects of a concurrent highly demanding secondary task on response
latency on the reasoning task were substantially greater for high-anxious than
for low-anxious participants. These findings suggest that individuals high in
trait anxiety had fewer available working memory resources to process the
reasoning task.
Additional evidence that the effects of anxiety on performance depend in
part on working memory capacity was reported by Johnson and Gronlund
(2009) in a study using a dual-task paradigm. They considered four groups of
individuals based on the two dimensions of trait anxiety and working mem-
ory capacity. There was a significant interaction between anxiety and work-
ing memory capacity: the adverse effects of high trait anxiety on dual-task
performance were especially great among those individuals low in working
memory capacity. This is consistent with the notion that reduced available
working memory capacity is in part responsible for anxiety’s impairment
effect on performance.
100 Eysenck
Eysenck, Payne, and Derakshan (2005) reported one of the most direct
attempts to test the prediction that anxiety impairs central-executive func-
tioning more than that of the other components of the working-memory
system. High- and low-anxious participants performed a primary com-
plex visuospatial task concurrently with a secondary task that varied in its
demands on the working memory system. More specifically, the secondary
task predominantly required use of the central executive or the phonological
loop or the visuospatial sketchpad. The key finding was that the high-anxious
group performed the primary visuospatial task significantly worse than the
low-anxious group only when the secondary task involved the central execu-
tive. These findings suggest that anxiety reduces the available capacity of the
central executive but has small or nonexistent effects on the capacity of the
phonological loop or the visuospatial sketchpad.
Owens et al. (2008) used a different experimental approach to show that
adverse effects of anxiety on performance depend on working memory. They
assessed verbal working memory (central executive + phonological loop) and
academic performance in individuals varying in their level of trait anxiety.
Anxiety was negatively associated with academic performance. However,
the key finding was that this association was mediated by verbal working
memory. In other words, much of the negative effect of anxiety on academic
performance occurred indirectly because anxiety impaired verbal working
memory.
Findings apparently discrepant with those of Owens et al. (2008) were
reported by Shackman et al. (2006). They found that threat-induced anxiety
impaired performance on a task involving spatial working memory but not
on one that involved verbal working-memory performance.
In sum, there is considerable evidence (much of it not discussed here) indi-
cating that high levels of trait anxiety are associated with impaired working-
memory functioning. Of the components of working memory, anxiety most
consistently impairs the central executive as predicted by processing efficiency
theory. However, there are apparently inconsistent findings concerning the
effects of anxiety on the phonological loop and the visuospatial sketchpad.
In principle, the most direct approach to identifying the components of the
working memory system adversely affected by anxiety is to use a dual-task
design with secondary tasks predominantly involving a single component
(Eysenck et al., 2005). It is more difficult to interpret the findings when the
effects of anxiety on a single task involving two separate components of the
working memory system are assessed (e.g., Owens et al., 2008; Shackman
et al., 2006).
The Impact of Anxiety on Cognitive Performance 101
2007, for a review). However, there is a limitation with most of these studies
in that they do not reveal the mechanisms responsible for the greater suscep-
tibility to distraction among high-anxious individuals.
The above issue was addressed by Derakshan et al. (2009). They assessed
the inhibition function by using the antisaccade task. On this task, partici-
pants are presented with a peripheral cue to the left or right of the fixation
point. They are instructed to avoid looking at the cue and instead to fixate on
the other side of the fixation point as rapidly as possible. What is of interest is
the latency of the first correct saccade to the side opposite that to which the
cue was presented. There is also a control condition (the prosaccade task), in
which the requirement is to fixate the cue as soon as it appears.
Derakshan et al. (2009) assumed that the antisaccade task requires use of
the inhibition function, whereas the prosaccade task does not. Accordingly,
they predicted that high-anxious individuals would take longer than low anx-
ious ones to make a correct saccade on the antisaccade task, but that anxiety
would have no effect on this dependent variable on the prosaccade task. This
was precisely what Derakshan et al. found in their first experiment, in which
the cue was an oval shape. In their second experiment, they used angry,
happy, and neutral facial expressions as cues. In view of the evidence that
anxious individuals have an attentional bias for threat-related stimuli (e.g.,
Bar-Haim et al., 2007), it was predicted that the slowing effects of anxiety on
the antisaccade task would be greatest when the cue was an angry face. That
prediction was supported.
As mentioned earlier, there has been very little research on anxiety and the
shifting function. However, Ansari, Derakshan, and Richards (2008) recently
reported findings from a task-switching study involving the antisaccade
and prosaccade tasks. There were two conditions. In the single-task condi-
tion, there were separate blocks of antisaccade and prosaccade trials. In the
mixed-task condition, antisaccade and prosaccade trials were interspersed. In
line with findings previously reported by other researchers, they found that
there was a paradoxical improvement in that the latency of the first correct
saccade on the antisaccade task was faster in the mixed-task condition than in
the single-task condition. The precise reasons for this paradoxical improve-
ment when the shifting function is required are not known, although it is
likely that it reflects a greater level of task engagement in the task-switching
condition. The key finding reported by Ansari et al. was that this paradox-
ical improvement in the task-switching condition was not obtained from
high-anxious participants but only from low anxious ones. The implication is
that high-anxious individuals are less efficient than low anxious ones at using
the shifting function.
The Impact of Anxiety on Cognitive Performance 105
Derakshan, Smyth, and Eysenck (2009) carried out the most thorough
study to date. What is required in order to assess the effects of anxiety on the
shifting function in a relatively direct way is to have two conditions differing
only in terms of the demands on the shifting function. Derakshan et al. used
pairs of tasks (e.g., multiplication and division). In the switching condition,
the task alternated on every trial. In the non-switching condition, in contrast,
each block of trials was devoted to a single task. The problems used were the
same in the switching and non-switching conditions.
Derakshan et al. (2009) obtained a highly significant interaction between
anxiety and task switching, and the nature of this interaction was as predicted
by attentional control theory. The high-anxious participants performed much
more slowly when task switching was required than when it was not, whereas
the low-anxious participants were relatively unaffected by the presence versus
absence of task switching.
Santos et al. (submitted) also investigated the effects of anxiety on the shift-
ing function. Participants performed three simple tasks under high-switching,
low-switching, and no-switching conditions. The fact that the tasks were all
simple probably explains why there were no effects of anxiety on performance
effectiveness in terms of reaction times and error rate. In order to assess
processing efficiency, Santos et al. used fMRI to record brain activity. It was
assumed that the increase in brain activation in the high- and low-switching
conditions compared to the no-switching condition was due to greater use
of processing resources when the shifting function was required. The fur-
ther assumption that high-anxious individuals would make more inefficient
use of the shifting function than low anxious ones led to the prediction that
there should be a greater increase in brain activation for individuals high in
anxiety. It was also predicted that the effects of anxiety on brain activation
should be especially pronounced in areas activated when the shifting func-
tion is used (e.g., BA9/46; anterior cingulate: see Wager, Jonides, & Reading,
2004, for a review). Both of these predictions were confirmed.
In sum, there is accumulating evidence that anxiety impairs the inhibi-
tion and shifting functions. This is of considerable importance. Both of these
functions relate to attentional control, and both are required to perform a
very wide range of tasks. Accordingly, many of the negative effects of anxiety
on processing efficiency and performance effectiveness can be interpreted in
terms of adverse effects of anxiety on those two functions.
Miyake et al. (2000) also identified an updating and monitoring function.
There are various tasks that can be used to assess that function. For example,
there is the N-back task, in which a series of items is presented. As soon as
the series has finished, the participant has to indicate the identity of the item
106 Eysenck
presented a given distance back in the series (e.g., three back, four back). It
is assumed within attentional control theory that this function involves basic
memory processes and is essentially unaffected by anxiety. Some support for
this assumption was discussed by Eysenck et al. (2007). There is also a more
recent study by Walkenhorst and Crowe (2009), in which they considered
the effects of trait anxiety on verbal and spatial N-back tasks. They found that
their high-anxious participants responded faster than the low anxious ones
on both of these tasks, suggesting that anxiety does not impair the updating
and monitoring function.
Conclusions
Much progress has been made in understanding the various ways in which
the effects of anxiety on processing efficiency and performance effectiveness
are mediated by the cognitive system. As we have seen, there is convincing
support for several of the major assumptions incorporated within process-
ing efficiency theory and attentional control theory. First, anxiety impairs
the efficiency of the working memory system, especially the central execu-
tive component of that system. Second, more specifically, anxiety adversely
affects the efficiency of at least two of the functions associated with the cen-
tral executive, namely, the inhibition and shifting functions. Third, anxiety
has a greater negative effect on processing efficiency than on performance
effectiveness.
What issues remain to be investigated systematically in future research?
Two issues seem to be of special importance. First, it is assumed that anx-
iety impairs processing efficiency more than performance effectiveness
because high-anxious individuals often utilise more processing resources or
effort than low anxious ones. As yet, we have little understanding of the pro-
cesses responsible for this enhanced motivation. Eysenck and Calvo (1992)
speculated that high-anxious individuals attempt to reduce their negative
self-thoughts (e.g., ‘I can’t do this task properly’; ‘I am doing really badly’) by
increasing effort to produce a reasonable level of performance. The notion
that negative self-thoughts can have motivational consequences remains
plausible, but there is as yet a dearth of directly relevant evidence.
Second, attentional control theory made much use of Miyake et al.’s (2000)
identification of three central executive functions based on their impres-
sive empirical research. However, there is no consensus as yet concerning
the number and nature of executive functions. Collette and van der Linden
(2002) reviewed brain-imaging studies of executive functions, and concluded
that there was support from such studies for the three functions identified
The Impact of Anxiety on Cognitive Performance 107
References
Ansari, T. L., Derakshan, N., & Richards, A. (2008). Effects of anxiety on task switch-
ing: Evidence from the mixed antisaccade task. Cognitive Affective & Behavioral
Neuroscience, 8, 229–238.
Baddeley, A. D. (1986). Working memory. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
(2001). Is working memory still working? American Psychologist, 56, 851–864.
Bar-Haim, Y., Lamy, D., Pergamin, L., Bakermans-Kranenburg, M. J., & van Ijzendoorn,
M. H. (2007). Threat-related attentional bias in anxious and nonanxious individu-
als: A meta-analytic study. Psychological Bulletin, 133, 1–24.
Bishop, S. J. (2009). Trait anxiety and impoverished prefrontal control of attention.
Nature Neuroscience, 12, 92–98.
Collette, F., & van der Linden, M. (2002). Brain imaging of the central executive
component of working memory. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 26,
105–125.
Derakshan, N., Ansari, T. L., Hansard, M., Shoker, L., & Eysenck, M. W. (2009). Anxiety,
inhibition, efficiency, and effectiveness: An investigation using the antisaccade
task. Experimental Psychology, 56, 48–55.
Derakshan, N., & Eysenck, M. W. (1998). Working memory capacity in high trait-anxious
and repressor groups. Cognition & Emotion, 12, 697–713.
(2009). Anxiety, processing efficiency, and cognitive performance: New developments
from attentional control theory. European Psychologist, 14, 168–176.
Derakshan, N., Smyth, S., & Eysenck, M W. (2009). Effects of state anxiety on perfor-
mance using a task-switching paradigm: An investigation of attentional control
theory. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 16, 1112–1117.
Eysenck, M. W. (1992). Anxiety: The cognitive perspective. Hove, UK: Erlbaum.
Eysenck, M. W., & Calvo, M. G. (1992). Anxiety and performance: The processing effi-
ciency theory. Cognition & Emotion, 6, 409–434.
Eysenck, M. W., Derakshan, N., Santos, R., & Calvo, M. G. (2007). Anxiety and cognitive
performance: Attentional control theory. Emotion, 7, 336–353.
Eysenck, M. W., & Payne, S. (in preparation). Trait anxiety, processing efficiency and per-
formance effectiveness.
Eysenck, M. W., Payne, S., & Derakshan, N. (2005). Trait anxiety, visuo-spatial process-
ing and working memory. Cognition and Emotion, 19, 1214–1228.
Eysenck, M. W., & Santos, R. (2006). Anxiety and depression: Past, present, and future
events. Cognition and Emotion, 20, 274–294.
Fales, C. L., Barch, D. M., Burgess, G. C., Schaefer, A., Mennin, D. S., Gray, J. R., &
Braver, T. S. (2008). Anxiety and cognitive efficiency: Differential modulation of
transient and sustained neural activity during a working memory task. Cognitive
Affective & Behavioral Neuroscience, 8, 239–253.
108 Eysenck
Hayes, S., Hirsch, C., & Mathews, A. (2008). Restriction of working memory capacity
during worry. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 117, 712–717.
Hembree, R. (1988). Correlates, causes, effects, and treatment of test anxiety. Review of
Educational Research, 58, 47–77.
Johnson, D. R., & Gronlund, S. D. (2009). Individuals lower in working memory capacity
are particularly vulnerable to anxiety’s disruptive effect. Anxiety, Stress, & Coping,
22, 201–213.
Miyake, A., Friedman, N. P., Emerson, M. J., Witzki, A. H., Howerter, A., & Wager, T.
D. (2000). The unity and diversity of executive functions and their contributions
to complex ‘frontal lobe’ tasks: A latent variable analysis. Cognitive Psychology, 41,
49–100.
Murray, N. P., & Janelle, C. M. (2007). Event-related potential evidence for the process-
ing efficiency theory. Journal of Sports Sciences, 25, 161–171.
Owens, M., Stevenson, J., Norgate, R., & Hadwin, J. A. (2008). Processing efficiency
theory in children: Working memory as a mediator between trait anxiety and aca-
demic performance. Anxiety, Stress, & Coping, 21, 417–430.
Santos, R., Wall, M., & Eysenck, M. W. (submitted). Anxiety and task switching: A func-
tional neuroimaging study.
Savostyanov, A. N., Tsai, A. C., Liou, M., Levin, E. A., Lee, J.-D., Yurganov, A. V., &
Knyazev, G. G. (2009). EEG correlates of trait anxiety in the stop-signal paradigm.
Neuroscience Letters, 449, 112–116.
Schwarzer, R. (1990). Current trends in anxiety research. In P. J. D. Drenth, J. A. Sergeant,
& J. R. Takens (Eds.), European perspectives in psychology (pp. 225–244). Oxford:
John Wiley & Sons.
Shackman, A. J., Sarinopoulos, I., Maxwell, J. S., Pizzagalli, D. A., Lavric, A., & Davidson,
R. J. (2006). Anxiety selectively disrupts visuospatial working memory. Emotion, 6,
40–61.
Telzer, E. H., Mogg, K., Bradley, B. P., Mai, X., Ernst, M., Pine, D. S., & Murk, C. S.
(2008). Relationship between trait anxiety, prefrontal cortex, and attention bias to
angry faces in children and adolescents. Biological Psychology, 79, 216–222.
Wager, T. D., Jonides, J., & Reading, S. (2004). Neuroimaging studies of shifting atten-
tion: A meta-analysis. Neuroimage, 22, 1679–1693.
Walkenhorst, E., & Crowe, F. (2009). The effects of state worry and trait anxiety on work-
ing memory processes in a normal sample. Anxiety, Stress, & Coping, 22, 167–187.
6
Biological Foundations
The SEEKING System as an Affective Source
for Motivation and Cognition
. . . whatever elements an act of cognition may imply . . . it at least implies the existence
of a feeling.
William James, 1909 (1987), p. 833
This chapter will focus on how the most basic motivational urges – those
essential for all goal-directed actions – may be instantiated in brain systems.
We will first focus on dopamine as a principal factor in the embodied mecha-
nisms that bring about exploratory behavior in mammals; secondly, we will
focus on one core emotional-motivational command system that is ener-
gized by dopamine, namely the SEEKING/Expectancy system as described
in Affective Neuroscience (Panksepp, 1998a, 2005a). We will introduce
research findings and theoretical perspectives that make clearer the mean-
ing of motivation/exploration/SEEKING as a mental-affective function that
intrinsically helps us penetrate the many predictive relationships hidden in
environments – especially social ones – that are complex and often constantly
in flux. With the SEEKING system, animals can extract causal convictions
to guide behavior from predictive correlations among environmental events.
We will also suggest that the SEEKING system contributes a fundamental
phenomenal dimension of primary process consciousness, one that is affec-
tively full of positive zest and enthusiasm for life – essential ingredients for
effective learning.
Let us be clear at the outset: Our reading of the evidence is that felt dimen-
sions of certain basic (primary-process) brain activating systems lead to psy-
chological states that are accompanied by phenomenal experiences, namely
affectively experienced states. Further, we take these basic systems as cru-
cial to the developmental unfolding of higher order cognitive systems (i.e.,
those based on learning and thoughts, or secondary and tertiary processes as
we conceptualize them). Specifically, the core emotional command systems
109
110 Stewart & Panksepp
appear to generate specific affects essential for learning and thereby guar-
anteeing and fine-tuning the appropriate behavioral sequences and timings
necessary for diverse survival-promoting behaviors. The emotional com-
mand systems accomplish this partly by having evolutionary representations
of the body coded in neural circuits, yielding and experientially sensitising
the mind and the whole body into an affective action state that is immedi-
ate and undeniable and pervasive. Human infants, like most animals, live in
the immediacy of this felt world, and similar to other animals, they gradu-
ally develop complex behavioral patterns that are learned responses to the
affective MindBrain promptings experienced as bodily states. Unlike most
other animals, however, human children develop the capacity to cognitively
reflect on the unceasing patterns of emotional activations of their brains and
bodies as higher-order mental states. That is, they learn how to interpret the
language of their embodiment as a language of representations – elements
of experience that appear as discontinuous with the virtual body represen-
tations that gives rise to them. There is much work to be done in research-
ing this remarkable transformation of affective commands into higher-order
cognitive structures, and in this chapter we will provide an account of the
originating brain states that need to be understood before there can be any
full account of the developmental transitions that depend on them.
Motivation. Animals appear to be endowed with their own purposive
agency. Evolution has seen to it that they possess an innate group of emo-
tional mechanisms that are essential for the survival of animals by generating
“intentions in action,” which command sets of behaviors and supportive auto-
nomic changes that coordinate organismic actions needed for survival. Irving
Kupferman, in Principles of Neural Science (1991), writes: “Specific motiva-
tional states, or drives, represent urges or impulses based upon bodily needs
that impel humans and other animals into action.” However, as Kupferman
later adds:
against this state of affairs in describing the mechanisms that drive behaviors
and that seem to parallel in unmistakable ways the urges or impulses found in
humans. Things are slowly changing, however, and some are calling for better
conceptual approaches, such as that enunciated in the rapidly growing field
of affective neuroscience (Panksepp, 1998a, 2005b).
Affective Neuroscience. The core thesis of Affective Neuroscience (Panksepp,
1998a, 2005a) is that emotional processes and subjectively experienced feel-
ings do play a fundamental role in the unfolding neural events – large-scale
brain network functions – that organize the actions of humans and animals
alike. Various basic emotional systems provide a variety of internal values
upon which complex behavioral choices are based. However, such internally
experienced states are not simply mental events derived from higher cog-
nitive appraisals; rather, they are generated through neurobiological events
that directly shape instinctual emotional behaviors. This provides a straight-
forward empirical strategy to study how basic affective processes emerge
from brain activities: Affective feelings are part and parcel of the uncondi-
tioned responses generated by the primary-process emotional networks of
the brain.
This is a revolutionary idea. Since Darwin’s era, there has not been a more
coherent strategy for advancing our understanding of how we come to have
the kinds of core emotional feelings that we do, which highlights our deep
psychological connection with other animals. Affective Neuroscience offers
the detail Kupferman was calling for – it spells out the physiology behind the
ideas of motivation and drive through empirical research. It accomplishes
more than that, however. It brings back psychological processes as meaning-
ful brain events that cannot be discarded in our attempt to understand behav-
ior. Here are a few of the key points developed in the book.
Decades of empirical study have led to the proposal made in Affective
Neuroscience that there exist at least 7 primary-process emotional “command
systems” found in all mammals. We first go over criteria for selecting the 7,
and then briefly describe them. The idea of a command system or “emotional
circuit” is based on 6 neural-systems criteria: (1) Core emotional systems are
“genetically prewired” to function in relevant situations, and do not need
higher brain functions for activation (empirical verification is based on
studies of direct electrical brain stimulation to specific brain areas arousing
coherent emotional states); (2) relevant motor subroutines and autonomic
processes controlled by specific neurochemical processes reflect internal
regulations of these evolutionarily ancient circuits; (3) these circuits concen-
trate arousal and behavioral specificity by changing the sensitivities of sen-
sory systems; (4) arousal often continues in the neural circuits after the initial
Biological Foundations 113
elicitations; (5) the circuits may contribute to other behavioral outcomes than
those called emotions; and (6) the “[e]motive circuits have reciprocal inter-
actions with brain mechanisms that elaborate higher decision-making pro-
cesses” (Panksepp, 1998a, p. 49) and conscious awareness. A further corollary
is that raw emotional feelings are generated by the neurodynamics of these
coherently operating, functionally unified, BrainMindBody functions.
The 7 primary-process command systems that have been reasonably firmly
established (with secondary and tertiary manifestations once the systems
interact with cognitive structures) are:
1) SEEKING (motivation, expectancy, investigation)
2) RAGE (anger to frustration and hatred)
3) FEAR (anxiety to worry)
4) LUST (sexual eroticisms to obsessions)
5) CARE (nurturant social relationships to empathy)
6) PANIC (separation distress, loneliness, and grief)
7) PLAY (joyful social engagements to humorous delights)
The names of the core systems are written in the upper case to remind us that
the vernacular or folk-psychological terms are to be understood in an explic-
itly scientific way. These circuits are the “executive, command, and operating
systems” because “executive implies that a neural system has a superordinate
role in a cascade of hierarchical controls; command implies that a circuit can
instigate a full-blown emotional process; operating implies that it can coordi-
nate and synchronize the operation of several subsystems” (Panksepp, 1998a,
p. 49). The neural systems are concentrated in the subcortical regions of the
brain, but clearly they operate throughout the entire web of the brain/body
and regulate emotion-specific learning whereby neutral world events are
imbued with affective meaning (e.g., we are not just angry, we are angry at
someone).
The SEEKING system, which we describe in greater detail below, is the
biggest background emotional system that also participates in the control of
all the other emotions and it is a spontaneous generator of expectancies. This
“appetitive motivational system” (Panksepp, 1998a, p. 51) should be thought
of as a default active-waking state of the brain/body that initially simply pro-
motes forward movement and exploration. Dopamine facilitates the “antic-
ipatory eagerness” (Panksepp, 1998a, p. 54) that is a characteristic feature of
the SEEKING system.
The RAGE system energizes the body to angrily defend its territory and
resources. When conflicts or frustrations are present, this system contributes
the psychomotor responses that are crucial for resolving the situation.
114 Stewart & Panksepp
The FEAR system includes a variety of states from terror to anxiety, and
acts in a general way to help an animal avoid danger. It is evident in sev-
eral instinctual behavioral patterns in most mammals, but as documented by
many investigators (e.g., LeDoux, 2002), it is also tightly interconnected with
learning systems that support its safety features for obvious survival reasons.
FEAR brings about freezing and hiding when danger is some distance away,
but it leads to rapid fleeing when danger is nearby.
The remaining four systems mediate primary social emotions, highlighting
their difference in function from the basic emotional and motivational pro-
cesses of SEEKING, RAGE, and FEAR. The social emotions are responsible
for behaviors that are relevant to survival among conspecifics.
The LUST system relates to mate selection (fitness evaluation and courting
behaviors, among others), reproduction, and many gender-specific behav-
iors. LUST should be differentiated from nurturance, but it has many linkages
with it neurochemically and behaviorally, and may well have been its evolu-
tionary progenitor (Panksepp, 1998a).
The CARE system concerns the bonding and nurturing behaviors that dra-
matically increase with mammals. This affiliative capacity, generally, “refers to
social behaviors that bring individuals closer together” (Carter, Lederhendler
& Kirkpatrick, 1997, p. xiii). One of the most powerful activities of this sys-
tem may be the opioid and oxytocin-mediated mother/child bond, but it is
also prominent in the expressions of love, altruism, empathy, and maintain-
ing social tolerance.
The PANIC system becomes aroused when young animals are separated
from their social support system. It has evolutionarily emerged from the pain
circuits of the brain (Panksepp, 2003) and plays a significant role in human
loneliness, sadness, grief, and depression. PANIC is meant to ensure survival
by means of painful internal alerts when contact is lost with important social
supports.
The PLAY system remains the least studied of the above systems and is still
deemed a frivolous area of inquiry among many neuroscientists. Still, this may
be a crucial emotional circuit for helping developmentally in the organization
of the mature social brain. Early rough-and-tumble play may be essential for
determining subtle synaptic connections required for social knowledge and
sustaining joyful attitudes in mammals. It is widely recognized that laugh-
ter is most common during playful social interactions, and the possibility
has emerged that other animals, from rats and dogs to other primates, also
exhibit an ancestral form of laugher (Panksepp, 2007b; Panksepp & Burgdorf,
2003), accompanied by the capacity for joy (Burgdorf & Panksepp, 2005).
Children who are not given sufficient daily rough-and-tumble play may
Biological Foundations 115
It should be briefly noted here that this research on the emotional com-
mand systems – and especially the SEEKING system – is consistent with
experimental work in psychology generally called functional emotion theory.
Frijda (1987, 1988), Lazarus (1991), and Fischer et al. (1990), among others,
have given evidence for how emotions help elaborate general organizations
of bodily activity. The guiding concept that cognitive, motivational, and rela-
tional dimensions of emotion are found in a spectrum of activities from bio-
logical organization to social organization offers a helpful extension in our
understanding of emotion from its more general psychological and behav-
ioral manifestations to the evolutionarily “given” neural foundations. The
focus here on the research described in Affective Neuroscience is a further
exploration of functional emotion theory, developing in greater detail the
neurophysiological and neurochemical pathways of the emotional and affec-
tive organizing of behavior.
The SEEKING System. Affective Neuroscience envisions the appetitive moti-
vational SEEKING system (SS) to be “a goad without a goal” (p. 144) at the
onset of psychological life. (When quotes are followed by page numbers, they
refer to Panksepp, 1998a). This highlights the main function of the system:
It drives the animal forward into its environment, with no other directive
than to explore, investigate, and ultimately forage for resources in the ini-
tially unpredictable environments in which organisms find themselves. A
more fully elaborated designation for this the system might be “a ‘foraging/
exploration/investigation/curiosity/interest /expectancy/SEEKING’ system”
(p. 145). This system is especially active when animals are experiencing vari-
ous homeostatic imbalances such as hunger, thirst, and sexual arousal, but it is
also set to go when there are no special bodily urges to be fulfilled. It appears
that the SS is a default mechanism that activates (when other demands, such
as resting or eating, are satisfied) to arouse the animal to actions that may
potentially lead to future rewards. Thus, it is not surprising that positive affect
accompanies the SEEKING urge – getting to know the world should be an
intrinsically positive activity, at least until the organism encounters danger.
Why should it be so positively engaging to be in such a state of arousal?
It is not easy to contemplate how affective experiences participate in the
control of animal behavior without using our own types of felt emotions as
comparisons. This kind of anthropomorphism has been frowned on, but a
scientific variant of this kind of thinking is about the only way to fathom the
many homologies that exist in the brains of all mammals. The affective qual-
ities of human SEEKING states – those of intense interest, engaged curiosity,
and eager anticipation – make sense to us through the simple fact that we can
readily understand – almost feel – the meaning of such words. However, are
Biological Foundations 117
they in fact valid descriptors of the affective states of the SEEKING system as
manifested in the minds of animals? The answer appears to be yes, at least in
a class-similar way (i.e., nothing across species is precisely the same, which
led to the novel affective nomenclature of capitalizing the emotional primes).
Indeed, at present there is no other language that is available to help us artic-
ulate with any precision what is presumed to be happening in the core of the
behavioral expressions of the other animals. Researchers who caution against
anthropomorphizing animal behavior are, more often than not, the ones who
also tend to write about animals as if they felt no pain or have no conscious-
ness or are too simple (i.e., machinelike) to justify having homologous psy-
chological concerns for their own well-being as humans have.
When your pet dog sees you put your coat on and ready its leash, the
energetic tail wagging accompanied by rambunctious jumping and bark-
ing is eager anticipation! It seems indisputable, unless one is in denial about
the emotional subtlety of emotional life, that the animal is in the grip of a
strongly felt state. You could say that the dog is exhibiting high motor activ-
ity, repeated vocalizations within a specific range, increased respiratory func-
tion, and so on. Why should the fact that the animal is eagerly anticipating
going outside for a walk not qualify as a perfectly reasonable description?
Because this state has to be inferred only from behavioral signs, but follow-
ing traditional Cartesian skepticism, scientists to this day typically do not
deem behavioral changes to be sufficient evidence for any quality of mind.
Still, every aspect of the state of the animal suggests increased positive affect,
and by all measures imaginable, animals seek out such states, including via
self-administration of artificial stimuli (electrical and chemical stimulations)
directly into the relevant regions of the brain but not others (such as neocor-
tex). Thus, a very reasonable working hypothesis is that a distinct emotional
feeling is either primed or instantiated by arousal of the SEEKING system,
and that with a little experience, this system induces a positive anticipation
of the exploring of a world that is filled with potentially important informa-
tion about the psychic state of dogs. Before reaching any definitive conclu-
sions, however, we are well advised to go deeper into the neural nature of
the SEEKING affect, beyond outer behavioral expressions, to the underlying
functional components. Such work now definitively indicates the existence of
affect in all mammals that have been studied.
The SEEKING system, along with its affective intensity, coaxes each animal
to explore its environment: It makes a cow investigate anything new showing
up in her pasture; at times it makes us seek sweets when we should have no
more, and perhaps even wonder whether we should look for a different job.
It also promotes the addictive qualities of various activities from compulsive
118 Stewart & Panksepp
There is growing acceptance that this emotional function of the brain [the SS] –
the basic impulse to search, investigate, and make sense of the environment –
emerges from the circuits that course through the LH. The anatomy of brain DA
circuits corresponds to the general trajectory of this psychobehavioral system,
and brain DA itself is an essential ingredient in allowing the circuitry to operate
efficiently, although many other brain chemistries are involved in the overall con-
struction of the SEEKING response. (Panksepp, 1998a, p. 145)
Here, we will first go over a few details about the brain regions involved,
and then we will discuss the work of dopamine in those areas as well as in
the extended areas that form the larger dopamine-energized SEEKING sys-
tems. Readers wishing more details are directed to a variety of recent reviews
(Alcaro, Huber, & Panksepp, 2007; Berridge, 2007; Ikemoto & Panksepp,
1999; Panksepp & Moskal, 2008).
Hypothalamus. The hypothalamus and the thalamus make up the dienceph-
alon, a large and functionally diverse brain region situated in the uppermost
part of the brain stem just under the neocortex and the other telencephalic
structures. The thalamus processes information coming from the external
world to the cerebral cortex and also has intrinsic midline systems for elab-
orating social emotions and sustaining and amplifying cognitive conscious-
ness. The hypothalamus is concerned with the internal milieu – the regulation
of the autonomic, endocrine, and visceral systems as well as a host of emo-
tional urges. The regulation of those systems requires monitoring the internal
Biological Foundations 119
environment and bringing about appropriate changes in the heart, lungs, vis-
cera, musculature, and the exocrine and endocrine glands. The hypothalamus
regulates the moment-by-moment conditions in the body, and thereby has a
very sophisticated and diffuse intrinsic map of the viscera, the state of which
is essential for the nature of many emotional feelings. The hypothalamus
incorporates several nuclei (neuronal clusters), and more complex tissues
where many nuclei and pathways intersect (reticular regions), that are dedi-
cated to a variety of functions, among which is the temporal orchestration of
psychological and behavioral expressions (Card, 2002; Swanson, 2003). One
of those reticular regions is the lateral hypothalamic area (LH), which pro-
vides a “superhighway” for extensive intercommunication with other regions
up and down the neuroaxis – this is part of the medial forebrain “corridor” we
have described. The corridor is a network that extends from lower midbrain
regions such as the ventral tegmental area (VTA) through to regions of the
basal ganglia such as the nucleus accumbens, and further upward to medial
cortical regions. If this system is damaged on both sides of the brain, an ani-
mal’s capacity for normal motivated behavior and affective consciousness is
terminally compromised, and if the damage is not complete, the organism
has to be nursed for a long time before it will again sustain itself, albeit much
more weakly and inconsistently than before.
The ventral tegmental area (VTA). The ventral tegmental area is a brain
region that proceeds from the midbrain upward to the diencephalon. This
area is critical to SEEKING because it is a point of origination for mesolimbic
and mesocortical dopamine circuits, which we will consider in a moment.
The nucleus accumbens and ventral pallidum. This region of the basal fore-
brain is instrumental in reward and various kinds of pleasures (which are
the foundations of reinforcement processes), and it is the prime target of
mesolimbic dopamine activity from the VTA. It is also rich in endogenous
opioids, and thus plays an important role in practically all drug addictions
(Berridge & Robinson, 1998).
The Extended Reticular Activating System (ERTAS). This is another corri-
dor, consisting of a number of nuclear and reticular regions running from the
medulla and up the neuroaxis to thalamic regions of the diencephalon and
regions of the cortex. At the core of this system is the midbrain and pontine
reticular formation, which is necessary for generating the state of ordinary
waking arousal. It is also continuous with the VTA, regions of the dienceph-
alon, parabrachial and raphe nuclei, the nucleus coeruleus, and the periaque-
ductal gray, all of which play a significant part in generating a global state of
consciousness (Watt & Pincus, 2004; Solms & Turnbull, 2002). Activations of
these instinctual emotional systems (with continual regulation by the global
120 Stewart & Panksepp
specifically with the simple reward of pleasurable feeling, but rather has
much more to do with fine-tuning the prediction and anticipation of
rewards. This is not all it does, however. DA facilitates the incentive values
of the SEEKING system, but not simply by focusing them on specific envi-
ronmental objects; DA relies on the stimulation of internal, affective motive
states to bring about behaviors that are most likely to lead to consummatory
rewards that can sustain bodily homeostasis. It is likely these same systems
are active when children learn about new and exciting relationships that
exist in their environments.
Let us now consider how the DA pathways integrate with other brain sys-
tems to yield a “psychobehavioral integrative system” (Panksepp, 1998a) for
the elaboration of SEEKING urges. Essentially, the nigrostriatal pathway
contributes motor-sequence arousal and synchronization, the mesolimbic
pathway contributes much of the emotional valence, and the mesocortical
pathway contributes to the organization of the cognitive and memory pro-
grams important in appetitive behavior and related affective experiences.
The cognitive components are largely mediated by glutamatergic systems
originating in the cortex, providing downward control of SEEKING urges by
knowledge representations. We can think of these various components as the
acting, feeling, and thinking constituents of SEEKING urges. From a global
perspective, these components represent the evolutionary development of
the Triune Brain (MacLean, 1990), with the reptilian core dedicated to move-
ments, the mammalian limbic system orchestrating various social emotions,
and the mammalian frontal neocortex committed to episodic and working
memory that allow for planning and cognitive processing of changing world
events, with all being coordinated with each other. Mechanistically, this is
an oversimplification, but it helps to see how the motivational systems have
their sources in deep strata of the brain that evolved a long time ago, and how
they have been conserved and elaborated in each species as especially effi-
cient for behavioral organizing functions aimed at particular survival needs.
Even the happy sounds that rats make when they are playing and tickled are
strongly influenced by brain dopamine dynamics (Burgdorf et al., 2007), and
these dynamics contribute to our mirthful joy related to humor and laughter
(Panksepp, 2007a).
Chemical precursors of DA have also been found in insects, where they
appear to function in parallel ways with the DA functions of mammalian
SSs. There is a neurochemical in bees called octopamine that is active in
reward seeking, and its action in the bees’ neural connections underscores
an organization that “sends projections to every nook and cranny of the
bee brain” (Blakeslee, 1996, p. 2). When the earliest animals began moving
Biological Foundations 125
about on the ancient sea floors, there presumably already existed a family of
motivation-generating molecules that assisted in the coordination of motor
activity with homeostatic and consummatory requirements, and that were
conserved all the way up to us and all the other mammals. It is remarkable that
crayfish still exhibit conditioned place preferences where they received drugs
that promote DA activity (Nathaniel, Panksepp, & Huber, 2009; Panksepp
& Huber, 2004). The SEEKING system highlights a general principle of
brain function – the primitive affective regions of the brain generate global
affective-state functions that are essential tools for living and survival. We
will now take a closer look at some of the specifics of such global brain-body
states as possessing affective dimensions.
Motivation and “Experience.” When we think about the dopamine-
energized SEEKING states, we begin to glimpse how motivational urges
arise from bodily activation states that support specific types of action plans.
These global states are not simply tropisms or reflex arcs that mindlessly
reflect behavior programs triggered by environmental cues. Rather, such states
reflect wide-scale neural network activations and inhibitors that integrate
multiple brain/body processes in a global-dynamic brain-body entrainment
process. If we envision the evolutionary import of this kind of system-wide
engagement, we can begin to see an integrative strategy that seems to base the
guarantee of appropriate survival activities on the coherence of action plans
and psychological salience that transpires in animals as a recognizable aspect
of its own activity.
This is not simply proprioception, which is based in its own specific
somatic pathways, and which gives the animal information about its body
positioning. The global states that arise from SEEKING urges help to ensure
that the animal itself, as a single integrated entity, responds in the right way
to a variety of specific needs. The surest way of conferring this type of imper-
ative was to imbue it with brain functions that register as undeniable calls to
action, felt with unmistakable and unambiguous positively valenced salience.
This characterization of the global body state can most parsimoniously be
called a raw phenomenal “affective experience.” It is possible to go one step
further into the operation of the DA-energized SEEKING states, however,
to discover a final element in the search for clarifying how the physiology of
motivation is responsible for the felt, affective quality that generates subjec-
tive experience and consciousness.
As noted earlier, there is reason to suspect that the temporal dynamics of
some dopaminergically driven SEEKING functions may be central in pro-
ducing important dimensions of consciousness. We now introduce some
research supporting that idea.
126 Stewart & Panksepp
not only behavior but conscious experience, which is filled with enthusiasm,
interest, and zest for life.
If it is true that, along with the felt characteristics central to each global-state
emotional command system there is also a range of moment-by-moment
processing distinctions available to each system, then it could be said that
these systems have a felt aspect that is significant for the proper behavior
of the animal in its present moment. By definition, the ordered progression
of present moments is a characteristic of experience, at least in an incipient
form. By a remarkable evolutionary twist, it seems that DA and its precursors
hit upon the idea that the addition of the dimension of time could induce
the kind of psychological salience needed to make brain emotional operating
systems experientially functional. It may be possible that the goading quality
of such emotional/motivational command systems has a rough equivalence
to the degree of “now-ness” and the types of affective psychological pressure
that the systems can exert on cognitive processing. Indeed, it may be that the
“ticking” of DA neurons, which represents their background activity, amounts
to a clocking system for present moments, and when the ticking speeds up, as
in dopamine (DA) bursting, the passage of psychological time speeds up.
This may be better explicated through the main story line in two ground-
breaking books. In The Remembered Present (1989) and Bright Air, Brilliant
Fire (1992), Gerald Edelman explored how animals might have come to pos-
sess “primary consciousness,” an apparently necessary precursor to “higher
order consciousness.” His analysis of the neural organization of primary con-
sciousness resonates in striking ways with the systems described in Affective
Neuroscience; however, Edelman seems to think that the psychobehavioral
imperatives of the systems he describes emerge from the combinatorial
interactions within higher brain cognitive systems and are not, as we have
described, inherently powered by a few systems that remain continually oper-
ating at the base of all higher cognitive processes (without which those higher
processes could not effectively operate). Regarding the temporal aspect we
described above, Edelman (1992) says of primary consciousness:
It is limited to a small memorial interval around a time chunk I call the present.
It lacks an explicit notion or a concept of a personal self, and it does not afford
the ability to model the past or the future as part of a correlated scene. An animal
with primary consciousness sees the room the way a beam of light illuminates it.
(p. 122)
know what the precise experiences of each present moment might be for,
say, a mouse or a monkey. However, common sense allows us to realistically
infer their affective experiences from their instinctual emotional behaviors as
a sense of their now, perhaps as we watch them explore or otherwise respond
to new environments – cautious and alert, but with an evident determination
to discover what is there. We should not mistakenly anthropomorphize the
inner world of the animal, but neither should we make the mistake of remain-
ing oblivious to the nature of animal experience or of underestimating what
biology is capable of in the service of optimal survival.
It is worth considering the truth diagram that must be fully considered
as we attempt to relate human experiences and the nature of the animal
estate, because detailed functional neuroscience can only be done with ani-
mal models. We would like to have more accurate views of animal emotional
experiences because that is the only way to ever really obtain detailed neuro-
scientific insights into how primary-process human emotional brains might
operate. As summarized in Figure 6.1, we have some hard choices to make
about the true-world emotional nature of animal minds and our scientific
decisions about those minds. We want to avoid Type I and Type II errors, and
to accept anthropodenial when it is valid and anthropomorphism when it is
valid. Radical behaviorism made a shambles of this decision-making process
by following time-honored pre-neuroscientific Cartesian opinions that such
issues are outside the realm of science, a bias sustained to the present day
(Panksepp, 2005a), as opposed to recognizing that because of advances in
our ability to study psychobiological homologies, we must now consider and
weight all of the available evidence in our decision-making processes (e.g.,
Panksepp, 1998b, 2005b, 2010). There is now abundant evidence indicating
that there is much in the animal mind that will inform us of our own mental-
ity, especially in terms of the core processes such as basic emotional urges.
We believe that at the basic (primary-process) emotional level, anthropomor-
phism is a valid strategy for revealing the affective ground of being that is
common to all animals. Our primate and mammalian relatives may surprise
us with insights that will provide understanding of the nature of our own
affective experiences.
Such analyses of core emotional and motivational processes may also have
relevance for understanding the functions that support cognition. Cognition
is traditionally studied as a large set of relatively high-level processes that
inform and constitute the basic material of thinking; “cogito” means “I think.”
However, just as this chapter has looked into the basic-level processes that
not only shape specific behavioral repertoires but add to them a dimension
of felt activation that engages the entire mind and body, it might be helpful to
130 Stewart & Panksepp
Avoidance of Anthropomorphism
(e.g., “Anxiety-Like Behavior”)
Research tells us that plants possess remarkable abilities for evaluating details
of their environment (Narby, 2005). They can determine which species of para-
site is chomping on their leaves by analysis of chemicals in the saliva of the pest
(Buhner, 2002) and in response, they can release chemicals that attract a spe-
cific predator that will feed on the pest the plant has targeted (Whitfield, 2001).
Plants can even notify their neighbors to prepare for attack by chemical means.
These behaviors are sophisticated responses to specific environmental chal-
lenges, and from the perspective of information processing, they resemble cog-
nitive processes. If plants are this sophisticated in their precognitive operations,
then maybe we should rethink the view that wants to conceptualize cognition
merely as thought. Maybe cognition has roots that draw upon the same exten-
sive activating networks of the body that grounds our various emotional and
motivational systems? Maybe cognition is far more complex in nonhuman ani-
mals than our verbal thought-based view has allowed us to appreciate? Surely,
creatures can think in terms of visual images, perhaps even in more strict affec-
tive terms. Maybe cognition, at its base, is not simply what we thought it was –
the apotheosis of neocortical function through language – but also a system of
systems, computing vast amounts of information and delivering appropriate
output to motivational systems at every step of the response sequence geared
to specific environmental demands. That would mean that cognition, too, may
be rooted in a body-wide network (and is not just highest-level neocortical
processing alone), and that it, too, has ancient evolutionary origins (and is not
dependent on “big” brains alone) – that it too is ultimately subservient to the
bodily survival needs of organisms and hence cannot do much unless it is nour-
ished, more than just metabolically, by affectively resilient brain-bodily states.
In some sense, we are subject to seeing cognition and motivation as dis-
tinct because of the history of science. Of course, different neural systems do
contribute different types of processes to the behaviors we parse as observers,
but functional parsing seems to have led to assumptions about living systems,
such as the idea that plants are the ultimate in passivity (and mindlessness)
and humans have exclusive access to top-quality problem solving because
they “think.” It may be that these assumptions are severely skewing our abil-
ity to see the extraordinary solutions nature has provided to all her creatures.
In addition, if we have mistaken the neocortical origins of our own ways of
knowing, it appears likely that what we are trying to accomplish in educating
our children may be subject to biases that emphasize our species centrism
over a kind of knowledge that would help us find our place in nature – and
our responsibility as natural beings within the matrix of living things. It is
long past the time to pretend our children only deserve cognitive education
(the flawed central tenet of No Child Left Behind), and time to begin rec-
ognizing that it is only through new and sophisticated forms of emotional
132 Stewart & Panksepp
education that breeds social intelligence (Goleman, 2006) that we will truly
leave no child behind.
Education appears to divide children up along the lines of the sciences we
have used to study them. Because cognition is the domain of the “highest”
abilities, we devise a curriculum to enhance their thinking ability by train-
ing them to organize and memorize facts, and to look for new ways to use
the facts. Far behind the perceived importance of cognition, so important
for making a buck, are the emotional, motivational, and physical domains
that make us truly human. Such issues are grudgingly or barely considered in
mainstream educational practice, but perhaps the times they are a changing
(Sunderland, 2006). Yet, from what we have tried to focus on in this chap-
ter, those deep and pervasively felt domains are the very foundation of what
we experience as thinking and cognizing. This subtle affective fabric of mind
should be brought back into the understanding of human behavior, and that
understanding might then take the fair measure of each child as the breath-
takingly sensitive open experiencer he or she is, needing little extra moti-
vation to explore, act, express, and learn . . . if only given the opportunity
to employ their natural enthusiasms. Clearly, the computer revolution has
opened up a world of information that they like to explore, and helped them
become self-motivated learners. Albeit, we must take care to help ensure they
do not become addicted to the crap that is also abundantly available on the
web. They should also have plenty of time and be allowed to play freely with
each other, so their social brains are allowed to grow and connect up as a
result of rich engagements with others. Obviously, these engagements will
often lead to trouble and dissention, but bright young adults should be sitting
at the edges of our playgrounds (or play sanctuaries) to help assure that all
the kids learn the one important rule without which no human society can
thrive – do not hurt another. Do not do unto others what you would not have
done unto you. In this age when parents consider drugging their children
with Ritalin so that they will settle down enough to be filled up with facts,
we have to consider whether we have gotten the science about ourselves right
in any essential way (Panksepp, 1998b, 2007b). If not, can we use our deep
mammalian motivations and cognitions, along with a few profoundly and
uniquely human insights, to do better?
Educational Applications
We have looked at how aspects of the core emotional command systems,
especially SEEKING urges, shape behaviors and play an essential role in
Biological Foundations 133
their execution and timing as well as holding their expressions in robust and
dynamic experiential states. It may well be that almost all learning must be
accompanied by dynamic affective experiential states in order for lasting
and deeply positive behavioral-psychological change to occur. Cashing out
this suspicion in appropriate research is likely to have ramifications for how
learning is conceptualized – both in homes and in schools, and possibly in
social programs for workplace retraining. A clear recognition of how brain
dopamine dynamics and the resulting energizing of SEEKING urges inter-
face with our educational aspirations will be an interesting future chapter
of educational psychology. Perhaps we can see the importance of emotional
energies, especially the role of PLAY, most clearly during the preschool years,
when our children are supposed to become socialized, with emerging clear
ideas of what they can or cannot do to other people.
It may be that the best way to advance the healthy emotionally sensitive
socialization of our children, so as to promote increasing empathy and concern
for others – hopefully toward an “Empathic Civilization” (Rifkin, 2010) – is to
better deploy one of our most underutilized social resources – joyous child-
hood physical PLAY – to train each generation about what good humans can
and cannot do to each other. Let us re-emphasize the darker side of the point
just made: During the competitive joys of childhood play, kids will “naturally”
hurt each other. We adults should be there, more consistently, at many critical
moments, to gently intervene with sincere and nonpunitive guidance encourag-
ing the children toward pro-social options. If from the earliest ages we fostered
more independent, playful social engagements, under the watchful eye of those
who realize that playful joy brings children to the perimeters of their emotional
knowledge, might we more consistently train the young of our species not to
hurt each other? If at many critical moments, more of our young promptly
heard some good advice from above – “You shouldn’t have done that. . . . If you
want to play, don’t do that anymore. OK?” – might we be able to construct bet-
ter pro-social minds/brains? Can we diminish the potential for cruelty inher-
ent in our human bloodline through the promotion of more empathic touch/
speech and equitably joyous social policies? It’s at least worth a try.
Our raw emotions need to be used skillfully to educate our children. We
should reopen our playgrounds as perhaps the most important classrooms
that our children will ever have, as long as the instructors of the young are
sympathetically observing and assuring that no child is marginalized in those
all-important playful experiences that help construct social brains. Then,
when the SEEKING system takes over in full force, we can also guide that
joyful energy into optimal educational programs.
134 Stewart & Panksepp
References
Alcaro, A., Huber, R., & Panksepp, J. (2007). Behavioral functions of the mesolimbic
dopaminergic system: An affective neuroethological perspective. Brain Research
Reviews, 56, 283–321.
Bannon, M. J. (2002). Dopamine. Encyclopedia of Life Sciences. U.K.: Nature Publishing
Group.
Berridge, K. C. (2007). The debate over dopamine’s role in reward: The case for incentive
salience. Psychopharmacology, 191, 391–431.
Berridge, K. C., & Robinson, T. E. (1998). What is the role of dopamine in reward: hedonic
impact, reward learning, or incentive salience? Brain Research, 28(3), 309–369.
Blakeslee, S. (1996). How brain may weigh the world with simple dopamine system.
Science Desk March 19, 1996. New York: The New York Times Company.
Buhner, S. H. (2002). The Lost Language of Plants: The Ecological Importance of Plant
Medicines to Life on Earth. White River Junction, VT: Chelsea Green Press.
Burgdorf, J., & Panksepp, J. (2005). The neurobiology of positive emotions. Neuroscience
and Biobehavioral Reviews, 30, 173–187.
Burgdorf, J., Wood, P. L., Kroes, R. A., Moskal, J. R., & Panksepp, J. (2007). Neurobiology
of 50-kHz ultrasonic vocalizations in rats: Electrode mapping, lesion, and pharma-
cology studies. Behavioral Brain Research, 182, 274–283.
Card, J. P. (2002). Hypothalamus. Encyclopedia of Life Sciences. U.K.: nature Publishing
Group.
Carter, C. S., Lederhendler, I. I., & Kirkpatrick, B. (Eds.) (1997). The Integrative
Neurobiology of Affiliation. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, v. 807. New
York: The New York Academy of Sciences.
Civelli, O., & Zhou, Q. (2001). Dopamine receptors: Molecular pharmacology.
Encyclopedia of Life Sciences. U.K.: Nature Publishing Group.
Ding, L., & Perkel, D. J. (2002). Dopamine modulates excitability of spiny neurons in the
avian basal ganglia. Journal of Neuroscience, 22(12), 5210–5218.
Durstewitz, D., Seamans, J. K., & Sejnowski, T. J. (2000). Dopamine-mediated stabili-
zation of delay period activity in a network model of prefrontal cortex. Journal of
Neurophysiology, 83, 1733–1750.
Edelman, G. M. (1989). The Remembered Present: A Biological Theory of Consciousness.
New York: Basic Books.
(1992). Bright Air, Brilliant Fire: On the Matter of the Mind. New York: Basic Books.
Fischer, K. W., Shaver, P. R., & Carnochan, P. (1990). How emotions develop and how
they organize development. Emotion and Cognition, 4 (2), 81–127.
Frijda, N. H. (1987). The Emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
(1988). The laws of emotion. American Psychology, 43, 349–358.
Gao, W., Krimer, L. S., & Goldman-Rakic, P. S. (2001). Presynaptic regulation of recur-
rent excitation by D1 receptors in prefrontal circuits. Proceedings of the National
Academy of Sciences, 28(1), 295–300.
Biological Foundations 135
Manfred Wimmer
Introduction
Compared to behaviourism, cognitive psychology has largely neglected moti-
vational issues. With the cognitive revolution, the whole topic of motives
and motivations moved out of the focus of scientific mainstreams. Except
for some social psychologists, the cognitive revolution did not consider basic
motivational forces seriously (LeDoux, 1996, p. 323).
The working hypothesis for explaining the functional principles of cogni-
tion in general have been deeply influenced by the computer sciences. The
concept of the brain as a computer has become the leading idea, and a lot of
metaphors from computer sciences influenced the view of cognitive func-
tions, which were treated as purely neocortical processes. Emotional and
motivational factors were considered as neutral energy or unspecified arousal
processes (Schachter & Singer, 1962).
In the course of the last decade, the situation changed as research from
the booming fields of neurobiology and neurophysiology increasingly pro-
vided evidence that cognitive functions are being seriously influenced by
deeper layers (motivational as well as emotional) of the brain. The view of
cognitive processes as purely neocortical functions more and more appears as
one-sided and insufficient (e.g., Ciompi, 1988, 2003; Damasio, 2003; LeDoux,
1996, 2002; Panksepp, 1998; Wimmer & Ciompi, 1996). The necessary exten-
sion that integrates emotional as well as motivational factors leads to a deeper
understanding of cognition in general, and clearly demonstrates the linkages
between cognitive processes and their emotional-motivational bases. This
shift has a deep impact on cognitive sciences and related fields of research as
well as on philosophy in general. Neglecting the whole emotional-biological-
motivational substructures of brain functions and reason in general leads to
one-sided and insufficient conceptions.
137
138 Wimmer
Where to Begin?
A serious challenge for each phylogenetic approach is the problem of the start-
ing point. It is a question located near the borderline between scientific and
more metaphysical issues. For the framework of this article, I will take into
account the perspectives from K. Lorenz and J. Piaget. Lorenz’s approach is close
to general phylogenetic considerations; Piaget’s frame is closer to ontogeny.
Concerning cognition, for Lorenz, as an evolutionary thinker, ‘life itself is
a process of acquiring knowledge’ (Lorenz as cited in Weiss, 1971, p. 231). This
statement was one of the basic ideas for Evolutionary Epistemology (Lorenz
1973; Lorenz & Wuketits, 1983; Riedl, 1984; Vollmer, 1981), which was designed
to enable a kind of naturalization of cognition in general. This means that the
typical frame of analysis for cognitive processes in general – containing sym-
bols, consciousness, language, rationality, and so forth – is enlarged to include
biological-evolutionary processes in a broad sense. Life itself and evolution in
general are considered as processes close to cognition.
From another perspective, J. Piaget, the founder of Genetic Epistemology,
argues, that ‘cognitive processes are the result of organic autoregulation,
whose main mechanisms they reflect’ (Piaget, 1967, p. 27; trans. M. W.). Piaget
also tried a specific kind of naturalization of cognitive processes beyond
Lorenz’s evolutionary naturalization with emphasis on autoregulative pro-
cesses (Piaget, 1967; Vuyk, 1981; Wimmer 1998, p. 181f).
Motivation, Cognition, and Emotion 139
One major approach that serves as background for both kinds of argu-
ments is Bertalanffy’s General Systems Theory, which considers organisms
as open systems whose permanent interactions with the environment estab-
lish a dynamic equilibrium (or steady-state). This means that specific inter-
nal structures are kept stable over a permanent change of matter and energy
(Bertalanffy, 1968, p. 149). These structures are maintained by regulative pro-
cesses, and it is these processes that are the main signs of life (Piaget, 1967, p.
27). A deeper understanding of motivational processes in general (i.e., basic
motivational as well as higher motivational processes) requires considering
these regulatory activities.
For a phylogenetic-evolutionary approach to motivation and related
emotional-cognitive fields, it is necessary to distinguish between three kinds
of regulative activities: structural, functional, and cognitive regulations.
According to Piaget and Bertalanffy, these different kinds of regulatory activ-
ities are closely interrelated, depending on the level of phylogenetic or onto-
genetic development.
a) Structural regulations: At the base of structural regulation there are reg-
ulatory activities without any specified regulatory organs. This kind of
regulatory activity depends on dynamic interactions, ‘where the order
is effectuated by a dynamic interplay of processes . . . e.g., embryonic
regulations where the whole is re-established from the parts in equifi-
nal processes’ (Bertalanffy, 1968, p. 43). Further structural regulations
are based on the endocrine system and lead to changes of an ‘anatom-
ical or histological kind’ (Piaget, 1967, p. 31; trans. M. W.). Essentially,
this type of regulation involves concrete physiological parameters (e.g.,
body temperature, cellular dehydration) that have to be kept stable in
relation to permanently changing environmental conditions.
140 Wimmer
Taxis
On this level, the undirected locomotor activity of kinesis is replaced by a type
of behaviour that is ‘directly determined by the impinging stimulus’ (Lorenz,
1981, p. 227). The main characteristic that differentiates taxis from kinesis is
the goal directedness of this kind of behaviour. Examples are positive pho-
totaxis of moths and negative phototaxis of wood lice. Compared to kine-
sis, which in case of homoeostatic disruption leads to undirected increase of
locomotor activities, taxis is characterised by different kinds of goal-directed
behaviours, such as, ‘away from light’.
Higher forms of taxis reactions can be seen for example in the behaviour
of turbellarian worms. Their movement towards an olfactorily located feed-
ing site depends on their actual internal state (Holzkamp-Osterkamp, 1975,
Motivation, Cognition, and Emotion 143
p. 156). The hungry animal will move towards the feeding site; the satiated
organism does not react to the same olfactory stimulation.
It has to be emphasised, that on this level the differentiation of the internal
conditions of the organism leads to different kinds of motoric patterns and
perceptions. Different types of internal states (e.g., hungry, satiated) render
the organism sensitive towards different kinds of external stimuli, connected
with corresponding motoric patterns, leading to appetitive (approach) or
aversive (avoid) reactions. Perceptive as well as motoric capacities are highly
dependent on the actual internal state. Compared to kinesis reactions, in
which stimulus and response are closely interrelated, in taxis behaviour a new
internal component appears between perception and reaction, which seems
to be one of the precursors of emotions.
This dependence of perceptive and motoric activities on the internal
organismic state appears as a fundamental functional principle within the
emotion-motivation-cognition triangle. In anticipation of later statements,
the internal organismic state may be considered as close to emotions, and
perceptions as close to cognitions. Each cognitive activity is closely con-
nected to the emotional-internal base, providing the necessary connection to
the basic organismic layers.
by a specific colour pattern and prey by their shape. Compared to the motor
component, which appears as highly rigid, this sensory part is a major target
of learning processes and evolutionary changes (Lorenz, 1963).
The IRM appears as a function of the nervous system and shows increasing
specialization with growing complexity of neuronal activities. Invertebrates,
especially insects and spiders (Arachnidae), have IRMs not modifiable by
learning (Lorenz, 1981, p. 175). In higher animals, especially vertebrates, all
IRMs can be modified by learning, which O. Storch calls ‘receptor learning’,
demonstrated, for example, by Schleidt (1962). Examples of further modi-
fications of this sensory component appear in conditioned learning pro-
cedures, such as conditioned appetitive behaviour, conditioned aversion,
and conditioned action (Hassenstein, 1987, p. 274ff; Lorenz, 1981, p. 289ff;
Wimmer, 1996, p. 49).
All these modifications of behavioural schemes cannot be properly under-
stood if the emotional components are not taken into account. In general, they
provide the organism with a necessary feedback for behavioural acts, which
emotionally colour specific actions or situations. It seems evident that with
growing behavioural flexibility, these emotional capacities grew, allowing for
the evaluation of the outcomes of actions and their attendant conditions. ‘We
consider these evaluations as the most general character of emotional quali-
ties of life.’ (Holzkamp-Osterkamp, 1975, p.155; trans. M. W.)
These evaluations emotionally colour the sensory as well as the motor
component, clearly demonstrating that one main function of increasing emo-
tional capacities is the evaluation of internal as well as external stimuli in
relation to the organismic actual state (Holzkamp–Osterkamp, 1975, p. 155;
Obuchowski, 1982, p. 238ff; Panksepp, 1998a; Scherer, 1981, p. 311). According
to Panksepp (1998, p. 48), ‘Each emotion has a characteristic “feeling tone”
that is especially important in encoding the intrinsic values of these interac-
tions, depending on whether they are likely to promote or hinder survival’.
Notably, evaluative processes are primarily not manifested as conscious
deliberations. They refer to relations between the internal state and external
conditions (Holzkamp-Osterkamp, 1975, p. 157). The sensitivity of the IRMs
depends on the internal-central-motivational state (a component of the cen-
tral part) of the organism, making the organism sensitive in regard to these
categories of stimuli that are relevant for its actual state (for a comparison
with the ontogenetic level, see Wimmer, 1998).
The central coordinating part: The central part can be viewed as a mediator
between a sensory surface and motor pattern. In general, the main function
of the central component, which is also considered as internal state, is media-
tion between the sensory surface and behavioural (motoric) programs.2
146 Wimmer
Human Level
‘With the disintegration of instincts, the hereditary programming disappears.
There follow two new types of cognitive self-regulation, which are mobile and
Motivation, Cognition, and Emotion 149
constructive’ (Piaget, 1967, p. 59; trans. M. W.). Among the numerous fac-
tors leading to a fundamental change of behavioural organization in humans,
symbol usage can be considered as one of the core elements. Its tremendous
impact on emotional-motivational and cognitive issues in general (Deacon,
1998) will be discussed in relation to some specific topics.
The present context is not adequate for dealing with the issues of human
ontogeny and the developmental processes leading from concrete senso-motor
processes to symbolic behaviour. Piaget´s naturalistic theory of symbol for-
mation provides a detailed framework for these highly complex stages of
human ontogenetic development, emphasizing in particular the idea that
symbols arise from concrete actions (Piaget, 1967; Wimmer, 1995, p. 46f).
In contrast to basic assumptions of AI research and linguistically orientated
philosophical positions, within this context symbols are not taken as neutral
signs computed by specific rules and governed by language. This idealised
view of symbol manipulation is adequate only for so-called discursive modes
of symbolic expression, appearing very late in human ontogeny, representing
in its most developed version something such as an ideal language, which
most probably is realised only in mathematics. Symbols in these areas are
clearly defined and their usage follows generally accepted grammatical rules
(Langer, 1967, p. 155). The main advocates of discursive symbolisms, such as
Carnap, Russel, and Wittgenstein, drew clear boundaries between scientific
or discursive symbol usage and other more subjective ways of symbol usage,
in domains such as metaphysics, art, and emotions.
Susan Langer’s concept of presentational symbols plays an important role
in the latter type of symbolisation. Presentational symbols differ from dis-
cursive symbols mainly in that they have implicit meaning as well as per-
ceptual and emotional qualities. Consequently, the semantic relations of this
type of symbols are not stable and fixed (as, for example, in scientific lan-
guage or mathematics), and depend more on the whole context (Lachmann,
2000, p. 73).
Presentational symbols also have some affinity to metaphors, namely, ‘the
power of seeing one thing in another’, which is of major importance in regard
to feelings and language (Langer, 1962, p. 153). The concept of presentational
symbolism also embeds the arts and emotions within a framework of articu-
lated experiences and expressions, which are not irrational but follow another
kind of rationality.
Symbolic behaviour in this broad sense and its relations to the underly-
ing motivational bases was one of the major topics of H. Furth’s research. In
contrast to Freud, he tries to embed the Piagetian cognitivist view in a more
dynamic motivational-energetic framework (Furth, 1987, 1998; Wimmer,
150 Wimmer
1998). This view emphasises the affective transitions between concrete behav-
ioural acts and emerging symbolic systems. According to Furth (1987, p. 26ff),
there is an essential difference between the concrete motor output of behav-
iour, as it can be seen in animal behaviour, and human behaviour, where con-
crete motoric action patterns are replaced by symbolic forms of behaviour.
In early prehuman as well as most animal behaviour patterns, the con-
nection between cognition (perception), motivations, and related (motoric)
action patterns is very close. As discussed previously, classical ethology has
demonstrated in detail how the internal states (drives), cognitive activi-
ties, and action patterns are related and activated (Lorenz, 1981; Tinbergen,
1952). In most cases of animal behaviour, activated behavioural programs
include specific motor patterns. The major gap arises when the close rela-
tions between perception, motivation, and action get lost. When this occurs,
the genetically fixed sensory and motor components can escape from their
organizing frame.
Concerning motivational processes, Furth proposes that the energetic
dimensions of the motoric activities that have not been spent in concrete
behavioural acts remain active and are redirected into the symbolic sphere.
Therefore, the energy that normally supports concrete behavioural acts (i.e.,
sensorimotor actions) is now used within the symbolic domain for the gen-
eration and manipulation of symbols. This means that impulses to actions
that are no longer part of concrete actions are transformed in the symbolic
domains, opening up a new field of human experience. Increasing symbolic
capacities lead to a large expansion of motivationally relevant objects as well
as changing problem-solving strategies. The range of concrete stimuli guiding
behaviour gets broader through mentally constructed stimuli.
The new organizing principle is essentially guided by emotions, evaluat-
ing or colouring symbolic as well as sensory and motor components. These
emotional guidelines provide something such as a guarantee or yardstick that
the increasing (symbolic) freedom of behaviour keeps in touch with basic
biological necessities (Wimmer, 1995).3
According to Piaget, Furth considers object constancy as a major fact which
provides the basis for all kinds of symbolizing processes. An object attains a
permanent character, because ‘it is recognised as continuing to exist beyond
the limits of the perceptual field, when it is no longer felt, seen or heard etc.’
(Piaget, 1953, p. 9). Thus, an object is no longer just a ‘thing of action’, but
becomes an ‘object of contemplation’ (Werner & Kaplan, 1963, p. 67).
Within human ontogeny, object constancy appears in the sixth stage of
the sensorimotor period (between eighteen and twenty-four months) and
implies serious changes in affective as well as cognitive dynamics. To take
Motivation, Cognition, and Emotion 151
only one example, releasing stimuli – which were normally concrete stimuli
configurations – eliciting concrete behavioural acts (e.g., fight, flight, mating)
are now effective also in the mental domain. This means that imagined situ-
ations and those projected in the future are now able to seriously influence
behaviour and probably destabilise the whole psychic domain.
Object constancy may be considered as leading to a stabilization of the
whole affective life because the mentally represented symbols as well as the
related affective qualities can remain active, even if the relevant object is out
of range for providing concrete input. Thus, affective qualities colouring
the mental entities remain active in absence of the concrete object.
In general, object constancy leads to a stabilization and expansion of inter-
nal, mental representations and the corresponding affective qualities. If these
representations are paired with phonetic cues, stabilization as well as storage
qualities seem to improve greatly. When phonetic entities such as words are
expressed, they can have strong effects on the affective as well as cognitive
bases.
A word – that is, a symbolic utterance – stored within a specific
affective-cognitive context, can be reproduced beyond this primary con-
text with weaker affective intensities. This leads to increasing flexibility and
increasing abstract modes of symbol usage and representation. Beside abstract
usage of symbols, the same word – produced in a more or less neutral atmo-
sphere – can evoke the primary, context-related original feelings and cog-
nitions. This opens a new dimension of sociocultural development, because
words can be representatives for specific events, persons, and situations and
can thus generate strong emotions – with related cognitions – which are now
beyond the primordial, concrete context (Wimmer, 2004).
There is strong evidence that language arises after symbolisation, and that
the phonologic dimension appeared after the semantic one. Semantic and
phonetic dimensions together seem to have a reciprocal feedback, resulting
in the phenomenal development of human language capacities.
According to Tomasello (1999, p. 96), ‘The central theoretical point is
that linguistic symbols embody the myriad ways of constructing the world
inter-subjectively that have accumulated in a culture over historical time,
and the process of acquiring the conventional use of these symbolic artifacts,
and so internalizing these construals, fundamentally transforms the nature
of children´s cognitive representations’. The core of the argument is that this
new symbolic dimension underlies two major influences: vertical and hori-
zontal conditions. The vertical dimension can be found in all the necessary
cognitive, social, and neuronal preconditions, providing the basis for the abil-
ity to produce and handle symbols.
152 Wimmer
The horizontal dimension takes into account all of the pre-existing sym-
bolic universes, into which the individual human mind gets socialised (e.g.,
Assmann, 2000; Luckmann, 1967; Luhmann, 1980). These symbolic systems
have their internal coherence, their history, and social foundation.
In this field, culture, in a broad sense – including symbols, language, and
all kinds of meaning – functions as the necessary interface, intersubjectively
coordinating the arising subjective fields of symbolic experience, and adjust-
ing human spheres of life and biological programs (Eibl, 2009). It is especially
concepts originating in sociology and the cultural sciences that emphasise the
existence of something such as a ‘cultural memory’ (Assmann, 2000, p. 11f), a
‘sociohistoric apriori’ (Knoblauch, 1996, p. 16) reaching far beyond individual
memory and forming a necessary frame for human ontogeny. This frame pro-
vides basic dimensions of meaning and sense for each individual and also
transcends individual memory. Language can be considered an essential
Motivation, Cognition, and Emotion 153
Notes
1. The author considers classical ethology as the early period of ethological research
mainly situated in Europe with the major figures of N. Tinbergen, E.v. Holst, and K.
Lorenz. Their ideas contradicted those of behaviourism.
2. The relations between this central, coordinating part and feelings is a controversial
topic. One line of argument interprets the feeling part merely as accompanying the
completion of these instinctive behavioural patterns (McDougall, 1933; Sullivan).
In the framework of this tradition, the feeling part is a secondary phenomenon, an
epiphenomenon, appearing as the result of brain and motor activities and neuro-
physiological changes. These are the primary sources of feelings, which arise as a
side effect of such activities.
A similar position was held by W. James who likewise proposed a close connec-
tion between instincts and emotions: ‘Instinctive reactions and emotional expres-
sions thus shade imperceptibly into each other. Every object that excites an instinct
excites an emotion as well’ (1890, p. 442; cit. from Hillman, 1992, p. 49).
The core thesis of James’ theory of emotions is ‘that the bodily changes fol-
low directly the perception of the exciting fact, and that our feeling of the same
changes as they occur is the emotion. . . . Every one of the bodily changes, whatso-
ever it be, is felt, acutely or obscurely, the moment it occurs’ (James, 1890, p. 449f;
cit. from Hillman, 1992, p. 50). Thus, for James, feelings are just perceptions of
physiological-motor changes.
Other, more functionalist models view emotion as a mediating phase or event
between cognitive and motor parts (e.g., Plutchik, 1980, 1984). The close relation
between instinctive behavioural patterns and emotions seems evident, but the
hypothesis of ‘emotion as an accompaniment’ (Hillman, 1992, p. 45f) does not take
into account the evaluative functions of emotions leading to a broad scale of expe-
rienced emotions as well as modifications of behaviour.
3. Concerning the ‘decoupling’ of behavioural components, Scherer also emphasizes
the essential role of emotions: ‘Emotions “decouple” the behavioral reaction from
the stimulus event by replacing rigid reflex-like stimulus response patterns or
instinctive innate releasing mechanisms’ (Scherer, 1984, p. 295).
4. Operator is defined as a variable, influencing and changing other variables.
References
Assmann, J. (2000). Religion und kulturelles Gedächtnis. München: Beck´sche Reihe.
Baerends, G. P. (1958). The contribution of ethology to the study of causation of behav-
ior. Acta physiologica et pharmacologica neerlandica, 7, 466–499.
Bateson, G. (1983). Ökologie des Geistes. Anthropologische, psychologische, biologische und
epistemologische Perspektiven. (Trans. V. Holl H. G.) Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp
154 Wimmer
Knoblauch, H. (1996). Die Verflüchtigung der Religion ins Religiöse. Thomas Luckmanns
Unsichtbare Religion. In Th. Luckmann (Ed.), Die unsichtbare Religion (pp. 7–41).
Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
Lachmann, R. (2000). Susanne K. Langer. Die lebendige Form des Fühlens und Verstehens.
München: Wilhelm Fink Verlag.
Langer, S. (1942). Philosophy in a new key. A study in the symbolism of reason, rite and art.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
(1962). Philosophical sketches. Baltimore, MD: John Hopkins Press.
(1967). Mind: An essay on human feeling. Vol.1. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins
University Press.
LeDoux, J. (1996). The emotional brain: The mysterious underpinnings of emotional life.
New York: Simon & Schuster.
(2002). Synaptic self: How our brains become who we are. New York: Viking Penguin.
Leeper, R. W. (1948). A motivational theory of emotion to replace emotion as disor-
ganised response. Psychological Review, 55, 5–21.
(1970). Feelings and emotions. In M. Arnold (Ed.), Feelings and emotions: The Loyola
symposium (pp. 151–168). New York: Academic Press.
Leyhausen, P. (1965). Über die Funktion der relativen Stimmungshierarchie: In K.
Lorenz & P. Leyhausen (Eds.), Antriebe tierischen und menschlichen Verhaltens.
Gesammelte Abhandlungen (pp. 169–267). München: Piper.
Livesey, P. J. (1986). Learning and emotion: A biological synthesis. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence
Erlbaum Associates.
Lorenz, K. (1963). Evolution and modification of behavior. Chicago: Chicago University
Press.
(1966). On aggression. New York: Harvest Book. [Das sogenannte Böse. Zur
Naturgeschichte der Aggression. München: Piper, 1963].
(1973). Die Rückseite des Spiegels. Versuch einer Naturgeschichte menschlichen
Erkennens. München: Piper.
(1977). Behind the mirror. A Search for a natural history of human knowledge.
London: Methuen&Co.
(1981). The foundations of ethology. New York: Springer.
Lorenz, K., & Wuketits, F. (Eds.) (1983). Die Evolution des Denkens. München: Piper.
Luckmann, Th. (1967). The Invisible Religion. The Problem of Religion in Modern
Society. Virginia: Macmillan.
Luhmann, N. (1980). Gesellschaftsstruktur und Semantik. Bd.1. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp..
Luckmann, Th. (1967). The invisible religion. New York: MacMillan.
McDougall, W. (1933). The energies of men. New York: Scribner.
Nussbaum, M. C. (2001). Upheavals of thought: A theory of emotions. Cambridge, MA:
Cambridge University Press.
Obuchowski, K. (1982). Orientierung und Emotion. Köln: Pahl-Rugenstein.
Oeser, E. (1987). Psychozoikum. Evolution und Mechanismus der menschlichen
Erkenntnisfähigkeit. Berlin/Hamburg: Parey.
Ohman, A. (1993). Fear and anxiety as emotional phenomena: clinical phenomenology,
evolutionary perspectives and information processing. In M. Lewis & J. Haviland
(Eds.), The handbook of emotions (pp. 511–536). New York: The Guilford Press.
Panksepp, J. (1998). Affective neuroscience. The foundations of human and animal emo-
tions. New York: Oxford University Press.
156 Wimmer
(1998a). The preconscious substrates of consciousness: Affective states and the evolu-
tionary origins of the SELF. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 5, 566–582.
Piaget, J. (1967). Biologie und Erkenntnis. Über die Beziehungen zwischen organischen
Regulationen und kognitiven Prozessen. Frankfurt: S. Fischer.
Platt, J. (1970). The two faces of perception. In J. Platt (Ed.), Perception and change (pp.
25–73). Ann Arbor, MI: The University of Michigan Press.
Plutchik, R. (1980). A general psychoevolutionary theory of emotion. In R. Plutchik
& H. Kellerman (Eds.), Emotion: Theory, research and experience (pp. 3–33). New
York: Academic Press.
(1984). Emotions: A General Psychoevolutionary Theory. In: K. Scherer /P. Ekman
(Eds.) Approaches to Emotions. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Publishers:
Hillsdale.
Riedl, R. (1984). Biology of knowledge. The evolutionary basis of reason. Chichester/New
York/Brisbane: John Wiley & Sons.
(2000). Strukturen der Komplexität. Berlin/Heidelberg: Springer.
Schachter, S., & Singer, J. (1962). Cognitive, social and physiological determinants of
emotional state. Psychological Review, 69, 379–399.
Scherer, K. R. (1981). Wider die Vernachlässigung der Emotion in der Psychologie. In
W. Michaelis (Ed.), Bericht über den 32. Kongreß der dt. Gesellschaft für Psychologie
in Zürich (pp. 304–317). Göttingen/Toronto/Zürich: Hochgreve-Verlag für
Psychologie.
(1984). On the nature and function of emotion: A component process approach. In
K. Scherer & P. Ekman (Eds.), Approaches to emotions (pp. 293–318). Hillsdale, NJ:
Erlbaum.
(1994). Emotions serve to decouple stimulus and response. In P. Ekman & R. J.
Davidson (Eds.), The nature of emotion: Fundamental questions (pp. 127–130). New
York: Oxford University Press.
Schleidt, W. M. (1962). Die historische Entwicklung der Begriffe “Angeborenes aus-
lösendes Schema” und “Angeborener Auslösemechanismus”. Zeitschrift für
Tierpsychologie, 19, 397–722.
Spector, N. H. (1982). The central state of the hypothalamus in health and disease. Old
and new concepts. In P. Morgane & J. Panksepp (Eds.), Handbook of the hypothala-
mus (pp. 203–219). New York: Marcel Dekker.
Sullivan, H.S. (1953). The interpersonal theory of psychiatry. New York: Norton
Tinbergen, N. (1952). Instinktlehre. Berlin/Hamburg: Parey.
Tomasello, M. (1999). The cultural origins of human cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Tomkins, S. S. (1980). Affect as amplification: Some modifications in theory. In R.
Plutchik & H. Kellerman (Eds.), Emotion – Theory, research, and experience. New
York: Academic Press Inc.
Tversky, A., & Kahnemann, D. (1973). Availability: A heuristic for judging frequency and
probability. Cognitive Psychology, 2, 207–232.
Vincent, D. (1990). Biologie des Begehrens. Reinebeck bei Hamburg: Rowohlt.
Vollmer, G. (1981). Evolutionäre Erkenntnistheorie. Stuttgart: S. Hirzel Verlag.
Vuyk, R. (1981). Overview and critique of Piaget`s genetic epistemology 1965–1980. Vols. I
and II. New York: Academic Press.
Motivation, Cognition, and Emotion 157
For too long, culture has been conceptualized as a contextual variable. The
key question of what culture is has not received adequate attention. In this
chapter, we attempt to directly address this question. Drawing on extant
research on cognitive psychology, we present a knowledge perspective on
culture. First, we describe cultural differences in cognition (i.e., procedural
knowledge, declarative knowledge, including cognitive representations of
others, the self, the group, events, and norms). Next, we describe how social
and situational contexts influence the relative accessibility of different kinds
of cultural knowledge. We will conclude the chapter by highlighting the
motivational base of cultural knowledge. That is, use of cultural knowledge
is motivated by basic social and psychological needs. For instance, individu-
als activate their cultural knowledge to reduce uncertainty in social living, to
manage existential terror, and fulfill the need for belongingness.
Individuals sharing the same cultural tradition incorporate similar cognitive
elements into their thought systems and assimilate their cognitive processes
and responses to certain culture-characteristic patterns. As such, culture’s cog-
nitive consequences bespeak the influence of context on human cognitions. At
the same time, cognitive effects of culture are flexible across situations; indi-
viduals recruit the cognitive resources their culture confers to achieve valued
social and personal goals in concrete settings. Contemporary research on cul-
ture and cognition has taken a trait approach to culture, focusing on overt
expressions of culture-characteristic cognitive traits in designated populations.
On the one hand, this approach illuminates chronic group differences in cog-
nition. On the other hand, it obscures the situational flexibility of the cognitive
effects of culture and the agentic nature of cultural cognition (Hong & Chiu,
2001). In this chapter, we take a knowledge perspective to culture, likening
enculturation to an expertise building process (Chiu & Hong, 2006, 2007).
We begin by describing how culture is conceptualized in this perspective,
158
The Social and Cultural Context of Cognition 159
Procedural Knowledge
Procedural knowledge provides us with information about how we can achieve
a particular result. It is knowledge acquired through practice. When a partic-
ular sequence of cognitive operations is frequently used, its performance is
automated and requires little cognitive deliberation. There is good evidence
for country differences in procedural knowledge. For example, compared
to each other, European Americans have a spontaneous tendency to engage
attention in the focal objects in the perceptual field, whereas East Asians tend
to focus on the relationship between the focal objects and the background
(Masuda & Nisbett, 2001).
Cultural experiences mold the development of procedural knowledge
through two major paths. First, particular aspects of the physical and social
environment in a culture offer opportunities to practice certain responses
repeatedly. Miyamoto, Nisbett, and Masuda (2006) illustrated this path in a
series of experiments. Based on a detailed textual analysis of pictures taken
of American and Japanese cities, the investigators discovered that objects
are usually distinct and stand out from the background in American cities.
Conversely, in Japanese cities, objects are ambiguous and tend to blend in
with the background. Miyamoto et al. posit that the experience of living in
the American environment may draw one’s attention to the distinctive focal
160 Au, Wan, & Chiu
objects rather than on the background, whereas the experience of living in the
Japanese environment may direct one’s attention to the relationship between
the focal object and the background. To test this hypothesis, Miyamoto
et al. had Japanese and European American undergraduates view scenes
from either Japan or America. As predicted, for both Japanese and American
participants, viewing Japanese scenes increased sensitivity to changes in the
background and viewing American scenes increased awareness of changes in
the focal objects.
Second, culture shapes procedural knowledge by structuring its members’
motivational environment. As members of a culture routinely pursue cultur-
ally important goals, the procedures for attaining these goals become auto-
mated and can be activated in response to the controlling stimuli without
the individual’s conscious awareness. For example, individuals seeking to
avoid social isolation are more attentive to contextual information. Because
avoidance of social isolation is a chronic concern in East Asian contexts, East
Asians have ample opportunities to practice the attention strategy connected
to this goal. In a series of studies, Kim and Markman (2006) showed that
East-West differences in the fear of isolation mediate East-West differences in
attention strategies described previously. Furthermore, experimental induc-
tion of the fear of isolation increases European Americans’ sensitivity to con-
textual information.
Declarative Knowledge
Declarative knowledge describes whether or not a certain object and event
possesses certain characteristic properties (Turban & Aronson, 1988). A
piece of declarative knowledge, when activated, may constrain subsequent
inferences and decisions, facilitating some and inhibiting others. Among the
many types of declarative knowledge, the three that have received the most
attention in culture and psychology research are representations of persons,
events, and norms.
Person representations. A person representation is a network connecting a
central concept with a number of individual features. The referent of the cen-
tral concept can be the self, a person other than the self, a group, or a social
category. The features linked to the central concept may include traits, pro-
totypic behaviors, or physical characteristics. The associations between the
central concept and the individual features differ in associative strength and
may be specific to a particular type of situation.
Numerous representations may be constructed for the same referent,
each having a different set of associative features. For example, a person can
The Social and Cultural Context of Cognition 161
from bad to good again. This belief is grounded on a widely accepted idea
in Confucian societies: two opposing forces (yin and yang) are constantly
at work, each pushing oneself into the place of the other, which results in
changes. These forces are assumed to manifested in various forms in nature
such as weak versus strong, evil versus divine, illness versus health, coldness
versus warmth, and darkness versus light. Although this conceptualization of
nature’s forces mandates a cyclical trajectory of changes, it also may give rise
to a stable reality over the course of time because all changes are transient.
The belief that changes caused by one force will be negated by changes engen-
dered by its opposing force may reinforce the belief in a fixed reality in East
Asia (Chiu et al., 1997).
In contrast, optimism and the belief in progress have dominated the social
philosophy of Western Europe and the New World since the beginning of the
Industrial Revolution. Witnessing the technological progress in their world
led the intellectuals to be optimistic about their future. They believed that
a better world was just around the corner, and the making of it was in the
people’s own hands (Burchell, 1966). At this time, the theories of biological
evolution and economic development that surfaced predicted the extinction
of unfit species and the decline of adaptive social systems; as a result, the
superior species will dominate and more advanced social systems will be
developed. These beliefs about the trajectory of change support a malleable
view of the world and its institutions in the West (Chiu et al., 1997).
These culture-characteristic beliefs about the trajectory of change con-
tinue to have authority over Chinese and North American students. When
things are moving in a particular direction, Chinese undergraduates are more
likely to anticipate a change in the direction of movement than their North
American peers. For example, compared to European Americans, Chinese
believe more strongly that a couple who have been dating each other for 2
years will break up, a student from a poor family will become rich one day,
and 2 kindergarten children who have been fighting will become friends one
day (Ji, Nisbett, & Su, 2001). Following this line of logic, individuals who
expect the development of events to change course should be less surprised
by unexpected events than those who expect events to progress in a linear
fashion. Consistent with the idea that East Asians subscribe to a cyclical
theory of change and Americans to a linear one, unexpected events surprise
Korean undergraduates more than they do American undergraduates (Choi
& Nisbett, 2000).
The belief that opposing forces operate at the same time also increases peo-
ple’s sensitivity to competing concerns in conflict situations and the motiva-
tion to reconcile them (Cheung et al., 2003). In one study, Peng and Nisbett
The Social and Cultural Context of Cognition 163
(1999) asked Chinese and American students to analyze everyday life situa-
tions that involve intrapersonal conflicts (e.g., a conflict between having fun
or going to school) or interpersonal conflicts (e.g., a conflict between mothers
and their daughters). Consistent with the idea that the Confucian theory of
change is more widely distributed in Asia than in the United States, Chinese
responses tended to focus on the reconciliation of contradictions by consider-
ing merit and fault on both sides (“both the mothers and the daughters have
failed to understand each other”). In contrast, American responses tended to
come down in favor of one side or the other (“mothers should respect their
daughters’ independence”).
Norm representations. A norm representation consists of three elements:
the antecedent circumstances, norm, and consequent conditions (Lindahl &
Odelstad, 2000). The first element – the antecedent conditions – specifies
the circumstances under which the norm should be activated, including the
range of concrete situations where the norm is applicable. The norm refers
to the state of affairs that is generally believed to be the case (e.g., the shared
belief that the needy will receive help). In constructing a norm representa-
tion, individuals need to have access to the distribution of social knowledge
in the society (e.g., they need to know the extent of agreement in the group
with the idea of helping the needy; Ho & Chiu, 1998). Finally, the consequent
conditions specify the behavioral implications of the norm. When the ante-
cedent circumstances are present in a given situation, a certain state of affairs
is designated as the norm, and the individual is expected to ensure that this
state of affairs will take place. Because norm representations are implicative
propositions, they have direct authority over behavior.
Cultural norms are widely distributed norm representations. For example,
one of the most uniform norms in the United States is one for experiencing
emotions – Americans agree that they should feel happy (Eid & Diener, 2001).
However, different cultures have different norms. For example, in resolving
conflicts, the prevailing norms in East Asian societies prescribe the use of
mediational and accommodating strategies to minimize interpersonal ani-
mosity. In contrast, the prevailing norms in Western countries prescribe the
use of more direct, confrontational strategies to win the negotiation game
(Leung, 1987).
In summary, culture-characteristic declarative knowledge are represen-
tations of people, events, and norms individuals abstracted from cultural
experiences. Although people in every culture may have constructed many
different cognitive presentations, the dominant motivational structure in the
culture and its attendant practices render some of these representations more
accessible than others. Accordingly, cultural differences can be understood
164 Au, Wan, & Chiu
in terms of the differing contents of the widely circulated and highly acces-
sible knowledge structures in different cultures. Defining a culture tradition
in terms of its component knowledge items (procedural knowledge, person
representations, event representations, and norm representations) invites
researchers to clearly articulate the type and nature of each knowledge item
as well as its range of applicability, activation circumstances, and inferen-
tial and behavioral implications. For example, environmental affordances
support the development of procedural knowledge, which is activated auto-
matically in the presence of the controlling situational cues. Activation of a
particular representation of the self (e.g., interdependent self) will call out
its associated behaviors (e.g., behavioral mimicry) (Van Baaren et al., 2003).
The applicability of a norm is augmented in situations where cultural iden-
tities are salient (Jetten, Postmes, & McAuliffe, 2002) and when people are
accountable to their cultural group for their behaviors (Briley, Morris, &
Somonson, 2000).
more cooperative choices when they play a prisoner’s dilemma game with
friends, but not when they play it with strangers (Wong & Hong, 2005).
Self-relevance and contrast effect. Although priming a culture often leads
to assimilative responses, culture priming may lead to contrastive responses
if the participants feel that they do not belong to the primed culture. Bond
and his colleagues have reported contrast effects in a study that used lan-
guages to prime culture. For example, in one study (Bond & Cheung, 1984),
Cantonese-speaking Hong Kong Chinese undergraduates filled out a survey
of traditional Chinese beliefs. Mainland Chinese are generally seen as more
traditional than Hong Kong Chinese. Participants who received oral instruc-
tions in Putonghua (the spoken language in Mainland China) responded
more like Westerners than those who received instructions in Cantonese (a
dialect used in Hong Kong). For the participants who received instructions in
Putonghua, the presence of an out-group language reminded the participants
that they did not belong to the primed culture group of Mainland Chinese,
and as a consequence, a contrast effect was found.
Among bicultural individuals, whether they view their dual cultural iden-
tities as oppositional (e.g., I cannot be both a Chinese and an American at the
same time) or as independent or complementary (e.g., I am both a Chinese
and an American) influences their responses to culture priming (Benet-
Martinez et al., 2002). Those who view their dual identities as independent
or complementary tend to assimilate their responses to the primed culture,
whereas those who view their dual identities as oppositional may feel ambiv-
alent about either cultural identity, and respond reactively to the culture
primes, displaying contrastive responses. In summary, activation of cultural
knowledge follows the basic principles of knowledge activation, which govern
the dynamic interactions between cultural knowledge, the situation, the indi-
viduals’ current cognitive and motivational states, and cultural identities.
Conclusion
The cognitive effects of culture illustrate the contextual nature of human cog-
nitions: First, individuals acquire a habitual pattern of performing cognitive
operations and representing the reality as they develop expertise in a certain
culture. Second, individuals change their mental habits when they assimilate
into a new culture. Taking a knowledge perspective to culture, researchers
can go beyond viewing cultural differences as manifestations of culture-char-
acteristic latent cognitive traits and start to examine the situational flexibil-
ity of culture’s cognitive consequences. Furthermore, our review emphasizes
the important role of motivation in cultural cognition. On the one hand, the
dominant motivational structure in a cultural context (e.g., the kinds of goals
The Social and Cultural Context of Cognition 169
References
Barth, F. (2002). An anthropology of knowledge. Current Anthropology, 43, 1–18.
Baumeister, R. F., & Leary, M. R. (1995). The need to belong: Desire for interpersonal
attachments as a fundamental human motivation. Psychological Bulletin, 117,
497–529.
Benet-Martinez, V., Leu, J., Lee, F., & Morris, M. W. (2002). Negotiating biculturalism:
Cultural frame switching in biculturals with oppositional versus compatible cul-
tural identities. Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology, 33, 492–516.
Bond, M. H., & Cheung, M-k. (1984). Experimenter’s language choice and ethnic affir-
mation by Chinese trilinguals in Hong Kong. International Journal of Intercultural
Relations, 8, 347–356.
Brewer, M. B. (1991). The social self: On being the same and different at the same time.
Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 17, 475–482.
Briley, D. A., Morris, M. W., & Simonson, I. (2000). Reasons as carriers of culture:
Dynamic versus dispositional models of cultural influence on decision-making.
Journal of Consumer Research, 27, 157–178.
Burchell, S. C. (1966). Age of progress. New York: Time-Life Books.
Cheung, T-S., Chan, H-M., Chan, K-M., King, A. Y-K., Chiu, C-y., & Yang, C-F. (2003).
On Zhongyong rationality: The Confucian doctrine of the mean as a missing link
between instrumental rationality and communicative rationality. Asian Journal of
Social Science, 31, 107–127.
Chiu, C-y., Dweck, C. S., Tong, J. Y-y., & Fu, J. H-y. (1997). Implicit theories and concep-
tions of morality. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 73, 923–940.
Chiu, C-y., & Hong, Y-y. (2005). Cultural competence: Dynamic processes. In A. Elliot
& C. S. Dweck (Eds.), Handbook of motivation and competence (pp. 489–505). New
York: Guilford.
(2006). The social psychology of culture. New York: Psychology Press.
(2007). Cultural processes: Basic principles. In E. T. Higgins, & A. E. Kruglanski (Eds.),
Social psychology: Handbook of basic principles (pp. 785–809). New York: Guilford.
Chiu, C-y., Morris, M. W., Hong, Y-y., & Menon, T. (2000). Motivated cultural cognition:
The impact of implicit cultural theories on dispositional attribution varies as a func-
tion of need for closure. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 78, 247–259.
Choi, I., & Nisbett, R. E. (2000). Cultural psychology of surprise: Holistic theories
and recognition of contradiction. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 79,
890–905.
170 Au, Wan, & Chiu
Eid, M., & Diener, E. (2001). Norms for experiencing emotions in different cultures:
Inter- and intranational differences. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
81, 869–885.
Greenberg, J., Solomon, S., & Pyszczynski, T. (1997). Terror management theory of
self-esteem and cultural worldview: Empirical assessments and conceptual refine-
ments. In P. M. Zanna (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 29,
pp. 61–141). San Diego, CA: Academic Press.
Harmon-Jones, E., Simon, L., Pyszczynski, T., Solomon, S., & McGregor, H. (1997).
Terror management theory and self-esteem: Evidence that increased self-esteem
reduces mortality salience effects. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 72,
24–36.
Hetts, J. J., Sakuma, M., & Pelham, B. W. (1999). Two roads to positive self-regard:
Implicit and explicit self-evaluation and culture. Journal of Experimental Social
Psychology, 35, 512–559.
Higgins, E. T., & Brendl, C. M. (1995). Accessibility and applicability: Some “activa-
tion rules” influencing judgment. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 31,
218–243.
Ho, D. Y. F., & Chiu, C-y. (1994). Component ideas of individualism, collectivism, and
social organization: An application in the study of Chinese culture. In U. Kim, H.
C. Triandis, C. Kagitcibasi, G. Choi, & G. Yoon (Eds.), Individualism and collectiv-
ism: Theory, method and applications (pp. 137–156). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
(1998). Collective representations as a metaconstruct: An analysis based on method-
ological relationalism. Culture and Psychology, 4, 349–369.
Hong, Y-y., Benet-Martinez, V., Chiu, C-y., & Morris, M. W. (2003). Boundaries of cul-
tural influence: Construct activation as a mechanism for cultural differences in
social perception. Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology, 34, 453–464.
Hong, Y-y., & Chiu, C-y. (2001). Toward a paradigm shift: From cultural differences
in social cognition to social cognitive mediation of cultural differences. Social
Cognition, 19, 118–196.
Hong, Y-y., Ip, G., Chiu, C-y., Morris, M. W., & Menon, T. (2001). Cultural identity and
dynamic construction of the self: Collective duties and individual rights in Chinese
and American cultures. Social Cognition, 19, 251–269.
Hong, Y-y., Morris, M. W., Chiu, C-y., & Benet-Martinez, V. (2000). Multicultural
minds: A dynamic constructivist approach to culture and cognition. American
Psychologist, 55, 709–720.
Jetten, J., Postmes, T., & Mcauliffe, B. (2002). “We’re all individuals”: Group norms of
individualism and collectivism, levels of identification and identity threat. European
Journal of Social Psychology, 32, 189–207.
Ji, L-j., Nisbett, R. E., & Su, Y. (2001). Culture, change, and prediction. Psychological
Science, 12, 450–456.
Kashima, Y., Kashima, E., Chiu, C-y., Farsides, T., Gelfand, M., Hong, Y., Kim, U., Strack,
F., Werth, L., Yuki, M., & Yzerbyt, V. (2005). Culture, essentialism, and agency:
Are individuals universally believed to be more real entities than groups? European
Journal of Social Psychology, 35, 147–169.
Kim, K., & Markman, A. B. (2006). Differences in fear of isolation as an explanation of
cultural differences: Evidence from memory and reasoning. Journal of Experimental
Social Psychology, 42, 350–364.
The Social and Cultural Context of Cognition 171
Knowles, E. D., Morris, M. W., Chiu, C-y., & Hong, Y-y. (2001). Culture and process of
person perception: Evidence for automaticity among East Asians in correcting for
situational influences on behavior. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 27,
1344–1356.
Kosic, A., Kruglanski, A. W., Pierro, A., & Mannetti, L. (2004). The social cognition of
immigrants’ acculturation: Effects of the need for closure and the reference group
at entry. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 86, 796–813.
Lau, I. Y-m., Chiu, C-y., & Lee, S-l. (2001). Communication and shared reality: Implications
for the psychological foundations of culture. Social Cognition, 19, 350–371.
Lehman, D., Chiu, C., & Schaller, M. (2004). Psychology and culture. Annual Review of
Psychology, 55, 689–714.
Leung, K. (1987). Some determinants of reactions to procedural models for conflict res-
olution: A cross-national study. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 53,
898–908.
Lindahl, L., & Odelstad, J. (2000). An algebraic analysis of normative systems. Ratio
Juris, 13, 261–278.
Lyons, A., & Kashima, Y. (2003). How are stereotypes maintained through communi-
cation? The influence of stereotype sharedness. Personality and Social Psychology
Bulletin, 85, 989–1005.
Masuda, T., & Nisbett, R. E. (2001). Attending holistically versus analytically: Comparing
the context sensitivity of Japanese and Americans. Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology, 81, 922–934.
Menon, T., & Morris, M. W. (2001). Social structure in North American and Chinese
cultures: Reciprocal influence between objective and subjective structures. Journal
of Psychology in Chinese Societies, 2, 27–50.
Menon, T., Morris, M. W., Chiu, C-y., & Hong, Y-y. (1999). Culture and the construal of
agency: Attribution to individual versus group dispositions. Journal of Personality
and Social Psychology, 76, 701–717.
Miyamoto, Y., Nisbett, R. E., & Masuda, T. (2006). Culture and the physical environ-
ment: Holistic versus analytic perceptual affordances. Psychological Science, 17,
113–119.
Morling, B., Kitayama, S., & Miyamoto, Y. (2002). Cultural practices emphasize influ-
ence in the United States and adjustment in Japan. Personality and Social Psychology
Bulletin, 28, 311–323.
Peng, K., & Nisbett, R. E. (1999). Culture, dialectics, and reasoning about contradiction.
American Psychologist, 54, 741–754.
Pickett, C. L., Bonner, B. L., & Coleman, J. M. (2002). Motivated self-stereotyping:
Heightened assimilation and differentiation needs result in increased levels of pos-
itive and negative self-stereotyping. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
82, 543–562.
Solomon, S., Greenberg, J., & Pyszczynski, T. (1991). A terror management theory of
social behavior: The psychological functions of self-esteem and cultural world-
view. In L. Berkowitz (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 24, pp.
93–159). San Diego, CA: Academic Press.
Trafimow, D., Triandis, H. C., & Goto, S. G. (1991). Some tests of the distinction between
the private self and the collective self. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
60, 649–655.
172 Au, Wan, & Chiu
Triandis, H. C. (1989). The self and social behavior in differing cultural contexts.
Psychological Review, 96, 506–520.
Turban, E., & Aronson, J. (1988). Decision support systems and intelligent systems. Upper
Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall, Inc.
Van Baaren, R. B., Maddux, W. W., Chartrand, T., de Bouter, C., & van Knippenberg, A.
(2003). It takes two to mimic: Behavioral consequences of self-construals. Journal
of Personality and Social Psychology, 84, 1093–1102.
Wong, R. Y-M., & Hong, Y-y. (2005). Dynamic influences of culture on cooperation in
the prisoner’s dilemma. Psychological Science, 16, 429–434.
Wyer, R. S., Jr. (2004). Social comprehension and judgment: The role of situated models,
narratives, and implicit theories. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
9
Karl Edlinger
Introduction
This chapter deals with the importance and function of various models of liv-
ing organisms for epistemological concepts, on the one hand, and the philo-
sophical and epistemological presuppositions of organismic biology, on the
other hand. The objective is to show that for every epistemological approach,
not only philosophy is of importance but also biology as the science of the
neuronal basis of psychological as well as epistemological processes. This
interdependency claims for a theory of science, which avoids a predominance
of philosophy or natural sciences as well as of a vicious circle, which must
occur automatically when an attempt is made to establish philosophy or biol-
ogy as a so-called meta-level of cognition.
Constructive realism (CR) abstains from every meta-level of cognition and
knowledge. It conceives cognition as an outcome of knowledge of practice, as
a knowledge resulting from the individual’s activity in the world of everyday
life. Sciences function as microworlds, which contain a small sector of real-
ity, whereby reality is understood as the world that is constructed by human
beings rather than the totality of the given, in the sense of environment.
Knowledge in the sense of CR means to be able to act with competence
and handle objects in accordance with some special goals. This conception
does not provide any idea about the real structure of world and environment,
but it lets us better understand various contexts in which human beings are
engaged in acting and reflecting. In addition, the conception of CR gives us
the chance to highlight some essential methodological presuppositions of sci-
entific disciplines that are valid in every cultural context, despite differences
in conceptions of nature, techniques, or society, and serve as a basis of under-
standing various cultural developments.
173
174 Edlinger
Historical Retrospective
The development of European sciences during the modern age brought about
an impressive predominance of the so-called empirical natural sciences over
philosophy in many respects. Physics and chemistry as the classical empirical
sciences presented an enormous number of scientific facts and information
about nature; our most discussed models of the world are based mainly on
the results of physical and chemical experiments and theories, which result
from the former.
Human beings too are affected by this trend. By establishment of evolu-
tionary theories as common sense views of the realm of organisms and their
origin, humans have been incorporated definitively into the animal realm.
The generally accepted fact that humans are closely related to every member
of the animal realm gave rise to a different biological view of their nature and
abilities, the mental and intellectual in particular, than had prevailed before.
In this manner, the discussion about the basic mechanisms of thinking
and reflecting, cognition and epistemology as well as the mental construction
of the world by human beings eventually changed into a discussion about
biological reasons of activities in many respects. When human beings are
conceived as biological organisms, their various faculties may be reduced to
a biologically explicable basis. This becomes increasingly evident when the
close relations between some patterns of neuronal activities and mental con-
ditions are revealed in research.
This view of human development makes it possible to discuss and find
solutions to many urgent philosophical questions and problems, such as the
origin and function of consciousness, the isomorphism or non-isomorphism
between the outer world and its inner representations, the relations between
sensory data and physical processes affecting the human sensory system, and
the biological elements that contribute to shaping our models of nature and
world.
However, before attempts to solve these questions are discussed, it is neces-
sary to clarify whether these issues concern mankind in general at all times
or only a special cultural area at a special period of cultural development. In
addition, we must ask whether these problems are consequences of some spe-
cial ways of thinking and researching. It is possible that these questions arise
out of a special view of organisms, which are in turn conditioned by cultural
Biological Models and Evolution 175
factors. It is necessary to consider that these questions make sense only when
we accept some special kinds of polarity, such as the polarity between the
individual and his or her environment as well as the polarity between physi-
cal processes and the nervous system and between biological and neuronal
structures and the outcomes of their respective activity.
Polarity, as well as dualism in general, is a characteristic of European think-
ing at the beginnings of the so-called period of Enlightenment. It seems to be
a special way of dealing with the contradiction between new experimental
methods of mechanistic physics, which are interpreted only quantitatively,
and the overwhelming variety of qualities in human minds in many respects.
By means of a rigid separation of matter, on the one hand, and the mental
experience with its various qualities, on the other hand, it was possible for
early philosophers such as Descartes to establish a mechanistic science and
save Christian religion as a domain of spirituality. The progress of the mecha-
nistic sciences has led with time to an absolute predominance of science over
religion and the so-called human sciences.
Evolutionary Theories
According to this general trend, the conception of organisms changed, too.
At the end of the eighteenth century, organisms were commonly conceived
by many authors, such as G. Cuvier, as some kind of mechanical working
machines consisting of finely balanced components. Some vague ideas of
evolutionary change and adaptation as presented by Buffon resulted in the
evolutionary theories of Lamarck, Wallace, and Darwin.
Organisms, including human beings, were seen as the outcome of a long
chain of step-by-step alterations. In contrast to Lamarck, who presented a
theory with teleological features – which had been disproved a long time
before – Wallace and Darwin elaborated ideas, which were in accordance
with mechanical theories about human societies. Similarly to human beings
in the period of capitalism, animals and plants were believed to be under
pressure of competition for food, energy, and biotopes.
The fittest or best adapted individuals were expected to have the optimal
chances for survival and reproduction. In line with this view, evolution is a
play of trial and error, resulting in the extinction of the nonadapted organ-
isms. Evolutionary change, just as natural selection, is a process of adapta-
tion according to the well-known procedures and techniques of the breeders.
The analogies with some economic and social processes as well as with the
experiences of breeders may have led to serious misconceptions in the early
Darwinian evolutionary theory and biology. Organisms were not conceived as
176 Edlinger
active entities, but in correspondence with the analogies with breeders, were
dissolved into aggregates and arrangements of features or characteristics. The
so-called synthetic theory of evolution gave rise to a transformed concep-
tion of evolution, which came to be considered as a process of permanently
changing frequencies of characteristics, namely, genetic alleles within animal
or plant populations. According to this view, organisms as well-integrated
units do not exist. All organs or characteristics were believed to be the out-
come of the play of various genetic changes and rigid selection, which should
result automatically in perfect adaptations. Each characteristic and feature of
an organism could be conceived as possible and, because it has necessarily
evolved by selection, it was viewed as a kind of reproduction or portrayal of
some environmental pressures and needs. This way of thinking has left quite
a number of problems unsolved, or rather, swept under the carpet. The state-
ment that a special characteristic or feature of an organism may be of evolu-
tionary advantage does not provide information about the reason for the real
character of this advantage nor an explanation of its origin.
In this manner, a mechanistic interpretation of world and nature led to a
dilemma. On the one hand, there was a world – including living beings and
humans in particular – which was believed to consist of eternally existing parti-
cles of matter, pushing and attracting one another and resulting in special mate-
rial arrangements. On the other hand, there was the world of human mind and
consciousness, which seemed to be poised upon lifeless physical structures.
On the background of the success of materialism and mechanism, it is
not surprising that the existence of mind and consciousness was denied or
that they were interpreted as epiphenomena, for which no reason could be
given at the time. For the future, it could be expected that reasons support-
ing the emergence of mind and consciousness would eventually be given by
Darwinian evolutionary theory.
Haeckel (1866), Lorenz (1941, 1978), Campbell (1974a, 1988), Campbell &
Paller (1989), Riedl (1981), Vollmer (1975) and others attempted to provide
new arguments for this view on a Darwinian theoretical foundation, sug-
gesting an evolution by adaptation, which means the survival of well-adapted
living beings as a result of selection by the environment. Actually, the objec-
tive was to present a biological and realistic foundation for Kant’s Newtonian
concepts of space and time and his apriori tenets.
In consideration of modern physics, Vollmer developed the ideas of
Evolutionary Epistemology in terms of the very restricted concept of a
so-called mesocosmos (i.e., the Newtonian world of our everyday experience).
Further, Riedl revised his positions by considering the highly complicated
network-like causality of ecology, human societies, and “cultural evolution”
(Cavalli-Sforza & Feldman, 1981; Boyd & Richerson, 1985). Hence, it seems
necessary to conceive Evolutionary Epistemology, in the Lamarckistic sense
of Spencer as well as in the Darwinian sense, as a partial theory of an adap-
tational concept of evolution (Campbell, 1974a, 1974b, 1985, 1988; Riedl, 1981).
That means that the validity of the modern Darwinian evolutionary episte-
mology depends on the validity of Darwinism. If the theory of adaptation is
untenable, then evolutionary epistemology is also obsolete.
Also, in former periods other biologists and philosophers (e.g., Uexküll
1921, 1928; Cassirer, 1955–1957) proposed theories considering organismic
conditions of human thought and cognition. Yet, Evolutionary Epistemology,
just as original Darwinism, does not present concepts of organisms as sub-
jects, which fulfill the basic requirements for consistent theories of function-
ing organisms.
Stimulation of Musculature
Permanent activity of contractile fibers, namely muscles, is caused by perma-
nent interactions between the elements of the locomotor apparatus. Muscle
cells and muscles can stimulate one another. In this manner, highly compli-
cated patterns of excitation can be formed. Musculature can act as its own
pacemaker system. In more complicated constructions, this task can fall to
highly specialized cells of the musculature, which evolve step by step to vari-
ous kinds of nerve cells.
Nerve cells stand in contact with the musculature and other nerve cells,
arranging themselves in nervous systems. Synaptic connections between
nerve cells and, as a consequence, the patterns of the neuronal network, are
organized by trial and error processes in the neuromotor system (Edlinger,
1991). Only those connections that are ingenious for a frictionless locomotion
and efficient compensatory activity of the organism can persist.
Nervous systems always function in accordance with the needs of the loco-
motor apparatus, which in most cases persists in being symmetrical over all
evolutionary changes. So, all patterns that are generated by nervous systems
must be useful for conserving the symmetrical structure of the locomotory
apparatus and all adjacent and dependent structures, such as skeletons.
Reduction of Symmetry
It can be concluded that reduction and decrease of the perfect symmetry of
a globular shape to a bilateral symmetry causes the evolution of highly com-
plicated and effective organismic constructions as well as of effective nervous
systems (Linden, 2007). This aspect should also be seen in connection with
the ontogenetical development. Also, prior to fertilization the organisms are
complicated and permanently working constructions.
Eggs are not homogeneous, as suggested by many theories, which are
focused only on molecular biology. They have a complicated structure as
good as adult organisms. All transitory stages of development must function
frictionless as energy converters. Formation processes are mechanical and
depend on internal needs and constraints. Symmetry and asymmetry also
follow very strict mechanical rules during ontogenetical development.
He (v. Uexküll) too wanted to draw far-reaching conclusions from the anatomical
type to which an animal belongs, and he insisted that these conclusions would
have perfect certainty. . . . We know its characteristics and its activities; we look
into its “inner life” and we see its environment, for whatever it undergoes from
the outer world depends strictly upon the way it is able to accept and act on exter-
nal stimuli. An animal can receive only those impressions for which it is prepared
by its structure and can react to stimuli only in so far as it possesses the appropri-
ate organs (Cassirer 1944, pp. 23–24).
This highly selective approach to the environment, namely, only to some spe-
cial sectors of the environment is the rationale underlying v. Uexküll’s sugges-
tions that every organism fits perfectly, from the very beginning, to its special
environment, but always in accordance with its internal needs and not as a con-
sequence of Darwinian adaptation. Darwinian adaptation cannot take place in
Uexküll’s and Cassirer’s view. So for Cassirer every animal is closely bound up
with its environment through such functional circles, of which a number are
recognizable for almost every organism and which can be named by reference
to their corresponding objects, such as prey, enemy, sex, and habitat. Here it
is obviously erroneous to speak of an “adaptation to the environment” in the
Darwinian sense, for to do so is to convert into a process which requires time
something that is actually determinate and indispensible from the first to the
survival of the animal. If it is the inner structure that creates the environment
by its own activity, one should not say that an animal is more or less adapted to
186 Edlinger
the environment. Only thanks to itself alone is each animal entirely fitted into
into its environment (Cassirer 1944, p. 24).
In accordance with his non-adaptational conception, Uexküll claims that
every animal has an inner world, a world specific to it, which depends on its
special structure or construction and to which there is so far no access for
human beings. Cassirer wrote:
The experiences – and therefore the realities – of two different organisms are
incommensurable with one another. In the world of a fly, says Uexküll, we find
only “fly things”; in the world of a sea urchin we find only “sea urchin things”
(Cassirer 1944, p. 23).
Because effectors and receptors are connected, on the one hand, by an inter-
nal network of nervous structures and the environment, on the other hand,
Uexküll calls this circular arrangement of various activities and perceptions,
the arrangement of the perception system and the effector system, the “func-
tional circle” (Funktionskreis) of the animal (Cassirer 1944, p. 24). According
to Uexküll, organisms are highly autonomous in all respects. They create their
own worlds: the urchin an urchin world; the dog a dog world; and human
beings a human world.
Ernst Cassirer supports this view of organismic autonomy, but focuses his
interest on those sectors of the human world that seem to be exceptions of
Uexküll’s rule in some respect. Cassirer assumes that the so-called worlds
of animals consist of systems of signs, whereby signs resemble symptoms of
things and are defined as directly representing objects in actual situations;
hence, their importance for the animal’s actions and reactions. In contrast,
humans are characterized by a special mental activity that results in the con-
struction of “symbols.” S. Langer, a modern representative of Cassirer’s view
of symbolic forms, writes: “It is only when we penetrate into the varieties of
symbolic activity – as Cassirer, for instance, has done – that we begin to see
why human beings do not act as superintelligent cats, dogs, or apes would
act” (Langer 1957, p. 43).
Thus, in Cassirer’s philosophy, symbols function as substitutes of real
things, to which there is no direct access. Symbols occur within special sys-
tems of thinking and reflecting called the symbolic forms. Cassirer identifies
different symbolic forms, such as language, myth, religion, the arts, and the
sciences.
Because humans are endowed with the special ability of thinking in sym-
bolic forms, Cassirer calls man the “animal symbolicum.” In humans, the
circle of functions is complemented through the addition of the symbolic
system. It is this symbolic system that enables humans to get various views
Biological Models and Evolution 187
of world and reflect about the world in highly different ways, which cannot
be considered as true or false in a traditional manner. This corresponds to
the approach of constructivist thinking, in particular constructive realism.
In this sense, Cassirer’s Philosophy of Symbolic Forms is a predecessor of
constructivism, especially constructive realism.
Cassirer’s philosophy is based to a high degree on biological presupposi-
tions, and in particular on Uexküll’s view of the relations between organisms
and the environment. The question now arises whether this basis is valid and
can survive in the face of critiques from the quarters of epistomology and
biology. Its survival depends on a well-founded refutation of the adaptation-
ist view of evolution and the presence of an alternative non-adaptationist
view of organisms and evolution, which can provide reasons for organismic
complexity by a non-reductionist model. Notably, although one of Uexküll’s
books is entitled Theoretical Biology, he did not develop a consistent theory of
the autonomous organism and its evolution.
Evolution of Cognition
The theoretical foundations of this kind are provided by the theory of organ-
ismic constructions. As was shown previously, it is possible to reconstruct
on this basis not only the evolution of organismic constructions but the evo-
lution of mental and cognitive abilities, as well. These are, in contrast with
Darwinian evolutionary epistemology, the outcome of special costructional
properties of autonomous organisms. They cannot be considered without a
very close connection with their organismic basis.
This holds also in regard to the evolution of complicated nervous systems
and the their abilities. In some special groups of animals, in particular the
vertebrates, there occur some inner spaces that are undisturbed by movement
and deformation. In these spaces, some concentration effects of nervous tis-
sues take place and enable many additional neuronal operations. With increas-
ing concentration, primitive anticipatory operations occur increasingly. They
cause the origin of some kind of an inner world, which, however, depends in
accordance to Uexküll on organismic properties.
The consequence of evolution of increasingly complicated nervous systems
is a continuous increase in the complication as well as autonomy of the inner
world of organisms. This development also entails a growing emancipation
from the organismic construction. This emancipation happened with the
increase of a mechanically undisturbed brain in vertebrate head capsules and,
in particular, with the evolution of special ape constructions whose eman-
cipation enabled them to evolve a differentiated symbolic language. This is
188 Edlinger
Cultural Implications
As a consequence of the presuppositions of the theory of organismic construc-
tions and the autonomy of cultural development, only a constructivist view of
knowledge and cognition can be accepted. Constructivism can be considered
as the outcome of various traditions of thinking, the Kantian in the European
tradition in particular. Further, the suggestion of organismic autonomy has
highly radical and far-reaching consequences not only for thinking about
the relation between organisms and their environment but even for thinking
about the approach to nature in general. Although it has to be conceded that
every ontological description of nature is invalid, the mechanistic approach
in the tradition of European sciences cannot be upheld. Autonomous organ-
isms must act independently in their environment and must be pushed to
activity by their own inner mechanisms. Hence, they cannot be regarded any
more as some kind of cogwheels of a gigantic clockwork, as has been sug-
gested by some models of traditional natural philosophy.
Consequently, the theory of organismic constructions accepts the philos-
ophy of A. N. Whitehead in many respects. The acceptance of Whitehead’s
concepts can be seen as a strangification of traditional biology. Whitehead
conceived nature as an organic and organismic-like structure that is per-
manently in motion, change, and development, but is always spontaneously
pushed by impulses that come from within the organism. Whitehead’s world
consists of organisms. Organisms in the sense of Whitehead are very man-
ifold and occur on various levels of complexity. Because of the organismic
nature of the world, this philosophy is based on an all-embracing permanent
process and stands in no need of a “god” such as the supernatural clockmaker
so common in the European tradition. Indeed, a better understanding of the
complexity of the world is provided by some physicalistic theories, such as
the chaos theories, synergetics, or theory of dissipative structures, but they
cannot present a consistent view of living organisms.
References
Arias, A. M. (2008). Drosophila melanogaster and the development of biology in the
20th century. Methods in Molecular Biology, 420, 1–25.
Biological Models and Evolution 189
Boyd, R., & Richerson, P. (1985). Culture and the evolutionary process. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press.
Campbell, D. T. (1974a). Evolutionary epistemology. In P. A. Schilpp (Ed.), The philoso-
phy of Karl R. Popper (pp. 412–463). LaSalle, IL: Open Court.
(1974b). Unjustified variation and selective retention in scientific discovery. In F. J.
Ayala & T. Dobzhansky (Eds.), Studies in the philosophy of biology (pp. 139–161).
London: Macmillan.
(1985). Pattern matching as an essential in distal knowing. In H. Kornblith (Ed.),
Naturalizing epistemology (pp. 49–70). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
(1988). Popper and selection theory. Social Epistemology, 2, 371–377.
Campbell, D.T., & Paller, B. T. (1989). Extending evolutionary epistemology to “justify-
ing” scientific beliefs (A sociological rapprochement with a fallibilist perceptual
foundationalism?). In K. Hahlweg & C. A. Hooker (Eds.), Issues in evolutionary
epistemology (pp. 231–257). Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.
Cassirer, E. (1944). An essay on man. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
(1946). The myth of the state. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
(1955–1957). The philosophy of symbolic forms. 3 Vols. New Haven: Yale University
Press.
Cavalli-Sforza, L., & Feldman, M. (1981). Cultural transmission and evolution: A
quantitative approach. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Dawkins, R. (1978). Replicator selection and the extended phenotype. Zeittschrift für
Tierpsychologie, 47, 61–76.
Edlinger, K. (1991). Organismus und Kognition – Zur Frage der biologischen Begründung
kognitiver Fähigkeiten. In M. F. Peschl (Ed.), Formen des Konstruktivismus in
Diskussion (pp. 108–150). Viena: WUV-Universitätsverlag.
(2004). Alle Evolution ist Anpassung – Ist alle Evolution Anpassung? Eine Kritik der
Darwinschen Anpassungsmetapher. In G. Fleck, K. Edlinger, & W. Feigl (Eds.), Die
Theorie der Anpassung in Psychologie und Biologie. Frankkfurt: Peter Lang – Europ.
Verlag der Wissenschaften.
Edlinger, K., & Gutmann, W. F. (2002). Organismus – Evolution – Erkenntnis. Grundzüge
der Kritischen Evolutionstheorie und der Organismischen Konstruktionslehre.
Frankfurt: Peter Lang – Europ. Verlag der Wissenschaften.
Edlinger, K., Gutmann, W. F., & Weingarten, M. (1989). Biologische Aspekte der
Evolution des Erkenntnisvermögens – Spontaneität und synthetische Aktion in
ihrer organismischkonstruktiven Grundlage. Natur & Museum, 119, 113–128.
(1991). Evolution ohne Anpassung. In W. Ziegler (Ed.), Aufs. u. Reden Senckenb.
Naturforsch. Ges. 37.
Foerster, H. v. (1988). Constructing a reality. In Sherman (Ed.), Adolescent Psychiatry
15: Developmental and clinical studies (pp. 77–95). Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
(1990). Understanding understanding. Methodologia, 7, 7–22.
(1998). On constructing a reality. In E. Rehfeld (Ed.), Borderline, Lebbeus Woods (pp.
72ff). New York: Springer.
Frischeisen-Köhler, M. (1925). Die Philosophie der Gegenwart. In M. Dessoir (Ed.), Die
Geschichte der Philosophie (pp. 553–630). Wiesbaden: Fourier.
Ghosh, K., Thodeti, C. K., Dudley, D. Mammoto, A., Klagsbrun, M., & Ingber, D. E.
(2008). Tumor derived endothelial cells exhibit aberrant Rho-mediated mechano-
sensing and abnormal angiogenesis in vitro. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci., 32, 11305–11310.
190 Edlinger
Nüsslein-Volhard, C. (2004). Das Werden des Lebens. Wie Gene die Entwicklung steuern.
München: Beck
Prigogine, I. (1979). Vom Sein zum Werden. Braunschweig: Viehweg.
Prigogine, I., & Stengers, I. (1981). Dialog mit der Natur. München: Piper.
Riedl, R. (1981). Biologie der Erkenntnis. Hamburg: P. Parey.
Roth, G. (1987). Visual behavior in salamanders. Studies in brain function. Vol. 14. New
York: Springer-Verlag.
Uexküll, J. v. (1921). Umwelt- und Innenwelt der Tiere. Berlin: Springer.
(1928). Theoretische Biologie. Berlin: Springer.
(1980). Der Funktionskreis. In Kompositionslehre der Natur (pp. 226–290). Frankfurt:
Ullstein.
Vollmer, G. (1975). Evolutionäre Erkenntnistheorie. Stuttgart: S. Hirzel.
Wallner, F. (1992a). Acht Vorlesungen über den Konstruktiven Realismus. Vienna: WUV.
(1992b). Konstruktion der Realität. Vienna: WUV.
Whitehead, A. N. (1960). Process and reality. New York: Harper & Row.
(1967). Science and modern world. New York: Harper & Row.
Yung, C., & Ingber, D. E. (2009). Micromagnetic – microfluidic blood cleansing microde-
vice. Lab on a Chip.
10
The genes sing a prehistoric song that today should sometimes be resisted but which
it would be foolish to ignore.
– David Lykken (Bouchard et al., 1990, p. 228).
Cognition is a scientific term for the process, content, and quality of thought.
As the rest of this book makes clear, it is a very broad concept that has very
different specific meanings to different psychologists, philosophers, cognitive
scientists, neurologists, and even linguists, computer scientists, and anesthe-
siologists. To all of them at some level, however, it refers to some faculty for
processing information, applying knowledge, and evaluating or expressing
preferences, whether consciously or unconsciously. As such, it has no content
at all that is distinct from the environment in which it develops and is main-
tained and used. To many, therefore, the possibility of genetic influences on
cognition is foreign, even frightening. How can something as ephemeral and
dependent on the environment as the momentary aesthetic appreciation of a
bird’s song or the knowledge that one can spell a particular word be genetically
influenced? The idea challenges our notions of ourselves as agents expressing
free will and our values of human equality. Yet any measure of cognition from
intelligence to memory to content of thought to problem-solving strategy will
show heritability or evidence of genetic influence.
We can say very similar things about motivation. Motivation is a scientific
term for the driving forces through which we achieve our goals. Again, it is
a very broad concept that takes different and very specific meanings to dif-
ferent scientists who make use of it. For none of them does the term carry
meaning that is distinct from the environment in which humans and other
organisms actualize it. Thus, the possibility of genetic influences on moti-
vation is as foreign and potentially frightening as the possibility of genetic
influences on cognition. How can something as ephemeral and dependent on
the environment as the impulse to comfort a hurt child or the drive to train
192
What Do Genes Have to Do with Cognition? 193
The ideas of the Modern Evolutionary Synthesis came together in the late
1940s, before the discovery of DNA. As augmented to recognize the role of
DNA, they can be summarized as follows:
1) Heredity occurs through the transmission from one generation to the
next of germ-line DNA that is located on chromosomes and organized
into discrete units known as genes.
2) Hereditary variation reflects variation in DNA base sequence.
3) The variation in DNA base sequence that explains hereditary variation
results from the many random combinations of existing alleles that are
generated by the sexual reproductive processes and new variants in
DNA (mutations) that occur accidentally and spontaneously.
4) Selection occurs at the level of the individual organism and its pheno-
type (manifested trait), which may co-evolve with its symbionts and
parasites.
5) Heritable variations have small effects and evolution is gradual, with
few points at which mutation pressure has been of particular impor-
tance. The small changes involved in gradual evolution are important
when extended over time and can explain the large changes observed
in the paleontological record.
in the contexts of the other genes present and the environment in which the
offspring develops. This means that tall parents tend to have tall children, but
the variance in heights of children with tall parents is only slightly less than
that of the population as a whole.
Heritability takes two forms that are often distinct yet rarely clearly dis-
tinguished. People working with domesticated plants and animals had long
been aware and taken advantage of the fact that quantitative characteristics
are passed in varying degrees from parents to offspring, but Fisher and the
other early population geneticists specified how the varying degrees could be
quantified using various combinations of biological relatives who differed in
degree of biological relatedness. These “breeding values” or “narrow-sense
heritabilities” reflect the proportions of population variance that can be
attributed to the combined actions of genes that act independently of each
other and thus additively. However, not all genetic influences are additive
in this way. Genes recombine during the formation of each parent’s gam-
etes, and then the gametes with different genetic heritages combine to form
the zygote. This process produces combinations of genes that interact with
each other and generate other epistatic effects that can be very important
to genetic influences on characteristics in the individual. These nonadditive
effects tend to be dispersed during recombination in transmission to the next
generation, and thus are not part of narrow-sense heritability, but they may
be very important in the manifestation of traits in individuals. “Broad-sense
heritabilities” include all sources of genetic variance.
The best ways to estimate heritability make use of situations in which repro-
duction can be controlled, as in agriculture and laboratory situations; it is not
possible to use them in humans. The formulas generally used to estimate her-
itabilities of human traits rely on differences in extent of similarity of biolog-
ical relatives of different degrees. The most common comparison is between
similarity of monozygotic (MZ) and dizygotic (DZ) twins. MZ twins are
derived from a single fertilized egg that splits early in gestation, and thus are
effectively genetically identical. DZ twins are derived from two eggs released
during a single ovulatory period and fertilized separately, and thus are genet-
ically related in the same way as singleton full siblings. When mating is ran-
dom, they share on average 50 percent of the genes that differ among human
individuals (Guo, 1996). Genetic similarity of MZ twins can thus arise from
both additive and nonadditive genetic influences, but genetic similarity of DZ
twins will tend to arise only from additive genetic influences, so the distinc-
tion between narrow- and broad-sense heritabilities is blurred. A correlation
between members of MZ twin pairs on a trait that is twice as large as the DZ
correlation is generally interpreted as indicating that similarity is due entirely
What Do Genes Have to Do with Cognition? 197
to estimate heritabilities, and exploring this uneasy position will help to illu-
minate how genes are involved in cognition. Darwin’s theories of evolution
and natural selection give a prominent role to environmental circumstances
in determining the long-term fate of genetic variation, but Mendel’s genetic
results, derived as they were essentially from a single pea plot, leave little
room for environmental variation because there essentially was none. Given
his approach of reconciling Mendel’s results with evolutionary theory mathe-
matically and statistically, Fisher (1918, 1930) saw the reconciliation problem
as how much of total variation could be attributed to genetic sources and how
much to environmental sources. This focus on variance was a both a major
conceptual departure and a major contribution to population genetics and
statistical analysis more generally.
To this day, most statistical analysis focuses on mean differences. This kind
of analysis incorporates assessment of variance because it is through com-
parison of mean differences with variance that we develop a conclusion that
mean differences are important. Focus tends to be on the standard deviation
as the measure of variance, however, because the standard deviation is stated
on the same scale as the mean, which makes it possible to directly assess
the relative importance of variation in ratio scales with real zero points. (Of
course, in psychology in general and cognitive science in particular we are
seldom working with ratio scales with real zero points, so the emphasis in this
field is not particularly well placed.) Despite this, the scale of mean and stan-
dard deviation is not natural for variability itself, so independent sources of
deviation from the mean cannot be summed to obtain total deviation when
they are stated as standard deviations. If stated as variances, however, they
can be summed, at least presuming they are independent. This was Fisher’s
reason for focusing on variance rather than standard deviation: it made his
conceptual goal of reconciling Mendel’s genetics with evolutionary theory
tractable using his methodological approach of choice – statistical mathemat-
ics – at least as long as genetic and environmental influences could be con-
sidered independent. Fisher was aware that nonadditive interactions between
genetic and environmental influences interrupted the ability to sum variance
components, but he treated this as merely a statistical complication. To him,
the statistical methods of analysis of variance that he developed were capable
of revealing the presence and importance of such interactions, and statistical
treatments to remove their effects were appropriate means of dealing with
them if they appeared. Fisher’s treatment was mathematically rigorous and
his (rather limited) experimental work convinced him that interactions were
rare and of little practical importance. Many followed him in effectively dis-
regarding them.
200 Johnson
0.8
0.6
Viability
0.4
0.2
16.5°C.
25.5°C.
0.0 Genotype
Figure 10.1. Norms of reaction in viability in 2 genetic lines of fruit flies in response
to differences in temperature. A and B refer to chromosomal types. Adapted from
Dobzhansky (1951).
1.0
Genetic
Shared
Nonshared
0.8
Proportion of Variance
0.6
0.4
0.2
0.0
1 3 5 7 9 11 15 17 21 35
Age
Figure 10.2. Typical patterns of changes in genetic and environmental influences on
intelligence with age.
the correlation likely centers on the home environment and its extension, the
school environment that parents have selected for their children. Brighter
parents pass whatever genes are involved in intelligence on to their children,
and brighter parents – particularly those with higher socioeconomic status
(SES), as that is the way the question has most often been studied – also pass
on more optimal childhood environments for the development of intelli-
gence (Hart & Risley, 1995; Heath, 1982). They read more to their children,
speak to them more using larger vocabularies, are more likely to talk to them
in intellectually stimulating ways, are more likely to expose them to intel-
lectually stimulating activities such as visits to museums and concerts and
participation in enrichment classes and science fairs, and are more likely to
make active choices about the schools their children attend. These activities
probably reflect some combination of parental lifestyle and parenting phi-
losophy applied consistently across siblings, tailoring of parental activities
to the individually expressed responsiveness and needs of each child, and
parental life circumstances that dictate available parenting resources. For
example, parents may read to each of their children in very similar amounts
because they believe that reading to children is important, but may find that
What Do Genes Have to Do with Cognition? 207
one child wants to hear the same book over and over and therefore ends up
being exposed to relatively few books, and another is always asking for some-
thing new and ends up being exposed to many more. Parents may also find
it easy to pay for and transport a child to an enrichment course one year
and much more difficult another, due purely to their own job or financial
circumstances.
Because genes and environments are correlated this way in biological fam-
ilies, we know less than we would like about how much these activities actu-
ally matter in the development of intelligence. The best evidence we have
comes from studies of children born to parents of one SES and adopted by
parents in another. These studies generally show that children born to low
SES parents who are adopted into higher SES families tend to have higher
IQs than their siblings who remain with their birth parents by perhaps 12–15
IQ points (Capron & Duyme, 1989; van IJzendoorn, Juffer, & Klein Poelhuis,
2005). These studies also tend to show that adoptees born to high SES parents
tend to have higher IQs than adoptees born to low SES parents, no matter
who raises them, again by perhaps 12 IQ points. These findings are rather soft,
due to the relative rarity of studies, small sample sizes, and the absence of ran-
domized assignment to adoptive circumstances, appropriate control samples,
clear before and after adoption measurement, and follow up of most adoptive
samples into adulthood (van IJzendoorn, Juffer, & Klein Poelhuis, 2005).
Still, together, these adoption findings suggest that high SES environment
helps increase IQ, but it matters less to those born to high SES parents than
to those born to low SES parents. One way to interpret these findings is that
whatever genetic or prenatal or perinatal characteristics are associated with
being born to high SES parents are relatively insensitive to the kinds of dif-
ferences in environments associated with SES, but whatever genetic or pre-
natal or perinatal characteristics are associated with being born to low SES
parents are quite sensitive to those same differences in environments asso-
ciated with SES. Intelligence is unquestionably a developmental trait that
emerges at least partly through the acquisition of cognitive habits and skills
and knowledge. We could explain these findings if genes for traits that pre-
dispose children to seek experiences that develop intelligence – such as thirst
for knowledge, curiosity about how things work, desire to express themselves
clearly and accurately, and so on – were more common among children born
to high SES parents. If children carrying these genes but growing up in low
SES adoptive families had just enough access to books and other learning
materials to acquire these developmental experiences themselves, they could
acquire higher intelligence than most of their low SES peers through correla-
tion between genetic and nonshared environmental influences. Were these
208 Johnson
children growing up in their high SES birth environments, some of this cor-
relation would likely instead be between genetic and shared environmental
influences. At the same time, if genes for traits that predispose children to
adapt to the cognitive behaviors of those around them were more common
among children born to low SES parents, then these children might develop
higher intelligence when raised in high SES adoptive homes than they would
have if they had been raised by their low SES birth parents, and they would do
so through correlation between (different) genetic and shared environmental
influences as well as interaction between genetic and shared environmental
influences.
There is precedent for and some evidence supporting these propositions.
Hayes (1962) and Bouchard (1997) have proposed that genes drive the acqui-
sition of experiences through which intelligence develops, and Cronbach
and Snow and others (Cronbach & Snow, 1977; Freebody & Tirre, 1985; Shute
et al., 1996; Snow, 1982) have gathered considerable evidence that high-ability
students tended to benefit more from open-ended educational curricula that
encouraged active exploration and experimentation than from structured
instruction, but the opposite is the case for lower-ability students. If it were
the case that this involved genetic differences that had frequencies that varied
with SES, there might be relatively few if any genes for intelligence per se, yet
intelligence would show substantial genetic influence or heritability because
of the genetic influences on the traits contributing to its development. In a
general population of children containing representatives of all genetic back-
grounds growing up in all levels of SES, estimates of shared environmental
influences would tend to be exaggerated due to the presence of correlation
between genetic and shared environmental influences in those children
whose intelligence was developing in conformance with the cognitive behav-
iors of those around them. At the same time, estimates of genetic influences
would tend to be exaggerated, too, due to the presence of both interaction
between genetic and shared environmental influences in those same children
and correlation between genetic and nonshared environmental influences in
those children whose intelligence was developing in response to their own
intellectual exploratory behaviors. If the genes for intellectual exploratory
behaviors were more common among children born to high SES parents,
and those for adapting to others’ cognitive behaviors more common among
children born to low SES parents, we could expect that heritability estimates
would be higher (and exaggerated to a greater degree) in high SES groups and
estimates of shared environmental influences would be higher (and exagger-
ated to a greater degree) in low SES groups. Several studies have provided
evidence that this is the case (Harden, Turkheimer, & Loehlin, 2007; Rowe,
What Do Genes Have to Do with Cognition? 209
Jacobson, & van den Oord, 1999; Turkheimer et al., 2003). Of course, it is
extremely unlikely that genetic influences on the development of any child’s
intelligence would be either exclusively exploratory or exclusively adaptive.
If we understand performance on intelligence tests to reflect cognitive skills
and habits broadly in use at time of testing, this same developmental empha-
sis on gene-environment correlation and interaction can be used to explain
the increases in estimates of genetic influences and decreases in estimates
of shared environmental influences on intelligence as samples move from
childhood to adulthood. Although gene-environment correlation and inter-
action likely center on the family environment in childhood, this changes
as children grow to adulthood. Once people reach school-leaving age, the
day-to-day need to maintain intellectual activity varies widely with occupa-
tion and interest, and tends to center on peer group rather than the families
in which people were raised. This means a likely shift of current environ-
mental influences from being primarily shared to being primarily nonshared.
Thus, in those whose intelligence is adaptive, the correlation between genetic
and shared environmental influences in childhood that acted to exaggerate
estimates of shared environmental influences would shift to a correlation
between genetic and nonshared environmental influences that acts to exag-
gerate estimates of genetic influences in adulthood. At the same time, the
interaction between genetic and shared environmental influences in those
same people that acted to exaggerate genetic influences in childhood would
shift to an interaction between genetic and nonshared environmental influ-
ences that acts to exaggerate estimates of genetic influences in adulthood.
The correlation between genetic and nonshared environmental influences
in those whose intelligence is exploratory that acted to exaggerate estimates
of genetic influence in childhood would continue to operate in adulthood.
Taken together, if these genetic and environmental correlative developmental
processes were operative, we would expect estimates of shared environmental
influences on intelligence to drop dramatically from childhood to adulthood,
and estimates of genetic influences to increase, exactly as has been observed.
Similar developmental processes could be involved in many other, if not all,
aspects of cognition.
References
Bouchard, T. J. (1997). Experience producing drive theory: How genes drive behavior
and shape personality. Acta Paediatrica, 86, 60–64.
Bouchard, T. J., Lykken, D. T., McGue, M., Segal, N. L., & Tellegen, A. (1990). Sources
of human psychological differences: The Minnesota Study of Twins Reared Apart.
Science, 250, 223–228.
Capron, C., & Duyme, M. (1989). Assessment of the effects of socio-economic status on
IQ in a full cross-fostering study. Nature, 340, 552–554.
Caspi, A., Roberts, B. W., & Shiner, R. L. (2005). Personality development: Stability and
change. Annual Review of Psychology, 56, 453–484.
Cronbach, L. J., & Snow, R. E. (1977). Aptitudes and Instructional Methods: A Handbook
for Research on Interactions. New York: Irvington.
Darwin, C. (1859). On the Origin of Species. London: John Murray.
What Do Genes Have to Do with Cognition? 213
Dobzhansky, T. (1951). Genetics and the Origin of Species, 3rd Edition. New York:
Columbia University Press.
Dobzhansky, T., & Spassky, B. (1944). Genetics of natural populations. XI. Manifestation
of genetic variants of drosophila pseudoobscura in different environments.
Genetics, 20, 270–290.
Fisher, R. A. (1918). The correlation between relatives on the supposition of Mendelian
inheritance. Transactions of the Royal Society of Edinburgh, 52, 399–433.
(1930). The Genetical Theory of Natural Selection. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Flint, J., & Mackay, T. F. (2009). Genetic architecture of quantitative traits in mice, flies,
and humans. Genome Research, 19, 723–733.
Freebody, P., & Tirre, W. C. (1985). Achievement outcomes of two reading programs –
An instance of aptitude-treatment interaction. British Journal of Educational
Psychology, 55, 53–60.
Gerhart, J., & Kirschner, M. (2007). The theory of facilitated variation. Proceedings of the
National Academy of Sciences, 104, 8582–8589.
Gibson, G., & Dworkin, I. (2004). Uncovering cryptic genetic variation. Nature Reviews
Genetics, 5, 681–690.
Guo, S. W. (1996). Variation in genetic identity among relatives. Human Heredity, 46,
61–70.
Harden, K. P., Turkheimer, E., & Loehlin, J. C. (2007). Genotype by environment inter-
action in adolescents’ cognitive aptitude. Behavior Genetics, 37, 273–283.
Hart, B., & Risley, T. (1995). Meaningful Differences in the Everyday Experience of Young
American Children. Baltimore: Brookes.
Hay, K. J. (1962). Genes, drives, and intellect. Psychological Reports, 10, 299–342.
Heath, S. B. (1982). What no bedtime story means: Narrative skills at some and school.
Language in Society, 11, 49–79.
Hill, W. G., Goddard, M. E., & Visscher, P. M. (2008). Data and theory point to mainly
additive genetic variance for complex traits. PLoS Genetics, 4, e1000008.
Huxley, J. S. (1942). Evolution: The Modern Synthesis. London: Allen & Unwin.
Inlow, J. K., & Restifo, L. L. (2004). Molecular and comparative genetics of mental retar-
dation. Genetics, 166, 835–881.
Johnson, W., Gangestad, S. W., Segal, N. L., & Bouchard, T. J. (2008). Heritability of fluc-
tuating asymmetry in a human twin sample. American Journal of Human Biology,
20, 651–658.
Johnson, W., & Krueger, R. F. (2005a). Genetic effects on physical health: Lower at higher
income levels. Behavior Genetics, 35, 579–590.
(2005b). Higher perceived life control decreases genetic variance in physical health:
Evidence from a national twin study. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
88, 165–173.
(2006). How money buys happiness: Genetic and environmental processes finances
and life satisfaction. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 90, 680–691.
Johnson, W., Turkheimer, E., Gottesman, I. I., & Bouchard, T. J. (2009). Beyond her-
itability: Twin studies in behavioral research. Current Directions in Psychological
Science, in press.
Kim-Cohen, J., Caspi, A., Taylor, A., Williams, B., Newcombe, R., Craig, I. W., & Moffitt,
T. E. (2006). MAOA, maltreatment, and gene-environment interaction predicting
214 Johnson
“Each of us lives within the universe – the prison – of his own brain. Projecting
from it are millions of fragile sensory nerve fibers, in groups uniquely adapted
to sample the energetic states of the world around us: heat, light, force and
chemical composition. That is all we ever know of it directly; all else is logical
inference” (Mountcastle, 1975, p. 131). Within a few million years, the central
nervous system has evolved at a spectacular rate and has become predomi-
nant in behavior control. It shapes our thoughts, hopes, dreams, and imagina-
tions. The brain – a spongy, one-and-a-half–kilo mass of fatty tissue – is what
makes us human. The present chapter will provide only a glimpse of what
is known about the relationship between brain functioning and cognition –
several facets of this relationship rather than a comprehensive overview.
215
216 Jaušovec & Jaušovec
Neuroimaging Techniques
A simple method for recording the electrical activity of the brain is electro-
encephalography (EEG). To record EEG, a small metal disk is attached to
the scalp to detect the electrical activity of neurons in the underlying brain
area. EEG measurement requires collection of a huge amount of data that are
unusable in raw form. Therefore, they are subjected to data-reduction meth-
ods. These reduction methods could be roughly classified into two groups:
first, methods that are partly or completely based on the magnitude of EEG
(e.g., absolute power measures); and second, methods that measure the inter-
relations of EEG activity between different scalp locations (e.g., coherence
measures). Most often, a Fast Fourier Transformation (FFT) is performed on
artifact-free chunks of data to derive estimates of absolute power values or
relative percentage power values in different frequency bands: δ = 1.5 – 3.5
Hz; ϑ = 3.6 – 6.5 Hz; α1 = 6.6 – 8.5 Hz; α2 = 8.6 – 10.5 Hz; α3 = 10.6 – 12.9 Hz;
β1 = 13.0 – 17.5 Hz; β2 = 17.6 – 23.5 Hz; β3 = 23.6 – 31.5 Hz. The decision to select
these eight bands is mainly based on recent findings relating some of the
bands to different mental processes. In several studies using the event-related
Brain, Behavior, and Cognition 217
can be used to assess task related changes in blood oxygenation, which yields
an fMRI (Binder & Rao, 1994).
In recent years, fMRI has become the method of choice because it has excel-
lent spatial resolution and subjects are not exposed to radiation. However, a
major problem derives from the so-called subtraction technique that is used
for determining areas of high activity for a particular task. Numerous t-tests
are performed to identify significant differences in the pixels of a pair of
images. If the significance levels are not adjusted to compensate for the num-
ber of tests performed, errors of statistical inference could occur. Another
problem is that fMRI, and especially PET, are rather expensive techniques that
restrict the sample size to less than 10 per group, thus rendering questionable
the reliability of statistical inferences made. Further, the low temporal resolu-
tion of PET and fMRI is inappropriate for investigating brain activity during
the solution of simple tasks, when the involved cognitive processes are in the
range of milliseconds (Wirth et al., 2007).
Another brain imaging technique is near-infrared spectroscopy (NIRS),
an optical technique that can noninvasively measure changes in the state of
hemoglobin oxygenation in the human brain. NIRS is based on the principle
that near-infrared light is absorbed by oxygenated (oxyHb) and deoxygen-
ated hemoglobin (deoxyHb) but not so much by other tissues. When a certain
brain region becomes activated, oxyHb increases due to the dilation of the
blood vessels and the acceleration of cerebral blood velocity. Simultaneously,
deoxyHb decreases because the increase in cerebral blood volume is larger
than that of the oxygen consumption in the activated region. Although the
spatial resolution of NIRS is inferior to those of other functional neuroimag-
ing methodologies such as PET and fMRI, NIRS has a high time resolution
of less than 0.01 s, and subjects can be scanned under natural conditions.
The recent trend in neuroimaging consists in combining methods with high
temporal resolution such as EEG or MEG and those having high spatial res-
olution such as fMRI.
Ability
The goal of understanding the relationship between brain activity and ability
is fairly old. Almost two centuries ago, Gall (1825) claimed that gross anatom-
ical features of the brain are related to personality traits, such as wit, causality,
self-esteem, and many others. These phrenological inquiries gradually gave
way to eloquent studies of brain-ability relationships. Since Pavlov (1949),
brain function is understood to consist of distributed interactions between
cortical regions united to perform a common cognitive task. This approach
220 Jaušovec & Jaušovec
provides the conceptual framework that is the basis for most modern neu-
roimaging studies of intelligence, problem solving, and reasoning (Jung &
Haier, 2007).
Intelligence
Intelligence represents the individual’s overall level of intellectual ability. It
serves as a general concept that includes several groups of mental abilities.
One of the most influential divisions of intelligence splits it into verbal, per-
formance, and social intelligence (Thorndike, 1920). In recent years, the term
“social intelligence” has been replaced largely by emotional intelligence – the
ability to recognize emotion, reason with emotion and emotion-related infor-
mation, and process emotional information as part of general problem solv-
ing (Mayer, Caruso, & Salovey, 2000). Neurophysiological research has been
mainly interested in the verbal and performance components of intelligence
(Haier & Benbow, 1995; Jaušovec, 1996; Lutzenberger et al., 1992; Neubauer,
Freudenthaler, & Pfurtscheller, 1995) and only recently has paid some atten-
tion to emotional intelligence (Jaušovec & Jaušovec, 2004a, 2005; Jaušovec,
Jaušovec, & Gerlič, 2001). Most of these studies demonstrated a negative cor-
relation between brain activity under cognitive load and intelligence. These
findings were explained by means of the efficiency theory. Efficiency may
derive from the non-use of many brain areas irrelevant for good task per-
formance as well as from the more focused use of specific task-relevant areas
in highly intelligent individuals. It has even been suggested that individuals
with high and low intelligence preferentially activate different neural circuits
even when no reasoning or problem solving were required (Haier, White, &
Alkire, 2003). Some studies showed a specific topographic pattern of differ-
ences related to the level of intelligence. High-ability subjects made relatively
greater use of parietal regions, whereas low-ability subjects relied more exclu-
sively on frontal regions (Gevins & Smith, 2000; Jaušovec & Jaušovec, 2004a).
More generally, these results suggest that higher-ability subjects tend to better
identify strategies needed for the solution of the task at hand. It was further
reported that individuals with high intelligence displayed more brain activ-
ity in the early stages of task performance; those with average intelligence
showed a reverse pattern. This temporal distribution of brain activity suggests
that cognitive processes are faster in highly intelligent individuals than in
those with average intelligence (Jaušovec & Jaušovec, 2004b).
A second line of research focuses on structural correlates of human intelli-
gence, attempting to answer the question: “Where in the brain is intelligence
located?” This body of research has recently been synthesized by Jung and
Brain, Behavior, and Cognition 221
Emotional Intelligence
Only recently has neurophysiological research paid some attention to emo-
tional intelligence. In our lab, we have conducted several studies investigat-
ing mainly individual differences in brain functioning related to the level of
emotional intelligence.
In our first two studies (Jaušovec et al., 2001; Jaušovec & Jaušovec, 2005),
we compared high and average to below-average emotionally intelligent stu-
dents when they were solving items from an emotional intelligence test. In
this task, the respondents had to mentally determine how much each feeling
(happiness, sadness, fear, surprise, etc.) is expressed by the presented face or
picture. In both studies, respondents in the alpha band displayed brain activ-
ity patterns that were in line with the neural efficiency theory. Similar find-
ings were also reported by Freudenthaler, Fink, and Neubauer (2006). On the
other hand, the pattern of ERD/ERS in the induced gamma band (Jaušovec &
Jaušovec, 2005) was contrary to what would be predicted by the neural effi-
ciency theory: the subjects high in emotional intelligence displayed induced
gamma band ERS; those of average emotional intelligence displayed induced
222 Jaušovec & Jaušovec
gamma band ERD. The difference increased from stimulus onset until 4000
ms. A possible explanation for the findings could be that the individuals high
in emotional intelligence identified emotions in faces by relying more on fig-
ural and less on semantic information provided by the displayed pictures.
This would account for the increased ERS in the induced gamma band and
the decreased ERD in the induced upper alpha band manifested by the group
high in emotional intelligence. It could be hypothesized that the group aver-
age in emotional intelligence would apply a reverse strategy – being more
semantically and less figurally oriented.
Creativity
Researchers investigating the relationship between creativity and brain func-
tion have been most attracted by hemisphericity. From a theoretical point
of view, this is a reasonable inference. Several authors have recognized the
importance of conceiving two or more opposites for the creative process.
Rothenberg (1983) used the term “Janusian process” to denote the simul-
taneous conceptualization of opposite or antithetical ideas; Koestler (1967)
proposed the term “bisociation,” which describes the creative process as an
act of combining unrelated structures, separate ideas, facts, and frames of
perception within a single brain. Therefore, two hemispheres representing
two distinct modes of cognitive processing seemed the ideal neurological
explanation of creativity. Still another characteristic in the creative process –
the phases of incubation and illumination, where attention to the problem is
defocused and later followed by the spontaneous appearance of solutions to
problems – gave rise to speculations that creativity is related to the nonspeak-
ing right hemisphere.
Two concepts relating creativity to hemisphericity were proposed.
According to the first, creativity was regarded mainly as a right-hemispheric
process (Gowan, 1979); according to the second, as an alternation between
left- and right-hemisphere modes of processing (Bogen & Bogen, 1969;
Torrance, 1982). Moderate research support exists for the relationship between
hemisphericity and creativity. Martindale and colleagues (1984) found that
the relationship between creativity and right-hemispheric activation is not
a general one. A difference between more and less creative respondents was
observed during creative production, but not during basal recordings or dur-
ing a reading task.
Recently, the idea of a right-hemisphere advantage in highly gifted indi-
viduals has gained new theoretical support. Giftedness is seen as a kind of
left-hemisphere pathology. This speculation is supported by several research
Brain, Behavior, and Cognition 223
Learning
The best currently accepted idea about how information is stored in the ner-
vous system is based on the concept of the cell assembly, and what is now
called the Hebb synapse (Hebb, 1949). The Hebb synapse is a model synapse
with a rule that simultaneous presynaptic and postsynaptic activity increases
synaptic efficacy. The cell assembly is a sort of irregular three-dimensional
net of units connected to each other in a closed loop that reactivates itself
repeatedly. This recurrent connectivity and reverbatory activity keeps the cell
assembly active, allowing a newly formed assembly to retain information.
Therefore, cell assemblies are acquired, dependent on learning and develop-
mental experience. They are stored in a distributive way in the cerebral cor-
tex, and are built from neural building-blocks processes, described in Hebb’s
neurophysiological postulate. Hebb synapses generate cell assemblies. At a
superordinate level, in line with Hebb’s hierarchical scheme, cell assemblies
can be linked together associatively to form phase sequences. These consti-
tute the neural bases for higher-order percepts and concepts – the brain’s real-
ization of thoughts. Changes in the synapses resulting from the simultaneous
(or near-simultaneous) activation of the neurons that form them is generally
thought to be the basis for all changes in behavior due to experiences, includ-
ing those that involve learning. Hebb’s (1949) notion of the cell assembly was
based on evidence suggesting that memory is a time-dependent process, so
that it can be influenced in different stages. Priming refers to the facilitative
effect of performing one task on the subsequent performance of the same or
similar tasks; whereas consolidation refers to the post-training period during
which the hypothesized process of synaptic change occurs and transforms
from a labile state into a more permanent one. There is also evidence that
certain post-training treatments can modulate memory storage in a way that
enhances retention.
A recent study in our lab investigated the impact of Mozart’s music on
brain activity in the process of learning – priming and memory consolidation
(Jaušovec, Jaušovec, and Gerlič, 2006). It was shown that music had a benefi-
cial influence on both learning stages; however, physiological differences in
EEG patterns were observed only in groups that had been exposed to Mozart’s
music prior to and after learning. The displayed pattern of brain activity was
lower alpha and gamma-approximated entropy, which is a measure of low
Brain, Behavior, and Cognition 225
Personality
Hans Eysenck and Jeffrey Gray have been among the foremost exponents of
the hypothesis that personality traits provide a window on individual dif-
ferences in brain functioning. Eysenck (Eysenck & Eysenck, 1985) identified
two key components of his conceptual nervous system: reticulo-cortical and
reticulo-limbic circuits. The reticulo-cortical circuit controls the cortical
arousal generated by incoming stimuli, whereas the reticulo-limbic circuit
controls response to emotional stimuli. Extraversion-introversion (E) relates
to arousability of the reticulo-cortical circuit, so that introverts are typically
more aroused than extraverts. However, methodological analyses of extra-
version studies (Gale, 1973) have illuminated two basic problems for testing
226 Jaušovec & Jaušovec
this theory. The first problem is that people actively seek a moderate level
of arousal; therefore, the relationship between extraversion and arousal may
also reflect individual differences in strategies for seeking or avoiding stimu-
lation. Second, according to Eysenck (1994), increasing stimulation provokes
increasing central nervous system reactivity until an optimal point is reached,
beyond which inhibition and decreasing reactivity set in. Hence, introverts
may have an arousal level higher, lower, or equal to that of extraverts, due to
complex interactions of personality type and environmental manipulation.
Neuroticism (N) was explained in terms of activation thresholds in the
sympathetic nervous system or visceral brain (the limbic system). Individuals
with higher scores in neuroticism had greater activation levels and lower
thresholds within subcortical structures (Eysenck, 1990)
There exist several reviews of the relationship between raw EEG measures
and E (Gale, 1983; O’Gorman, 1984; Zuckerman et al., 1991; Eysenck, 1994;
Matthews & Gilliland, 1999). According to Gale, several studies supported
the hypothesis that introverts are higher in cortical arousal than extraverts.
However, a similar number of studies found no differences, and three stud-
ies found results that contradicted the theory. Gale argued that moderate
arousal-inducing environments were the most amenable to testing the pre-
dictions of Eysenck’s theory. Low arousal-inducing environments resulted in
paradoxical arousal, especially in extraverts; high arousal-inducing environ-
ments (e.g., task-performance demands) resulted in possible over-arousal,
again especially in extraverts. Several recent studies (Fink, Schrausser, &
Neubauer, 2002; Fink & Neubauer, 2004) lend some support to Gale’s the-
ory. On the other hand, Matthews and Gilliland (1999) and Zuckerman
et al. (1991) have been less enthusiastic about the level of support that previ-
ous EEG studies provided for the cortical arousal hypothesis of extraversion.
Yet, Zuckerman et al. (1991) pointed out that studies using female subjects or
equal numbers of both genders seem more often to support Eysenck’s theory
than those relying on male subjects.
There have been a few more recent studies that are noteworthy in this con-
text. Matthews and Amelang (1993) reported significant correlations between
personality and EEG measures that were low in magnitude (i.e., not exceed-
ing 0.20) but on the whole matched expectations. Smith et al. (1995) reported
that introverts were generally found to produce lower levels of alpha activity
reflecting higher levels of arousal, showing a hemisphere by gender interac-
tion effect. Schmidtke and Heller (2004) found that neuroticism was associ-
ated with greater relative right posterior activity, whereas predicted effects for
neuroticism with frontal regions and extraversion with brain activity were
not significant. Gale et al. (2001) found that extraverts were less cortically
Brain, Behavior, and Cognition 227
aroused than introverts, and that neuroticism was associated with larger left
versus right hemisphere differences in alpha-wave activity related to mood.
Tran, Craig, and McIsaac (2001) showed extraverted persons to be at least
three times more likely to have larger peak amplitudes in frontal alpha-wave
activity. However, they found no association between extraversion and alpha
activity in posterior regions, and no alpha-wave activity differences were
found between those with high and low anxiety levels.
Gray’s personality theory began as a modification of Eysenck’s theory, but
is now usually seen as an alternative theory (Gray, 1991). Gray has proposed
two major neurological systems: the behavioral inhibition system (BIS) and
the behavioral activation system (BAS). The BIS is sensitive to signals of pun-
ishment and frustrating non-reward promoting avoidance behavior, whereas
the BAS is sensitive to signals of reward and matches approach behavior.
These two brain systems underlie the personality dimensions of anxiety
(neurotic introversion) and impulsiveness (neurotic extraversion). Research
by Knyazev (Knyazev, Slobodskaya, & Wilson, 2002; Knyazev et al., 2003)
revealed that BAS was positively related to delta and negatively to alpha power
measures, whereas the BIS showed an opposite pattern of correlations. These
findings suggest higher arousal in subjects high on BIS and neuroticism, and
lower arousal in subjects high on BAS and extraversion.
From a psychometric perspective, there has been a growing acceptance of a
five-factor model of personality (FFM), incorporating two of Eysenck’s dimen-
sions, E and N, together with Openness to Experience (O), Agreeableness
(A), and Conscientiousness (C). Despite the growing acceptance of the FFM
of personality, there have been very few studies that examined the biologi-
cal basis of O, A, and C. In a preliminary study, Stough (Stough et al., 2001)
showed that individuals with higher scores in O tend to have a greater amount
of theta production. Because theta activity decreases with age, the interpre-
tation of the authors was that respondents high on O may have retained a
somewhat childlike wonderment and open-mindedness about their world,
coupled with a willingness to explore alternative views about issues. In a
recent large-scale study, Tran and colleagues (Tran et al., 2006) found only
mild significant correlations in the delta and theta band with E and C, and
few associations between personality and faster frequency bands.
Gender Differences
Gender-based differences in performance have been reported for complex and
simple cognitive tasks. Probably one of the first written accounts for female
superiority in verbal ability is found in an ancient Sanskrit book, suggesting
228 Jaušovec & Jaušovec
that nine shares of talk were given to women and one to men (Nyborg, 1994).
However, more recent systematic analyses suggest that females surpass males
in some but not necessarily all domains of verbal ability (Halpern, 2004).
Specifically, women seem to have an advantage in episodic memory tasks
where verbal processing is required or can be used as well as in verbal fluency
(Maitland et al., 2004). Further, it was found that females surpass males in
tests of emotional intelligence (Mayer et al., 2000; Mayer, Salovey, & Caruso,
2002). It is also proposed that in selective attention tasks, female subjects’
processing entails more detailed elaboration of information content than
that of males (Myers-Levy & Maheswaran, 1991), and that female subjects
are more efficient in recognizing faces and facial expressions (Hampson, van
Anders, & Mullin, 2005). Female superiority in perceptual speed – namely,
the ability to rapidly absorb the details of a visual stimulus – has been recog-
nized since the 1940s (e.g., Kimura, 1999). On the other hand, men typically
demonstrate a distinct advantage in a broad range of visual tasks, including
visual-spatial orientation. A meta-analysis of studies published prior to 1973
found an average difference of about one-half of a standard deviation in favor
of males on tests of visuospatial ability (Hyde, 1981). Factor analytic studies
showed that spatial ability is not a unitary process, and can be divided into
three categories: spatial perception, mental rotation, and spatial visualiza-
tion (Linn & Peterson, 1985). Most pronounced gender differences of nearly
one standard deviation have been reported mainly for mental rotation tasks
(Mackintosh & Bennett, 2005).
Differences in brain activity between the genders have been observed
when respondents were solving complex and simple cognitive tasks. Some
recent EEG studies relating intelligence with brain activity under cognitive
load showed that when males are engaged in solving numerical and figural
tasks, they are more likely to produce cortical activation patterns that are
in line with the neural efficiency hypothesis (e.g., less activation in brighter
individuals), whereas in females, for the same tasks no significant differences
were reported (Neubauer, Fink, & Schrausser, 2002; Neubauer et al., 2005).
Similar gender-related differences as those reported for intelligence could also
be observed in regard to creative problem solving (Fink & Neubauer, 2006)
and emotional intelligence (Jaušovec & Jaušovec, 2008). Perhaps the most
important finding of these studies was that the inverse intelligence-activation
relationship (i.e., neural efficiency) appears to be moderated by task content
and the individuals’ gender. Males and females displayed the expected inverse
IQ–activation relationship in precisely that domain in which they usually
perform better: females in the verbal and emotional-intelligence domain and
males in the visuospatial-ability domain.
Brain, Behavior, and Cognition 229
male and female auditory P3 (Polich, 1986) or visual and auditory P3 (Shelton,
Hartmann, & Allen, 2002). Still others reported that males have larger P3
amplitudes for spatial-attention tasks (Vaquero et al., 2004). A possible expla-
nation for the diversity of the obtained results could be a methodological
one (e.g., differences in tasks, type of responses required, time windows used,
etc.). However, to our mind, the main shortcoming of the reported studies
is that they did not control for possible differences in ability that might have
biased the results. Research has shown that peak latencies as well as ampli-
tudes correlate with IQ (e.g., Jaušovec & Jaušovec, 2000).
Recently, gender-related differences were reported also for the gamma
response of the brain (Karakaş et al., 2006, Jaušovec & Jaušovec, 2009). There
are two basic types of event-related gamma responses: late and early. The late
gamma occurs in the 130–400 ms poststimulus time window, has an induced
character, and is of special relevance in pattern perception or higher-order
recognition processes (Karakaş & Başar, 1998). The early gamma response
occurs within 150 ms poststimulus and is time locked to the stimulus. It is
related to sensory processing and is basically a phenomenon of the sensory
register (Karakaş et al., 2001). To our knowledge, there are only two stud-
ies that have investigated the gamma response in relation to gender. Karakaş
and colleagues (2006) found no significant gender-related difference in the
amplitude of the evoked-gamma response for an auditory oddball task. On
the other hand, Jaušovec and Jaušovec (2009) found significant gender-
related differences, which were only observed in the amplitudes of the early
evoked-gamma response and the P3 component. Women displayed higher
amplitudes than men. A second finding was that these differences were
more pronounced for the visual than for the auditory stimuli. The NIRS data
showed that males displayed a higher percentage of StO2 in their frontal brain
areas than females; and males also showed a higher increase in percent of
StO2 during task performance as compared with the resting condition. Taken
all together, the results suggest that the females’ visual event-categorization
process is more efficient than males’.
References
Bechtereva, N. P., Korotkov, A. D., Pakhomov, S. V., Roudas, M. S., Starchenko, M. G., &
Medvedev, S. V. (2004). PET study of brain maintenance of verbal creative activity.
International Journal of Psychophysiology, 53, 11–20.
Benbow, C. P. (1986). Physiological correlates of extreme intellectual precocity.
Neuropsychologia, 24, 719–725.
(1988). Sex differences in mathematical reasoning ability in intellectually talented pre-
adolescents: Their nature, effects, and possible causes. Behaviour and Brain Science,
11, 169–232.
Bialystok, E., Craik, F. I. M., Klein, R., & Viswanathan, M. (2004). Bilingualism, aging,
and cognitive control: evidence from the Simon task. Psychology & Aging, 19,
290–303.
Binder, R. J., & Rao, S. M. (1994). Human barin mapping with functional magnetic reso-
nance imaging. In A. Kertesz (Ed.), Localization and neuroimaging in neuropsychol-
ogy (pp.185–212). San Diego: Academic Press.
Bogen, J., & Bogen, G. (1969). The other side of the brain: III. The corpus callosum and
creativity. Bulletin of the Los Angeles Neurological Society, 34, 191–220.
Braitenberg, V., & Schutz, A. (1991). Anatomy of the cortex. Statistics and geometry. New
York: Springer-Verlag.
Bullock, T. H. (1980). Reassessment of neural connectivity and its specification. In H.
M. Pinsker and W. D. Willis (Ed.), Information processing in the nervous system (pp.
119–220). New York: Raven Press.
Chu, N. S. (1987). Pattern-reversal visual evoked potentials: Latency changes with gen-
der and age. Clinical Electroencephalography, 18, 159–162.
Craik, F. I. M. (2006). Brain–behavior relations across the lifespan: A commentary.
Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 30, 885–892.
Cranberg, L. D., & Albert, M. L. (1988). The chess mind. In L. K. Obler & D. Fein (Ed.),
The exceptional brain (pp. 156–190). New York: The Guilford Press.
Detterman, D. K. (1994). Intelligence and the brain. In P. A. Vernon (Ed.), The neuropsy-
chology of individual differences (pp. 35–57). London: Academic Press INC.
Eccles, J. & Robinson, D. N. (1984). The wonder of being human: Our brain and our mind.
New York: The Free Press.
232 Jaušovec & Jaušovec
Ehlers, C. L., Wall, T. L., Garcia-Andrade, C., & Phillips, E. (2001). Auditory P3 findings
in mission Indian youth. Journal of Studies on Alcohol & Drugs, 62, 562–570.
Eysenck, H. J. (1990). Biological dimensions of personality. In L. A. Pervin (Ed.),
Handbook of personality: theory and research (pp. 244–270). New York: Guilford
Press.
(1994). Personality: Biological foundations. In P. A. Vernon (Ed.), The neuropsychol-
ogy of individual differences. London: Academic Press.
Eysenck, H. J., & Eysenck, M. W. (1985). Personality and individual differences. New York:
Plenum.
Fink, A., Benedek, M., Staudt, B., & Neubauer, A. C. (2007). Creativity meets neuro-
science: Experimental tasks for the neuroscientific study of creative thinking.
Methods, 42, 67–75.
Fink, A., & Neubauer, A. C. (2004). Extraversion and cortical activation: Effects of task
complexity. Personality & Individual Differences, 36, 333–347.
Fink A., & Neubauer, A. C. (2006). EEG alpha oscillations during the performance of ver-
bal creativity tasks: Differential effects of sex and verbal intelligence. International
Journal of Psychophysiology, 62, 46–53.
Fink, A., Schrausser, D. G., & Neubauer, A. C. (2002). The moderating influence of
extraversion on the relationship between IQ and cortical activation. Personality &
Individual Differences, 33, 311–326.
Freudenthaler, H. H., Fink, A., & Neubauer, A. C. (2006). Emotional abilities and corti-
cal activation during emotional information processing. Personality and Individual
Differences, 41, 685–695.
Friston, K. (2003). Learning and inference in the brain. Neural Netw. 16, 1325–1352.
Gale, A. (1973). The psychophysiology of individual differences: studies of extraversion
and the EEG. In P. Kline (Ed.), New approaches in psychological measurement (pp.
211–256). London: Wiley.
(1983). Electroencephalographic studies of extraversion-introversion: A case study in
the psychophysiology of individual differences. Personality & Individual Differences,
4, 371–380.
Gale, A., Edwards, J. A., Morris, P., Moore, R., & Forrester, D. (2001). Extraversion–
introversion, neuroticism-stability, and EEG indicators of positive and negative
empathic mood. Personality & Individual Differences 30, 449–461.
Gall, F. J. (1825). Sur les fonctions du cerveau et sur celles de chacune de ses parties. [On the
Functions of the Brain and Each of Its Parts] Paris: Bailliere.
Gazzaniga, M. S. (1985). The social brain. New York: Basic Books, Inc., Publishers.
Geschwind, N. A., & Galaburda, A. M. (1987). Cerebral lateralization. Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
Gevins, A., & Smith, M. E. (2000). Neurophysiological measures of working memory
and individual differences in cognitive ability and cognitive style. Cerebral Cortex,
10, 830–839.
Gootjes, L., Bruggeling, E. C., Magneé, T., & Van Strien, J. W. (2007). Sex differences in
the latency of the late event-related potential mental rotation effect. Neuroreport,
19, 349–353.
Gowan, J. C. (1979). The production of creativity through right hemisphere imagery.
Journal of Creative Behavior, 13, 39–51.
Brain, Behavior, and Cognition 233
Jung-Beeman, M., Bowden, E. M., Haberman, J., Frymiare, J. L., Arambel-Liu, S.,
Greenblatt, R., Reber, P. J., & Kounios, J. (2004). Neural activity when people solve
verbal problems with insight. PLOS Biology, 2, 500–510.
Kameyama, M., Fukuda, M., Uehara, T., & Mikuni, M. (2004). Sex and age dependen-
cies of cerebral blood volume changes during cognitive activation: a multi-channel
near-infrared spectroscopy study. NeuroImage 22, 1715–1721.
Karakaş, S., & Başar, E. (1998). Early gamma response is sensory in origin: a conclu-
sion based on cross-comparison of results from multiple experimental paradigms.
International Journal of Psychophysiology, 31, 13–31.
Karakaş, S., Başar, E., Özesmi, Ç., Kafadar, H., & Erzengin, Ö. U. (2001). Gamma
response of the brain: a multifunctional oscillation that represents bottom-up with
top-down processing. International Journal of Psychophysiology, 39, 137–150.
Karakaş, S., Tüfekçi, İ., Bekçi, B., Çakmak, E. D., Doğutepe, E., Erzengin, Ö. U., Özkan,
A., & Arikan, O. (2006). Early time-locked gamma response and gender specificity.
International Journal of Psychophysiology, 60, 225–239.
Kimura, D. (1999). Sex and cognition. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
Klimesch, W., Doppelmayr, M., Schimke, H., & Ripper, B. (1997). Theta synchronization
and alpha desynchronization in a memory task. Psychophysiology, 34, 169–176.
Klimesch, W., Schabus, M., Doppelmayr, M., Gruber, W., & Sauseng, P. (2004).
Evoked oscillations and early components of event-related potentials: an analysis.
International Journal of Bifurcation & Chaos, 14, 705–718.
Klimesch, W., Schimke, H., & Pfurtscheller, G. (1993). Alpha frequency, cognitive load
and memory performance. Brain Topography, 5, 1–11.
Knyazev, G. G., Slobodskaya, H. R., Safronova, M. V., Sorokin, O. V., Goodman, R.,
& Wilson, G. D. (2003). Personality, psychopathology and brain oscillations.
Personality & Individual Differences, 35, 1331–1349.
Knyazev, G. G., Slobodskaya, H. R., & Wilson, G. D. (2002). Psychophysiological corre-
lates of behavioural inhibition and activation. Personality & Individual Differences,
33, 647–660.
Koestler, A. (1967). The ghost in the machine. New York: Macmillan.
Kok, A. (2001). On the utility of P3 amplitude as a measure of processing capacity.
Psychophysiology, 38, 567–577.
Linn, M. C., & Peterson, A. C. (1985). Emergence and characterization of sex differences
in spatial ability: A meta-analysis. Child Development, 56, 1479–1498.
Luck, S. J., & Girelli, M. (1999). Electrophysiological approaches to the study of selective
attention in the human brain. In R. Parasuraman (Ed.), The Attentive Brain (pp.
71–94). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Lutzenberger, W., Birbaumer, N., Flor, H., Rockstroh, B., & Elbert, T. (1992). Dimensional
analysis of the human EEG and intelligence. Neuroscience Letters, 143, 10–14.
Mackintosh, N. J., & Bennett, E. S. (2005). What do Raven’s matrices measure? An analy-
sis in terms of sex differences. Intelligence, 33, 663–664.
Maguire, E. A., Gadian, D. G., Johnsrude, I. S., Good, C. D., Ashburner, J., Frackowiak, R.
S. J., & Frith, C. D. (2000). Navigation-related structural change in the hippocampi of
taxi drivers. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA, 97, 4398–4403.
Maitland, S. B., Herlitz, A., Nyberg, L., Backman, L., & Nilsson, L.G. (2004). Selective
sex differences in declarative memory. Memory & Cognition, 32, 1160–1169.
Brain, Behavior, and Cognition 235
Mansour, C. S., Haier, R. J., & Buchsbaum, M. S. (1996). Gender comparison of cerebral
glucose metabolic rate in healthy adults during a cognitive task. Personality and
Individual Differences, 20, 183–191.
Martindale, C., Hines, D., Mitchell, L., & Covello, E. (1984). EEG alpha asymmetry and
creativity. Personality & Individual Differences, 5, 77–86.
Matthews, G., & Amelang, M. (1993). Extraversion, arousal theory and performance: a
study of individual differences in the EEG. Personality & Individual Differences, 14,
347–363.
Matthews, G., & Gilliland, K. (1999). The personality theories of H. J. Eysenck and J. A.
Gray: a comparative review. Personality & Individual Differences, 26, 583–626.
Mayer, J. D., Caruso, D. R., & Salovey, P. (2000). Emotional intelligence meets traditional
standards for an intelligence. Intelligence, 27, 267–298.
Mayer, J. D., Salovey, P., & Caruso, D. R. (2002). Mayer-Salovey-Caruso emotional intel-
ligence test (MSCEIT). Toronto: MHS.
Metter, E. J., & Hanson, W. R. (1994). Use of positron emition tomography to study
aphasia. In Kertesz (Ed.), Localization and neuroimaging in neuropsychology
(pp.123–149). San Diego: Academic Press.
Michel, C. M., Thut, G., Morand, S., Khateb, A., Pegna, A. J., Grave, P., Gonzalez, S.,
Seeck, M., & Landis, T. (2001). Electric source imaging of human brain functions.
Brain Research Brain Research Review, 36, 108–118.
Mölle, M., Marshall, L., Wolf, B., Fehm, H., & Born, J. (1999). EEG complexity and per-
formance measures of creative thinking. Psychophysiology, 36, 95–104.
Mountcastle, V. B., (1975). The view from within: Pathways to the study of perception.
Johns Hopkins Medical Journal, 136, 109–131.
Myers-Levy, J., & Maheswaran, D. (1991). Exploring differences in males and females
processing strategies. Journal of Consumer Research, 18, 63–70.
Neubauer, A. C., Fink, A., & Schrausser, D. G. (2002). Intelligence and neural efficiency:
The influence of task content and sex on the brain – IQ relationship. Intelligence,
30, 515–536.
Neubauer, A. C., Grabner, R. H., Fink, A., & Neuper, C. (2005). Intelligence and neural
efficiency: further evidence of the influence of task content and sex on the brain–
IQ relationship. Cognition & Brain Research, 25, 217–225.
Neubauer, V., Freudenthaler, H. H., & Pfurtscheller, G. (1995). Intelligence and spatio-
temporal patterns of event-related desynchronization. Intelligence, 3, 249–266.
Nunez, P. L. (1995). Mind, brain, and electroencephalography. In P. L. Nunez (Ed.),
Neocortical dynamics and human EEG rhythms (pp. 133–194). New York: Oxford
University Press.
Nyberg, L., Habib, R., & Herlitz, A. (2000). Brain activation during episodic memory
retrieval: sex differences. Acta Psychologica, 105, 181–194.
Nyborg, H. (1994). The neuropsychology of sex-related differences in brain and specific
abilities: Hormones, developmental dynamics and new paradigm. In P. A. Vernon
(Ed.), The neuropsychology of individual differences (pp. 59–113). London: Academic
Press.
O’Boyle, M. W., Alexander, J. E., & Benbow, C. P. (1991). Enhanced right hemisphere
activation in the mathematically precocious: A preliminary EEG investigation.
Brain & Cognition, 17, 138–153.
236 Jaušovec & Jaušovec
O’Boyle, M. W., Benbow, C. P., & Alexander, J. E. (1995). Sex differences, hemispheric
laterality, and associated brain activity in the intellectually gifted. Developmental
Neuropsychology, 4, 415–443.
O’Gorman, J. G. (1984). Extraversion and the EEG: I. An evaluation of Gale’s hypothesis.
Biological Psychology, 19, 95–112.
Olofsson, J. K., & Nordin, S. (2004). Gender Differences in Chemosensory Perception
and Event-related Potentials. Chemical Senses, 29, 629–637.
Pascual-Marqui, R. D., Michel, C. M., Lehmann, D. (1994). Low resolution electro-
magnetic tomography: a new method for localizing electrical activity in the brain.
International Journal of Psychophysiology, 18, 49–65.
Pavlov, I. P. (1949). Complete collected works. Moscow, Izd.
Petsche, H. (1997). EEG coherence and mental activity. In F. Angeleri, S. Butler, S.
Giaquinto, & J. Majakowski (Eds.), Analysis of the electrical activity of the brain (pp.
141–168). Chichester, UK: John Wiley & Sons Ltd.
Pfleiderer, B., Ohrmann, A. P., Suslow, B.T., Wolgast, B.M., Gerlach, B. A. L., Heindela,
C. W., & Michael, N. (2004). N-acetylaspartate levels of left frontal cortex are asso-
ciated with verbal intelligence in women but not in men: a proton magnetic reso-
nance spectroscopy study. Neuroscience, 123, 1053–1058.
Polich, J. (1986). Normal variation of P300 from auditory stimuli. Electroencephalography
& Clinical Neurophysiology, 65, 236–240.
Razoumnikova, O. M. (2000). Functional organization of different brain areas during
convergent and divergent thinking: an EEG investigation. Cognitive Brain Research,
10, 11–18.
(2007). Creativity related cortex activity in the remote associates task. Brain Research
Bulletin, 73, 96–102.
Roalf, D., Lowery, N., & Turetsky, B. I. (2006). Behavioral and physiological findings
of gender differences in global-local visual processing. Brain & Cognition, 60,
32–42.
Rothenberg, A. (1983). Psychopatology and creative cognition. Archives of General
Psychiatry, 40, 937–942.
Schmidtke, J. I., & Heller, W. (2004). Personality, affect and EEG: predicting patterns
of regional brain activity related to extraversion and neuroticism. Personality &
Individual Differences, 36, 717–732.
Sejnovski, T. J., & Churchland, P. S. (1989). Brain and cognition. In M. I. Posner (Ed.),
Foundations of cognitive science (pp. 301–358). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Shelton, P. P., Hartmann, A. M., & Allen, J. (2002). Seasonal photoperiod, gender, and
P300. Bioogical Psychology, 60, 151–171.
Shen, X. (2005). Sex differences in perceptual processing: performance on the color-kanji
stroop task of visual stimuli. International Journal of Neuroscience, 115, 1631–1641.
Smith, B. D., Kline, R., Lindgren, K., Ferro, M., Smith, D. A., & Nespor, A. (1995). The
lateralized processing of affect in emotion-ally labile extraverts and introverts: cen-
tral and autonomic effects. Biological Psychology, 39, 143–157.
Steffensen, Scott C., Ohran, A. J., Shipp, D. N., Hales, K., Stobbs, S. H., & Fleming, D.
E. (2008). Gender-selective effects of the P300 and N400 components of the visual
evoked potential. Visual Research, 48, 917–925.
Stein, A., & Petsche, H. (1995). EEG synchronization seems to reflect functional prop-
erties of the underlying cortical networks in the human brain. European Journal of
Neuroscience, 8, 32–37.
Brain, Behavior, and Cognition 237
Stough, C., Donaldson, C., Scarlata, B., & Ciorciari, J. (2001). Psychophysiological cor-
relates of the NEO PI-R Openness, Agreeableness and Conscientiousness: prelimi-
nary results. International Journal of Psychophysiology, 41, 87–91.
Szentagothai, J. (1979). Local neuron circuits of the neocortex. In F. O. Schmitt & F.
G. Worden (Eds.), The neurosciences 4th study program (pp. 399–415). Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Thorndike, E. L. (1920). Intelligence and its use. Harper’s Magazine, 140, 227–235.
Torrance, E. P. (1982). Hemisphericity and creative functioning. Journal of Research &
Development in Education, 3, 29–37.
Tran, Y., Craig, A., Boord, P., Connell, K., Cooper, N., & Gordon, E. (2006). Personality
traits and its associations with resting regional brain activity. International Journal
of Psychophysiology, 60, 215–224.
Tran, Y., Craig, A., & McIsaac, P. (2001). Extraversion–introversion and 8–13 Hz waves
in frontal cortical regions. Personality & Individual Differences, 30, 205–215.
Traub, R. D., Whittington, M. A., Buhl, E. H., Jefferys, J. G. R., & Faulkner, H. J. (1999).On
the mechanisms of the γ→β frequency shift in neuronal oscillations induced in rat
hippocampal slices by tetanic stimulation. Journal of Neuroscience, 19, 1088–1105.
Tulving, E. (2005). Episodic memory and autonoesis: uniquely human? In H. S. Terrace
& J. Metcalfe (Eds.), The Missing link in cognition: Origins of self-reflective conscious-
ness (pp. 3–56). New York: Oxford University Press.
Vaquero, E., Cardoso, M. J., Vázquez, M., & Gómez, C. M., (2004). Gender differences
in event-related potentials during visual-spatial attention. International Journal of
Neuroscience, 114, 541–557.
Weiss, E., Siedentopf, C. M., Hofer, A., Deisenhammer, E. A., Hoptman, M. J., Kremser,
C., Golaszewski, S., Felber, S., & Fleischhacker, W. W. (2003). Sex differences in
brain activation pattern during a visuospatial cognitive task: a functional magnetic
resonance imaging study in healthy volunteers. Neuroscience Letters, 344, 169–172.
Wirth, M., Horn, H., Koenig, K., Stein, M., Federspiel, A., Meier, B., Michel, C. M., &
Strik, W. (2007). Sex differences in semantic processing: event-related brain poten-
tials distinguish between lower and higher order semantic analysis during word
reading. Cerebral Cortex, 17, 1987–1997.
Zuckerman, M., Kuhlman, D. M., Joireman, J., Teta, P., & Kraft, M. (1993). A comparison
of three structural models for personality: the big three, the big five, and the alter-
native five. Journal of Personality & Social Psychology, 4, 757–768.
12
Introduction
This chapter deals with the impact of physical health on cognition. There
are several lines of research and thinking that support the conception that
physical health may be an important factor affecting cognition. One line of
research is represented by the body of studies showing that good health in
adulthood manifested in longer life expectancy (Deary et al., 2004; Hart et al.,
2003; Kuh et al., 2003; Osler et al., 2003), low prevalence of cardio-vascular
disease (Batty et al., 2005), and low incidence of serious illness, at least in the
30–39 year age group (Martin et al., 2004), is associated with good mental
ability (intelligence) during childhood. Martin et al. (2004) calculated that a
lower level of serious disease by a third is correlated with a 15 points higher
IQ. Further correlational studies show that straightforward indicators of
health in early childhood, such as birth weight and height growth, are related
positively to cognitive function in childhood, adolescence, and early adult-
hood as well as to educational attainment (Richards et al., 2001, 2002). The
impact of physical state on cognition is however not limited to childhood.
Cognitive ability at 18–20 years is also related to coronary health in middle
age (Hemmingsson et al., 2007). Notably, early cognitive function is a major
predictor of cognitive function and its rate of change in midlife and beyond
as well as of educational and occupational attainment (McCall, 1979). One
explanation for these effects is that a variety of hormones target brain areas
responsible for cognition at the same time they are playing a critical role in
determining body size and physical health. The effect remains valid even if
the explanation that hinges on the intermediation of socioeconomic factors
proves to be correct (Gottfredson & Deary, 2001).
Another relevant line of research refers to the beneficial effects of aerobic
health and exercise on cognition. For example, when previously sedentary
238
Physical Health and Cognition 239
adults 60–75 years old were randomly assigned to either aerobic (walking) or
anaerobic (stretching and toning) exercise for a period of six months, those
who received aerobic training manifested substantial improvements in per-
formance on tasks requiring executive control – such as planning, scheduling,
inhibition, and working memory – compared with anaerobically trained sub-
jects (Kramer et al., 1999). There are many further examples: physical exercise
at 36 years is associated with a slower decline in memory between 43 and 53
years (Richards, Hardy, & Wadsworth, 2003); and moderate physical activity
for 12 months improved the cognitive performance of elderly participants on
the Digit Symbol Substitution Test (DSST), Rey Auditory Verbal Learning Test
(RAVLT), modified Stroop test, and Modified Mini-Mental State Examination
(Williamson et al., 2009). A review by Ploughman (2008) concludes that in
clinical studies, exercise increases brain volume in areas implicated in exec-
utive processing, improves cognition in children with cerebral palsy, and
enhances phonemic skill in school children with reading difficulty.
A third line of research focuses on the influence that fulfilling basic physi-
cal needs has on cognitive functioning. Major among these is adequate nutri-
tion and sleep. Thus, concerning nutrition, a recent review emphasized the
beneficial effects of bioflavonoids on memory (Spencer, Vauzour, & Rendeiro,
2009). Further, it was found that an overall index of diet quality was correlated
positively with overall cognitive performance. Observations over a follow-up
period of 11 years showed that consuming a diverse diet that includes a variety
of recommended foods may help to attenuate age-related cognitive decline
among the elderly (Wengreen et al., 2009). A large body of evidence shows
that sleep, too, plays an important role in learning, memory encoding, and
cognition. Insufficient quantity or quality of sleep leads not only to short-term
neurocognitive dysfunction but also to permanent changes to the central ner-
vous system (Malhotra & Desai, 2010).
The three types of examples introduced indicate that good or improved
physical state has beneficial effects on cognition. Evidence of this kind
enhances the importance of studying the effects of impaired physical health
on cognition. Indeed, it is surprising that physical health and cognition have
remained largely dissociated. If a study in cognition is reported in a journal,
it is expected of the investigators to mention impaired mental health, such
as schizophrenia of all or some of the participating subjects. However, it is
still not the habit to report how many of the participants suffer from elevated
blood pressure, gastrointestinal disorders, or diabetes, or for that matter
which medication they use on a habitual basis.
There may be several reasons for that. One could mention lack of infor-
mation about specific effects or general medical knowledge in researchers
240 Kreitler, Weissler, & Barak
Diabetes
It has long been observed that diabetes mellitus is associated with an increased
rate of cognitive decline (Allen, Frier, & Strachan, 2004), which was attrib-
uted to chronic hypoglycemia, vascular disease, cumulative effect of hypo-
glycemic events, and possible direct effects of insulin on the brain (Biessels
et al., 2002) as well as insulin dysregulation (Craft & Watson, 2004). The
broad range of cognitive functions that have been studied in individuals with
type 2 diabetes include memory, psychomotor speed, visuospatial functions,
frontal executive functions, processing speed, verbal fluency, attention, and
complex motor functions. A comprehensive review of literature on the asso-
ciation between impaired glucose tolerance, type 2 diabetes, and cognitive
function showed that the most consistently reported measures were impair-
ment in verbal memory and processing speed, with preservation of functions
in other areas including visuospatial function, attention, semantic memory,
and language (Awad, Gagnon, & Messier, 2004). The preservation of memory
and learning functions occurred mainly in subjects younger than 65 years of
age, in contrast to older subjects where impairments in those domains were
largely because of interaction between diabetes-related changes and the nor-
mal ageing changes in the brain (Ryan & Geckle, 2000). Younger subjects
with type 2 diabetes mellitus consistently showed impairment in psychomo-
tor efficiency, similar to subjects with type 1 diabetes. Impairments in work-
ing memory, frontal executive functions, learning, and complex psychomotor
abilities have also been found to be associated with a higher level of HbA1c
(Munshi et al., 2006). Further, it was shown that poor glucose control and a
rise in average blood sugar are strongly associated with poorer functioning
abilities, especially poorer memory function (Cukierman-Yaffe et al., 2009).
244 Kreitler, Weissler, & Barak
Gastrointestinal Disorders
Helicobacter pylori is a bacterium that can inhabit various areas of the stom-
ach and duodenum and causes a chronic low-level inflammation of the
stomach lining that is strongly linked to the development of duodenal and
gastric ulcers. It was found that the prevalence of this bacterium is higher
in individuals who exhibit symptoms of mild cognitive impairment than in
those who do not (Kountras et al., 2007). In individuals diagnosed with celiac
disease, cognitive impairment was found in the form of amnesia, acalculia,
confusion, and a score on the Short Test of Mental Status indicating moder-
ate impairment (Hu et al., 2006). Findings of a different order were reported
for individuals diagnosed with irritable bowel syndrome. They were found to
exhibit global hypersensitivity to a broad range of stimuli (Lawal et al., 2006),
manifested for example in a word-association task in which they recognized
words representing symptoms and affects, both positive and negative, more
quickly than others (Posserud et al., 2009).
Hematological Disorders
Anemia is a common hematological symptom, prevalent in a broad range
of physical disorders. There is a lot of evidence that anemia is related to cog-
nitive impairment. For example, elderly individuals (above 65) with anemia
score low (<7) on the Abbreviated Mental Test (Zamboni et al., 2006) or the
Mini Mental State Examination even with mild anemia (Argyriadou et al.,
2001). Cancer patients undergoing treatments depressing hemoglobin levels
were found to have serious cognitive deficits (Jacobsen et al., 2004).
the beginning of the study, was linked with a more rapid rate of decline over
the next several years in episodic, semantic, and working memory, but not in
visuospatial ability or perceptual speed (Buchman, 2009). In younger indi-
viduals, findings indicated that individuals with kidney transplant or chronic
kidney disease demonstrated significantly worse verbal learning and memory
as well as lowered response inhibition and other executive functioning skills
in comparison to controls. Further, those with chronic kidney disease also
performed significantly worse on a set-shifting task (Gelb et al., 2008).
Respiratory Disorders
There are various disorders manifested in respiratory difficulties, including
apnea, asthma, and chronic lung diseases. Cognitive dysfunction has been
repeatedly reported in individuals suffering from obstructive sleep apnea,
characterized by repeated episodes of upper airway obstruction and lowered
blood oxygen levels during sleep (see review in Beebe et al., 2003). For exam-
ple, it was found that both snoring and breathing stoppage were associated
with low scores in tests requiring visual attention skills, the Trail Making Test,
and the Digit Symbol Substitution Test. These relationships were significant
only when either snoring or breathing stoppage was associated with daytime
sleepiness (Dealberto et al., 1996).
Allergic rhinitis, which also affects breathing, was found to be related to
difficulties in cognition and learning (Borres, 2009). Pollen-allergic young
people, tested on computer simulation of different learning situations, mani-
fested lower concentration ability than healthy controls (Vuurman et al.,
1993). Patients allergic to ragweed were shown to have impaired cognitive
learning during the pollen season and some also had memory impairment.
Individuals with allergic rhinitis symptoms take a longer time to make deci-
sions and have a slower psychomotor rate than healthy control subjects
(Marshall, O’Hara, & Steinberg, 2000). Students with allergic rhinitis tend to
get lower grades in school (Borres et al., 2007; Walker et al., 2007).
When individuals with chronic obstructive pulmonary disease (COPD)
were compared with healthy controls, they were consistently found to be
impaired in verbal memory (Huppert, 1982; Incalzi et al., 1993; Stuss et al.,
1997), and to a lesser degree also in aspects of attention and working memory
(Berry et al., 1989; Della Sala et al., 1992). Further, studies showed that there
may be a pattern of cognitive dysfunction specific to COPD: the incidence
of cognitive dysfunction is higher in but hypoxaemia; hypoxaemia, hyper-
capnia, smoking, and comorbidities (such as vascular disease) are unlikely to
account for all of the cognitive dysfunction seen in COPD; and the observed
cognitive dysfunction were unrelated to mood, fatigue, or health (Dodd,
246 Kreitler, Weissler, & Barak
Getov, & Jones, 2010). Individuals with asthma or COPD were found to have
significantly lower oxygen saturation compared to the healthy controls, and
performed significantly poorer on tests of delayed word recall and serial sub-
tractions but not on other tasks of immediate word recall, word fluency, and
digit-symbol substitution (Moss et al., 2005).
Hormonal Disorders
There is a large body of studies reporting cognitive correlates of hormonal
disorders of various kinds. The thyroid gland is associated with several
hormones. Cognitive changes have frequently been detected in patients
with hypothyroidism, including defects ranging from minimal to severe in
general intelligence, psychomotor speed, visual-spatial skills, and memory
(Burmeister et al., 2001; Denicoff et al., 1990; Dugbartey, 1998). Several
recent studies have suggested that hypothyroid-related memory defects are
attributable to specific retrieval deficits rather than to an attentional deficit
(Dugbartey, 1998; Miller et al., 2007). Motor skills, language, inhibitory effi-
ciency, and sustained attention appear to be less affected by hypothyroidism
(Burmeister et al., 2001; Dugbartey, 1998). Thus, the memory deficit char-
acteristic of hypothyroidism seems to be distinct from that associated with
major depression, which affects broad executive difficulties (Miller et al.,
2007). Individuals with subclinical hypothyroidism performed poorer than
normal controls on neuropsychological tests including the Wechsler Adult
Intelligence Scale, the Wechsler Memory scale, and verbal fluency (Baldini et
al., 1997). In subclinical hypothyroidism, most detected cognitive deficits are
minimal in severity and appear mainly in regard to working memory (Bauer
et al., 2008; del Ser Quijano et al., 2000).
Cushing disease is one of the pituitary disorders. Individuals with Cushing
disease were found to score significantly lower than controls on four of five
verbal IQ subtests, but only on one nonverbal performance IQ subtest (block
design). Their verbal, but not visual, learning and delayed recall at 30 min-
utes were significantly decreased. Despite the lower score on verbal delayed
recall, the retention index (percentage), which compares the amount of ini-
tially learned material to that recalled after the delay, was not significantly
decreased. The cognitive performance was not associated with depression,
but a higher degree of cortisol elevation was associated with poorer perfor-
mance on several subtests of learning, delayed recall, and visual-spatial ability
(Starkman et al., 2001).
Cortisol is a hormone that fulfills an important role in the context of the
hypothalamic-pituitary-adrenal axis in promoting and maintaining arousal.
Physical Health and Cognition 247
Its impact on cognition, however, is unclear (de Kloet, Oitzl, & Joels, 1999). A
body of studies has demonstrated a relationship between cortisol levels and
memory impairment (de Bruin et al., 2002). In a population-based study of
adults 50–70 years old, higher levels of pretest and mean cortisol were found
to be associated with worse performance in language, processing speed,
eye-hand coordination, executive functioning, verbal memory and learning,
and visual memory (Lee et al., 2007). On the other hand, there is also evi-
dence about the facilitatory effects of cortisol on cognitive activities where
working memory and attention are required (Annett et al., 2005; Koob &
Britton, 1990). It has been concluded that inhibiting effects of cortisol initially
influence neuropsychological processes such as learning in a positive manner
(Luine et al., 1996), although prolonged cortisol secretion can adversely affect
attention, memory, and learning processes (Lupien, Gillin, & Hauger, 1999;
Newcomer et al., 1994; Wolkowitz et al., 1990).
A growing literature shows that gonadal hormones influence cognition,
although these hormone-induced changes are fairly small. Positive effects
have been demonstrated in regard to specific kinds of memory, especially spa-
tial and learning visual memory (Luine, 2008). Efficacious effects on verbal
and working memory by both estrogen and testosterone were demonstrated
in young women who had undergone surgical menopause (i.e., ovarian
removal). Furthermore, the Baltimore Longitudinal Study of Aging provided
evidence of better maintenance of many aspects of cognition in normal aging
women on hormone replacement therapy (Sherwin & Henry, 2008).
Cancer
There is a lot of research concerning the impact of cancer on cognition, but
the overwhelming part of it refers to the effects of chemotherapy on cognitive
functioning (see following section) and a smaller part to the impact of cancer
types that directly involve the central nervous system (CNS) (Meyers & Perry,
2008). Yet, the few studies of individuals prior to undergoing cancer treatments
show that the disease as such also affects cognitive functioning. For example,
in a study of individuals about to undergo hematopoietic stem-cell transplan-
tation (HSCT), 26 percent were classified as impaired before as well as after
HSCT. Neuropsychological test results did not vary systematically accord-
ing to medical variables such as extent of pretreatment, graft-versus-host-
disease (GvHD), and kind of conditioning protocol (Schultz-Kindermann et
al., 2007). A comparison of mean neuropsychological test scores of individ-
uals with invasive and noninvasive breast cancer prior to treatment showed
that those with Stage 1–3 cancer scored significantly lower than healthy
248 Kreitler, Weissler, & Barak
controls on the Reaction Time domain and were significantly more likely to
be classified as having lower than expected overall cognitive performance (22
percent) as compared to Stage 0 patients (0 percent) and healthy controls
(4 percent) (Ahles et al., 2008).
Neurological Diseases
Neurological diseases are a controversial section in the present context
because it is likely that they include central nervous system (CNS) involve-
ment. Yet, we cite a few examples because CNS pathology may not be the sole
factor contributing to the observed cognitive deficits. Thus, in lyme disease,
cognitive impairment was found in attention span, memory retrieval, read-
ing comprehension, concentration, organizing and planning, and identifying
imagery (Edlow, 2003). In multiple sclerosis, cognitive disfunction occurs in
about 50 percent of the individuals (Rao et al., 1991). The consistently reported
neuropsychological profile includes deficits concerning learning and working
memory as well as reduced attentional and executive abilities, whereas lin-
guistical competence and global intellectual capacity remain relatively intact
(Brassington & Marsch, 1998; Rao et al., 1991; Rao, 1995). In adults with new-
onset epilepsy, cognitive deficits were detected with regard to delayed recall in
verbal memory, selective attention, and psychomotor performance (Rösche,
Uhlmann, & Fröscher, 2010).
Chronic Pain
The effects of pain on cognitive functioning have been studied quite exten-
sively, mainly because these effects are likely, first, to exacerbate the patients’
suffering and reduce their already compromised quality of life (Niv & Kreitler,
2001); secondly, to restrict the patients’ ability to communicate their pain
symptoms (Kreitler & Kreitler, 2007); and third, to limit the application of
cognitively based treatments of pain that are highly common. In addition, it
is expected that information about the cognitive impact of pain could shed
light on brain mechanisms that mediate both pain and cognition, thereby
pointing the way toward new treatment strategies of pain.
The summary of the findings is based on studies dealing directly with the
effects of chronic pain on cognitive processes (for all references, see Kreitler
& Niv, 2007). We focused on studies from about 1990 onward (n = 42), which
reported significant findings based on comparing at least one measure of a
cognitive function, assessed by means of a valid and reliable test, in chronic-
pain patients (with no cancer pain and who did not undergo traumatic brain
Physical Health and Cognition 249
injury and had no neurological disorders) and controls (who had no chronic
or acute pain or psychiatric disorder). The chronic-pain patients suffered
mostly from musculoskeletal pain at mixed sites, including whiplash-injury
patients.
Cognitive complaints reported by chronic-pain patients (at least one by 54
percent of the responders) in one study included forgetfulness (23.4 percent),
minor accidents (23.1 percent), difficulty finishing tasks (20.5 percent), and
difficulty with attention (18.7 percent). In another study, complaints included
memory flaws referring to films and books (61 percent), forgetfulness (44
percent), handling of everyday things (38 percent), and flaws about conversa-
tions (38 percent). These and similar surveys indicate that the majority of the
cognitive problems is focused on memory and attention. Memory and atten-
tion deficits figure prominently also in objective findings about cognitive
impairments related to chronic pain. Thus, 88.2 percent of 34 relevant publi-
cations reported lower performance by chronic-pain patients on a varied set
of memory functions, including verbal and nonverbal memory, immediate
and delayed memory, long-term and short-term memory, and memory span.
On the whole, it seems justified to conclude that the most affected aspects of
memory are those that lean heavily on verbal materials, delayed memory, and
require new learning and the use of information previously acquired in the
framework of the task. There are indications that memory for figural mate-
rials, visual memory, spatial memory, and incidental memory tend on the
whole to be less affected by chronic pain.
Attention deficits of chronic-pain patients were reported in 69.2 percent of
13 relevant publications, which however did not include the common mea-
sures in the field – namely, the Stroop and the attention and concentration
indices based on the Wechsler Memory Scale (WMS-R). Verbal deficits of
chronic-pain patients were found in 88.9 percent of the 9 relevant studies,
including tests of vocabulary and word or category fluency.
Deficits of chronic-pain patients in varied measures of speed, ranging from
verbal tasks through information processing speed to psychomotor speed,
were reported in 82.3 percent of 17 relevant studies. Notably, in all three
applications of one speed test – the Number Connection Test –chronic-pain
patients did not differ from healthy controls.
Chronic-pain patients were found in most studies (72.7 percent of 11 stud-
ies) to have lower mental flexibility based mostly on requirements of switching
from one task or set of instructions to another. Further, lower performance
was found for chronic-pain patients in each of the following, tested mostly
by five or less studies: reasoning, construction ability, calculation, the tests of
block design and similarities, visual-motor coordination, abstract thinking,
250 Kreitler, Weissler, & Barak
Dermatological Diseases
The relations between skin disorders and cognition have not been studied
extensively. In a study on psoriasis, it was shown that individuals with pso-
riasis had an automatic attentional bias to specific classes of information
relative to controls. On a computer-based attentional interference task (the
modified Stroop task), they manifested a significant interference for disease-
specific, self-referent, and others’ behavior stimuli relative to controls. Recall
bias was limited to disease-specific stimuli only (Fortune et al., 2003). In
a sample of non-elderly persons without a psychiatric disorder evaluated
with the Repeatable Battery for the Assessment of Neuropsychological
Status (RBANS) and the Wisconsin Card Sorting Test, serological evidence
of Herpes Simplex Virus type 1 (HSV-1) was significantly associated with a
lower RBANS total score independent of demographic factors and the cate-
chol-o-methyl transferase (COMT) Val158Met genotype, as well as a severe
impairment in the domain of delayed memory. The Val/Val genotype of the
COMT Val158Met polymorphism was also significantly associated with the
RBANS total score and a moderate decrease in the domain of attention.
Infections with HSV-1 and the COMT Val158Val genotype are risk factors
252 Kreitler, Weissler, & Barak
Sensory Disabilities
Major sensory disabilities that may affect cognition include hearing, vision,
olfaction, and tactility. The relations between sensory disabilities and cogni-
tion are difficult to disentangle. The senses are an important, indeed essential
means of developing and functioning cognitively in a world shaped by and
for individuals with all senses intact. For an outside observer, it may seem
feasible to overcome the likely difficulties in the cognitive domain by diverse
compensatory means. The question is if that actually takes place.
For example, research has demonstrated cognitive differences between
deaf and hearing students at all levels, including visual perception, memory,
and problem solving, even in mathematics (Dye, Hauser, & Bavelier, 2008;
Hauser, Lukomski, & Hillman, 2008; Kelly, 2008). Memory impairment was
found to be associated with sound processing disorder and hearing loss (Gates
et al., 2008; Wingfield, Tun, & McCoy, 2005). These findings should not be
surprising in view of the important role of verbalization and language under-
standing in cognition. At the same time, there is a lot of evidence showing
that deaf and hearing students share many similarities in cognition. It is nec-
essary to consider the possibility that even small differences in learning abili-
ties and knowledge have significant cumulative effects over time (Marschark
& Hauser, 2008).
In blindness, the major issue is the difficulties or deficits in regard to con-
tacts with the environment. Orientation in space and the structure of space
provide two examples of difficulties that may affect a variety of cognitive
functions (Spencer et al., 1992). However, in addition, other functions such
as verbal fluency have also been found to be affected (Wakefield, Homewood,
& Taylor, 2006).
A study on age-related macular degeneration (AMD) showed that indi-
viduals who had more severe AMD had poorer average scores on cognitive
tests, regardless of factors such as age, sex, race, education, smoking, diabetes,
use of cholesterol-lowering medications, and high blood pressure. Average
scores also decreased as vision decreased (Clemons et al., 2006). A study of
more than 2,000 older adults (69–97 years) revealed an association between
early-stage AMD and cognitive impairment, as assessed by the Digit Symbol
Substitution Test (a test of attention and processing speed). There was no asso-
ciation with performance on the Modified Mini-Mental State Examination
(used to assess dementia) (Baker et al., 2009).
Physical Health and Cognition 253
The olfactory sense is not often considered when studying cognition. Yet,
it is of interest to note that difficulty identifying odors predicts over five years
the development of mild cognitive impairment in elderly people who have
normal cognitive function at baseline. The finding is not changed by control-
ling for age, sex, education, and semantic memory (Wilson et al., 2007).
The involvement of haptic deficits in cognition was demonstrated by
studying groups with different degrees of dementia. The results show that
haptic tasks are sensitive to early perceptive-cognitive and functional deficits
in patients with minimal cognitive impairment (Grunwald et al., 2002).
Even sensory difficulties that do not represent deficits may affect cogni-
tion adversely. For example, individuals with chronic, moderate tinnitus
do more poorly on demanding working memory and attention tests than
those without tinnitus. However, they do not do more poorly on less com-
plex tasks involving involuntary automatic responses (Rossiter, Stevens, &
Walker, 2006).
and reaction time have been observed only 6 or 12 months after pregnancy
(Eidelman, Hoffman, & Katz, 1993; Silber et al., 1990).
Menstruation is another natural physical state whose effects on cognition
were explored. Both reaction time and error rate in a mental rotation task
were negatively impacted in menstruation and ovulation phases in women
(Kozaki & Yasukouchi, 2009). There is further evidence that menstruation
negatively impacts performance requiring spatial memory (Postma et al.
1999). Further, in the proximity of the estrogen, peak performance in autom-
atized tasks is facilitated and performance of perceptual-restructuring tasks
is impaired, compared with performance in the postovulatory phase when
progesterone is thought to counteract the action of estrogen (Broverman et
al., 1981). Several studies showed that verbal fluency, manual dexterity, and
speeded articulation were performed by women better and visuospatial tasks
worse when estrogen and progesterone levels were high than when they were
low (Kimura & Hampson, 1994). A slight deficit in memory in women with
premenstrual syndrome was found (Keenan et al., 1995).
Sleep plays an important role in learning, memory encoding, executive
function, and attention. Insufficient quantity or quality of sleep leads to neu-
rocognitive dysfunction in the short-term and possibly also in the long-term
(Durmer & Dinges, 2005). Sleep loss, whether because of poor sleep qual-
ity, restricted sleep opportunities, or prolonged sleep deprivation, has been
linked with cognitive slowing, increased attention lapses, memory impair-
ment, decreased vigilance, and reduced capacity for sustained attention
(Himashree, Banerjee, & Selvamiinhy, 2002). Sleep deprivation negatively
affects most notably decision making, flexibility, task switching, evaluating
complex situations, and tracking dynamically changing states (Harrison &
Home, 2000).
There is growing evidence of a possible association between being over-
weight and poor cognitive function. Increased body weight is independently
associated with decreased visuospatial organization and general mental
ability already among school-age children (Li et al., 2008). In adults, body
mass index was found to be inversely related to performance on all cogni-
tive tests (Elias et al., 2003; Gunstad et al., 2010; Jeong et al., 2005; Karnehed
et al., 2006; Sǿrensen & Sonne-Holm, 1985). Body mass index was inde-
pendently associated both with cognitive function (word-list learning and
Digit–Symbol Substitution Test) and changes in word-list learning in healthy,
nondemented, middle-aged men and women (Cournot et al., 2006). In one
study, after controlling for confounding variables such as age, gender, IQ, and
years of education, only impaired executive function significantly differenti-
ated overweight or obese subjects from those with normal weight (Gunstad et
Physical Health and Cognition 255
Medical Treatments
Medical treatments may also have side effects that impact cognitive function-
ing. The examples that will be provided refer to surgery, chemotherapy, and
various drugs. The evidence about cognitive dysfunction following surgery
with general anesthesia has been accumulating steadily since the late nine-
ties, so that it came to earn the name of a distinct syndrome – post-operative
cognitive dysfunction. It involves difficulties in memory, learning, and con-
centration that may last for months following surgery.
In one study, it was found in 25.8 percent after one week and in 9.9 percent
after three months. The syndrome was not canceled by controlling for factors
such as age, duration of anesthesia, respiratory complications, and infectious
complications (Moller et al., 1998). In another study, memory and cognitive
function were tested in 1,000 adult patients of different ages prior to elective
noncardiac surgery, at the time of hospital discharge, and three months after
surgery. Cognitive dysfunction was detected at the time of discharge from the
hospital in 36.6 percent of young adults, 30.4 percent of the middle-aged, and
41.4 percent of the elderly. Three months later, the syndrome persisted, but
more in the elderly (12.7 percent) than the younger patients (6 percent) (Price,
Garvan, & Monk, 2008). The assumed etiology includes residual concentra-
tions of general anesthetics, a long-lasting effect of general anaesthestics on
cholinergic or glutaminergic neurotransmission, and possibly psychologi-
cal factors related to illness and environment during hospitalization (Bruce
et al., 2008).
The incidence of cognitive dysfunction following cardiac surgery has
attracted a lot of attention. It has been found to be 30–80 percent after one
week and still common (10–40 percent) after several months and later (Shaw
et al., 1987). Language, concentration, and motor control are most consis-
tently reported to be affected. Memory, attention, and executive function are
more variably affected (Bruce et al., 2008).
The occurrence of cognitive deficits related to treatments of cancer is one
of the most widely studied and discussed issues in regard to medicine and
psychological health. Major cognitive deficits have been detected follow-
ing chemotherapy and biological treatments (Wefel, Collins, & Kayl, 2008),
256 Kreitler, Weissler, & Barak
hormonal treatments (Schilder, Schagen, & van Dam, 2008), and radiation
therapy (Shaw, & Robbins, 2008). Best known are the effects of chemotherapy
(also known as chemo-brain or chemo fog), that occur in about 10–40 per-
cent of the patients, and may last even for more than 10 years. The functions
most often affected involve visual and semantic memory, attention and motor
coordination, and may be manifested in difficulties in regard to decision
making, multitasking, comprehending read material, following the thread of
a conversation, and retrieving words. The causes for the deficiencies are still
unclear and are attributed to toxic drugs that affect brain tissues (Vardy et al.,
2010).
In view of the mass of medical drugs and their potential effects on cogni-
tion, only a few examples will be mentioned. Thus, in regard to antihyperten-
sive medication it was shown that they are likely to increase the inefficiency
of the brain’s work during memory tasks (Astle et al., 2007), and that chronic
use of drugs with anticholinergic properties is associated with impairment
in verbal memory and the ability to perform daily-living tasks. The effect
was independent of age, education, morbidities, and severity of hyperten-
sion, and increased with amount of drug ingested (Han, Agostini, & Allore,
2008).
The cognitive effects of the use of statins are one of the most controversial
issues in the medical arena at present. Accordingly, the best one can do in
view of this situation is to quote support for all different claims: first, that the
use of statins does not affect cognition at all (Trompet et al., 2010); secondly,
that the use of statins is cognitively beneficial and reduces the extent and
rate of cognitive decline (Cramer et al., 2008); and thirdly, that the use of
statins is associated with deleterious effects on cognition (Elias et al., 2005).
The most unexpected and disturbing results are the later, which show a sig-
nificant positive linear association between total cholesterol and measures of
verbal fluency, attention/concentration, abstract reasoning, and a compos-
ite score measuring multiple cognitive domains. Individuals with so-called
desirable cholesterol levels (<200 mg/dL) performed more poorly than those
with borderline-high levels (200–239 mg/dL) or high levels (>240 mg/dL)
on cognitive tasks that place high demands on abstract reasoning, attention/
concentration, word fluency, and executive functioning.
Antihistamins are mentioned here because as an antiallergy treatment,
they are one of the most often-used drugs by individuals of all ages. It was
shown that subjects who were treated with the agent diphenhydramine had
significant performance deficits on tests of divided attention, working mem-
ory, vigilance, and speed (Kay, 2009).
Physical Health and Cognition 257
Some Conclusions
The material presented in this chapter demonstrates the extent of the impact
of physical disorders on cognitive functioning. Almost all of the major physi-
cal disorders have been mentioned. The omission of some does not indicate
that they do not affect cognition but rather that they have not been studied
or had to be deleted from our necessarily short review. There is no doubt that
the studies suffer from a fair number of shortcomings. Some of the major
ones are inadequate considerations of relevant confounding factors such as
age, comorbidity, phase of disease, and use of medication; the use of lim-
ited or inadequate control groups; and inadequate or incomplete selection
of variables or tasks for testing cognitive functioning. As a result, it is impos-
sible at present to compare the extent and severity of cognitive effects in the
various diseases. Neither is it possible to conclude that the assessed cognitive
variables are the major ones or those that are most affected in that particular
disease.
Yet, despite all the evident shortcomings, the amount, diversity, and nature
of the findings render it barely possible to avoid the conclusion that cogni-
tive functioning is affected by physical disorders and the physical state of the
258 Kreitler, Weissler, & Barak
individual. As such, this conclusion should not come as a surprise. It has long
been known that the mental state of the individual affects cognitive func-
tioning. Accordingly, regular samples in cognitive psychology that were not
designed to study psychopathological cognition did not include individuals
suffering from depression, paranoia, or schizophrenia, to mention just a few
examples. Yet, no consideration has been paid up to now to the effects of
physical disorders on cognitive functioning, despite the fact that physical
disorders are much more prevalent and possibly exert even more pervasive
effects on cognition than mental disorders.
However, it is precisely the prevalence and pervasiveness of the effects of
physical disorders on cognition that render it so difficult to discuss the impli-
cations of these findings in regard to the study of cognition. Should all indi-
viduals with any physical disorder be excluded from studies in cognition? Or
should it become practice that any individual who participates in a study of
cognition is to be asked to list in detail all one’s physical disorders in the pre-
sent or the past?
It is evident that recommendations along these lines are impractical and
unreasonable. Moreover, they would not be very helpful in promoting the
study of cognition because at present too little is known about the mecha-
nisms and processes involved in enabling the impact of physical states on
cognition. A great amount of research is still needed in order to specify which
physical diseases affect which cognitive functions negatively and perhaps
even positively and why.
The field is in dire need of models of a theoretical nature, grounded in
biopsychological data, that would specify the kind of mechanisms likely to be
involved in the mediation of the effects of diseases on cognition. These mech-
anism would include states and processes in the brain, in different body parts
and bodily systems (hormonal, hematological) as well as psychological pro-
cesses contributing directly or indirectly to the likelihood of the occurrence
of a disease and affecting its course and impact on the individual’s quality
of life and overall functioning. The outlined models may well constitute the
next phase of studies in health psychology. Before the evidence flows in, how-
ever, it seems reasonable to recommend that major physical diseases of the
individual participating in a study on cognition be at least listed for further
reference and future attempts to deepen the exploration and analysis of the
findings.
References
Ahles, T. A., Saykin, A. J., McDonald, B. C., Furstenberg, C. T., Cole, B. F., Hanscom, B.
S., Mulrooney, T. J., Schwartz, G. N., & Kaufman, P. A. (2008). Cognitive function
Physical Health and Cognition 259
in breast cancer patients prior to adjuvant treatment. Breast Cancer Research &
Treatments, 110, 143–152.
Allen, K. V., Frier, B. M., & Strachan, M. W. (2004). The relationship between type 2
diabetes and cognitive dysfunction: Longitudinal studies and their methodological
limitations. European Journal of Pharmacology, 490, 169–175.
Annett, R. D., Stansbury, L. K., Kelly, H. W., & Strunk, R. C. (2005). Association of
hypothalamic-pituitaryadrenal axis function with neuropsychological performance
in children with mild/moderate asthma. Child Neuropsychology, 11, 333–348.
Argyriadou, S., Vlachonikolis, I., Melisopoulou, H., Katachanakis, K., & Lionis, C.
(2001). In what extent anemia coexists with cognitive impairment in elderly: a
cross-sectional study in Greece. BMC Family Practice, 2, 5–10.
Astle, K., Muldoon, M., Christie, I., Price, J., & Meltzer, C. (2007). Memory tasks require
more coordinated brain blood flow for people with high blood pressure. American
Heart Association meeting report, Presentation P105.
Awad, N., Gagnon, M., & Messier, C. (2004). The relationship between impaired glucose
tolerance, type 2 diabetes and cognitive function. Journal of Clinical & Experimental
Neuropsychology, 26, 1044–1080.
Baker, M. L., Wang, J. J., Rogers, S., Klein, R., Kuller, L. H., Larsen, E. K., & Wong, T. Y.
(2009). Early age-related macular degeneration, cognitive function, and dementia:
The Cardiovascular Health Study. Archives of Ophthalmology, 127, 667–673.
Baldini, I. M., Vita, A., Mauri, M. C., Amodei, V., Carrisi, M., Bravin, S., & Cantalamessa,
L. (1997). Psychopathological and cognitive features in subclinical hypothyroidism.
Progress in Neuropsychopharmacology & Biological Psychiatry, 21, 925–935.
Barclay, L. L., Weiss, E. M., Mattis, S., Bond, O., & Blass, J. P. (1988). Unrecognized cogni-
tive impairment in cardiac rehabilitation patients. Journal of the American Geriatric
Society, 36, 22–28.
Batty, G. D., Mortensen, E. L., Nybo, A. A.-M., & Osler, M. (2005). Childhood intelli-
gence in relation to adult coronary heart disease and stroke risk: evidence from a
Danish birth cohort study. Paediatric & Perinatal Epidemiology, 19, 452–459.
Bauer, M., Goetz, T., Glenn, T., & Whybrow, P. C. (2008). The thyroid-brain interac-
tion in thyroid disorders and mood disorders. Journal of Neuroendocrinology, 20,
1101–1114.
Baune, B. T., Miller, R., McAfoose, J., Johnson, M., Quirk, F., & Mitchell, D. (2010). The
role of cognitive impairment in general functioning in major depression. Psychiatry
Research, 176, 183–189.
Beebe, D. W., Groesz, L., Wells, C., Nichols, A., & McGee, K. (2003). The
Neuropsychological effects of obstructive sleep apnea: a meta-analysis of
norm-referenced and case-controlled data. Sleep, 26, 298–307.
Berry, D. T., McConnell, J. W., Phillips, B. A., Carswell, C. M., Lamb, D. G., & Prine,
B. C. (1989). Isocapnic hypoxemia and neuropsychological functioning. Journal of
Experimental & Clinical Neurology, 11, 241–251.
Biessels, G. J., van der Heide, L. P., Kamal, A., Bleys, R. L., & Gispen, W. H. (2002). Ageing
and diabetes: Implications for brain function. European Journal of Pharmacology,
441, 1–14.
Borres, M. P. (2009). Allergic rhinitis: more than just a stuffy nose. Acta Paediatrica, 98,
1088–1092.
Brassington, J. C., & Marsh, N. V. (1998). Neuropsychological aspects of multiple sclero-
sis. Neuropsychology Review, 8, 43–77.
260 Kreitler, Weissler, & Barak
Breteler, M. M. B., Claus, J. J., Grobbee, D. E., & Hofman, A. (1994). Cardiovascular dis-
ease and distribution of cognitive function in elderly people: the Rotterdam study.
British Medical Journal, 308, 1604–1608.
Broverman, D. M., Vogel, W., Klaiber, E. L., Majcher, D., Shea, D., & Paul, V. (1981).
Changes in cognitive task performance across the menstrual cycle. Journal of
Comparative and Physiological Psychology, 95, 646–654.
Bruce, K., Smith, J. A., Yelland, G., & Robinson, S. (2008). The impact of cardiac surgery
on cognition. Stress & Health, 24, 249–266.
Buchman, A. S., Tanne, D., Boyle, P. A., Shah, R. C., Leurgans, S. E., & Bennett, D. A.
(2009). Kidney function is associated with the rate of cognitive decline in the
elderly. Neurology, 73, 920–927.
Buckwalter, J. G., Stanczyk, F. Z., McCleary, C. A., Bluestein, B. W., Buckwalter, D. K.,
Rankle, K. P., Chang, L., & Goodwin, T. M. (1999). Pregnancy, the postpartum, and
steroid hormones: Effects on cognition and mood. Psychoneuroendocrinology, 24,
69–54.
Buckwalter, J. G., Buckwalter, D. K., Bluestein, B. W., & Stanczyk, F. Z. (2001). Pregnancy
and post partum: changes in cognition and mood. Progress in Brain Research, 133,
303–319.
Burmeister, L. A, Ganguli, M., Dodge, H. H., Toczek, T., DeKosky, S. T., & Nebes, R. D.
(2001). Hypothyroidism and cognition: preliminary evidence for a specific defect
in memory. Thyroid, 11, 1177–1185.
Castaneda, A. E., Tuulio-Henriksson, A., Marttunen, M., Suvisaari, J., Lönnqvist, J.
(2008). A review on cognitive impairments in depressive and anxiety disorders
with a focus on young adults. Journal of Affective Disorders, 106, 1–27.
Clark, A. (1998). Embodied, situated, and distributed cognition. In W. Bechtel & G.
Graham (Eds.), A companion to cognitive sciences (pp. 506–517). Malden, MA:
Blackwell.
Clemons, T. E., Rankin, M. W., McBee, W. L., (2006). Association between mild age-related
eye disease study research group: Cognitive impairment in the age-related eye dis-
ease study: AREDS report no. 16. Archives of Ophthalmology, 124, 537–543.
Cournot, M., Marquié, J. C., Ansiau, D., Martinaud, C., Fonds, H., Ferrières, J., &
Ruidavets, J. B. (2006). Relation between body mass index and cognitive function
in healthy middle-aged men and women. Neurology, 67, 1208–1214.
Craft, S., & Watson, S. G. (2004). Insulin and neurodegenerative disease: Shared and
specific mechanisms. Lancet Neurology, 3, 169–178.
Cramer, C., Haan, M. N., Galea, S., Langa, K. M., & Kalbfleisch, J. D. (2008). Use of
statins and incidence of dementia and cognitive impairment without dementia in a
cohort study. Neurology, 71, 344–350.
Cukierman-Yaffe, T., Gerstein, H. C., Williamson, J. D., Lazar, R. M., Lovato, L., Miller,
M. E., Coker, L. H., Murray, A., Sullivan, M. D., Marcovina, S. M., Launer, L. J.,
for the Action to Control Cardiovascular Risk in Diabetes-Memory in Diabetes
(ACCORD-MIND) Investigators (2009). Relationship between baseline glycemic
control and cognitive function in individuals with type 2 diabetes and other cardio-
vascular risk factors: the action to control cardiovascular risk in diabetes-memory
in diabetes (ACCORD-MIND) trial. Diabetes Care, 32, 221–226.
de Bruin, V. Am, Vieira, M. C., Rocha, M. N., & Viana, G. S. (2002). Cortisol and dehy-
droepiandosterone sulfate plasma levels and their relationship to aging, cognitive
function, and dementia. Brain & Cognition, 50, 316–323.
Physical Health and Cognition 261
Dealberto, M. J., Pajot, N., Courbon, D., & Alpérovitch, A. (1996). Breathing disorders
during sleep and cognitive performance in an older community sample: the EVA
Study. Journal of the American Geriatric Society, 44, 1287–1294.
Deary, I. J., Whiteman, M. C., Starr, J. M., Whalley, L. J., & Fox, H. C. (2004). The impact
of childhood intelligence on later life: Following up the Scottish mental surveys of
1932 and 1947. Journal of Personality & Social Psychology, 86, 30–47.
de Kloet, E. R., Oitzl, M. S., & Joels, M. (1999). Stress and cognition: Are corticosteroids
good or bad guys? Trends in Neuroscience, 22, 422–426.
del Ser Quijano, T., Delgado, C., Martı´nez Espinosa, S., & Va´zquez, C. (2000).
Cognitive deficiency in mild hypothyroidism. Neurologia, 15, 193–198.
Della Sala, S., Donner, C. F., Sacco, C., & Spinner, H. (1992). Does chronic lung failure
lead to cognitive failure? Archives of Neurology and Psychiatry, 143, 343–354.
Denicoff, K. D., Joffe, R. T., Lakshmanan, M. C., Robbins, J., & Rubinow, D. R. (1990).
Neuropsychiatric manifestations of altered thyroid state. American Journal of
Psychiatry, 147, 94–99.
Dickerson, F., Stallings, C., Sullens, A., Origoni, A., Leister, F., Krivogorsky, B., & Yolken
R. (2008). Association between cognitive functioning, exposure to Herpes Simplex
virus type 1, and the COMT Val158Met genetic polymorphism in adults without a
psychiatric disorder. Brain, Behavior & Immunity, 22, 1103–1107.
Dodd, J. W., Getov, S. V., & Jones, P. W. (2010). Cognitive function in COPD. European
Respiratory Journal, 35, 913–922.
Dugbartey, A. T. (1998). Neurocognitive aspects of hypothyroidism. Archives of Internal
Medicine, 158, 1413–1418.
Durmer, J. S., & Dinges, D. F. (2005). Neurocognitive consequences of sleep deprivation.
Seminars in Neurology, 25, 117–129.
Dye, M. W. G., Hauser, P. C., & Bavelier, D. (2008). Visual attention in deaf children and
adults. In M. Marschark & P. C. Hauser (Eds.), Deaf cognition (pp. 250–263). New
York: Oxford University Press.
Eccleston, C., & Crombez, G. (1999). Pain demands attention: a cognitive-affective
model of the interruptive function of pain. Psychological Bulletin, 125, 356–366.
Edlow, J. A. (2003). Bull’s eye: Unraveling the medical mystery of Lyme disease. New
Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Eidelman, A. I., Hoffman, N. W., & Katz, M. (1993). Cognitive deficits in women after
childbirth. Obstetrics & Gynecology, 81, 764–767.
Elias, P. K., Elias, M. F., D’Agostino, R. B., Sullivan, L. M., & Wolf, P. A. (2005). Serum cho-
lesterol and cognitive performance in the Framingham heart study. Psychosomatic
Medicine, 67, 24–30.
Elias, M. F., Elias, P. K., Sullivan, L. M., Wolf, P. A., & D’Agostino, R. B. (2003). Lower cog-
nitive function in the presence of obesity and hypertension: the Framingham Heart
Study. International Journal of Obesity & Related Metabolic Disorders, 27, 260–268.
Elias, M. F., Wolf, P. A., D’Agostino, R. B., Cobb, J., & White, L. R. (1993). Untreated
blood pressure is inversely related to cognitive functioning: The Framingham
Study. American Journal of Epidemiology, 138, 353–364.
Elwood, P. C., Pickering, J., Bayer, A., & Gallacher, J. E. (2002). Vascular disease and cog-
nitive function in older men in the Caerphilly cohort. Age & Ageing, 31, 43–48.
Fortune, D. G., Richards, H. L., Corrin, A., Taylor, R. J., Griffiths, C. E. M., & Main, C.
J. (2003). Attentional bias for psoriasis-specific and psychosocial threat in patients
with psoriasis. Journal of Behavioral Medicine, 26, 211–224.
262 Kreitler, Weissler, & Barak
Hauser, P. C., Lukomski, J., & Hillman, T. (2008). Development of deaf and hard-of-hearing
students’ executive function. In M. Marschark & P. C. Hauser (Eds.), Deaf cognition
(pp. 286–308). New York: Oxford University Press.
Hemmingsson, T., von Essen, J., Melin, B., Allebeck, P., & Lundberg, I. (2007). The
association between cognitive ability measured at ages 18–20 and coronary heart
disease in middle age among men – a prospective study using the Swedish 1969
conscription cohort. Social Science & Medicine, 65, 1410–1419.
Hendrie, H. C., Albert, M. S., Buttersc, M. A., Gaod, S., Knopmane, D. S., Launer, L. J.,
Yaffeg, K., Cuthbert, B. N., Edwardsi, E., & Wagster, M. V. 2006. The NIH Cognitive
and Emotional Health Project: Report of the critical evaluation study committee.
Alzheimer’s & Dementia, 2, 12–32.
Henry, J. D., & Rendell, P. G. (2007). A review of the impact of pregnancy on memory
function. Journal of Clinical & Experimental Neuropsychology, 29, 793–803.
Himashree, G., Banerjee, P. K., & Selvamiinhy, W. (2002). Sleep and performance: recent
trends. Indian Journal of Physiotherapy & Pharmacology, 46, 6–24.
Hu, W. T., Murray, J. A., Greenaway, M. C., Parisi, J. E., & Josephs, K. A. (2006). Cognitive
impairment and celiac disease. Archives of Neurology, 63, 1440–1446.
Huppert, F. A. (1982). Memory impairment associated with chronic hypoxia. Thorax,
37, 858–860.
Incalzi, R. A., Gemma, A., Marra, C., Muzzolon, R., Capparella, O., & Carbonin, P.
(1993). Chronic obstructive pulmonary disease. An original model of cognitive
decline. American Review of Respiratory Disorders, 148, 418–424.
Jacobsen, P. B., Garland, L. L., Booth-Jones, M., Donovan, K. A., Thors, C. L., Winters,
E., & Grendys, E. (2004). Relationship of hemoglobin levels to fatigue and cogni-
tive functioning among cancer patients receiving chemotherapy. Journal of Pain &
Symptom Management, 28, 7–18.
Karnehed, N., Rasmussen, F., Hemmingsson, T., & Tynelius, P. (2006). Obesity and
attained education. Cohort study of more than 700 000 Swedish men. Obesity, 14,
421–1428.
Kay, G. (2009). The effects of antihistamines on cognition and performance. Journal of
Allergy and Clinical Immunology, 105, 622–627.
Keenan, P. A., Lindamer, L. A., & Jong, S. K. (1995). Menstrual phase-independent
retrieval deficit in women with PMS. Biol Psychiatry, 38, 369–377.
Keenan, P. A., Yaldoo, D. T., Stress, M. E., Fuerst, D. R., & Ginsburg, K. A. (1998). Explicit
memory in pregnant women. American journal of Obstetrics & Gynecology, 179,
731–737.
Kelly, R. R. (2008). Deaf learners and mathematical problem solving. In M. Marschark
& P. C. Hauser (Eds.), Deaf cognition (pp. 226–249). New York: Oxford University
Press.
Kimura, D., & Hampson, E. (1994). Cognitive pattern in men and women is influenced
by fluctuations in sex hormones. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 3,
57–61.
Koob, G. F., & Britton, K. T. (1990). Behavioral effects of corticotropin-releasing factor.
In E. B. DeSouza & C. B. Nemeroff (Eds.), Corticotropin-releasing factor: Basic and
Clinical studies of a neuropeptide (pp. 254–265). Boca Raton, FL: CRC Press.
Kountourasa, J., Tsolakib, M., Bozikib, M., Gavalasa, E., Zavosa, C., Stergiopoulosa, C.,
Kapetanakisa, N., Chatzopoulosa, D., & Venizelosa, I. (2007). Association between
264 Kreitler, Weissler, & Barak
Schulz-Kindermann, F., Mehnert, A., Scherwath, A., Schirmer, L., Schleimer, B., Zander,
A. R., & Koch, U. (2007). Cognitive function in the acute course of allogeneic
hematopoietic stem cell transplantation for hematological malignancies. Bone
Marrow Transplantation, 39, 789–799.
Selnes, O. A., Grega, M. A., Bailey, M. M., Pham, L. D., Zeger, S. L., Baumgartner, W. A.,
& McKhann, G. M. (2009). Do management strategies for coronary artery disease
influence 6-year cognitive outcomes? Annals of Thoracic Surgery, 88, 445–454.
Sharp, K., Brindle, P. M., Brown, M. W., & Turner, G. M. (1993). Memory loss during
pregnancy. British Journal of Obstetrics & Gynecology, 100, 209–215.
Shaw, E. G., & Robbins, M. E. (2008). Biological bases of radiation injury to the brain.
In C. A. Meyers & J. R. Perry (Eds.), Cognition and cancer (pp. 83–96). New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Shaw, P. J., Bates, D., Cartlidge, N. E. F., French, J. M., Heaviside, D., Julian, D. G., & Shaw, D.
A. (1987). Long-term intellectual dysfunction following coronary artery bypass graft
surgery: a six month follow-up study. Quarterly Journal of Medicine, 62, 259–268.
Sherwin, B. B., & Henry, J. F. (2008). Brain aging modulates the neuroprotective effects
of estrogen on selective aspects of cognition in women: a critical review. Front
Neuroendocrinology, 29, 88–113.
Silber, M., Almkvist, O., Larsson, B., & Uvnas-Moberg, K. (1990). Temporary peripartal
impairment in memory and attention and its possible relation to oxytocin concen-
tration. Life Science, 47, 57–65.
Singh-Manoux, A., Britton, A. R., & Marmot, M. (2003). Vascular disease and cognitive
function: evidence from the Whitehall II study. Journal of the American Geriatric
Society, 51, 1445–1450.
Singh-Manoux, A., Lajnef, S. S. M., Ferrie, J. E., Nabi, H., Britton, A. R., Marmot, M.
G., & Shipley, M. J. (2008). History of coronary heart disease and cognitive perfor-
mance in midlife: the Whitehall II study. European Heart Journal, Advance Access
published on July 22, 2008. doi:10.1093/eurheartj/ehn298.
Solomon, A., Kåreholt, I., Ngandu, T., Wolozin, B., MacDonald, S., Winblad, B.,
Nissinen, A. Tuomilehto, J., Soininen, H., & Kivipelto, M. (2009). Serum total cho-
lesterol, statins and cognition in non-demented elderly. Neurobiology of Aging, 30,
1006–1009.
Sǿrensen, T. I. A., & Sonne-Holm, S. (1985). Intelligence test performance in obesity in
relation to educational attainment and parental social class. Journal of Biosocial
Science, 17, 379–387.
Spencer, C., Morsley, K., Ungar, S., Pike, E., & Blades, M. (1992). Developing the blind
child’s cognition of the environment: the role of direct and map-given experience.
Geoforum, 23, 191–197.
Spencer, J. P., Vauzour, D., & Rendeiro, C. (2009). Flavonoids and cognition : The molec-
ular mechanisms underlying their behavioral effects. Archives of Biochemistry &
Biophysics, 492, 1–9.
Starkman, M. N., Giordani, B., Berent, S., Schork, M. A., & Schteingart, D. E. (2001).
Elevated cortisol levels in Cushing’s disease are associated with cognitive decre-
ments. Psychosomatic Medicine, 63, 985–993.
Stuss, D. T., Peterkin, I., Guzman, D. A., Guzman, C., & Troyer, A. K. (1997).
Chronic obstructive pulmonary disease: Effects of hypoxia on neurological and
268 Kreitler, Weissler, & Barak
Wingfield, A., Tun, P. A., & McCoy, S. L. (2005). Hearing loss in older adulthood:
What it is and how it interacts with cognitive performance. Current Directions in
Psychological Science, 14, 144–148.
Wolkowitz, O. M., Reus, V. I., Weingartner, H., Thompson, K., Breier, A., Doran, A.,
Rubinow, D., & Pickar, D. (1990). Cognitive effects of corticosteroids. American
Journal of Psychiatry, 147, 1297–1303.
Zamboni, V., Cesari, M., Zuccal, G., Onder, G., Woodman, R. C., Maraldi, C., Ranzini,
M., Volpato, S., Pahor, M., Bernabei, R. (2006). Anemia and cognitive performance
in hospitalized older patients: results from the GIFA study. International Journal of
Geriatric Psychiatry, 21, 529–534.
Part II
Introduction
Problem solving and motivation are closely intertwined, as is indicated by the
classic definition of a problem situation from Duncker (1945, p. 1), “A prob-
lem arises when a living organism has a goal but does not know how this goal
is to be reached.” Before proceeding further, we will briefly discuss some defi-
nitional issues and consider the relationships between goals and motives.
Austin and Vancouver (1996, p. 338) proposed that goals be defined as
“internal representations of desired states.” In a broad sense, a goal reflects
a preference for some proposition to be true versus not true (e.g., the goal
to have more money tomorrow than today reflects a preference for “having
more money tomorrow” to be true rather than false). According to one dic-
tionary definition (Chambers, 1962), “a motive is a consideration that excites
to action (from the Latin, movere, to move).” Motives and goals are clearly
very closely related concepts in that both involve representations of desired
states. Austin and Vancouver made the useful suggestion that goals can vary
in degree of specificity or abstractness and that more abstract goals, such as
Need for Cognition (Caccioppo et al., 1996) or Achievement Need (Atkinson,
1964), are usefully labelled as motives and more specific representations of
desired states should be labelled as goals. If a motive is to lead to action, it
would seem that it must ultimately lead to the activation of a specific goal
representation, which can then play a role in initiating and controlling behav-
iour. Research on problem solving tends to theorise at the level of goals rather
than at the level of very broad motives (which are dealt with largely in per-
sonality and motivational psychology).
Goals can be said to vary in terms of structure and content (Austin &
Vancouver, 1996). Content refers to what desired state is represented by
the goal, and can vary essentially infinitely in detail. Austin and Vancouver
273
274 Gilhooly & Fioratou
state of the problem is very limited. Figure 13.1 lays out the possible states
and moves in this task. It appears that people generally choose which move
to execute at each choice point by assessing which move will lead to a state
closest to the goal state. The degree of looking ahead is typically just one step.
This type of procedure is sometimes known as hill-climbing, by analogy with
a method of climbing a hill in a thick fog by testing out one step in each of the
four principal directions and taking the step that leads to the highest ground.
To apply hill-climbing in well-defined tasks, an evaluation function is applied
to possible states in order to index closeness to the goal. A possible evalua-
tion function in the Hobbits and Orcs problem would be to count the number
of creatures on the target side and use the resulting score to indicate which
move to execute at each step (choose the move that leads to the highest scor-
ing state). A simple application of this type of approach can lead to difficulties
with problems that require a detour, in that the sequence of states leading to
solution do not yield monotonically increasing evaluations. The Hobbits and
Orcs problem is a detour problem because there is a state which has four crea-
tures on the target side, but the solution requires moving from that apparently
promising state to an apparently less promising state with only two creatures
on the target side. As would be predicted, if people are using forward search
guided by a simple evaluation function for this task, the state from which a
detour is needed for progress causes marked difficulties in terms of latencies
and error moves (Thomas, 1974). Many solvers initially go backwards from
the detour state and then must retrace their steps. To avoid perpetual loop-
ing, some memory for previous moves must be postulated, with extra rules
about avoiding previously visited states. This need for memory-guided search
is particularly strong in problems that permit a great deal of looping such as
Water Jars (Atwood, Masson, & Polson, 1980). More recently, forward search
guided by goal-based evaluation functions has been shown to be implicated
in the difficulties engendered by a number of classic insight tasks such as
the 9-dot problem (Chronicle, MacGregor, & Ormerod, 2004). In such tasks,
some redefinition of the problem is typically required, but initial attempts
within the normal “obvious” interpretation typically show a hill-climbing
pattern, and it is only after repeated failures of the hill-climbing approach
that problem redefinition or restructuring is likely to occur.
Forward search guided by a goal-based evaluation function to assess
possible intermediate states seems most common when problems are well-
defined and few actions are possible at each state. In tasks where there are
many possible actions (which is often the case for ill-defined or only partially
well-defined tasks) or in which simple evaluation functions are not helpful,
a problem-reduction approach is often adopted. In this approach, the overall
278 Gilhooly & Fioratou
320
HHH O
OO Boat
10
331 000
HHH HHH
OOO OOO
Boat Boat
1H 10 20 1H 10 20
1H 10 1H 10
321 010
HHH HHH
OO O O OO
Boat Boat
20 20
300 031
HHH HHH
OOO OOO
Boat Boat
10 10
300 020
HHH HHH
O OO OO O
Boat Boat
2H 2H
110 221
1H 10
H HH HH H
O OO OO O
Boat Boat
Figure 13.1. Problem-space figure for the Hobbits and Orcs problem.
Note: The figure above sets out all the possible moves that can be made and resultant
states, given that the boat can only hold two creatures and Hobbits must never be out-
numbered by Orcs. The starting state of the problem is the second state down from the
top. The solver does not have the layout below, but rather sees only one state at a time
and must imagine possible moves and choose amongst such moves. When a move is
made the next state is displayed. The number Hs and Os on the left- and right-hand side
of each box indicate the number of Hobbits and Orcs on each side of the river at any
given time.
Motivation, Goals, Thinking, and Problem Solving 279
goal is progressively specified into subgoals, which in turn are specified fur-
ther into still lower-level subgoals. In complex tasks, many alternative sub-
goals will often need exploration before solution. An everyday example of
problem reduction is that of making travel plans. The overall goal is to be at a
distant place. Means are sought to reduce the distance between where one is
and where one wishes to be, such as using a commercial flight. To apply such
a means, a new goal (subgoal) is established of meeting the conditions needed
to take a flight (be at airport, have valid ticket, etc). These subgoals in turn
generate new subgoals, until immediately actionable subgoals are generated
(e.g., logon to internet to make booking). The generation of subgoals proceeds
by a process of means-ends analysis. Goals or ends lead to subgoals (means),
which in turn act as ends to generate further subgoals. This approach was
instantiated in Newell and Simon’s (1963) General Problem Solver program,
and is evident in later programs such as Newell’s (1992) SOAR.
Duncker’s (1945) study of the X-ray task provides a laboratory example
of problem reduction in a task with some ill-defined elements (particularly
regarding possible actions). Participants are to find a way of using X-radiation
to destroy a tumour in the middle of a patient without destroying healthy tis-
sue around the tumour. Thinking-aloud records indicated a strong tendency
to use a problem-reduction approach. For example, a participant suggested
that the major goal of “treating the tumour by rays without destroying healthy
tissue” could be reached by means of the subgoal of “avoiding contact between
rays and healthy tissue” and this could perhaps be achieved via a subgoal of
“using a cannula” or a subgoal of “reaching tumour through the esophagus”.
The “avoiding contact” subgoal was unproductive and had to be abandoned
for the subgoal of “lowering intensity of rays on their way through the healthy
tissue”, which led to the solution “use a lens to concentrate a bundle of weak
rays on the tumour” (Figure 13.2).
The Tower of Hanoi provides an example of a well-defined problem in
which simple evaluation functions are not clearly available or helpful. In this
task (see Figure 13.3), one is presented with three vertical rods or pegs on
one of which are n discs assembled in order of size with the largest at the
bottom and the smallest on top. The goal is to move the entire assembly of
discs from the starting peg to a target peg, moving one disc at a time and
never putting a larger disc on top of a smaller disc. The non-target peg is to
be used for temporary storage. With n discs, the number of moves required
increases rapidly according to the function 2n – 1, so the 3-disc version in
Figure 13.3 requires 7 moves, a 4-disc version requires 15 moves, a 5-disc ver-
sion requires 31 moves, a 6-disc version 63 moves, and so on. Although naïve
solvers do often begin trying a hill-climbing approach (Anzai & Simon,
280 Gilhooly & Fioratou
Radiation
source
Body wall
Tumor
A B C
Figure 13.3. Three-disc Tower of Hanoi. Move all discs from peg A to peg C, one disc
at a time, and never put a larger disc on top of a smaller disc.
contributors to the arts and sciences indicate extremely high levels of com-
mitment (motivation) and immersion in the field of work (Boden, 2004).
“Normal” expertise in the chosen domain must be developed initially (and
we have seen that normal expertise requires c. 10 years of devoted study and
deliberate practice) before the potential creative contributor can understand
a complex conceptual space (e.g., classical geometry or classical music) and
then transform it in a useful way. In Edison’s famous saying, creativity is “one
per cent inspiration and 99 per cent perspiration” (Rosanoff, 1932).
approach. It was found that both types of problem responded positively to the
incentives, which suggests that insight and non-insight problems have more
in common than is sometimes suggested (Gilhooly & Murphy, 2005).
Overall, the current view is that both intrinsic and extrinsic sources of
motivation are important in creative problem solving, but that the effects
of extrinsic motivation are more variable and depend on the nature of the
incentive or reward and how it is dependent on quality of behaviour. If the
external reward is the same no matter what level of performance is reached,
this could induce “learned helplessness” (Eisenberger & Cameron, 1996) and
impair performance. External reward dependent on results has an informa-
tional aspect and is more likely to be helpful. In the light of recent research,
Amabile (1996, p. 119) has revised her earlier hypothesis and formulated the
Intrinsic Motivation Principle as follows: “ Intrinsic motivation is conducive
to creativity; controlling extrinsic motivation is detrimental to creativity, but
informational or enabling extrinsic motivation can be conducive, particularly
if initial levels of intrinsic motivation are high”.
Concluding Comments
It is clear that problem solving and motivation are closely intertwined. Without
unmet motives and active unsatisfied goals, there would be no problems to
solve. General motives lead to more specific goals, and goals play a crucial
role in problem-directed thinking by guiding the would-be solver towards
promising actions in searching a state-action space or useful developments
of subgoals and subsubgoals that in turn lead to suitable actions towards the
overall goal or goals.
Expert problem solving is based on extensive domain knowledge, which is
built-up slowly over many years (around 10 years being a common estimate
across domains) and results from continued motivation to develop the par-
ticular skill in question. Deliberate practice and guided training seem cru-
cial to developing expertise in all domains. Clearly, long-term motivation is
essential to develop expertise. Having acquired expert knowledge, leading
thinkers can then develop their domain further by creative thinking, which is
largely motivated by an intrinsic interest and enjoyment of the field.
References
Adelson, B. (1981). Problem solving and the development of abstract categories in pro-
gramming languages. Memory and Cognition, 9, 422–433.
Amabile, T. M. (1983). The social psychology of creativity. New York: Springer-Verlag.
286 Gilhooly & Fioratou
Introduction
An advertisement was recently distributed among many Israeli families by
the Israeli National Lottery (Mifal Hapais) in which joining a subscription
program by purchasing a certain number was offered. According to the offer,
the number would participate weekly in the lottery, and the unique aspect of
it was its being a personal lucky number, especially chosen for each recipi-
ent. Furthermore, it was promised that this personal lucky number would
increase the chances of winning. Because the National Lottery is a profitable
organization, it seems logical to assume that the advertisement succeeded in
recruiting enough members that at least the costs of producing the campaign
were paid back.
A rational analysis of that advertisement readily reveals several nonrational
biases: (1) The idea that a fixed number increases the chances of winning; (2)
there are lucky numbers; and (3) a personal number augments the chances
of winning. Yet, there are people who fall into such traps. Furthermore,
most probably, some of those who do are aware of the misleading informa-
tion included in the advertisement. In a study conducted by Klar, Zakay,
and Sharvit (2002), it was found that many Israelis adopted unique behavior
patterns in order to cope with the threat of terrorist attacks. Many of those
patterns (e.g., avoiding going to shopping centers at the same day and hour of
the week in which a terrorist attack previously occurred) might be considered
as reflecting superstitious behavior. In effect, many of those who adopted such
behaviors were aware of the fact that this did not really reduce their chances of
being involved in terrorist attacks; still, they could not give up these behaviors,
mainly because it gave them some feeling of control over the situation. Those
two examples raise questions about why people swallow intuitive nonrational
baits, on the one hand, but, on the other hand, can justify such behaviors from
289
290 Zakay & Fleisig
thinking is that individuals are frequently unaware that they rely on it, a state
which poses an obstacle in regard to amending the suboptimality resulting
from it.
Heuristics base their claim to fame on the three general-purpose heuris-
tics identified by Tversky and Kahneman (1974) that underlie many intuitive
judgments under uncertainty: availability, representativeness, and anchor-
ing and adjustment. Since then, many more have been identified in the area
of judgments under uncertainty, but heuristics can be identified in various
thinking domains such as problem solving, planning, choice, metacognitive
processes, causality judgment, social judgment, and others. Some examples
are briefly presented here.
Problem solving. Several heuristics are associated with the problem-solving
process. The anti-looping (Davies, 2000) and the hill-climbing (Chronicle,
MacGregor, & Ormerod, 2004) heuristics can serve as examples. Both heu-
ristics are concerned with strategies of problem solving – avoiding previous
moves in the anti-looping heuristic or taking whichever next step brings one
closest to or least distant from the goal in the hill-climbing process.
Planning. The planning fallacy (Kahneman & Tversky, 1979) exhibits the
tendency to estimate optimistically future task-completion times, so that pre-
dicted completion times are more optimistic than can be justified by actual
completion time.
Choice. The diversification heuristic (Simonson, 1990) is relevant in regard
to choice tasks, and is concerned with the degree of diversity in people’s
choices based on their need for variety. It was found that when asked to make
several choices at the same time, people tend to diversify, and they do so not
only for a simultaneous choice condition (i.e., choosing three courses in a
certain meal) but also for a sequential choice (i.e., choosing at a certain time
what to eat in sequential meals). It is clear that this heuristic is sensible under
the simultaneous condition, but less so under the sequential one. Ayal and
Zakay (2009) showed that people tend to choose the alternative that is per-
ceived to be more diversified, even when this actually reduces their chances
of maximizing utility.
Language. Some heuristics were defined even in the domain of language
comprehension. For example, instead of focusing on a mutual perspective
when communicating, people rely more on an egocentric interpretation,
which is fast and cheap in mental resources. Keysar et al. (2000) argued that
using such a process, which they called the egocentric heuristic, is successful
in reducing ambiguity, although it could lead to systematic errors.
Magical thinking. Some heuristics characterize magical thinking. One is the
contagion heuristic, which reflects the belief that when objects make physical
Motivation and Heuristic Thinking 293
they actually have (Trope, Gervey, & Liberman, 1997). It was found that per-
ceived vulnerability to risk is heavily influenced by the perceived control over
the risk (Zakay, 1984), and that people generally overestimate their level of
control over many kinds of risks (Bronwell, 1991) as well as their relative con-
trol, compared to their peers (Harris, 1996). Klar, Zakay, and Sharvit (2002)
examined whether such illusions of control were extended to the domain of
terrorism during a period of intense terrorist threat in Israel. It was found
that no illusion of control and comparative control were manifested regard-
ing the risk of being a victim of terrorist attacks. Again, the one who prefers
to take a lottery ticket in his/her own hand rather than be handed the card
is making an internal mistake of judgment, but is actually not harming one’s
actual chances of winning. On the other hand, in all of these examples and in
contradistinction to the cognitive biases, the motivational heuristics lead to
an obvious motivational gain – a higher feeling of control, better self-esteem,
and so forth.
The distinction between cognitive and motivational biases suggests that
the criticism and debate about the legitimacy of the term “biases” should be
treated in the context of motivational and cognitive biases. It seems, how-
ever, that making a distinction between cognitive and motivational heuristics
without referring to the nature of their outcomes is almost impossible. Both
types of heuristics are actually similar in terms of process. The distinction
between the two types is sensible only when the motivation to utilize them
and the degree of motivational gain associated with their outcomes are con-
sidered. Examples of “pure” cognitive heuristics are the “classic” ones such
as anchoring and adjustment or availability. “Naive optimism” can serve as
an example of a pure motivational heuristic. Naive optimism is responsible
for the tendency of people to assign higher probabilities to the occurrence
of positive events to themselves and people who are socially close to them
than to unknown people who are socially distant (Zakay, 1985). These judg-
ments are biased in cases for which occurrence probabilities are objectively
equal to anyone who belongs to a certain population. The motivational gain
associated with the outcomes of the naive optimism heuristic can be classi-
fied as a possible gain enhancing one’s feeling of well-being and self-esteem,
which in most cases might help adaptation. However, in some cases, such as
in the case of a potential illness, this can delay treatment and might be dan-
gerous for survival. It is of interest to note that naive optimism is activated
when there is a motivational threat involved with an unfavorable outcome.
However, when such a threat does not exist, for example when one has to
judge his/her chances of winning the lottery in comparison with the chances
of some unknown person, people tend to judge their own chances as lower.
Motivation and Heuristic Thinking 297
This might be due to the lack of any meaning that might threaten one’s ego or
self-esteem if he/she does not win the lottery. The outcome is still biased, but
this is a cognitive bias, most probably resulting from utilizing the availability
heuristic. Essentially, most people never win such a prize, but they read a lot
about unknown people who do win (Zakay, 1985). However, one cannot deny
the possibility that the motivation to avoid regret also plays some role in this
case. Therefore, it is plausible to think also about “mixed” biases, in which the
outcome is caused by an inappropriate cognitive process but also serves some
motivational goal.
one side of the coin, but on the other side, under many real-life conditions
the utilization of heuristics might yield maladaptive results, regardless of any
comparison to any “normative” criteria. Illustrations for this claim are pro-
vided by some metacognitive heuristics involved in the formation of the feel-
ing of knowing (Koriat, 1998) and the latency heuristic (Zakay & Tuvia, 1998)
involved in the emergence of the feeling of confidence (see previous section).
The criterion for the reliability of FOK is the existence of relevant knowl-
edge. This does not depend on any normative model, but simply reflects the
actual state of knowledge that one can retrieve from memory at a certain
point in time. The same holds for FOC, as feelings of overconfidence might
lead one to suboptimal behavior, as in the case of answering forced-choice
questions in examinations (Zakay & Glicksohn, 1992).
References
Allais, M. (1997). An outline of my main contributions to economic science. American
Economic Review, 87, 3–12.
304 Zakay & Fleisig
Ayal, S., & Zakay, D. (2009). Perceived diversification heuristic: the case of pseidodiver-
sity. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 96, 559–573.
Bazerman, M. H. (2006). Judgment in managerial decision making. New York: John
Wiley & Sons.
Breznitz, S. (1983). The denial of stress. New York: International Universities Press.
Bronwell, K. D. (1991). Personal responsibility and control over our bodies: When expec-
tation exceeds reality. Health Psychology, 10, 303–310.
Camerer, C. F., & Loewenstein, G. (2002). Behavioral economics: Past, present, future.
In C. F. Camerer, G. Loewenstein, & M. Rabin (Eds.), Advances in behavioral eco-
nomics (pp. 3–51). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Chronicle, E. P., MacGregor, J. N., & Ormerod, T. C. (2004). What makes an insight
problem? The roles of heuristics, goal conception, and solution recoding in
knowledge-lean problems. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory
and Cognition, 30, 14–27.
Chaiken, S., Liberman, A., & Eagly, A. (1989). Heuristic and systematic information pro-
cessing within and beyond the persuasion context. In J. S. Uleman & J. A. Bargh
(Eds.), Unintended thought (pp. 212–252). New York: Guilford Press.
Cohen, L. J. (1979). On the psychology of prediction: Whose is the fallacy? Cognition,
7, 385–407.
Davies, S. P. (2000). Memory and planning processes in solutions to well-structured
problems. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Experimental
Psychology, 53, 896–927.
Dorpat, T. L. (1985). Denial and defense in the therapeutic situation. New York: Aronson.
Epstein, S. (1994). Integration of the cognitive and the psychodynamic unconscious.
American Psychologist, 49, 709–724.
Fleisig, D., & Zakay, D. (2005). The confidence weighting heuristic: an explanation to the
overconfidence paradox. Unpublished manuscript. Tel-Aviv University (Hebrew).
Frederick, S. (2002). Automated choice heuristics. In T. Gilovich, D. Griffin, & D.
Kahneman (Eds.), Heuristics and biases (pp. 548–558). New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Freud, S. (1956). Inhibitions, symptoms and anxiety. In J. Strachey (Ed.), The standard
edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud (Volume 20, pp.
75–175). London: Hogarth.
Gigerenzer, G. (2006). Heuristics. In G. Gigerenzer & C. Engel (Eds.), Heuristics and the
law (pp. 17–37). Boston, MA: The MIT Press.
Gigerenzer, G., Hoffrage, U., & Kleinbolting, H. (1991). Probabilistic mental models: A
Brunswikian theory of confidence. Psychological Review, 98, 506–528.
Gigerenzer, G., & Todd, P. M. (1999). Fast and frugal heuristics: The adaptive toolbox. In
G. Gigerenzer & P. M. Todd (Eds.), Simple heuristics that make us smart (pp.3–34).
New York: Oxford University Press.
Gilbert, D. T. (2002). Inferential Correction. In T. Gilovich, D. Griffin, & D. Kahneman
(Eds.), Heuristics and biases. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Gilovich, T., & Griffin, D. (2002). Introduction – heuristics and biases: Then and now.
In T. Gilovich, D. Griffin, & D. Kahneman (Eds.), Heuristics and biases (pp. 1–18).
New York: Cambridge University Press
Goldstein, D. G., Gigerenzer, G., Hogarth, R. M., Kacelnik, A., Kareev, Y., Klein, G.,
Martignon, L., Payne, J. W., & Schlag, K. (2000). Why and when do simple heuristics
Motivation and Heuristic Thinking 305
work? In G. Gigerenzer & R. Selten (Eds.), Bounded rationality: The adaptive tool-
box (pp. 173–190). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Harris, P. (1996). Sufficient ground for optimism? The relationship between perceived
controllability and optimistic bias. Journal of Social and Clinical Psychology, 15,
9–52.
Jolls, C., Sunstein, C. R., & Thaler, R. H. (2007). A behavioral approach to law and eco-
nomics. In C. R. Sunstein (Ed.), Behavioral law and economics (pp. 13–58). New
York: Cambridge University Press.
Kahneman, D., & Frederick, S. (2002). Representativeness revisited: Attribute substi-
tution in intuitive judgment. In T. Gilovich, D. Griffin, & D. Kahneman (Eds.),
Heuristics and biases (pp. 49–81). New York: Cambridge University Press.
Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1979). Intuitive prediction: Biases and corrective proce-
dures. TIMS Studies in Management Science, 12, 313–327.
(1984). Choices, values and frames. American Psychologist, 39, 341–350.
(1996). On the reality of cognitive illusions. Psychological Review, 103, 582–591.
Keysar, B., Barr, D. J., Balin, J.A., & Brauner, J. S. (2000). Taking perspective in conversa-
tion: The role of mutual knowledge in comprehension. Psychological Science, 11(1),
32–38.
Klar, Y., Zakay, D., & Sharvit, K. (2002). “If I don’t get blown up. . .”: Realism in face of
terrorism in an Israeli nationwide sample. Risk Decision and Policy, 7, 203–219.
Koriat, A. (1993). How do we know that we know? The accessibility model of feeling of
knowing. Psychological Review, 100, 609–639.
(1998). Illusions of knowing: the link between knowledge and metaknowledge. In V.
Y. Yzerbyt, G. Lories, & B. Dardenne (Eds.), Metacognition: Cognitive and social
dimensions (pp. 16–34). London, England: Sage.
Koriat, A., & Levy-Sadot, R. (1999). Processes underlying metacognitive judgments:
Information-based and experience-based monitoring of one’s own knowledge. In
S. Chaiken & Y. Trope (Eds.), Dual-process theories in social psychology (pp. 483–
502). New York: Guilford Press.
Kruglansky, A. W. (1975). The endogenous-exogenous partition in attribution theory.
Psychological Review, 82, 387–406.
Kunda, Z. (1990). The case for motivated reasoning. Psychological Bulletin, 108,
480–498.
Lazarus, R. S. (1983). The costs and benefits of denial. In S. Breznitz (Ed.), The denial of
stress (pp. 1–30). New York: International Universities Press.
Lee, W. (1971). Decision theory and human behaviors. New York: John Wiley & Sons.
Monin, B. (2003). The warm glow heuristic: When liking leads to familiarity. Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology, 85, 1035–1048.
Muramatsu, R., & Hanoch, Y. (2005). Emotions as a mechanism for boundedly rational
agents: The fast and frugal way. Journal of Economic Psychology, 26, 201–221.
Nisbett, R. E., & Ross, L. D. (1980). Human inference: Strategies and shortcomings of
social judgment. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Peterson, C. R., & Beach, L. R. (1967). Man as an intuitive statistician. Psychological
Bulletin, 68, 29–46.
Rozin, P., & Nemeroff, C. (2002). Sympathetic magical thinking: The contagion and sim-
ilarity heuristics. In T. Gilovich, D. Griffin, & D. Kahneman (Eds.), Heuristics and
biases (pp. 201–216). New York: Cambridge University Press.
306 Zakay & Fleisig
Samuels, R., Stich, S., & Faucher, L. (2004). Reason and rationality. In I. Niiniluoto, M.
Sintonen, & J. Wolenski (Eds.), Handbook of epistemology (pp. 131–179). Dordrecht,
The Netherlands: Kluwer.
Schwarz, N., & Clore, G. L. (1988). How do I feel about it? Informative functions of
affective states. In K. Fiedler & J. Forgas (Eds.), Affect, cognition and social behavior
(pp. 44–62). Toronto: Hogrefe International.
Silvera, D. H., Josephs, R. A., & Giesler, R. B. (2002). Bigger is better: the influence
of physical size on aesthetic preference judgments. Journal of Behavioral Decision
Making, 15, 189–202.
Simon, H. A. (1957). Models of man: Social and rational. New York: Wiley.
Simonson, I. (1990). The effect of purchase quantity and timing on variety-seeking
behavior. Journal of Marketing Research, 28, 150–162.
Slovic, P., Finucane, M., Peters, E., & MacGregor, D. G. (2007). The affect heuristic.
European Journal of Operational Research, 177, 1333–1352.
Spence, D. P. (1983). The paradox of denial. In S. Breznitz (Ed.), The denial of stress
(pp. 103–123). New York: International Universities Press.
Stein, E. (1996). Without good reason. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Sunstein, C. R., Kahneman, D., & Schkade, D. (2007). Assessing punitive damages (with
notes on cognition and valuation in law). In C. R. Sunstein (Ed.), Behavioral law
and economics (pp.232–258). New York: Cambridge University Press.
Svenson, O. [Chapter, current book, pp. xxx]
Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (1995). ‘Foreword’ to S. Baron-Cohen, Mindblindness: An essay
on autism and theory of mind, (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press), pp. xi-xviii.
Trope, Y., Gervey, B., & Liberman, N., (1997). Wishful thinking from a pragmatic
hypothesis-testing perspective. In M. S. Myslobodsky (Ed.), The mythomanias: The
nature of deception and self-deception (pp.105–131). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum
Associates, Publishers.
Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1974). Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases.
Science, 185, 1124–1131.
Webster (1961). Webster’s third new international dictionary of the English language
(Unabridged). Hagen Westfalen: Koenemann.
Wilson, T. D., & Schooler, J. W. (1991). Thinking too much: Introspection can reduce the
quality of preferences and decisions. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
60, 181–192.
Yun Dai, D., & Sternberg, R. J. (2004). Motivation, emotion and cognition. Mah- wah:
Lawrence Erlbaum.
Zakay, D. (1984). The influence of perceived event’s controllability on its subjective
occurrence probability. Psychological Record, 34, 233–240.
(1985). Post-decisional confidence and conflict experienced in a choice process. Acta
Psychologica, 58, 75–80.
Zakay, D., & Fleisig, D. (2010). Heuristic thinking in judges’ decisions. Law & Business,
VOl. 12, pp. 91–116. Interdisciplinary Center, Herzeliya, Radzyner School of Law.
(Hebrew).
Zakay, D., & Glicksohn, J. (1992). Overconfidence in a multiple-choice test and its rela-
tionship to achievement. The Psychological Record, 42, 519–524.
Zakay, D., & Tuvia, R. (1998). Choice latency times as determinants of post-decisional
confidence. Acta Psychologica, 98, 103–115.
15
Ola Svenson
Introduction
Human decision-making researchers investigate people who make choices
between two or more alternatives, how the choices are made, and how they
deviate from predictions of normative models of rational behavior. Although
decisions are made in response to a decision maker’s needs reflected in her or
his motivation, discussions of motivation are rare in the mainstream decision
research literature; needs and motivation seem to be taken for granted with-
out any presentation or discussion of them.
To illustrate, two volumes summarizing the most important research
of judgment and decision making at the time (Arkes & Hammond, 1986;
Gilovich, Griffin & Kahneman, 2002) do not have a single reference to moti-
vation or even goal in their subject indices. Goldstein and Hogarth’s (1997)
edited volume includes 2 chapters out of 24 that briefly mention the con-
cept of motivation, and of the remaining 22 chapters only 1 has a reference
to goal – the other chapters do not treat either motivation or goal. However,
Schneider and Shanteau (2003) edited a volume with a whole chapter on
motivation, and several chapters including the concepts of motivation and
goal. Textbooks on psychology and decision making follow the main trend,
and they typically do not have motivation in their subject indices (e.g., Baron,
2008; Plous, 1993).
To be able to understand the role played by motivation in earlier traditional
mainstream behavioral decision-making research, it is necessary to uncover
hidden assumptions related to motivation. In process approaches to decision
making, the researchers are often more explicit about what motivates the pro-
cesses than in mainstream decision research.
The author wishes to thank Torun Lindholm, Ellen Peters, and Ilkka Salo for valuable comments
on an earlier version of this chapter.
307
308 Svenson
& Eagly, 1989, p. 293). Janis and Mann (1977) listed some major categories of
needs related to personal involvement that can activate goals and motivation.
They differentiated between the needs of (1) own utilitarian gains; (2) utili-
tarian gains for significant others; (3) need of self-approval; and (4) need for
social approval. All four types of needs are relevant to some extent in the most
important decisions that a person makes.
Svenson (1992) differentiated between four different kinds of decisions. He
ordered them on levels. Level 1 contains repeated, quick automatic decisions,
habits, and all decisions, which – when they are made – have no direct refer-
ence to values, needs, or goals. Most of the decisions in human lives belong
to this category, and many of them are not even experienced as decisions.
However, these decisions were once related to needs, values, and goals before
they became automated. That is, when the first of the repeated decisions were
made, they were made on higher levels and related to needs and goals.
Level 2 includes decisions with direct couplings to a dominating need,
value, or goal. The decisions on this level are motivated by a wish to approach
one particular goal state (e.g., to find the cheapest flight). Here, the decisions
may also be quick, as for example, when a positive or emotional reaction
with its origin in a need is elicited by one or several alternatives. Decisions on
this level may also take longer, and depend on more elaborate processing to
approach the goal.
On level 3, one finds decisions activating different needs, with different and
conflicting motivational forces as a result. There is not one alternative that
is better on all significant attributes. Most decision research has treated this
kind of decisions, which invite trade-offs between goals, resulting in deci-
sions depending on the relative strengths of different motivations to reach
these goals.
Level 4 decision making includes decisions with alternatives that are
actively created by the decision-makers themselves. This is sometimes a pos-
sible solution for a decision maker who is presented with a decision problem
that does not seem to offer any satisfactory solution at all.
occurrence. The alternative with the greatest long-run expected value should
be preferred even if there was only one decision to be made.
Equation (15.1) describes the expected value (EV) of one alternative with
two possible outcomes with probabilities p1 and (1–p1). The values of the out-
comes are denoted V1 and V2:
EV = p1 ⋅ V1 + (1–p1) ⋅ V2 (15.1)
This equation, originating from economic statistical theory, was translated
into a theory for human decision making by inserting U (subjective value or
utility) for V and ψ for p. The result was a theory that has dominated human
decision research for 50 years. Instead of EV, the subjective expected utility
(SEU) was used:
SEU = ψ1 ⋅ U1 + ψ2 ⋅ U2 (15.2)
SEU theory assumes that a decision maker can and is motivated to order
aspects characterizing the alternatives on a continuum of utility. Equation
(15.2) shows that a decision maker who makes even one single choice would
be motivated to calculate and decide according to a normative rule that was
developed to maximize the gain from repeated decisions. Thus, SEU theory
assumes that decision makers share the goal of maximizing their own utility
only, and that this motivates them to estimate the expected utility for each
alternative.
However, people do not follow SEU theory in most situations, and later
research has shown, for example, that ψ1 and ψ2 do not necessarily add to 1
and that the relation between value (e.g., money) and utility is not linear and
changes from one function to another when it passes from losses to gains
(Kahneman & Tversky, 1979). In many situations, decision makers satisfice
(select the first alternative that is good enough – satisficing) and do not
maximize (Simon, 1955). Although the facts against the SEU theory are over-
whelming, the model, empirical data deviating from it, and its relatives have
dominated behavioral decision research for half a century.
In multiattribute utility theory (MAUT), an alternative is represented by
aspects (e.g., SEK 35,000 a month, 40 km from home) on attributes (e.g.,
salary, distance to work). The model is an extension of the SEU model to the
multidimensional case with independent attributes. This kind of representa-
tion of decision alternatives is also used in most process theories.
SEU theory and variations of the fundamental theory model human deci-
sion making without any description of the psychological processes leading
to a decision. It only takes into account the decision problem and describes
the outcome of the decision. Such an approach to behavioral decision theory
Human Decision Making 311
has been called structural. There has been no explicit room for motivation in
this context. Instead, one may say that the empirical results have been used to
find out about the decision makers’ motivation (e.g., to maximize or satisfice)
even if motivation was not the focus of the research. When the results from
structural decision studies have been reported in terms of interindividual dif-
ferences, needs and motivation may be inferred hypothetically even if they
are not treated as such in the original work. To illustrate, a need of security
can be assumed to motivate decision makers who avoid taking risks. Risk
avoidance, risk taking, and conservatism have been explained as reflecting
personal strategies, and in general no elaborated analyses have been made
in terms of motivation. However, Cacioppo and Petty (1982) explain differ-
ences in decision making in terms of need for cognition motivating different
decision-making strategies. Webster and Kruglanski also address individual
differences and explain them in terms of need of cognitive closure (Webster
& Kruglanski, 1994).
There are different techniques for aiding and supporting decisions. Most
decision-aiding techniques use the MAUT model as the theoretical founda-
tion, and start the aiding process with an exploration of fundamental needs,
goals, and motivations of a client. The aim of this process is to find a common
utility scale on which all the different motives can be mapped.
Thus, Festinger identified the need of reducing cognitive dissonance and the
goal of cognitive consonance. The magnitude of dissonance determines the
strength of the motivation to reduce the dissonance. The magnitude of dis-
sonance depends on the importance of the elements that are dissonant and
the relative attractiveness of the non-chosen alternative to the chosen one. The
more important the elements and the greater the relative attractiveness of the
non-chosen alternative in comparison to the chosen alternative are, the stron-
ger the motivation to reduce cognitive dissonance. Festinger was only interested
in what happens after a decision, and paid no attention to what was happening
before a decision. So, contemporary SEU theory treated antecedents to a deci-
sion and the decision itself, but the Theory of Cognitive Dissonance only cov-
ered postdecision processes. This was also the case in the volume by Festinger
and collaborators who presented a number of empirical studies about a decade
after the first presentation of the theory (Festinger, 1964).
Festinger’s approach to studying postdecision processes was largely
ignored by mainstream decision researchers who concentrated their efforts
on investigating antecedents of a decision and the ensuing decision and not
the consequences of decisions. Furthermore, Svenson’s (1979) review of the
few process studies of decision making in the 1960s and 1970s did not have
one single reference to Festinger or any of the studies based on his theoretical
concepts.
In most process studies of decision making there is an assumption of a
process need to spend as little energetic effort as possible in a decision pro-
cess. This motivates a decision maker to use simplifying rules requiring less
information search and processing if this will not affect the decision qual-
ity in a serious way. In other situations, there may be a conflict between the
needs of spending as little energetic effort and of finding the best solution of
a decision problem, in turn leading to a trade-off between the corresponding
motivations.
Janis and Mann (1977) followed in the Festinger tradition, but they did not
agree with the focus on postdecision processes only. Instead, they claimed on
empirical grounds that even before a decision, processes such as bolstering
(selecting and interpreting information so that it supports the chosen alter-
native) take place. Janis and Mann concentrated their research on level-three
decisions and focused on the effects of motivational conflicts on decision
processes.
Human Decision Making 313
They used the term “psychological stress” “as a generic term to designate
unpleasant emotional states evoked by threatening environmental events or
stimuli” (Janis & Mann, 1977, p. 50).
There is always a need to avoid or decrease psychological stress, and this
motivates decision processes that are able to relieve the decision maker from
stress. Janis and Mann presented a number of ways in which the decision pro-
cess can be affected as a result of different ways of solving decision conflicts
under different conditions, activating other kinds of needs and motivations.
It is interesting to note that according to Janis and Mann, predecision reac-
tions to decision conflict, such as bolstering, are motivated by anticipatory
imagination of postdecision conditions. “We regard bolstering as one of the
most common forms of defensive avoidance, and we assume that it is moti-
vated primarily by a need to ward off the stress of postdecisional conflict
rather than by an invariable tendency to reduce cognitive dissonance” (Janis
& Mann, 1977, p. 85). This corresponds to the later concept of anticipated
postdecision regret (Zeelenberg, 1999), which is a fundamental motive mod-
eled as a negative cognitively based emotion experienced when imagining (or
realizing) that the outcome of a decision would have been better after another
choice.
According to Svenson (1992, 2003, 2006), who continued the process tra-
dition with his Differentiation and Consolidation (Diff Con) theory, one goal
of a decision process is a chosen alternative that is sufficiently superior in
comparison to its closest competitor. If this is not the case from the begin-
ning, a “winning alternative” has to be created in different kinds of differen-
tiation processes. These processes start before the decision in differentiation
and continue beyond the decision and its implementation in consolidation
processes using different decision rules and changing mental representations
of evaluations and facts to arrive at a superior alternative.
There are at least two groups of process and representation needs motivating
differentiation and consolidation processes in Diff Con theory. The first group
relates to cognitive prototype “gestalt” factors. “This set of driving factors can be
related to predominantly cognitively driven explanations [Bem, 1967], to attribu-
tion theory [Kelley, 1967], and to self-serving biases [Greenwald, 1980]” (Svenson,
2003 p. 317). Also belonging to this set of factors is the need of dissonance reduc-
tion (Festinger, 1957), specified in terms of both predecision differentiation and
postdecision consolidation in Diff Con. The stability and safety motive belongs
to the second group of these needs-motivating differentiation and consolidation
processes: [It] is related to a safety or stability motive and refers more clearly to a
decision maker’s predictions of aspects, images, or scenarios in the postdecision
phase. This set of (motivating) components drives predecision differentiation in
314 Svenson
a process that is explicitly related to the future much more than the first set of
(motivating) factors. After a decision the same set of components drives consoli-
dation, so that in spite of adverse events and regret, the chosen alternative appears
or becomes sufficiently superior to its competitors (Svenson, 2003, p. 318).
(when the outcome was evaluated). Kahneman, Wakker and Sarin (1997)
distinguished between instantaneous utility (ongoing via sensory input),
remembered utility, predicted utility, and decision utility (at the time of the
decision). These interdependent utilities may create interacting motives at the
time of a decision. Mellers, Schwartz, and Ritov (1999) developed and tested
a theory that was centered around anticipated emotions as motivating deci-
sions. The decision affect theory by Schneider and Barnes (2003) went further
and investigated fundamental goals of decision makers, identifying eight dif-
ferent areas that were experienced as motivating their participants’ decisions.
Goals in these areas were elaborated and set into a context of essential motives
according to evolutionary and motivational theories. Krantz and Kunreuther
(2007) reintroduced goals and plans (Miller, Glanter, & Pribram, 1960) and
multiple goal-based models, and used it in their decision research in a very
fruitful way. They point out that one plan and its associated decision(s) may
satisfy several goals (and not just maximize a common value function) at the
same time, and that this is important when people make decisions.
For more than a decade, a number of structural-decision investigators have
shown an interest in fundamental motivation related to emotion. Affect and
emotion have been contrasted with cognitive evaluations and utility as moti-
vating decisions. Zajonc’s (1980) brought attention to the fact that affective
and emotional reactions can be extremely quick, and that they do not have to
be transmitted via elaborate cognitions. Zajonc’s 1980 paper was important
for decision researchers who started to include basic needs and motivations
in structural approaches. Another important influence for these researchers
was dual-process theories, in which a cognitive rational system and an emo-
tional affective system are assumed to work in parallel. An example of this is
Epstein (1994), who models an individual’s interaction with the environment
as transmitted by two different and parallel systems. The rational system is
a deliberative analytic cognitive system following rules of logic. The experi-
ential system perceives reality in an affective emotional way using feeling as
an important component. Although the systems work in parallel they also
interact.
As found by a number of decision researchers (e.g., Isen, 2000; Luce,
Bettman, & Payne, 1997), affect and emotion may influence process and rep-
resentation motivation (e.g., positive affect and mood are coupled with moti-
vation to search less information) and fundamental motivation (e.g., decision
makers in a positive affect and mood are motivated to recall and search more
information that is positive in relation to fundamental goals). Affect and emo-
tion can also influence fundamental motivations and the trade-offs between
them (e.g., under some conditions, security becomes a weaker motive and
316 Svenson
Concluding Remarks
In this chapter, fundamental motives have been distinguished from process
and representation motives. Other authors have presented similar distinc-
tions. To illustrate, Weinberger and McClelland (1990) differentiate between
cognitive motivation and more primitive motivation models. Samsone and
Harackiewicz (1996) present an overview of different motivation models and
differentiate between process and outcome motivation. For a long time, the
fundamental motives of a decision maker were considered to be self-evident
and never discussed in traditional decision theory and research. All funda-
mental motivations were assumed to be possible to evaluate in money or util-
ity and to be integrated into a general motivation to get as much money or
utility as possible in the long run, even if only a single decision was made.
Process and representation motivation was assumed to coincide with the laws
of logic and statistics. Empirical results showing that decision makers did not
follow these laws were described as human biases and heuristics. However,
quite early, individual differences in terms of risk aversive or risk prone
behavior were included as motivating decisions.
In contrast, process-oriented decision researchers had a lot to say explicitly
about motivation, but most of their interest concerned process and repre-
sentation motivation and not much was said about fundamental motivation.
Much of the process-oriented research was focused on the solution of con-
flicts between different motives in a decision situation.
318 Svenson
Around 1990, the roles played by affect and motivation regarding decision
making were brought into focus by structural decision researchers; thereaf-
ter, it became an important topic for many researchers. However, it is easier
to differentiate affect and emotion from cognitive processes in theory than
in empirical research, and there is yet much work to be done concerning this
issue. Generally speaking, decision research has emphasized the creation of
cognitive congruence between motives and decisions (Simon, Snow, & Read,
2004), postulated maximization of expected personal utility, acknowledged
the effect of emotional and affective motivation in parallel with motivation
grounded in cognitive processes, and pointed out the trade-off between
needs of high-quality decisions and resource preservation (e.g., time, effort).
At present, it seems as if decision research is slowly leaving the prison of a
too-strong theory and moving into theoretical and empirical research driven
by decision makers’ motives, their own realities and psychological decision
processes, and not by a theory that cannot be refuted. This is a promising
trend for future developments of decision research.
References
Arkes, H. R., & Hammond, K. R. (1986). Judgment and decision making: An interdisci-
plinary reader. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Baron, J. (2008). Thinking and deciding (4th edition). Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Beach, L. R. (1990). Image theory: Decision making in personal and organizational con-
texts. Chichester: Wiley.
Bem, D. J. (1967). Self perception: An alternative interpretation of cognitive dissonance
phenomena. Psychological Review, 74, 183–200.
Cacioppo, J. T., & Petty, R. E. (1982). The need for cognition. Journal of Personality and
Social Psychology, 42, 116–131.
Connolly, T., Ordonez, L. D., & Coughlan, R. (1997). Regret and responsibility in the
evaluation of decision outcomes. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision
Processes, 70, 473 485.
Edwards, W. (1954). The theory of decision making. Psychological Bulletin, 41, 380–417.
Epstein, S. (1994). Integration of the cognitive and the psychodynamic unconscious.
American Psychologist, 49, 709–724.
Festinger, L. (1957). A theory of cognitive dissonance. Stanford California: Stanford
University Press.
(1964). Conflicts, decision and dissonance. Stanford CA: Stanford University Press.
Finucane, M. L., Peters, E., & Slovic, P. (2003). Judgment and decision making: The
dance of affect and reason. In S. L. Schneider & J. Shanteau (Eds.), Emerging per-
spectives on judgment and decision research (pp. 327–364). Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Frisch, D., & Jones, S. K. (1993). Assessing the accuracy of decisions. Theory and
Psychology, 3, 115–135.
Human Decision Making 319
Gilovich, T., Griffin, D., & Kahneman, D. (2002). Heuristics and biases: The psychology of
intuitive judgment. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Goldstein, W. M., & Hogarth, R. M. (1997). Research on judgment and decision making:
Current connections and controversies. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Greenwald, A. G. (1980). The totalitarian ego: Fabrication and revision of personal his-
tory. American Psychologist, 35, 603–618.
Isen, A. M. (2000). Positive affect and decision making. In M. Lewis & J. M. Havieland
(Eds.), Handbook of emotions (2nd ed., pp. 417–435). London: Guilford.
Janis, I. L., & Mann, L. (1977). Decision making. New York: Free Press.
Johnson, B. T., & Eagly, A. H. (1989). The effects of involvement on persuasion: A meta
analysis. Psychological Bulletin, 106, 290–314.
Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1979). Prospect theory: an analysis of decisions under
risk. Econometrica, 47, 263–291.
Kahneman, D., Wakker, P., & Sarin, R. (1997). Back to Bentham? Explorations of experi-
enced utility. The Quartely Journal of Economics, 112, 375–406.
Kelley, H. H. (1967). Attribution theory in social psychology. In D. Levine (Ed.), Nebraska
Symposium on Motivation (Vol. 15, pp. 192–238). Lincoln: University of Nebraska
Press.
Krantz, D. H., & Kunreuther, H. C. (2007). Goals and plans in decision making. Judgment
and Decision Making, 2, 137–168.
Kwong, J. Y. Y., & Leung, K. (2002). A moderator of the interaction effect of procedural
justice and outcome favourability: Importance of the relationship. Organizational
Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 87, 278–299.
Loewenstein, G., & Schkade, D. (1999). “Wouldn’t it be nice?” Predicting future feelings.
In D. Kahneman, E. Diener, & N. Schwartz (Eds.), Well-being: The foundation of
hedonic psychology (pp. 85–108). New York: Russel Sage.
(1996). Out of control: Visceral influences on behavior. Organizational Behavior and
Human Decision Processes, 65, 272–292.
Loewenstein, G., Weber, E. U., Hsee, C. K., & Welch, E. S. (2001). Risks as feelings.
Psychological Bulletin, 127, 267–286.
Luce, M., Bettman, J., & Payne, J. W. (1997). Choice processing in emotionally difficult
decisions. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory and Cognition,
23, 384–405.
Mellers, B., Schwartz, A., & Ritov, I. (1999). Emotion-based choice. Journal of
Experimental Psychology: General, 128, 332–345.
Miller, G., Galanter, E., & Pribram, K. (1960). Plans and the structure of behavior. New
York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.
Montgomery, H. (1998). Decision making and action. The search for a dominance struc-
ture. In M. Kofta, G. Weary, & G. Sedek (Eds.), Personal control in action. Cognitive
and motivational mechanisms (pp. 279–298). New York: Plenum Press.
Payne, J. W., Bettman, J. R., & Johnson, E. J. (1993). The adaptive decision maker.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Plous, S. (1993). The psychology of judgment and decision making. New York:
McGraw-Hill.
Samsone, C., & Harackiewicz, J. M. (1996). “I don’t feel like it”: The function of inter-
est in selg-regulation. In L. L. Martin & A. Tesser (Eds.), Striving and feeling (pp.
203–228). Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum.
320 Svenson
Schneider, S. L., & Barnes, M. D. (2003). What do people relly want? Goals and con-
text in decision making. In S. L. Schneider & J. Shanteau (Eds.), Emerging per-
spectives on judgment and decision research (pp. 394–427). Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Schneider, S. L, & Shanteau, J. (2003). Emerging perspectives on judgment and decision
research. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Simon, H. A. (1955). A behavioral model of rational choice. Quarterly Journal of
Economics, 69, 99–118.
Simon, D., Snow, C. J., & Read, S. J. (2004). The redux of cognitive consistency theories:
Evidence judgments by constraint satisfaction. Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology, 86, 814–837.
Svenson, O. (1979). Process descriptions of decision making. Organizational Behavior
and Human performance, 23, 86–112.
(1992). Differentiation and consolidation theory of human decision making: A frame
of reference for the study of pre- and postdecision processes. Acta Psychologica, 80,
143–168.
(2003). Values, affect, and processes in human decision making: A differentiation
and consolidation theory perspective. In S. L. Schneider & J. Shanteau (Eds.),
Emerging perspectives on judgment and decision research (pp. 287–326). Cambridge:
Cambridge University press.
(2006). Pre- and post-decision construction of preferences: Differentiation and con-
solidation. In S. Lichtenstein & P. Slovic (Eds.), The construction of preference (pp.
356–371). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Tetlock, P. E. (1992). The impact of accountability on judgment and choice: Towards
a social contingency model. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, 25,
331–376.
Weber, E. U., & Johnson, E. J. (2009). Mindful judgment and decision making. Annual
Review of Psychology, 60, 53–85.
Webster, D. M., & Kruglanski, A. W. (1994). Individual differences in need for cognitive
closure. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 67, 1049–1062.
Weinberger, J., & McClelland, D. C. (1990). Cognitive versus traditional motivational
models: Irreconcilable of complementary? In E. T. Higgins & R. M. Sorrentino
(Eds.), Handbook of motivation and cognition: Foundations of social behavior (pp.
562–597). New York: Guilford.
Zajonc, R. B. (1980). Feelings and thinking: Preferences need no inferences. American
Psychologist, 35, 151–175.
Zeelenberg, M. (1999). Anticipated regret, expected feedback and behavioural decision
making. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 12, 93–106.
16
Introduction
Knowledge Management suffers in some way from the fact that economic
decisions in many cases rest upon incomplete information. Far too often one
believes in the correctness of decision calculi, for example, Decision Support
Systems (DSS), and is at a loss if one needs experience in order to evaluate
consequences and correct the actions (considered to be meaningful because
they are supported by calculations or computations). What is missing is addi-
tional knowledge stemming from expertise; that is, an understanding of the
signals (or the meaning of those signals) that come from experience – signals
that help select good solutions and eliminate bad ones, insofar as we consider
our expectations. These signals provide constraints to generate solutions that
are acceptable both on a personal as well as societal (i.e., ethical and cultural)
levels. As will be seen, one can argue for an interesting parallel to Jerome
Bruner’s (1990, p. 4) ideas concerning the need for a second cognitive revolu-
tion. Bruner seems to be very unhappy about the replacement in psychology
of the “construction of meaning” by the algorithmic/computational “process-
ing of information” in the first cognitive revolution.
The developments in Knowledge Management took a similar course.
Instead of constructing meaning (for details, see following information) in
psychology, it was, and in Knowledge Management it still is, important to
construct the inherent/intrinsic knowledge (based on information and exper-
tise in use) in order to explain, for example, the competitive advantages of
enterprises. In Knowledge Management, knowledge is therefore considered
to be essential in order to explain the economic success of an enterprise. It is
understood that the missing knowledge could not be brought about simply
by the monetary means to organize a firm.
321
322 Born & Gatarik
ideas – is to argue and draw conclusions in such a way that the validity of the
inference can be justified. The point here is that those means of justifying the
validity of an inference are not necessarily literally descriptive of the causal
mechanisms governing our brain-states and their transitions as far as the
logical/formal side of thinking is studied. Why does this matter in our con-
text? The question is of particular significance in view of Gödel’s insistence
that the mind can do more than a computer, at least in abstract mathematical
thinking, or, as Hilary Putnam (1981) claimed: reason can transcend whatever
reason can formalize.
As far as cognition is concerned, let us consider the fact (see the drum-
mer’s example, 9.3) that we think we were successful in calculating some of
the information that an individual may have available in the situation, and
that we know how it is encoded in the sign system/language in use at the
level of that individual. In that case, we might be able to test our hypotheses
by presenting to that individual meaningful signs (although calculated with
formal means). We may test our hypotheses with respect to expected or pre-
dicted reactions. We may be able to predict reactions, reactions that could not
be explained just mechanically, but as we think presuppose the working of a
mind. Bruner (1990, p. 5) argued that a normal, mechanical, or plainly algo-
rithmically working system cannot deal for example with “vagueness, with
polysemy, with metaphoric or connotative connections” and other essential
matters in daily life. Therefore, the construction of meaning/processing of
knowledge or information need the “extra kick” of a mind, just as semantics
is more than syntax. However, the essential point of the picture has not yet
emerged. What is essential is that our means to calculate meaningful signs
are a technical or reconstructive means to reproduce the meaningfulness
of those signs (i.e., the cognitive part of formal/syntactical means). Those
means, however, are not necessarily literally descriptive as the “reality guys
seem to assume,” according to Bruner,4 just as logic when applied to a mathe-
matical proof reproduces the validity of a mathematical theorem with respect
to the mathematical/structural presuppositions.
So, the means to reproduce the meaningfulness (but not an understand-
ing of the message per se) will not necessarily be the means employed by an
individual to produce the information encoded in those signs in order to
behave properly in the situation under investigation. The last and perhaps
most important point, however, seems to be the following (see Figure 16.1):
Even if we are successful in making good predictions of the behavior of
some individual, we have to consider the pre-experience of that individ-
ual, the soil upon which the seeds of information fall that gives meaning to
those calculated items of information. Wittgenstein (1953, p. 38) insists that
Cognitive Science and Knowledge Management 327
+ ==>
Reactions/
(Special) Information/signs
behaviour
situation (s) (knowledge)
(predictions)
seems to have been well aware of the problem and addressed it (as mentioned
above) in the following way: “We understand abstract terms more and more
precisely as we go on using them.” This use of the abstract terms belongs to the
building up of experiences, the construction of meaning in Bruner’s terms,
which cannot be achieved simply by “following the rules” (Wittgenstein, 1952,
§ 190a) in the sense of instantiating algorithms to produce meaningful signs
and sentences.
To our mind, Gödel’s message can be reformulated as trying to become
intimate with some mental matters (e.g., abstract concepts), and this will lead
to some kind of new insights that can guide our behavior (e.g., the applica-
tion of information in the light of those experiences), our use of the signs,
and will also produce a new use according to some agreed-upon shorthand.
Winterson (1995, pp. 79–80) expresses the same idea in the following way:
“Communication between you and me relies on assumptions, associations,
communalities and the kind of agreed shorthand, which no-one could pre-
cisely define but which everyone would admit exists. It would seem that for
most of us, most of the time, communication depends on more than words.”
In other words, the signs are abbreviations for some new practices that can-
not simply be built up in following rules but that need to be established by
some kind of intimacy6 with a topic that essentially rests upon what may be
described as the possibility of “reflective correction.” Taking up the quote from
Winterson, one could say the agreed-upon shorthand establishes a new prac-
tice, a new tie, a new form of life, in the sense of Wittgenstein’s Philosophical
Investigations.
This kind of practical knowledge need not be computational; it cannot be
reproduced with formal/syntactical means alone. It will become to be pos-
sible to see this only in pragmatical ways, however, taking into account the
application, context, and use of processed information. On the other hand,
it may well be possible to use it in many cases in everyday life, reducing the
application of knowledge to rules and taking into account what all people
have in common insofar as epistemic presuppositions are considered.
Thus, the problem is how can we build up knowledge, how can we com-
municate information in such a way that successful applications of knowl-
edge are guaranteed? Needless to say, responsibility comes in here, and ethics
in a more general way, as well. The technique to convey information in the
sense that it has to rest upon experience is essential, however (and not only
for being able to deal with abstract mathematical concepts). One chance to
build up meaning differently might be found in the technology of virtual
reality, but the direction of development in connection with information
Cognitive Science and Knowledge Management 329
Bruner’s Proposal
Bruner’s (1990, p. 11) proposal for a sort of reassessing of the cognitive revolu-
tion is to “return to the question of how to construct a mental science around
the concept of meaning and the processes by which meanings are created and
negotiated within the community.” One of Bruner’s critical remarks is that:
Information processing [especially in the context of preparing for and provid-
ing material for decision making etc.] cannot deal with anything beyond well-
defined and arbitrary entries that can enter into specific relationships that are
strictly governed by a program of elementary operations. Such a system can-
not cope with vagueness, with polysemy, with metaphoric or connotative con-
nections. . . . Information processing needs advance planning and precise rules
(Bruner, 1990, p. 5).
The classes that did correspond to some concepts had to consist of elements
that had to have something in common all by themselves.9 Later on, with the
advent of modern science, it became clear that they did not need to literally
correspond to reality and have something in common all by themselves.
Can we find new concepts or maps/charts/models to fulfill our urge for
mixing causality and logic effectively, providing us with a new computation-
alism? Or are those concepts due to some research programs in cognitive
science just a gleam in Paul Churchland’s eyes, as Hilary Putnam (1992) once
put it? Or can we find a compromise, something such as Dennett’s “inten-
tional stance” in a different guise? Sometimes we know that we are caught by
perceptual deceptions, but the perceptions stay on – we cannot easily change
our way of seeing the world.
If one looks at the graphic in Figure 16.2 as a plane and is told that the
straight line from Madrid to New York is longer than the curved one just
above it in the figure, one might easily mistrust this statement. One “sees”
immediately that this cannot be correct if one looks at the map as a bidimen-
sional object, which metaphorically speaking is governed by the grammar
of Euclidean geometry in our modern understanding. If, on the other hand,
the description of one line as above the other refers to the globe, one can
easily see that Madrid and New York are approximately on the same circle of
latitude and that another geodesic indicates a shorter distance if you want,
for example, to fly. Your decision to follow the route of the straight line on a
334 Born & Gatarik
long-distance flight may prove to be disastrous if you run out of gas, the
amount of which might have been calculated by someone else who thought
you would fly along the geodesic. So the inference from the map to guide
your actions using everyday imagination might be wrong with respect to
your aims. Could you really provide an argument within everyday language
to convey both the meaning and the validity of Figure 16.2, an argument that
is not dependent on visualization, extra knowledge, and experience and still
helps us survive in the situation above? There would then be a host of argu-
mentative gaps to be filled up by intuition or common experiential and men-
tal background knowledge. In any case, we do have to step out of the picture
just as in the case of the solution of linking the 9 points (in Figure 16.3) by 4
lines without lifting the pencil.10
P Q
Figure 16.4. The background knowledge E applied to the problem P yields a solution Q.
P Q* Q
Figure 16.5. The rule system K applied to the problem P under the presupposition of
the background knowledge E yields the solution Q*.
you how they did it. Now, there is a standard technique to ask for an exact doc-
umentation: One expects that with the help of this documentation one could
reproduce the given results. Looking at the matter superficially this sounds
correct. The problem, however, is that in many cases this kind of documenta-
tion is produced by the experts themselves, that is, from within the world of
their experience. On the other hand, we are quite often unaware how docu-
mentations really work. In many cases, they consist of signs whose meaning
or interpretation presuppose the existence of some experience E – the latter
produces reference to reality (i.e., it is constitutive for meaning and practically
relevant and therefore action-guiding). This can be understood in such a way
that the experts – and in many areas of our daily life we are all experts with
respect to our own personal experiences – in some sense establish rules that
enable them to reproduce their positive results in a controlled manner.
Reflecting on and explaining success has led to the construction of a set of
rules K with whose help one can explain the coming about of [Q*] and even-
tually reproduce the set [Q*] (presupposing that the conditions of production
remain constant). In Figure 16.6, we depicted the situation visually by using
the arrow from E → P for describing the original application of knowledge E
to produce a concrete solution Q* (or a possible one Q), but now by way of a
detour via K, i.e., we replaced the original path from E → P by a detour via K,
i.e., E → K → P → Q or <K|E> (P) → Q [K under the condition of E applied to
P to produce Q].
338 Born & Gatarik
Experience/
E
Knowledge-Roles
Keep:
constructions/rules/routines Commonsensical
automations/calculi/ background
documentations knowledge
K F Users
P Q* Q
Figure 16.6. Implicitly, this graphic rests upon the following assumption: First-person
experiential E-Knowledge can be used by every individual F and by every computer with
the same logic K to produce the same results Q*. E contains the implicit first-person
knowledge of experts and in the classical case it is fostered implicitly. Such that one can
then talk about “implicit knowledge management.”
DIGITALIZATION
evaluation
Reasons ; H & S computation R EFFECTIVE
EXPLANATIONs KNOWLEGDE
M E
The Scissors
Common Sense
of
Dialogue
Knowledge Life C
K F
Q??
[Q*]
Q?
causation
Causes ; P Q* Q
action
[Q]
Figure 16.7. [Q*] denotes the (equivalence) class of the predetermined concrete/actual
results Q*.
they have not lost sight of the limits of their expertise!), experts who are using
experiential knowledge E and rules K. The rectangle in Figure 16.7 is a sym-
bol for the amount of concrete solutions [Q*] under the knowledge condition
F. This set [Q*] symbolizes the equivalence class of predetermined possible
concrete results Q*, insofar as the latter are brought about by F background
knowledge by using the routines K.
As one can see from Figure 16.7, there can be cases of accepted results
(in sign: Q?), which cannot be reproduced with rules and routines K and
background knowledge F alone. Still, they are accepted as meaningful by the
experts E, (i.e., E-acceptable and therefore elements of the ellipse [Q]). There
are also cases (in sign: Q??), however, which can be produced by stubbornly
and mechanically (i.e., by instantiating some algorithm) following the rules/
routines with the help of F, but which are not accepted by the original experts
E (but later on and occasionally they may be reconstructed via K and E plus
some extra knowledge F* or even E* and motivation).
In order to explain the possible difference between the sets [Q] and [Q*],
eventually, the term “implicit knowledge” (available in E) was introduced.
Originally, Michael Polanyi used it in some more or less general scientific
context. Later on, the idea was reintroduced by Nonaka and Takeuchi as “tacit
knowledge” in the context of administrative business to explain the economic
success of certain Japanese enterprises. Their use of the term seemed to imply
that tacit knowledge could be explicated completely, and led knowledge man-
agement of the first generation astray into a technical information-processing
system (also Bruner’s qualms about cognitive science in the first place).
However, motivation (in F) can change common-sense knowledge F in
such a way (toward an enriched F*) that solutions Q*, which are brought
about by applying F* to the rules K, can be incorporated into [Q], but not
necessarily into [Q*]. As we can learn from Damasio and his brain research,
we can find out that F* is more than a cognitive enrichment of pre-given
common-sense knowledge F. F* (and furthermore, also E* as an enrichment
of E) also depends on feelings/emotions based on experience.
In Figure 16.7, one can also see how the difference between the extension
of the sets [Q] and [Q*] can be explained with the help of using different
components of background knowledge (i.e., either E or F). In explanatory
terms, we call this matter the “scissors of knowledge,”15 and in operational
terms, the “scissors of life (expertise).”16 Such an explanation must not rest
solely upon the inner (plainly cognitive) understanding of E (reconstructed
in M), however. In many cases, E corresponds to something such as spe-
cial and intensive experiences of a first person E (an ego) with a very spe-
cial epistemic resolution level (based on an inseparable interplay of cognition
Cognitive Science and Knowledge Management 341
A C
[3rd person] / singular
(formal) [2nd person] (material/concret)
check-Lists / routines /
rules / documentations user- /& action-guiding-
K knowledge of rules knowledge F
everyday knowledge,
ideologies, CULTURE
Causality
Causes P Q
A CT I N G
State-Transistions
Problems Results / solutions
[quest]
ought to be considered in their complexity but need not be taken into account
all of the time. When we first introduced the basics of LIR, we invented a
surrealistic example concerning the production of poetry with the help of
computer programs and what would be needed to fake an understanding of
the meaning of poems. At the time, the example was well ahead of technical
practice, but Max Black thought it well described the reality of the refereeing
system in poetry journals. The essential point with respect to the scheme LIR
in Figure 16.8 was an evaluation function from K to M such that structure
models in M – in the classical way of Tarskian Semantics (Bridge, 1977) –
could be used to evaluate the meaningfulness of poems in a strictly technical
way. Namely, that meaning would not literally be expressed but only some-
how coded. This would be in contrast to the real-flesh referees in a journal
who have to evaluate poems by understanding their content, so to speak, and
express their ideas about the meaning of those poems. The point was: What
would happen if the referees were replaced by some evaluation program in
M? In which way would the explanatory encoding of meaning be used to
freeze a certain fashion of the time, and when would a revolution by the next
generation of poets occur? A careful analysis shows that in the last count, the
same strategy was successful in programming the chess program Deep Blue,
but the point is that meaning or the evaluation of situations in a game of chess
is frozen, which further links up with Gödel’s point against Turing (i.e., that
meanings can evolve). In Gödel’s case, the intimateness with abstract math-
ematical terms and their application lead to a new understanding essential
for proper application. In the case of Deep Blue, we do not even know what
it really is that has been grasped by an evaluation function. What would hap-
pen if we used Deep Blue as an experts’ system to train chess students? In a
medical-experts system this is quite clear. If students are trained just by the
system and have no chance to learn corrective experience from outside, even-
tually they will be just as good as the program. If the medical-experts system
has, say, a success rate of 80 percent, the remaining 20 percent will somehow
get lost “in real life.”
There is, however, another even more ironic illustration of the scheme that
may somehow be considered as a “reductio ad absurdum” of the picture of
simply transferring natural science to studying the mind, especially meaning
in this case. A parallel idea is the following: Could we find out the meaning of
messages sent by drums without having contact with the people or being able
to communicate with them in another way except by drums? The only tech-
nical means allowed would be video cameras and special microphones as well
as loudspeakers to fake the noise of drums and watch the reaction behavior of
the addressees. Essential would be the difference between meaning as expli-
cated with the help of M and the meaning of the drumming noises as given to
346 Born & Gatarik
the sound by the experts E who use the drums. When do we think we would
be justified to say that some model in M has grasped the meaning of those
noises? Grasping can be used in a theoretico-explanatory manner as well as
literally in a descriptive way. It is essential to take into account the interplay of
the two – of both the theoretical and vernacular (background) knowledge –
which does not really happen in cognitive science nor in classical knowledge
management when dealing only with the administration of information (or
indirectly, of knowledge).
deconstruct those conceptions, one can test the Internet as a possible means
of extending cultural evolution.
We have to take care that the ideas to be transmitted fall onto a soil that has
already been prepared. We need to have prior knowledge; we already have to
have made experiences of our own in order to understand the signs of oth-
ers. When knowledge is passed on through learning, it is reassembled from
knowledge bricks.
The question now is what an evolutionist point of view is able to contrib-
ute to an understanding of the role of the Internet in further developing and
improving our cultural evolution, for instance, in view of initiating a new
phase of evolution. What, if anything, can be better understood, described,
and predicted insofar as the development of a global information network
through the Internet is concerned?
In cultural evolution, ideas are passed on for a better adaptation to the
environment. Yet, they are not so much concrete ideas that can be passed on
in a narrative but rather a kind of concept kernels. In analogy to the concept
of the gene, Dawkins (2006) introduces the term “meme” to denote elements
of cultural evolution, which are supposed to function in a way similar to the
transmission of genetic material in a gene.
Concept kernels/cores (and meaning environments) have the advantage
of enabling us to grasp different situations under one common aspect or one
function and thus to adjust quickly to similar situations. We are able to rec-
ognize a wheel and we have certain expectations about its functioning. Yet in
a different situation we can replace it with casters and move a heavy ward-
robe that way. We have grasped the essence of the concept “wheel.” Yet what
is responsible for a successful conveyance of the meaning of concepts that
denote environments and core competencies?
The real problem of cultural evolution is the passing on of experience/
expertise (not the passing away, as it may sometimes seem). Knowledge has
to be conveyed in a way that makes it useful in decisive decision situations.
Genetic knowledge can only be corrected in the long run, through muta-
tion or the dying out of a species. In contrast, external knowledge should be
open for correction. It should be possible to avoid mistakes in the replica-
tion of knowledge by individuals, collective or artistic reflection, or those due
to accidental mistakes. We consider this to be essential because nowadays
we think a lot about how knowledge may get conveyed with the help of the
Internet. However, knowledge in most cases gets transferred as texts. Hence,
the medium is primarily a syntactic means to convey knowledge. Could we
go as far as to say, metaphorically speaking, that knowledge is computed in
the Net and thus conveyed? Where are the real limits? What is really going
348 Born & Gatarik
on and how does it work? These are the questions that need to be resolved if
humans are to play the role of active agents rather than that of victims.
Notes
1. Emphasizes in quotes are ours, if not stated differently.
2. Today, we would say “algorithmic.”
3. Thus, computing became the means to produce meaningful signs and was consid-
ered to be the means to build up meaning (especially expertise).
4. Personal communication by Jerome Bruner to Rainer P. Born at the conference
“Reassessing the Cognitive Revolution”, Glendon College, York University, Toronto,
October 22–24, 1993. The reality guys are the ones who take the mechanical or other
procedures to stimulate meaning-making processes for real or rather descriptively.
5. http://www.iwp.jku.at/born/mpwfst/06/LIR_engl_230607.ppt.
6. A. de Saint-Exupéry (1991). The Little Prince, pp. 63–64: “I cannot play with you,”
the fox said. “I am not tamed.” . . . “What does that mean – tame?” “It is an act too
often neglected,” said the fox. “It means to establish ties.” . . . “Just that,” said the fox.
“To me, you are still nothing more than a little boy who is just like a hundred thou-
sand other little boys. And I have no need of you. And you, on your part, have no
need of me. To you, I am nothing more than a fox like a hundred thousand other
foxes. But if you tame me, then we shall need each other. To me, you will be unique
in all the world. To you, I shall be unique in all the world.”
7. Cf. the scissors of knowledge in chapter 8 and the scheme LIR in chapter 9.
8. We consider three postulates: 1. Our concepts are (with respect to reality) somehow
fuzzy (according to an extensional cutting up of the world). 2. Our charts, mod-
els, theories are usually incomplete (in the reality, there may turn up cases that are
accepted but neither justified nor predicted by theory). 3. Our theories are neither
literally descriptive nor definitely action-guiding.
9. Think about the term “game.” What do all games have in common (Wittgenstein)
and how can language game produce “meaning”?
10. Usually, people search for the solution just within the set of 9 points. The way, in
which we drew the graphic, shows that those 9 points are embedded in the 16 points.
These can be considered as a solution space, where one can see the solution con-
cerning the connection of the 9 points without lifting the pencil. In this case, one
stays within the solution space!
11. Q stands for quest (e.g., in quest of the holy grail, still being searched for).
12. M (explanatory knowledge) ← E (expertise, emotion/motivation)
13. “Sense-making” concerns models to orientate ourselves in the world.
14. [Q] is defined as the set of “possible” solutions (sometimes possible according to
assumptions/presuppositions).
15. The “Scissors of Knowledge” in the scheme LIR roughly concern the different influ-
ence of the knowledge components K (rules) and M (explanatory meta-knowledge/
principles) on the coming about and acceptance of problem solutions [Q] and [Q*].
After splitting up expertise E into a cognitive/explanatory knowledge component
M and the action-guiding part of the original expertise E based upon emotion and
motivation, one can thus explain the difference between the sets [Q] and [Q*] by
Cognitive Science and Knowledge Management 349
References
Barwise, J., & Perry, J. (1998). Situations and attitudes. Stanford, CA: Center for the Study
of Language and Information.
Beth, E. W. (1962). Formal methods: An introduction to symbolic logic and to the study of
effective operations in arithmetic and logic. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.
(1965). Mathematical thought: An introduction to the philosophy of mathematics.
Dordrecht: D. Reidel.
Beth, E. W., & Piaget, J. (1966). Mathematical epistemology and psychology. Dordrecht:
D. Reidel.
Bohm, D. (2004). On dialogue. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Born, R. (1987). Artificial intelligence: The case against. London: Routledge & Kegan
Paul.
(1993). Sprache – Information – Wirklichkeit. In H. J. Schneider & R. Inhetveen (Eds.),
Enteignen uns die Wissenschaften? (pp. 141–178). München: Wilhelm Fink Verlag.
Bridge, J. (1977). Beginning model theory: The completeness theorem and some conse-
quences. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Brinton, C. (1967). Enlightenment. In P. Edwards (Ed.), Encyclopedia of philosophy (pp.
519–525). London: Crowell Collier and Macmillan.
Bruner, J. (1990). Acts of meaning: Four lectures on mind and culture. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
Buber, M. (2004). I and Thou. London: Continuum.
Cassirer, E. (1983). Kant’s life and thought. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Damasio, A. R. (2003). Looking for Spinoza: Joy, Sorrow, and the Feeling Brain. Orlando,
FL: Harcourt.
Dawkins, R. (2006). The selfish gene (3th ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
de Geus, A. (1997). The living company. Boston: Harvard Business School Press.
(2006). Learning together in teams. DVD: SOL Conference 2006 – Fire, passion and
excellence, Helsinki, 13./14.11.2006.
de Saint Exupéry, A. (1991). The little prince. London: Egmont Childrens Books.
Encyclopedia Britannica (2000). CD-Rom Version.
Frege, G. (1918). Der Gedanke – Eine logische Untersuchung. In G. Patzig (Ed.), Logische
Untersuchungen. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck, pp. 35–62
350 Born & Gatarik
(2009). The element: How finding your passion changes everything. New York: Viking
Penguin.
Sen, A. K. (2006). Identity and violence: The illusion of destiny. New York: W. W.
Norton.
Sennett, R. (2006). The culture of the new capitalism. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Schlick, M. (1979). Allgemeine Erkenntnislehre. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. 1st ed.:
1925.
(1985). General theory of knowledge. La Salle, IL: Open Court Publishing.
Wang, H. (1974). From mathematics to philosophy. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
(1988). Beyond analytic philosophy: doing justice to what we know. Cambridge, MA:
The MIT Press.
(1997). A Logical journey: From Gödel to philosophy. Cambridge, MA: The MIT
Press.
Winterson, J. (1995). Art objects: Essays on ecstasy and effrontery. London: Jonathan
Cape.
(2007). The stone gods. London: Hamish Hamilton.
Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
(1961). Gesammelte Schriften (Vol. I). Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.
17
In her most recent interview, 15-year-old L – comments: “Every year they ask
me, do I want to be a scientist? And, every year I tell them no, I don’t want to
be a scientist. I don’t like science. It’s not for me.” Yet participant observation
notes indicate that L – has been staying after the workshop every day to work
on her lab notebook and to help get materials ready for the next day. She also
uses this time to engage in discussions and to ask questions. She seems to like
thinking about connections between the day’s focus and those of previous days.
She appears to want to understand how the experiments they have been doing fit
together. (Interview, Year 5)
352
Interest and Cognition 353
354
• Are developing • Are very focused on • Recognize others’
knowledge of the their own questions contributions to the discipline
content • Actively seek feedback
• Are developing a sense
of the content’s value
Needs/More • To have their ideas respected • To have their ideas • To have their ideas • To have their ideas respected
Closed Learning • To feel genuinely appreciated respected respected • Information and feedback
Environment for their efforts • To feel genuinely • To feel genuinely • To balance their personal
• To have others understand how appreciated for their appreciated for their standards with more widely
hard work with this content is efforts efforts accepted standards in the
• Limited concrete suggestions • Support to explore their • To feel that their ideas discipline
own ideas and goals are understood • To feel that their ideas have
been heard and understood
Phases of Interest Development
Triggered Situational Maintained Situational Emerging Individual Well-Developed Individual
• Feedback that enables • Constructive feedback
them to see how their • Challenge
goals can be more
effectively met
Needs/More Open • To have their ideas respected • To have their ideas • To have their ideas • To have their ideas respected
Learning • To feel genuinely appreciated respected respected • Information and feedback
Environment for the efforts they have made • To feel genuinely • To express their ideas • To balance their personal
• To know that they understand appreciated for the • Not to be told to revise standards with more widely
the content efforts they have made present efforts accepted standards in the
• To know what they have • To feel that their ideas discipline
355
learned and what they and goals are understood • To feel that their ideas have
still want to learn • To feel genuinely been heard and understood
appreciated for their • Constructive feedback
efforts • Challenge
• Feedback that enables
them to see how their
goals were met
356 Renninger & Riley
The participant observation notes and her interviews indicated that she
thought about science the way she would think about anything else; she was
more philosophical than scientific.1 For example, her questions during the
week she and her workshop group learned about worms included: “What do
worms die from?” “What kind of culture do they have?”
Five years later, L – asked to be a teaching assistant in the Chemistry
Workshop, a position that had not previously existed.
Interest and Cognition 357
She was now aware that science was fun for her. After some deliberation, the
workshop programming was adjusted to allow her to help out with the younger
children as a peer tutor. She worked with the younger children alongside a col-
lege student. Even before the workshop addressed acid-base neutralization, and
only two weeks into the workshop, she asked to take an experiment further by
combining an acid and base and observing the resulting solution. The instructors
suggested that she share this idea with the group of children to whom she was
assigned. She did and engaged them all in thinking with her about each of the
trials (and, as it turned out, all of the other children’s groups decided to explore
this issue as well). (Notes, Year 5)
L – ’s thinking about science had clearly changed, as had that of her peers. She
had a broader perspective. She now focused on patterns in phenomena and
how they could provide explanation. She was willing to think about content
generally and to explore new materials.
The studies in which L – and her peers were participants focused on what
needs to be in place in order for children with little to no background knowl-
edge in a discipline to seriously engage and learn. Data from L – ’s partici-
pation in the workshops are congruent with those of her peers, and allow
consideration of the interplay between interest development and cognition.
For the first few summers of workshop participation, L – had a triggered situ-
ational interest in the scientific material. Her affect could be heightened; she
clearly was attending and had some questions, but it was not until the fourth
year that her phase of interest began to shift, signaled by her independent
efforts to understand.
Although L – was aware and engaging in the workshop during the first
several years, she had not yet made the kind of connection to science content
that leads to asking curiosity questions and wanting to seek out, reflect on,
and raise more questions. Thus, although L – and her peers engaged excitedly
at times in the inquiry-informed workshop activities (e.g., group work to dis-
sect a mink) during their first years, five weeks following the workshop they
only retained an impression that science could be fun, with little if any sci-
ence-related content (Renninger et al., 2008). It was not until L – shifted from
simply engaging with the activities of the workshop to focusing on think-
ing about and wanting to explore their content that her interest changed; her
interest shifted in relation to its shifting focus, her cognition.
theorizing, the relation between interest and cognition concerned the devel-
opment of attention. James (1890), for example, described interest in terms
of the organization of experience. He suggested that interest improved the
ability to discriminate, and noted that interest, along with practice, improved
attention. Baldwin (1911), on the other hand, described interest in terms of the
activities in which a learner engaged. He focused on the cognitive structures
that the learner brings to activity, the competence that is experienced, and its
accompanying affect. Dewey (1913) elaborated on this relation by suggesting
that interest was in the content itself, suggesting that the interest value of
activities was related to whether they led to continuous engagement. Finally,
Piaget (1968) linked interest to both cognition and motivation, suggesting
that, “Interest is the proper orientation for every act of mental assimilation”
(p. 34). Taken together, the early theorists suggested that interest organizes
experience and channels attention, and they highlighted the roles of both
knowledge and value as components of interest.
The differing (and complementary) foci of the early theorists on the rela-
tion between interest and cognition also characterize the discussions and
studies that followed. The research has focused on the role of interest in cog-
nitive processing; the text, task, or people who contribute to the generation of
interest; and the relation of knowledge and value as components of interest.
Findings from each are reviewed briefly.
children were more likely to play longer, use more types of play, shift between
types of play, employ more types of action, and repeat particular sequences
of action than with other objects that were familiar and of less interest. Krapp
and Fink (1992) replicated these findings, and in discussing them, pointed to
the differentiation of interest based on experience. They reported data show-
ing that two children engaged in interest with the same play object would not
necessarily engage the object similarly. They and Neitzel and her colleagues
(Neitzel, Alexander, & Johnson, 2008) also documented that the interest
object could serve as a transition object as children moved from one learning
context to another (e.g., from the preschool to kindergarten).
Another line of research on interest and attention focused more specifi-
cally on text. During the 1980s, two hypotheses emerged in studies of text: (a)
that increased interest might increase attention and lead to better memory
(Anderson, 1982); and (b) that increased interest might require fewer cogni-
tive resources for basic text processing, freeing up resources for higher-order
processing (Hidi & Baird, 1988; see Hidi 1990, 1995). In order to test these
hypotheses, McDaniel et al. (2000) conducted studies of undergraduates
reading stories that they rated as being of higher or lower interest. Their find-
ings confirmed that more interesting text requires fewer cognitive resources
than less interesting text, and that text-based interest results in qualitative dif-
ferences in the kind of information that is processed and encoded. In conclu-
sion, they suggested that optimal learning of text might require assignment
of study strategies aligned with the particular level of interest for text. As
with the studies of young children’s play, it appears that what was of interest
for one person was not necessarily of interest to another. This then indicated
that although interest might free up resources for higher-level processing,
the expectation that one topic, for example, would be of similar interest to all
students was not appropriate.
Renninger et al.’s (2002) findings corroborate the conclusions of McDaniel
et al. (2000) regarding likely processing differences and instructional needs
introduced by the presence of interest. Renninger et al. (2002) studied
within-student differences in both the reading of text and work with math-
ematics problems, using interviews, think-alouds, and artifact analysis.
Passages and problems presented to middle-school–aged students were indi-
vidualized with contexts of interest and adjusted for level of difficulty. Their
findings suggested that well-developed interest served as a scaffold for work-
ing with assigned tasks. It allowed students to focus on meaning and task
demands. Well-developed interest also appeared to mask the level of passage
and/or problem difficulty, enabling the students to persevere to work with
difficult tasks.
360 Renninger & Riley
& Harackiewicz, 2005) and demonstrate that when participants are asked to
write out an explanation of the importance of a task they are assigned, this
triggers interest for the task (Hulleman et al., 2008). Their work on achieve-
ment goals and interest is complemented by studies demonstrating that when
participants are provided with goals such as trying to become experts (Hidi
et al., 1998) or participating in a community (Cobb & Hodge, 2004; Nolen,
2007), that this, too, results in increased interest.
Research has also indicated that the quality of social interactions (eye con-
tact, verbalization) influences the experience of interest and whether interest
is generated (Thoman, Sansone, & Pasupathi, 2006). Talking together after an
activity, for example, was found to increase interest, and the responsiveness
of a listener was more powerful than differences in interest in determining
interest in the activity (Thoman et al., 2006). Findings such as these further
extend those from both studies of talent development, in which changes in
the teacher and music-student relationship have been documented, and those
pointing to a reciprocal relation between interest and identity development
(Krapp, 2007; Renninger, 2009).
Based on retrospective interviews with accomplished musicians, for exam-
ple, Sloboda (1996; see also Sosniak, 1990) reports that the musicians’ first
experiences included having fun with music without being pushed to be sys-
tematic or to have specific skills. The first teacher was ideally friendly and
enthusiastic, able to communicate well, and to share a love of music. The
teachers could be said to be triggering and helping to maintain their students’
interest. As the prospective musicians were ready to focus on skill acqui-
sition, Sloboda notes that they also required more support from others to
sustain their skill development and positive feelings. During this phase of
instruction, many of their peers decided not to continue to study music. This
was a time when Sloboda observes that both teachers and parents encounter
difficulty knowing how to provide music students with support. In terms of
interest theory, they could be said to have difficulty helping music students
maintain their situational interest for music. Those who continue to study
music reportedly came to identify with music, and eventually studied with
a master teacher who enabled them to become artists. In other words, their
interest had developed to the point that they identified as musicians. With
interest, they were better able to self-regulate and needed less oversight than
they had in earlier phases of interest.
In describing the interest experience, Sansone and Thoman (2005a,
2005b) suggest that motivation and interest fluctuate in relation to the value
a person places on the goals of particular activities and any expectations
about attaining those goals. They suggest that interest can be regulated both
362 Renninger & Riley
suggested that there was a linear relation between interest (defined as positive
affect) and prior knowledge. He concluded that interest made more of a con-
tribution to comprehension and emotional associations than prior knowl-
edge, but also observed that as students develop familiarity, the development
of knowledge could be assumed. In an investigation of undergraduates in sta-
tistics and psychology classes, Lawless and Kulikowich (2006) examined this
premise and reported that interest (defined as affect) and knowledge were
correlated with each other regardless of domain. They also found that the
relation between interest and domain knowledge changed based on academic
level and preparation. Consistent with these findings, Alexander (1997, 2004)
described interest development in terms of developing expertise. Although
she described the relation of affect and cognition as distinct across each of the
stages of developing expertise, she and her colleagues began to use liking and
participation (which requires knowledge) to make distinctions between types
of interest (Alexander, 2004).
Schiefele and Krapp’s (1996; see also Krapp, 2003, 2007; Krapp & Prenzel,
2011; Schiefele, 2009) work has increasingly centered on feelings and value in
their discussion and assessment of interest, although they, too, have begun
to acknowledge the role of experience or knowledge in the development of
interest. Feelings and value are considered essential to personal significance:
“Positive evaluation results from the degree of identification with the object
of interest” (Krapp, 2003, p. 63). Krapp (2003) explains that although a per-
son may learn something new without being aware of this growth (and, as
such, knowledge), they are aware of personal significance. For this reason,
he argued that emphasis on feelings and value in interest development is
needed.
Summary
The relation between interest and cognition has been examined in terms of
attention and cognitive processing, characteristics of the learning environ-
ment, and the components of knowledge and value. Each of these foci points
to the impact of differences in interest. The work on attention and cogni-
tive processing suggests individual variation in the types of questions and/or
topic interest of the learner. The work on the characteristics of the learning
environment calls attention to the role of others and objects as supports for
engagement and likely differences in learners’ needs for support in their inter-
est development. The work on knowledge and value as components of inter-
est underscores potential differences in the contributions of each to interest
and also to their coordination as interest develops.
364 Renninger & Riley
How interest develops within individuals and how interest can be supported
to develop are critical questions for interest research. Although research on
interest generation or sources of interest has pointed to one or another poten-
tial triggers for interest, these studies have largely been descriptions of par-
ticular phases without consideration of what learners need in order to shift
from one phase of interest to another and begin asking curiosity questions,
seeking resources, and making use of feedback. As a result, learners such as
L –, who initially have little to no interest for learning content such as sci-
ence, pose a challenge for educators as well as researchers. Their interest can
be triggered, but little interest means little affect and/or knowledge. As they
age, they develop greater awareness that others have more developed skills
with respect to particular content than they do, making it even more difficult
for them to persevere to master that content even though it is possible for
them to do so (see discussion in Renninger, 2009). There is the possibility
that their attention, and as a result interest, can be triggered by some external
event (e.g., the excitement created by burning marshmallows and other foods
to see which burns faster), but it is also recognized that this type of triggering
may result in only momentary attention (Renninger et al., 2008). Sustaining
interest for unknown content and supporting engagement is difficult, because
there is too little knowledge to set goals or to know what questions to ask.
Happily engaging in an activity is not the same as reflecting on the content
of the activity, asking questions, exploring, and reorganizing understanding
(Flum & Kaplan, 2006).
Interest Development
Interest always refers to one or another of four phases in a learner or group
of learners’ cognitive and motivational engagement with particular con-
tent: triggered situational, maintained situational, emerging individual, and
well-developed individual interest (Hidi & Renninger, 2006; see Table 1).
Interest may reference a domain such as science or a more focused topic such
as structure and function, and always co-exists with a number of other inter-
ests and potential interests.
People typically think of the most developed phase – well-developed indi-
vidual interest – when they reference interest. Learners with a well-developed
individual interest for science, for example, can be expected to be attentive,
goal-oriented, and strategic (Renninger, 2000). Their feelings or affect are
generally positive (Ainley, 2006); they have a sense of possibility (Markus
& Nurius, 1986); and they know that they can be successful (Bandura, 1997).
Learners with developed interest have enough knowledge about their subject
Interest and Cognition 365
of interest to make effective choices (Flowerday & Schraw, 2003), and they
need little prodding to take advantage of opportunity and make use of the
feedback they receive (Lipstein & Renninger, 2007). When faced with the
need to revise a plan or practice, they persevere (Prenzel, 1992). As their
interest continues to develop, they are increasingly likely to self-identify with
the discipline – to think of themselves as someone who can do science, and as
someone who could be a scientist (Renninger, 2009). In the classroom, how-
ever, learners in this phase of interest are exceptions. For example, in a study
of 178 academically oriented middle school students, only 4 students were
identified as having a well-developed individual interest for writing (Lipstein
& Renninger, 2007). The other students were almost equally likely to be in
one of the three earlier phases of interest development.
Lipstein and Renninger (2007) used structured in-depth interviews and
questionnaires to compile representative descriptions or portraits of students
in each phase of interest development for writing. Here, these characteris-
tics are compared to those of L – and to data chronicling her engagement
in the science workshops.2 Comparison of the writing students’ experiences
with those of L – and her peers in the science workshops provides further
insight into the relation between interest development and cognition. The
experiences:
a topic of interest (e.g., basketball), but their interest was also likely to extend
only to completing the task. They did not identify as writers and would not
revise what they wrote, and for the most part they wanted to be told what to
do. They did not want to have to think about or work with feedback. Although
they might have heightened affect when their interest was triggered – when
working to write about basketball, for example – they were not aware that
their interest had been triggered, and did not seem to have enough knowl-
edge about writing to make choices about how to effectively provide details
and organize the information that they included about basketball.
Over the first three years of the workshop, L – is identified as having only
a triggered situational interest:
One day, for example, she and the other participants are looking at worms under
the microscope. At the end of the session, they put their worms back and as
everyone is packing up and preparing to leave, L – suddenly turns, runs back and
picks up a worm and takes it into the corner to look at it. Told that it is time to put
the worm back, she obliges but does not want to leave and sits on the steps of the
science building pouting. (Notes, June Year 1)
Similar to the student writer who had only a triggered situational interest
for writing but was momentarily excited to focus on an assignment to write
about basketball – a well-developed individual interest – L – experiences
heightened affect in the session focusing on worms and then does not follow
through to re-examine the worms in subsequent workshop sessions.
A few weeks later, during the week in the biology workshop on skulls, notes
on L – suggest that she chooses not to look at skulls or what animals they
must have come from based on size and teeth. Rather, she wanted to know if
“these [skulls] are real”; “how the skull fits with the rest of the animal”; and
“how it could move around.”
She had difficulty asking her questions though. She began to ask a question several
times, beginning with: “Not to be retarded or anything. . .” but had some difficulty
making herself clear and was seemingly frustrated by the other children talking. By
the time it was quiet enough for her to ask her first question, she initially forgot what
she was trying to ask but then remembered. Although the purpose of the activity
was identification of species, L – wanted to know about structure and function, and
how this one part of the animal fits with the other parts. (Notes, July, Year 1)
L – does not think of herself as a scientist and really only wants information
specific to her questions. Although her and her peers’ interest is triggered by
the worms and the skulls, she has difficulty learning with her peers. She has
trouble listening to others’ questions and issues and making her own connec-
tions to these as a member of the group.
Interest and Cognition 367
L – and her peers are not dependent on others in order to engage with the
content to be learned, but rather for making this content available to them
and supporting them to engage with it, even if what they engage with is not
necessarily what the instructors had anticipated as the focus of the activity.
368 Renninger & Riley
L – appeared able to refocus and explore her questions along with those of
the others in the hypothesis-generating and testing of their work to produce
colored lip gloss.
Differences between L – and the others are also evident. In addressing a ques-
tion about how sleep affects the amount of energy a person has, L – and her
peers decide that they should keep a sleep log over a long weekend, detailing the
times they go to sleep, wake up, and how they feel at each time point. No one
remembers to do this except L –, possibly because she thinks of the assignment
as an experiment, and the others think that it is work (like school). (Notes, July,
Year 4)
Lipstein and Renninger (2007) reported that it was only those with devel-
oped interest for writing who liked to work in groups. In earlier phases of
interest, the students in the writing classrooms primarily wanted to be told
what to do and were not interested in engaging in conversations about
options. They also had little interest for learning the canon, and little oppor-
tunity to generate the questions on which their writing would focus. They
were given opportunities to do “free writes” or choose the topic on which
they would write, but not only was the structure and the form of their writ-
ing specified, there were also expectations about format, development, and
content. The students who were in the phase of emerging individual interest
were described as wanting to establish autonomy so they could work on the
kind of writing that they themselves defined.
In the workshop context, L – not only helped develop the curriculum,
but was also free to refocus it with her questions. This type of context was
enabling (see related discussion in Cobb & Hodge, 2004). She generated curi-
osity questions based on her knowledge, the other things she knew and val-
ued, and her developing knowledge for this new content. This meant that
she needed less direct support to participate and engage than she did in the
earlier workshops, and less than the writing students needed. She also further
developed her willingness and ability to work with others, but she was con-
cerned about how she engaged with others in relation to the content of this
work and felt anxious about doing it correctly.
L – and her group were not constrained by the canon in science. They were
asked to generate questions and were encouraged to understand the science
in them. L – ’s approach to working with the younger children did suggest
that she had formed some sense of the way in which this work could unfold,
however. Presumably, her understanding was modeled on the way in which
her instructors had worked with her. 4
Neither L – nor the others in her group had yet reached the phase of well-
developed individual interest in her last year of workshops.
By the fifth year, when L – volunteers to work as a teaching assistant in the
Chemistry Workshop, she has a good understanding of what it means to do sci-
ence and its process and likes taking experiments one step further by testing addi-
tional substances or mixing chemicals. Moreover, she is able to help the younger
students to fill in the ICAN statements in their lab notebooks even though she is
not doing the experiments herself. (Notes, June, Year 5)
L – was not yet independently pursuing her own questions. Nor did she seem
aware that there were generally accepted disciplinary standards for science
beyond those of the workshop context. She appeared to need the support
of the workshop environment that provided resources and opportunities for
learning in order to know how her goals were met.
Not only do these data document a particular focus in her questioning over
the years, they reveal an increasing capacity to think and do science.5 They
also call attention to the time that this type of development can take, even
when the conditions of the learning environment include rich content, sup-
portive others, and opportunities to self-structure questions and engage. It
was four years before L – ’s interest began to shift from a triggered situational
interest to a maintained situational interest. It then took three weeks for her
interest to shift from a maintained situational interest to an emerging indi-
vidual interest.
The data from L – ’s case also highlight differences between learning envi-
ronments and the way in which learners engage content in each environ-
ment, and their needs in this process. As summarized in Table 17.1, L – and
her group seemed to benefit from and need additional information from
others, whereas in earlier phases of interest the student writers wanted to be
told only what they needed to know and no more – unless this information
acknowledged what they did. Only those student writers identified as hav-
ing a well-developed individual interest sought out and seemed positioned to
work with feedback.
There were differences in the participants’ perceptions of these learning
environments, in the goals and roles of the teachers and the instructors,
and in the backgrounds of the participants. Whereas the writing classrooms
focused on supporting the students to learn the rules of academic writing,
the science workshop environment was open-ended and did not have grades;
it was designed to promote fun and engagement with science. Although the
writing students’ teachers thought of themselves as supporting their students
in the same way that the instructors supported L – and her peers, this was not
the way that the writing students understood the expectations of their teach-
ers. The goals and roles of the workshop instructors changed, depending on
the activity and L – and her group’s responses; they provided information and
resources, asked and answered questions, stood back and allowed L – and her
group to explore, make mistakes, and reason.
The two groups of participants varied, as well. The writing students had
had instruction in writing throughout their schooling and came from fam-
ilies that valued education and had placed them in an academically ori-
ented school. L – and her group were learners new to science; only in the
last two years of the workshops had there been science instruction in their
schools; they came from families and a community with few or no scientists.
Although it is inappropriate to simply point to one or another feature of these
environments as accounting for differences, it is possible to note that the two
participant groups engaged content differently and that their perceptions
374 Renninger & Riley
Data from the writing students and those of L – and her peers also raise
questions about the interplay between interest development and cognition in
the learning environment. Is the interest of L – and her peers subject to the
kind of regression and possible change as that of the writing students? Is it
possible that L – and her peers have grown into thinking and doing science in
such a way that they internalize the questioning, predicting, experimenting,
modeling, applying, and identifying additional questions, and that these expe-
riences and the enjoyment of the process of engaging them cannot fall off?
Does what triggers interest vary if learners are free to respond to the oppor-
tunities and resources that are available to them, rather than feeling that their
engagement is controlled? Is it possible that in more open learning environ-
ments, learning does serve as a trigger for interest?
What are the differences in the nature of goals that learners set for them-
selves as opposed to those that are set for them? Could L – have developed
her interest for science without the group of peers who also participated in
the workshop – other learners who not only shared the experience but talked
with her about the workshop and listened to her?
When did L – start to realize that she was indeed learning science? What
were the supports that were in place for her that made a difference? How dif-
ferent would the experience of the writing students have been had they been
participants in a more open learning environment – and would it have made
a difference if they had been in an earlier phase of interest for writing?
How do knowledge and feelings work together to provide a basis for deep-
ening value? How do affect and value change as interest develops? What does
L – perceive science to be? What types of interactions would be needed in
order for L – to claim that she enjoys science or that she might want to be a
scientist?
L – ’s case and the experiences of her peers together with data from the writ-
ing students indicate that the phase of learner interest and his or her percep-
tions of the learning environment are likely to affect whether one or another
content is something to which to attend – how he or she engages and whether
interest is likely to develop. They also underscore the importance of knowledge
building and reflection as supports for and outcomes of interest development,
an interaction that is as critical for education as it is for theory and research.
Acknowledgements
We would like to acknowledge the role of many in the data reported in this chap-
ter and our thinking about it. We appreciate: the ongoing encouragement and
involvement of Elizabeth Vallen and the participants of the Science-for-Kids
Interest and Cognition 377
workshops over the years; the help of Jessica Bachrach, Robin Collin, Melissa
Emerson, and Alicia Niwagaba, who collected interview data and participant
observation notes that provided the basis of the data reported in this chapter;
editorial support from Nadine Kolowrat and Melissa Running; student fel-
lowship support from the Howard Hughes Medical Institute to Swarthmore
College; and for work on this chapter from the Swarthmore College Faculty
Research Fund.
Notes
1. Participant observation notes were collected continuously throughout the five
weeks of the workshop each summer; these were continuous anecdotal observa-
tional records (Carini, 1975) that were collected by one researcher who was blind to
study questions. The records chronicled instructors’ and participants’ conversations
and observable behaviors.
Interviews were conducted with workshop participants at three points during
each of the summers: before the workshop began, at the end of the workshop, and
five weeks following workshop completion. The interviews were used to identify
participant interest, feelings of self-efficacy, experience of the workshop, and abili-
ties to work with adaptations of established science tasks.
2. Data on L – ’s workshop participation included participant observation notes and
interviews before and after each of the workshops. The participant observation notes
consisted of running records of all classroom activities on each day of the workshop.
They chronicled instructor and participants’ conversations and behaviors. To the
extent possible, individual participation was systematically tracked. Following each
workshop session, the instructor(s) and the observer reviewed each day’s session,
at which time the observer adjusted the records to clarify confusion and/or record
additional information (e.g., things that happened on the other side of the room).
Identification of L – ‘s and her group’s phase of interest was informed by both the
interviews, whose questions were an adaptation of the questionnaire items com-
pleted by Lipstein and Renninger’s (2007) writing students, and by an adaptation
of Renninger and Wozniak’s (1985) analysis of young children’s behavioral records –
the likelihood of their voluntary reengagement, engagement overall, independent
engagement, and complexity of engagement.
3. ICANs (adapted from Chaconas; see Renninger & Nekoba, 2010) are a lab notebook
activity that involves reflecting on the concepts and skills of the day’s instructional
objectives in relation to those that have preceded. The day that the celery experi-
ment was set up, the ICAN probes in the lab books were:– I CAN use simple obser-
vations about light to explain why we see rainbows and why the sky is blue.
– I CAN use chromatography to find out what is in markers.
4. In other discussions, the workshop participants drew clear lines between school-
work and the workshops, along lines of the tasks, discipline, and interactions with
instructors.
5. Control data were collected and no such shifts were identified.
6. The workshop instructors were professors and their students in the particular field
of science (biology, chemistry).
378 Renninger & Riley
References
Ainley, M. (2006). Connecting with learning: Motivation, affect and cognition in inter-
est processes. Educational Psychology Review, 18, 391–405.
(2007). Being and feeling interested: transient state, mood, and disposition. In P. A.
Schutz & R. Pekrun (Eds.), Emotions in education (pp. 147–163). New York: Elsevier.
Alexander, P. A. (1997). Mapping the multidimensional nature of domain learning: The
interplay of cognitive, motivational, and strategic forces. In M. L. Maehr & P. R.
Pintrich (Eds.), Advances in motivation and achievement (Vol. 10, pp. 213–250).
Greenwich, CT: JAI Press.
(2004). A model of domain learning: Reinterpreting expertise as a multidimensional,
multistage process. In D. Y. Dai & R. J. Sternberg (Eds.), Motivation, emotion, and
cognition: Integrative perspectives on intellectual functioning and development (pp.
273–298). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Alexander, P. A., Jetton, T. L., & Kulikowich, J. M. (1995). Interrelationship of knowledge,
interest, and recall: Assessing a model of domain learning. Journal of Educational
Psychology, 87(4), 559–575.
Alexander, P. A., Kulikowich, J. M., & Jetton, T. L. (1994). The role of subject-matter
knowledge and interest in the processing of linear and nonlinear texts. Review of
Educational Research, 64(2), 201–252.
Anderson, R. C. (1982). Allocation of attention during reading. In A. Flammer & W.
Kintsch (Eds.), Discourse processing (pp. 292–335). Amsterdam: North-Holland.
Arnold, F. (1910). Attention and interest: A study in psychology and education. New York:
Macmillan.
Ashby, F., Isen, A., & Turken, A. (1999). A neuropsychological theory of positive affect
and its influence on cognition. Psychological Review, 106(3), 529–550.
Azevedo, F. S. (2006). Personal excursions: Investigating the dynamics of student engage-
ment. International Journal of Computers for Mathematical Learning, 11, 57–98.
(2011). Lines of practice: A practice-centered theory of interest relationships. Cognition
and Instruction, 29 (2), 147–184.
Baldwin, J. M. (1911). Thought and things: A study of the development of meaning of
thought (Vol. 1). New York: Macmillan.
Bandura, A. (1997). Self-efficacy: The exercise of control. New York: Freeman.
Barron, B. (2006). Interest and self-sustained learning as catalysts of development: A
learning ecology perspective. Human Development, 49, 193–224.
Bartlett, F. C. (1932). Remembering: A study in experimental and social psychology. New
York: Cambridge University Press.
Bergin, D. (1999). Influences on classroom interest. Educational Psychologist, 34(2), 87–98.
Berlyne, D. (1960). Conflict, arousal, and curiosity. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Brophy, J. (1999). Toward a model of the value aspects of motivation in education:
Developing appreciation for particular learning domains and activities. Educational
Psychologist, 34(2), 75–85.
Carini, P. F. (1975). Observation and description: An alternative methodology for the inves-
tigation of human phenomena. Grand Forks, ND: North Dakota Study Group on
Evaluation.
Chen, A., & Darst, P. (2001). Situational interest in physical education: A function of
learning task design. Research Quarterly for Exercise and Sport, 72(2), 150–164.
Interest and Cognition 379
Hidi, S., & Baird, W. (1988). Strategies for increasing text-based interest and students’
recall of expository texts. Reading Research Quarterly, 23(4), 465–483.
Hidi, S., & Renninger, K. A. (2006). The four-phase model of interest development.
Educational Psychologist, 41(2), 111–127.
Hidi, S., Weiss, J., Berndorff, D., & Nolan, J. (1998). The role of gender, instruction and
a cooperative learning technique in science education across formal and informal
settings. In L. Hoffmann, A. Krapp, K. A. Renninger, & J. Baumert (Eds.), Interest
and learning: Proceedings of the Seeon conference on interest and gender (pp. 215–
227). Kiel, Germany: IPN.
Hulleman, C. S., Durik, A. M., Schweigert, S. A., & Harackiewicz, J. M. (2008). Task val-
ues, achievement goals, and interest: An integrative analysis. Journal of Educational
Psychology, 100(2), 398–416.
James, W. (1890). The principles of psychology. London: Macmillan.
Katz, I., Assor, A., Kanat-Maymon, Y., & Bereby-Meyer, Y. (2006). Interest as a moti-
vational resource: Feedback and gender matter, but interest makes the difference.
Social Psychology of Education, 9, 27–42.
Krapp, A. (2003). Interest and human development: An educational-psychological per-
spective. British Journal of Educational Psychology Monograph Series, Development
and Motivation, 57–84.
(2007). An educational – psychological conceptualization of interest. International
Journal of Educational and Vocational Guidance, 7, 5–21.
Krapp, A., & Fink, B. (1992). The development and function of intrests during the crit-
ical transition from home to preschool. In K. A. Renninger, S. Hidi, & A. Krapp
(Eds.), The role of interest in learning and development (pp. 397–431). Hillsdale, MJ:
Erlbaum.
Krapp, A., & Prenzel, M. (2011). Research on interest in science: Theories, methods, and
findings. International Journal of Science Education, 33(1), 27–50.
Laukenmann, M., Bleicher, M., Fuβ, S., Gläser-Zikuda, M., Mayring, P., & Rhöneck,
C. (2003). An investigation on the influence of emotions on learning in physics.
International Journal of Science Education, 25, 489–507.
Lawless, K. A., & Kulikowich, J. M. (2006). Domain knowledge and individual inter-
est: The effects of academic level and specialization in statistics and psychology.
Contemporary Educational Psychology, 31, 30–43.
Lipstein, R., & Renninger, K. A. (2007). “Putting things into words”: 12–15-year-old stu-
dents’ interest for writing. In P. Boscolo & S. Hidi (Eds.), Motivation and writing:
Research and school practice (pp. 113–140). New York: Kluwer Academic/Plenum
Press.
Markus, H., & Nurius, P. (1986). Possible selves. American Psychologist, 4, 954–969.
McDaniel, M. A., Waddill, P. J., Finstad, K., & Bourg, T. (2000). The effects of text-based
interest on attention and recall. Journal of Educational Psychology, 92(3), 492–502.
Mitchell, M. (1993). Situational interest: Its multifaceted structure in the secondary
school mathematics classroom. Journal of Educational Psychology, 85, 424–436.
Neitzel, C., Alexander, J., & Johnson, K. E. (2008). Children’s early interest-based activi-
ties in the home and subsequent information contributions and pursuits in kinder-
garten. Journal of Educational Psychology, 100(4), 782–797.
Nolen, S. B. (2007). Young children’s motivation to read and write: Development in
social contexts. Cognition and Instruction, 25, 219–270.
Interest and Cognition 381
Palmer, D.H. (2009). Student interest generated during an inquiry skills lesson. Journal
of Research in Science Teaching, 46(2), 147–165.
Panksepp, J. (1998). Affective neuroscience: The foundations of human and animal emo-
tion. New York: Oxford University Press.
Piaget, J. (1968). The mental development of the child. In D. Elkind (Ed.), Six psycholog-
ical studies by Jean Piaget (pp. 3–73). New York: Random House.
Prenzel, M. (1992). The selective persistence of interest. In K. A. Renninger, S. Hidi, & A.
Krapp (Eds.), The role of interest in learning and development (pp. 71–98). Hillsdale,
NJ: Erlbaum.
Renninger, K. A. (1990). Children’s play interests, representation, and activity. In R.
Fivush & K. Hudson (Eds.), Knowing and remembering in young children (pp. 127–
165). New York: Cambridge University Press.
(2000). Individual interest and its implications for understanding intrinsic motiva-
tion. In C. Sansone & J. M. Harackiewicz (Eds.), Intrinsic and extrinsic motiva-
tion: The search for optimal motivation and performance (pp. 375–407). New York:
Academic.
(2009). Interest and identity development in instruction: An inductive model.
Educational Psychologist, 44(2), 1–14.
(2010). Working with and cultivating interest, self-efficacy, and self-regulation. In D.
Preiss & R. Sternberg (Eds.), Innovations in educational psychology: Perspectives on
learning, teaching and human development (pp. 107–138). New York: Springer.
Renninger, K. A., Bachrach, J. E., & Posey, S. K. E. (2008). Learner interest and achieve-
ment motivation. In M. L. Maehr, S. Karabenick, & T. Urdan (Eds.), Social psy-
chological perspectives Volume 15: Advances in motivation and achievement (pp.
461–491). Bingley, UK: Emerald Group.
Renninger, K. A., Ewen, E., & Lasher, A. K. (2002). Individual interest as context in
expository text and mathematical word problems. Learning and Instruction, 12,
467–491.
Renninger, K. A., & Hidi, S. (2002). Student interest and achievement: Developmental
issues raised by a case study. In A. Wigfield & J. S. Eccles (Eds.), Development of
achievement motivation (pp. 173–195). New York: Academic Press.
(2011). Revisiting the conceptualization, measurement, and generation of interest.
Educational Psychologist, 46(3), 168–184.
Renninger, K. A., & Lipstein, R. (2006). Come si sviluppa l’interesse per la scrittura;
Cosa volgliono gli studenti e di cosa hannobisogno? [Developing interest for writ-
ing: What do students want and what do students need?] Età Evolutiva, 84, pp.
65–83.
Renninger, K. A., & Nekoba, W. (2010, September). Identifying the phase of student
interest in mathematics for a study of classroom practices for at-risk students. Paper
presented at the meetings of the International Conference on Motivation, Oporto,
Portugal.
Renninger, K. A., Ray, L. S., Luft, I., & Newton, E. L. (2005). Coding online content
informed scaffolding of mathematical thinking. New Ideas in Psychology, 23,
152–165.
Renninger, K. A., Sansone, C., & Smith, J. L. (2004). Love of learning. In C. Peterson &
M. E. P. Seligman (Eds.), Character strengths and virtues: A classification and hand-
book (pp. 161–179). New York: Oxford University Press.
382 Renninger & Riley
Renninger, K. A., & Su, S. (2012). Interest and its development. In R. M. Ryan (Ed.),
Oxford Handbook of Motivation (pp. 167–187). New York: Oxford University Press.
Renninger, K. A., & Wozniak, R. H. (1985). Effect of interest on attentional shift, recogni-
tion, and recall in young children. Developmental Psychology, 21(4), 624–632.
Sansone, C. (2009). What’s interest got to do with it?: Potential trade-offs in the
self-regulation of motivation. In J. P. Forgas, R. Baumiester, & D. Tice (Eds.),
Psychology of self-regulation: Cognitive, affective, and motivational processes (pp.
35–51). New York: Psychology Press.
Sansone, C., & Thoman, D. B. (2005a). Does how we feel affect what we learn?: Some
answers and new questions. Learning and Instruction, 15, 507–515.
(2005b). Interest as the missing motivator in self-regulation. European Psychologist,
10(3), 175–186.
Schiefele, U. (2009). Situational and individual interest. In K. Wentzel & A. Wigfield
(Eds.), Handbook of Motivation at School (pp. 197–222). New York: Routledge.
Schiefele, U., & Krapp, A. (1996). Topic interest and free recall of expository text.
Learning and Individual Differences, 8, 141–160.
Senko, C. M., & Harackiewicz, J. M. (2005). Achievement goals, performance and
task interest: Why perceived difficulty matters. Personality and Social Psychology
Bulletin, 31, 1739–1753.
Silvia, P. J. (2005a). What is interesting? Exploring the appraisal structure of interest.
Emotion, 5, 89–102.
(2005b). Emotional responses to art: From collation and arousal to cognition and
emotion. Review of General Psychology, 9, 342–357.
(2006). Exploring the psychology of interest. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Sloboda, J. A. (1996). The acquisition of musical performance expertise: Deconstructing the
“talent” account of individual differences in musical expressivity. In K. Ericsson (Ed.),
The road to excellence: The acquisition of expert performance in the arts and sciences,
sports, and games (pp. 107–126). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Inc.
Sosniak, L. A. (1990). The tortoise, the hare, and the development of talent. In M. Howe
(Ed.), Encouraging the development of exceptional skills and talents (pp. 149–164).
Leicester, UK: British Psychological Society.
Springer, M. (2006). Soundings: a democratic student-centered education. Westerville,
OH: National Middle School Association.
Thoman, D. B., Sansone, C., & Pasupathi, M. (2006). Talking about interest: Exploring
the role of social interaction for regulating motivation and the interest experience.
Journal of Happiness Studies, 8, 335–370.
Tobias, S. (1994). Interest, prior knowledge, and learning. Review of Educational Research,
64, 37–54.
Tsai, Y. M., Kunter, M., Lüdtke, O., Trautwein, U., & Ryan, R. M. (2008). What makes
lessons interesting? The role of situational and individual factors in three school
subjects. Journal of Educational Psychology, 100(2), 460–472.
Turner, S. A., Jr., & Silvia, P. J. (2006). Must interesting things be pleasant? A test of com-
peting appraisal structures. Emotion, 6, 670–674.
Yamuchi, L. A., Wyatt, T. R., & Carroll, J. H. (2005). Enacting the five standards for
effective pedagogy in a culturally relevant high school program. In A. E. Maynard
& M. I. Martini (Eds.), Learning in cultural contexts: Family, peers, and schools (pp.
227–245). New York: Kluwer.
18
Anastasia Efklides
Introduction
The perspective in this chapter is on the relations of metacognition with cog-
nition, affect, and motivation in the context of school learning. The framework
within which these relations will be explored is that of self-regulated learning
(SRL; Boekaerts, 1999; Winne, 2004; Zimmerman, 1998). Extant SRL theories
posit various phases in SRL starting with the thoughts, motivation, and activ-
ities preceding the execution of a task to those during and, finally, to those
following the execution of the task (e.g., Zimmerman, 1998). In this concep-
tualization of SRL, person characteristics at the trait level (that is, motivation
and person characteristics that influence the person’s involvement in SRL),
metacognition (mainly in the form of strategies for the control of cognition)
as well as self-reflection and self-evaluation process are advocated.
However, the theoretical approach adopted here, namely the Metacognitive
and Affective model of Self-Regulated Learning (the MASRL model, Efklides,
2011), differs from other approaches because it draws attention to the meta-
cognitive and affective aspects of the person’s interaction with the task at
hand (Task x Person), that is, the subjective experiences the person has in
relation to learning tasks as cognitive processing takes place. Subjective expe-
riences during cognitive processing are influenced by and in their turn influ-
ence person characteristics and motivation as well as control decisions. Such
an approach to SRL brings together the person’s situational, momentary, and
changing experiences that are associated to a specific learning task and its
processing with the relatively stable and general person characteristics imply-
ing that cognition, metacognition, affect, and motivation act in synergy in the
person’s short- and long-term SRL.
The learning situations to which the MASRL model applies can be shown
through the following examples: (1) A student is working on a mathematical
383
384 Efklides
problem, solves it, and feels confident that the solution produced was the
proper one; (2) a student feels difficulty during mathematical problem solv-
ing, solves the problem correctly (or incorrectly), and feels uncertain about
the correctness of the solution; (3) a student refuses or avoids getting involved
in problem solving because the problem is unfamiliar or novel; and (4) a stu-
dent produces a solution to a mathematical problem but avoids reflection
on the feelings experienced during problem solving. In all these examples,
the following questions are raised: Which is the nature of the feelings stu-
dents experience in relation to the task at hand? How are task-related expe-
riences and reactions formed? Are they related to motivation and affect or
only to cognitive processing? Do such task-specific subjective experiences
and reactions influence the person’s short- and long-term SRL? The position
taken here is that these subjective experiences are metacognitive in nature
(i.e., metacognitive experiences) and inform the person on the progress
that is being (or has been) made toward achieving the learning goal posed.
Moreover, it is posited that metacognitive experiences are related to both
motivation/affect and cognition, and form an indispensable part of both the
short- and long-term SRL.
This claim is based on the idea that metacognition (i.e., monitoring and
control of cognition) cannot be effective unless it is guided by the goal(s)
the person pursues. Monitoring of cognitive processing – that is, monitor-
ing whether processing is fluent and leads to the attainment of one’s goal –
is crucial for both effort regulation and strategy use to achieve the goal(s)
set (Efklides, 2006). Effort regulation is determined by cognitive processing
demands as well as by metacognitive awareness of these demands. It is also
determined by motivation and affect – that is, the drive that gives direction and
energizes behavior and action (Efklides, 2007). Thus, in the self-regulation of
behavior and action (Carver & Scheier, 1998; Kuhl, 1985; Kuhl & Fuhrmann,
1998), both the metacognitive and affective regulatory loops are contributing.
Usually, each regulatory loop is studied by researchers on its own, without
considering the links between them; metacognitive experiences, however,
provide such a link (Efklides, 2006, 2011).
To sum up, the MASRL model (Efklides, 2011) serves two goals: to high-
light the interrelations of person characteristics as traits (including moti-
vation), functioning at what is called the Person level with metacognitive
experiences – that is, metacognition functioning at what is called the Person
× Task level; and to highlight the interrelations of metacognitive experiences
with affect and their impact on short- and long-term SRL. In what follows, I
shall briefly refer to SRL and then to the various facets of metacognition, one
of which is metacognitive experiences. The role of metacognitive experiences
Metacognition and Affect in School Context 385
in SRL will then be pointed out and, particularly, their interaction with moti-
vation and affect. Finally, the implications of the proposed MASRL model for
the conceptualization of the role of metacognition in SRL will be discussed.
Self-Regulated Learning
There is no doubt that school learning involves acquisition of content knowl-
edge as well as skills that form a very significant part of cognition. However,
learning is an effortful, long-lasting process in which previous acquisitions
form the building blocks for new higher-order and more-demanding learning
to be achieved. Moreover, learning requires awareness of thinking and its reg-
ulation, so that learning goals are attained. Consequently, learning requires
not only knowledge acquisition and knowledge restructuring but also per-
sistence and effort expenditure in face of adversity. For this to occur, motiva-
tion and positive affect are required (Aspinwall, 1998; Efklides, 2007; Efklides
et al., 2006) as well as metacognition and volition (i.e., self-regulation) to
secure action against distracters or obstacles (Kuhl, 1985; Kuhl & Fuhrmann,
1998). However, in the SRL process, we need to distinguish a Person level
that involves person characteristics functioning at a more general level and
determines what the person brings into various learning situations (long-
term SRL) and a Task x Person level; that is, what the person actually does
and feels during specific task processing (short-term SRL). These two levels
are depicted in Figure 18.1.
Before looking at the specific features of the MASRL model, some basic
components of SRL will be pointed out based on extant research. These com-
ponents will be presented from the perspective of the MASRL model, partic-
ularly in connection to its levels. Specifically, motivation in learning contexts
may take various forms, ranging from basic needs such as autonomy, com-
petence, and relatedness (Ryan & Deci, 2000) to expectancy-value beliefs
(Wigfield & Eccles, 2000) and achievement goal orientations (Nicholls, 1984;
Thrash & Elliot, 2001). Motivational needs or traits are task-independent;
thus, they function at the Person level and are setting the direction of one’s
action as well as the general policy on how much effort is to be invested in
the pursuit of one’s goal(s) (Kahneman, 1973). The actual effort, however, is a
function of both the task-specific motivation and the task difficulty (Brehm
& Self, 1989; Efklides, 2007; Efklides et al., 2006). Therefore, motivation at the
Person level is involved in the estimation of the effort to be exerted on a learn-
ing task at the Task x Person level, but this estimation (and actual effort) would
change as cognitive (task) processing takes place and more accurate monitor-
ing (e.g., in the form of feeling of difficulty) of task demands is made.
386 Efklides
Person level
Self-concept Affect
TASK Motivation
Task representation Monitoring and ME (prospective) Task-related Monitoring and Regulation of affect
control and MS control
Cognitive processing Monitoring and ME (during) and MS Activity-related Monitoring and Regulation of effort
control control
Figure 18.1. The MASRL model. Adopted from Efklides (2011). Interactions of meta-
cognition with motivation and affect in self-regulated learning: The MASRL model.
Educational Psychologist, 46(1), 6–25.
Note: ME = metacognitive experiences; MK = metacognitive knowledge; MS = meta-
cognitive skills.
At the Task x Person level, affect (e.g., mood) can also influence effort
exertion (Efklides & Petkaki, 2005; Gendolla & Brinkmann, 2005), and so do
achievement-related emotions such as interest (Hidi, 2006; Hidi & Ainley,
2007; Renninger, Sansone, & Smith, 2004; Sansone & Thoman, 2005). The
latter influence the extent to which students will engage in learning tasks
and will persist on them. Other emotions such as fear, anger, anxiety, pride,
or shame are also experienced before, during, or after working on learn-
ing tasks (Pekrun, Elliot, & Maier, 2006; Pekrun et al., 2002) and have an
impact on or interfere with learning behaviors or the regulation of learning.
These emotions can be related to the task itself, to the activity related to the
task, or to the outcome of one’s performance on the task. Emotions, unlike
motivation that functions at the Person level, are associated with the par-
ticular task or learning situation; that is, they are functioning at the Task x
Person level. Yet, some emotions can also function at the Person level. For
example, anxiety-trait (Spielberger, 1980) or interest in a particular knowl-
edge domain as disposition (Hidi & Renninger, 2006) can be more general
in scope and independent of the specific task at hand. If triggered by situ-
ational cues, then anxiety-trait and dispositional interest can influence the
decision to go on with task processing and effort exertion. Thus, although
emotions are critical for short-term task-specific SRL, they can also influ-
ence long-term SRL if they come to function at the Person level as disposi-
tional characteristics.
Metacognition and Affect in School Context 387
Metacognition
Metacognition is defined as cognition of cognition; that is, monitoring and
control of cognition (Flavell, 1979; Nelson, 1996). It is associated with con-
scious awareness (but not only; see Efklides, 2008) and regulation of cogni-
tion, whereas cognition is functioning mainly at a nonconscious, non-explicit
388 Efklides
The meta-loop gives rise to affect (positive or negative) and a hazy expectancy
about the effect of the rate of progress on one’s goal (Carver & Scheier, 1998).
Presumably, feeling of difficulty is a processing-related ME that draws from
this feedback loop (Efklides, 2002a). Specifically, an indicator of the rate of
progress in task processing is fluency. Fluency is a powerful cue for both feel-
ing of knowing and feeling of familiarity (Koriat, 1997, 2007). However, feeling
of difficulty denotes lack of processing fluency (Efklides, 2002a), possibly due
to task complexity and increased processing demands on working memory
resources. Lack of fluency is also due to processing interruption or conflict of
response (Touroutoglou & Efklides, 2010; van Veen & Carter, 2002) as well as
error detection (Fernandez-Duque, Baird, & Posner, 2000). In all these cases,
negative affect arises because error probability increases (see also Efklides &
Petkaki, 2005 for association of feeling of difficulty with negative affect).
However, fluency or the lack of it also has implications for outcome-related
ME, such as feeling of confidence. For example, if feeling of difficulty is expe-
rienced, uncertainty also increases, even if the outcome of processing is objec-
tively correct (Efklides, 2002a, 2002b). In contrast, the person can feel high
confidence (overconfidence), even if the outcome of cognitive processing is
not correct, just because the response was produced fluently. This is particu-
larly true for cases in which the person is not aware of the task demands and
of his/her ignorance (Kruger & Dunning, 1999). In such a case, she/he has
the illusion that the task is easy and the response correct (Efklides, 2002a).
What needs, therefore, to be stressed is that metacognitive feelings, through
their cognitive and affective quality, are making the person aware of qualities
of cognitive processing (e.g., interruption of processing, conflict, etc.) as well
as about the impact of cognitive processing on the attainment of one’s per-
sonal goal.
Metacognitive judgments/estimates, on the other hand, are cognitive in
nature (Koriat & Levy-Sadot, 1999). They may refer to the probability to learn
something (e.g., judgment of learning) that is crucial for the regulation of
effort (e.g., study time). They may also refer to one’s and others’ cognition.
For example, one may use normative information to judge the probability
to remember something or individualized information regarding one’s self
or other persons in similar situations (Lories, Dardenne, & Yzerbyt, 1998;
Salonen, Vauras, & Efklides, 2005). Social comparison processes or stereo-
typic knowledge can also be used to make judgments/estimates about one’s
own or others’ cognition (Salonen et al., 2005). Thus, metacognitive judg-
ments are interwined with social cognition and serve not only self-regulation
but also co- and other-regulation in peer collaborative learning or teacher/
parent regulation of a child’s cognitive processing.
Metacognition and Affect in School Context 391
feed back onto self-concept and trigger attributions about one’s competence
(Metallidou & Efklides, 2001).
However, the association of ME with self-concept is a complex process
because often the person has no analytic awareness of the factors that affect his/
her ME. For example, in the case of feeling of difficulty, the factors range from
task features (e.g., complexity; see Efklides, 2002a) to cognitive processing fea-
tures (such as cognitive interruption or response conflict; see Touroutoglou
& Efklides, 2010; van Veen & Carter, 2002) and to mood (Efklides & Petkaki,
2005) – for example, negative mood increases the reported feeling of difficulty.
Thus, for understanding the source of one’s feeling of difficulty, the person has
to make inferences based on online task-specific knowledge as well as MK
regarding tasks. In all these cases, the person attributes his/her feeling of dif-
ficulty to the task or to the situation; thus, attribution to ability is minimized.
Yet, in other cases the person may attribute the source of feeling of dif-
ficulty to one’s lack of knowledge or skills. This attribution is based on one’s
self-concept, because self-concept summarizes the person’s self-representation
of competence as well as self-efficacy in specific domains (Dermitzaki &
Efklides, 2000, 2001). When dealing with academic tasks, domain-specific
academic self-concept is activated, leading to expectancies of success/fail-
ure as well as to attributions about the difficulties to be experienced and the
outcome of cognitive processing. Feeling of confidence is directly related
to self-efficacy (Bandura, 1986) and in its turn triggers attributions of abil-
ity (Metallidou & Efklides, 2001). Estimate of effort also feeds back on the
self-concept in the sense that the higher the estimated effort the less the per-
ceived ability (Efklides & Tsiora, 2002; Nicholls, 1984). Thus, self-concept,
ME, and attributions are interrelated in a loop that connects metacognition
and motivation at the Task x Person level with motivation at the Person level,
where the general representation of the self lies. This loop gives coherence and
continuity to one’s self-regulatory behaviors and is getting updated through
intrinsic feedback about one’s competence coming from ME (Efklides &
Tsiora, 2002; Metallidou & Efklides, 2001) as well as by significant others’
external feedback that affects ME (Efklides & Dina, 2004, 2007) and, through
them, the self-concept.
Our research on ME and motivation has also shown that students’ achieve-
ment goal orientations are differentially related to students’ ME (Efklides
& Dina, 2007). The effects of achievement goal orientations are not on the
intensity of ME but on their calibration. Specifically, students with mastery
and performance-approach goal orientations have better calibrated ME than
students with performance-avoidance goal orientations. Mastery-oriented
students seem to closely monitor all their ME, even if ME convey negative
394 Efklides
information about one’s self as feeling of difficulty and estimate of effort do.
On the other hand, performance-approach oriented students mainly monitor
their outcome-related ME (e.g., estimate of solution correctness, feeling of
confidence, and feeling of satisfaction), particularly when negative external
feedback is provided. This finding suggests that these students are interested
in their performance outcome and use their ME as a basis to evaluate external
feedback. On the contrary, performance-avoidance oriented students do not
show any calibration of their ME in relation to their performance, indicat-
ing that they are unwilling to engage in a self-reflection process or that they
base the self-reports of their ME on cues (e.g., social comparison) other than
those emanating from the monitoring of cognitive processing and its out-
come. This lack of calibration, however, has adverse effects on SRL, because
neither effort regulation nor strategy use is adapted to task demands. As we
found in another of our studies (Efklides, 2002a; Efklides et al., 1999), stu-
dents who right from the beginning of task processing turned to others for
help did not show any change in their strategy use during problem solving,
and their reports of strategy use were not related to their task performance.
For students who changed strategy during task processing, however, their
reports on strategy use correlated with their task performance. Considering
that strategy use was also related to the reported feeling of difficulty, it is evi-
dent that the latter students monitored task-processing demands and adapted
their strategy use to the demands of task processing.
Taken together, our findings suggest that achievement goal orientations
may not directly impact the effort exerted on a task, as Efklides et al. (2006)
showed. They can do so, however, indirectly through their impact on the cali-
bration of the monitoring of task processing. Performance-avoidance goals,
by driving the person’s attention away from task processing, do not allow
effective monitoring and control of cognitive processing and therefore under-
mine SRL and achievement. This issue, however, merits further research
because students often have multiple goals as well as emotional dispositions,
such as interest, and attitudes toward knowledge domains that have motiva-
tional power. Attitudes, for instance, affect ME (Dina & Efklides, 2009) and
may lead to differentiation of SRL. If we look at ME in light of these findings,
then it is clear that ME are connected to motivation in multiple ways that can
be understood if we accept that the Person and the Task x Person levels have
their own functioning as well as interrelations between them.
beginning of the learning task to its end. Affect and emotions are not equated
to ME because they are triggered by various stimuli that are not necessarily
related to features of cognitive processing as it happens with ME. Positive
affect can arise from interest as dispositional or situational characteristics
(Hidi, 2006), expectancies for successful learning based on self-efficacy
beliefs (Bandura, 1986), fluency in cognitive processing (Efklides & Petkaki,
2005), positive feedback on the outcome of cognitive processing (Efklides &
Dina, 2004), social interaction (Salonen et al., 2005), or a positive mood state
that is independent from the learning situation (e.g., remembering a pleasant
event; Efklides & Petkaki, 2005).
How, then, do affect and emotions impact SRL and what are the relations
of affect and emotions with ME? Positive affect is a resource (Fredrickson,
2001) that can support SRL through its effect on goal selection as well as on
effort and persistence (Ainley, Hidi, & Berndorff, 2002). Positive affect arising
during task processing due to fluency of processing or the monitoring of the
outcome of task-processing as captured in ME is also input that informs the
person on the progress towards one’s goal (Carver & Scheier, 1998; Efklides,
2006), thus raising expectations for success (Aspinwall, 1998). Moreover, pos-
itive affect interacts with cognition, making the person more willing to take
risks, more flexible, and open to creative approaches. Yet, positive affect is
also associated with more holistic and less analytic thinking (Kuhl, 2001),
and this can have adverse effects on performance in cases that require critical
evaluation of the situation or the outcome of one’s efforts.
Positive affect also makes the person more willing to accept negative feed-
back about himself/herself (Trope, Hassin, & Gervey, 2001). With respect to
SRL, this finding implies that positive affect filters the impact of ME with
negative valence, such as feeling of difficulty, uncertainty, or lack of confi-
dence as well as of corrective external feedback so that these ME and exter-
nal feedback can be integrated into the self system without threatening one’s
self-concept. In this way, negative feedback makes self-concept more realistic
vis-à-vis learning tasks and outcomes.
Another implication of positive affect for SRL is coasting. Coasting is a
by-product of positive affect due to a fast progress toward one’s goal (Carver
& Scheier, 1998). Coasting entails that the person engages in activities not
directly related to one’s goal. This is helpful because it broadens one’s interests
and perspectives but has the risk for the student to give up the main goal, par-
ticularly if coasting starts early, before the student accomplishes his/her main
goal. One condition that can foster coasting is when the student is ill-informed
by his/her ME – for example, overconfidence that decreases effort although
the task is demanding. In such cases, coasting increases potential distracters
and endangers the learning process.
396 Efklides
All of the above considerations make clear that bringing metacognition and
affect at the forefront of the Task x Person level and in immediate connection
with cognition can accommodate findings that refer to a direct relationship of
cognition with metacognition and affect – with each one of them separately.
It can also allow testing of hypotheses regarding mediational effects of ME
in the relation of affect with cognition as well as of cognition and affect with
person characteristics, functioning at a more general level. For example, as
Touroutoglou and Efklides (2010) found, the same underlying feature of task
processing (e.g., cognitive interruption) leads to the formation of ME (e.g.,
feeling of difficulty) and emotions (e.g., surprise). On the other hand, one
may expect to do well on a task when she/he starts task processing and this
expectation triggers positive affect; if later on, during cognitive processing,
she/he feels difficulty, then this feeling might trigger an emotion such as sur-
prise, anger, and so forth. The same can happen when starting task processing
with negative affect ends up with less than expected difficulty and a success-
ful outcome of processing; then, an emotion such as joy is triggered. In such
cases, ME provide the cues for the change of affect.
On the other hand, negative affect can be due to situational characteris-
tics that give rise to fear, anxiety, boredom, anger (Pekrun et al., 2006); ME
regarding task processing and/or its outcome such as lack of fluency or unde-
sired outcomes (e.g., feeling of difficulty, high estimate of effort, low feeling of
confidence); low expectations for success because of a negative self-concept
(Bandura, 1986) as well as social rejection (Hubbard, 2001); negative external
feedback that affects ME and through them state anxiety (Dina & Efklides,
2009); and factors unrelated to the learning task or situation. Negative affect
constrains students’ self-regulation efforts because it turns their attention to
potentially harmful stimuli or undesirable outcomes and away from task fea-
tures that can facilitate processing (Ellis et al., 1997). It also lowers expectations
for performance (Cervone et al., 1994) and reduces effort and persistence,
thus facilitating disengagement and goal abandonment (Carver, 2003).
Despite its potential threats for self-regulation, negative affect is associated
with more critical, analytic, and systematic processing that can be beneficial
for performance depending on task requirements (Kuhl, 2001). Moreover,
negative affect can be beneficial for self-regulation if it focuses the person’s
attention on the task (e.g., monitoring of solution correctness) rather than
on emotional stimuli (Basso, Schefft, & Hoffmann, 1994; Martin & Davies,
1998). These findings imply that the effects of affect on cognition can be direct
(e.g., triggering analytic or holistic processing) or indirect via ME and the
cognitive regulatory loop. Increased negative mood, for example, increases
feeling of difficulty (Efklides & Petkaki, 2005) and, through it, the control
Metacognition and Affect in School Context 397
decisions – namely, change of strategy use (Efklides et al., 1999). If the strategy
is successful, then positive affect is experienced, thus changing the person’s
mood state. An alternative route could be the following: one starts cognitive
processing with negative mood, the negative mood triggers analytic process-
ing, and engagement with the task is leading to mood absorption (Erber &
Erber, 1994). This change of mood state may then impact the intensity of feel-
ing of difficulty. Which of the two patterns of interaction of affect with cogni-
tion, and under what conditions, is actually taking place has to be determined
by future research.
Nevertheless, the dynamic interplay between positive and negative affect is
important for understanding the interrelations of cognition and metacogni-
tion with affect in SRL, rather than the positive or negative affect by them-
selves. This dynamic interplay is also evident in ME; for example, a student
may start with negative mood when processing a task, but as she/he is get-
ting involved in it and processing is fluent, positive affect is restored (Efklides
& Petkaki, 2005). Moreover, progressing toward the goal makes the student
more confident and willing to get engaged in similar tasks again. Therefore,
the change of ME and the affect that goes with them can have an impact
on cognitive processing as well as on SRL because a change from negative
to positive affect can reinforce the activities that brought about that change.
Moreover, a change toward positive affect can moderate the impact of ME
on the self-concept, directing the control decisions in a self-congruent way.
Depending on a student’s affective state, feedback from ME can be integrated
to the self system and guide the control processes efficiently or aggravate the
student’s already negative affect and lead to disengagement from the task or
maladaptive SRL (Efklides & Dina, 2007).
On the other hand, the person can self-regulate his/her affective state
based on the awareness of his/her ME and emotions. Such self-regulation
of affect can be successful or unsuccessful. This might have implications for
both cognition and metacognition. For example, if students experience dif-
ficulty and make negative self-evaluations for their academic competence
based on attributions of lack of ability but at the same time they value school
achievement (Paris, 2002), then negative affect and self-focus increase, par-
ticularly in ruminative and depressed individuals as well as in females (Mor &
Winquist, 2002); this decreases the efficiency of SRL. Social rejection can also
lead to negative affect and negative self-evaluations (Rudolph, Caldwell, &
Conley, 2005), possibly aggravating mood, and through it, ME regarding task
processing. Emotional distress then leads to decreased perceptions of compe-
tence over time (Pomerantz & Rudolph, 2003) and devaluation of academic
learning (Jacobs et al., 2002). Negative self-concept and ME then strengthen
398 Efklides
correspond to what the other person is actually thinking, feeling, and doing,
and may (or may not) lead to successful control decisions at the individual or
interpersonal level. The situation becomes even more complicated if inter-
personal relations and dynamics enter the co-regulation process (Salonen
et al., 2005), particularly because emotions are also triggered by situational
characteristics and ME as well as by the others’ responses (e.g., feedback)
to our learning outcomes (Dina & Efklides, 2009). Consequently, the co-
regulation of learning cannot be successful if metacognition makes use of
only the cognitive regulatory loop; it should be orchestrated with affect and
regulation of affect.
Conclusion
In this chapter, the relations of metacognition with motivation and affect in
the context of SRL were pointed out. The MASRL model was the theoretical
framework that allowed the delimitation of interrelations between these com-
ponents of SRL. Moreover, self-regulation, co-regulation, or other-regulation
is a dynamic process, and understanding it is a challenge for future research.
By focusing on ME and their relations with person characteristics on the one
hand and affect at the Task x Person level on the other, a link between ME and
both the short- and long-term SRL was established. Motivation, self-concept,
and affect at the Person level can have an impact on ME, and ME on them,
thus enhancing (or impeding) students’ SRL. Moreover, the interplay between
affect (positive or negative), cognition, and metacognition at the Task x Person
level is important for efficient online self-regulation. More research is needed
in order to reveal whether metacognition exerts a direct effect on affect and
motivation or mediates the relations of cognition with affect and motivation.
Also, research is needed in order to understand the potential role of ME,
through self-awareness, to the functioning of the affective regulatory loop.
The MASRL model entails that all students, successful or not, self-regulate
their learning continuously but do it differently, because they pursue differ-
ent goals, have different ME, and use different regulatory strategies that lead
to different learning outcomes. An implicit assumption in SRL theory is that
SRL leads to successful learning outcomes because students autonomously
select their learning goals and strategies, enjoy learning activities, and take
pride in their achievements (Ryan & Deci, 2000). This assumption, however,
cannot be generalized to all students, because not all students self-regulate
successfully, nor all learning outcomes – even successful ones – give joy and
pride, as research on attribution theory has shown (Weiner, 1985). Anxiety,
shame, and boredom can be experienced as well as joy and pride, depending
Metacognition and Affect in School Context 401
on how (e.g., with how much effort) success was achieved and to what it was
attributed (Nicholls, 1984; Pekrun et al., 2006). Metacognition is a crucial
constituent of this process because ME provide the intrinsic feedback that the
person is using during self-reflection and self-evaluation. Intrinsic feedback
through ME can be congruent or incongruent, with external feedback com-
ing from others. The interaction of ME with external feedback (e.g., Dina &
Efklides, 2009) is a field that merits further research if we are to understand
the development of self-regulation/co-regulation/other-regulation of learn-
ing. Finally, the interaction of ME with affect can provide a theoretical basis
for describing different patterns of SRL so that more targeted and differenti-
ated interventions can be undertaken to change ineffective SRL.
References
Ainley, M., Hidi, S., & Berndorff, D. (2002). Interest, learning, and the psychological
processes that mediate their relationship. Journal of Educational Psychology, 94,
545–561.
Aspinwall, L. G. (1998). Rethinking the role of positive affect in self-regulation.
Motivation and Emotion, 22, 1–31.
Bandura, A. (1986). Social foundations of thought and action: A social cognitive theory.
Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Bandura, A., Caprara, G. V., Barbaranelli, C., Gerbino, M., & Pastorelli, C. (2003). Role
of affective self-regulatory efficacy in diverse spheres of psychosocial functioning.
Child Development, 74, 769–782.
Bartsch, K., & Wellman, H. M. (1995). Children talk about the mind. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Basso, M. R., Schefft, B. K., & Hoffmann, R. G. (1994). Mood-moderating effects of affect
intensity on cognition: Sometimes euphoria is not beneficial and dysphoria is not
detrimental. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 66, 363–368.
Boekaerts, M. (1999). Self-regulated learning: Where we are today. International Journal
of Educational Research, 31, 445–457.
Brehm, J. W., & Self, E. A. (1989). The intensity of motivation. Annual Review of
Psychology, 40, 109–131.
Byrne, B. M. (1996). Measuring self-concept across the life span: Issues and instrumenta-
tion. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.
Carver, C. S. (2003). Pleasure as a sign you can attend to something else: Placing positive
feelings within a general model of affect. Cognition and Emotion, 17, 241–261.
Carver, C. S., & Scheier, M. F. (1998). On the self-regulation of behavior. Cambridge, UK:
Cambridge University Press.
Cervone, D., Kopp, D. A., Schaumann, L., & Scott, W. D. (1994). Mood, self-efficacy, and
performance standards: Lower moods induce higher standards for performance.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 67, 499–512.
Dermitzaki, I., & Efklides, A. (2000). Aspects of self-concept and their relationship with
language performance and verbal reasoning ability. American Journal of Psychology,
113(4), 643–659.
402 Efklides
(2001). Age and gender effects on students’ evaluations regarding the self and
task-related experiences in mathematics. In S. Volet & S. Jarvela (Eds.), Motivation
in learning contexts: Conceptual advances and methodological implications (pp. 271–
293). Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Dina, F., & Efklides, A. (2009). Metacognitive experiences as the link between situational
characteristics, motivation, and affect in self-regulated learning. In M. Wosnitza,
S. A. Karabenick, A. Efklides, & P. Nenniger (Eds.), Contemporary motivation
research: From global to local perspectives (pp. 117–146). Goettingen, Germany:
Hogrefe & Huber.
Dunlosky, J., & Nelson, T. O. (1992). Importance of the kind of cue for judgments of
learning (JOLs) and the delayed-JOL effect. Memory and Cognition, 20, 373–380.
Efklides, A. (2001). Metacognitive experiences in problem solving: Metacognition, motiva-
tion, and self-regulation. In A. Efklides, J. Kuhl, & R. M. Sorrentino (Eds.), Trends and
prospects in motivation research (pp. 297–323). Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer.
(2002a). Feelings as subjective evaluations of cognitive processing: How reliable are
they? Psychology: The Journal of the Hellenic Psychological Society, 9, 163–184.
(2002b). The systemic nature of metacognitive experiences: Feelings, judgments, and
their interrelations. In M. Izaute, P. Chambres, & P.-J. Marescaux (Eds.), Metacogni
tion: Process, function, and use (pp. 19–34). Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer.
(2006). Metacognition and affect: What can metacognitive experiences tell us about
the learning process? Educational Research Review, 1, 3–14.
(2007). Effort and its conceptualization: Task difficulty, capacity, allocation policy, and
regulation. In P. Kordoutis, Z. Papaligoura, & E. Masoura (Eds.), Scientific Annals
of the Faculty of Philosophy, School of Psychology, Aristotle University of Thessaloniki
(Vol. 7, pp. 325–353). Thessaloniki, Greece: Aristotle University Press/Art of Text.
(2008). Metacognition: Defining its facets and levels of functioning in relation to self-
and co-regulation. European Psychologist, 13, 277–287.
(2011). Interactions of metacognition with motivation and affect in self-regulated
learning: The MASRL model. Educational Psychologist, 46(1), 6–25.
Efklides, A., & Dina, F. (2004). Feedback from one’s self and from the others: Their effect
on affect. Hellenic Journal of Psychology, 1, 179–202.
(2007). Is mastery orientation always beneficial for learning? In F. Salili & R. Hoosain
(Eds.), Culture, motivation and learning: A multicultural perspective (pp. 131–167).
Greenwich, CT: Information Age Publishing.
Efklides, A., Kourkoulou, A., Mitsiou, F., & Ziliaskopoulou, D. (2006). Effort regulation,
effort perceptions, mood, and metacognitive experiences: What determines the
estimate of effort expenditure? Metacognition and Learning, 1, 33–49.
Efklides, A., Papadaki, M., Papantoniou, G., & Kiosseoglou, G. (1997). The effects of
cognitive ability and affect on school mathematics performance and feelings of dif-
ficulty. American Journal of Psychology, 110(2), 225–258.
(1998). Individual differences in feelings of difficulty: The case of school mathematics.
European Journal of Psychology of Education, XIII(2), 207–226.
Efklides, A., & Petkaki, C. (2005). Effects of mood on students’ metacognitive experi-
ences. Learning and Instruction, 15, 415–431.
Efklides, A., Samara, A., & Petropoulou, M. (1999). Feeling of difficulty: An aspect of
monitoring that influences control. European Journal of Psychology of Education,
XIV(4), 461–476.
Metacognition and Affect in School Context 403
Efklides, A., & Tsiora, A. (2002). Metacognitive experiences, self-concept, and self-regulation.
Psychologia: An International Journal of Psychology in the Orient, 45, 222–236.
Ellis, H. C., Ottaway, S. A., Varner, L. L., Becker, A. S., & Moore, B. A. (1997). Emotion,
motivation, and text comprehension: The detection of contradictions in passages.
Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 126, 131–146.
Erber, R., & Erber, W. M. (1994). Beyond mood and social judgment: Mood incongruent
recall and mood regulation. European Journal of Social Psychology, 24, 79–88.
Fabricius, W. V., & Schwanenflugel, P. J. (1994). The older child’s theory of mind. In A.
Demetriou & A. Efklides (Eds.), Intelligence, mind, and reasoning Structure and
development (pp. 111–132). Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Fernandez-Duque, D., Baird, J. A., & Posner, M. I. (2000). Executive attention and meta-
cognitive regulation. Consciousness and Cognition, 9, 288–307.
Flavell, J. H. (1979). Metacognition and cognitive monitoring: A new area of cognitive
developmental inquiry. American Psychologist, 34, 906–911.
Fredrickson, B. L. (2001). The role of positive emotions in positive psychology. American
Psychologist, 56, 218–226.
Gendolla, G. H. E., & Brinkmann, K. (2005). The role of mood states in self-regulation:
Effects on action preferences and resource mobilization. European Psychologist, 10,
187–198.
Harter, S. (1986). Processes underlying the formation, maintenance, and enhancement
of the self-concept. In J. Suls & A. Greenwald (Eds.), Psychological perspectives on
the self (Vol. 3, pp. 137–181). New York: Wiley.
Hidi, S. (2006). Interest: A unique motivational variable. Educational Research Review,
1, 69–82.
Hidi, S., & Renninger, A. K. (2006). The four-phase model of interest development.
Educational Psychologist, 41(2), 111–127.
Hubbard, J. A. (2001). Emotion expression processes in children’s peer interac-
tion: The role of peer rejection, aggression, and gender. Child Development, 72,
1426–1438.
Iiskala, T., Vauras, M., & Lehtinen, E. (2004). Socially-shared metacognition in peer
learning? Hellenic Journal of Psychology, 1, 147–178.
Jacobs, J. E., Lanza, S., Osgood, W. D., Eccles, J. S., & Wigfield, A. (2002). Changes in
children’s self-competence and values: Gender and domain differences across
Grades one to twelve. Child Development, 73, 509–527.
Kahneman, D. (1973). Attention and effort. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Kitchener, K. S. (1983). Cognition, metacognition, and epistemic cognition: A three-level
model of cognitive processing. Human Development, 26, 222–232.
Koriat, A. (1997). Monitoring one’s own knowledge during study: A cue-utilization
approach to judgments of learning. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General,
126, 349–370.
(2007). Metacognition and consciousness. In P. D. Zelazo, M. Moscovitch, & E.
Thompson (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook of consciousness (pp. 289–325).
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Koriat, A., & Levy-Sadot, R. (1999). Processes underlying metacognitive judgments:
Information-based and experience-based monitoring of one’s own knowledge. In
S. Chaiken & Y. Trope (Eds.), Dual-process theories in social psychology (pp. 483–
502). New York: Guilford.
404 Efklides
Kruger, J., & Dunning, D. (1999). Unskilled and unaware of it: How difficulties in rec-
ognizing one’s own incompetencies lead to inflated self-assessments. Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology, 77(6), 121–134.
Kuhl, J. (1985). Volitional mediators of cognitive behavior consistency: Self-regulatory
processes and action versus state orientation. In J. Kuhl & J. Beckman (Eds.), Action
control (pp. 101–128). New York: Springer.
(2001). A functional approach to motivation: The role of goal enactment and
self-regulation in current research on approach and avoidance. In A. Efklides, J.
Kuhl, & R. M. Sorrentino (Eds.), Trends and prospects in motivation research (pp.
239–268). Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer.
Kuhl, J., & Fuhrmann, A. (1998). Decomposing self-regulation and self-control:
The Volitional Component Inventory. In J. Heckhausen & C. S. Dweck (Eds.),
Motivation and self-regulation across life span (pp. 15–49). Cambridge, UK:
Cambridge University Press.
Kuhn, D. (2000). Theory of mind, metacognition, and reasoning: A life-span perspec-
tive. In P. Mitchell & K. J. Riggs (Eds.), Children’s reasoning and the mind (pp. 301–
326). Hove, UK: Psychology Press.
Lockl, K., & Schneider, W. (2007). Knowledge about the mind: Links between theory of
mind and later metamemory. Child Development, 78, 148–167.
Lories, G., Dardenne, B., & Yzerbyt, V. Y. (1998). From social cognition to metacogni-
tion. In V. Y. Yzerbyt, G. Lories, & B. Dardenne (Eds.), Metacognition: Cognitive
and social dimensions (pp. 1–15). London: Sage.
Martin, L. L., & Davies, B. (1998). Beyond hedonism and associationism: A configural
view of the role of affect in evaluation, processing, and self-regulation. Motivation
and Emotion, 22, 33–51.
Metallidou, P., & Efklides, A. (2001). The effects of general success-related beliefs and
specific metacognitive experiences on causal attributions. In A. Efklides, J. Kuhl, &
R. M. Sorrentino (Eds.), Trends and prospects in motivation research (pp. 325–347).
Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer.
Mor, N., & Winquist, J. (2002). Self-focused attention and negative affect: A meta-analysis.
Psychological Bulletin, 128, 638–662.
Nelson, T. O. (1996). Consciousness and metacognition. American Psychologist, 51,
102–116.
Nelson, T. O., Kruglanski, A. W., & Jost, J. T. (1998). Knowing thyself and others:
Progress in metacognitive social psychology. In V. Y. Yzerbyt, G. Lories, & B.
Dardenne (Eds.), Metacognition: Cognitive and social dimensions (pp. 69–89).
London: Sage.
Nelson, T. O., & Narens, L. (1994). Why investigate metacognition? In J. Metcalfe & A.
Shimamura (Eds.), Metacognition: Knowing about knowing (pp. 1–25). Cambridge,
MA: The MIT Press.
Newell, A. (1990). Unified theories of cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Nicholls, J. G. (1984). Achievement motivation: Conceptions of ability, subjective
experience, task choice, and performance. Psychological Review, 91, 328–346.
Paris, S. G. (2002). When is metacognition helpful, debilitating, or benign? In M. Izaute,
P. Chambres, & P.-J. Marescaux (Eds.), Metacognition: Process, function, and use
(pp. 105–120). Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer.
Metacognition and Affect in School Context 405
Winkielman, P., & Cacioppo, J. T. (2001). Mind at ease puts a smile on the face:
Psychophysiological evidence that processing facilitation leads to positive affect.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 81, 989–1000.
Winne, P. H. (2004). Students’ calibration of knowledge and learning processes:
Implications for designing powerful software learning environments. Educational
Research, 41, 466–488.
Zimmerman, B. J. (1998). Developing self-fulfilling cycles of academic regulation: An
analysis of exemplary instructional models. In D. H. Schunk & B. J. Zimmerman
(Eds.), Self-regulated learning: From teaching to self-reflective practice (pp. 1–19).
New York: Guilford.
19
Motivation in Language
Klaus-Uwe Panther
Introduction
Whether natural language is motivated by extralinguistic (e.g., cognitive) fac-
tors has been a controversial topic since antiquity; it is much older than the
emergence of linguistics as a scientific discipline in the nineteenth century.
In Plato’s dialogue Cratylus, Socrates is asked by Hermogenes and Cratylus to
act as an umpire on the problem of “truth” or “correctness” in “names”, where
the last category is rather vague, including proper names, common names,
and adjectives (Sedley, 2003, p. 4). Cratylus’s position is usually referred to
as “naturalism”, in contrast to Hermogenes’s “conventionalism” (Sedley, 2003,
p. 4). Hermogenes describes Cratylus’s view, as opposed to his own, in the
following terms:
I should explain to you, Socrates, that our friend Cratylus has been arguing about
names; he says that they are natural and not conventional; not a portion of the
human voice which men agree to use; but that there is a truth or correctness in
them, which is the same for Hellenes as for barbarians. . . . I have often talked over
this matter, both with Cratylus and others, and cannot convince myself that there
is any principle of correctness in names other than convention and agreement.
(Hamilton & Cairns, 1961, p. 422)
407
408 Panther
Linguistic signs
Conventional Non-conventional
CONTENT
Pragmatic function
Conceptual content
SYMBOLIC RELATION
FORM
Syntax
Morphology
Phonology
Figure 19.2. The symbolic relation between content and form of the linguistic sign.
(d) (e)
SOURCE TARGET
Figure 19.3. Basic semiotic relations (adapted from Radden & Panther, 2004, p. 15).
Onomatopoeic Words
A reasonable assumption – in line with Saussure’s semiotics6 – is that
simple signs (i.e., signs that [roughly] cannot be analyzed into smaller
meaning-bearing units [morphemes]) are typically unmotivated in the sense
Motivation in Language 415
Isomophormism
(one form one
meaning)
Figure 19.4. Types of motivating factors (adapted from Radden & Panther, 2004, p. 24).
Table 19.1. Graphemic coding of the act of meowing and the interjection
for laughter in ten European languages
English German Dutch French Spanish Italian Portuguese Swedish Finnish Polish
meow miauen miauwen miauler Maullar miagolare miar jama naukua miaucze
miaow
ha! ha! haha! Ha! ha! ah! ah! Ja ah! ah! ah! ah! haha! ha ha Ha! Ha!
ha! ha!
SOURCE MOTIVATING
FACTOR
CONTENT
ICONICITY
FORM
TARGET
Directionality of motivation
Impact of motivational factors
Figure 19.5. Onomatopoeic signs.
Henceforth, I refer to the declarative and the imperative clauses proper as the
host clause, and to the italicized constituents in 3 and 4 as the tag. Tags have
a variety of communicative functions in English, and Bolinger (1989, p. 115)
notes that their use is “a typically English device” (quoted in Wong 2008, p. 89).
I will not try to develop a detailed taxonomy of the different communicative
functions of individual tags (see Huddleston & Pullum, 2002, pp. 851–945,
942–943). I also neglect the (crucial) role of intonation in the interpretation of
question tags. My aim is more modest: I intend to show how tags are related to
and motivated by the conceptual content and pragmatic function of the host
clause. I also address the important question of why some expressions that are
functionally and semantically compatible with the host do not appear as tags.
I begin with some possible and impossible tagged declaratives and impera-
tives that an adequate account in terms of motivation has to come to grips
with (unacceptable tags and only marginally acceptable ones are marked with
an asterisk and a superscripted question mark, respectively):
(5) Gore won the Nobel Prize,
a. did(n’t) he?
b. right?
c. or?
d. *do(n’t) I believe it?
(6) You are fired,
a. *are(n’t) you?
b. *right?
(7) Pour me some wine,
a. *do(n’t) you?
b. would you?
c. why don’t you?
d. *why do you?
f. shouldn’t you?
e. *must you?
418 Panther
The first observation about tags is that they are relatively short. This property
appears to be motivated by considerations of economy or brevity (see Figure
19.3).8 The same kind of communicative effect as with a question tag could,
in principle, be achieved by means of a full interrogative clause attached to
the host sentence. However, it would be highly uneconomical to render, for
example, 3 as 8:
(9) ?Hand me the book; will you hand me the book/hand it to me?
Tagged Declaratives
Before delving into the semantics and pragmatics of tagged declarative sen-
tences, it is crucial to review the formal properties of what one could call
“canonical tags,” as exemplified by “Mary left, didn’t she?” in sentence 3
above:
(11) i. There is referential identity between the host clause subject and the
tag subject, realized as an anaphoric pronoun: Mary is coreferential
with she.
ii. The host clause predicate (verb phrase) is anaphorically resumed in
the tag by an auxiliary verb: left is resumed by didn’t.
iii. The positions of the tag subject and the auxiliary are inverted: the aux-
iliary verb didn’t is positioned before the subject she.
iv. The polarity of the host clause is typically reversed from affirmative to
negative, or negative to affirmative, as the case may be: in 3, the host
clause is positive, the tag is negative.
v. The host clause and the tag are tightly linked: the tag functions as a
“sentence clitic.”
Motivation in Language 419
Tags such as “right?” and “or?” come very close to canonical tags. They fulfill
the requirement of being short, but they are syntactically less tightly linked
to the host clause than “do”-tags described in 11. In the case of “right?”, the
content expressed by the host clause is ellipted, but easily recoverable. In the
case of “or?”, alternatives to what is asserted in the host clause are evoked, but
there are no elements in the tag that are coreferential with elements in the
host clause.
The standard communicative function of declaratives is to perform
assertive speech acts, or more technically, assertive illocutionary acts.9 The
semantics and pragmatics of illocutionary acts can be represented by means
of conceptual frames. The notion of conceptual frame is based on the idea
that the meaning of a word “can only be properly understood and described
against the background of a particular body of knowledge and assumptions”
(Cruse, 2006, pp. 66–67). I assume that the frame semantic approach can
be applied to the analysis of speech acts, as well, and henceforth I refer to
the conceptual frames for speech acts as “scenarios.” A speech-act scenario
includes information about the context in which a speech act is felicitously
performed (in the sense of Austin, 1962, and Searle, 1969). In Figure 19.6, a
scenario for assertive speech acts is proposed.
In Figure 19.6, the assertive speech act itself is referred to as “core” (shaded
in grey), the background conditions for its felicitous performance as “before,”
and the consequences of the performance of the speech act as “result” and
“after.” The lines connecting conceptual components symbolize what Linda
Thornburg and I term (potential) metonymic links. These connections can
be called metonymic because one component in a speech-act scenario may
evoke other components or the whole scenario.
Depending on the components selected by the speaker, an assertive speech
act can be performed more or less directly or indirectly (see Searle, 1975 for the
notions of direct and indirect speech act):
(12) a. I claim that Auster wrote The Brooklyn Follies. (direct: sentence
addresses core)
b. I believe Auster wrote The Brooklyn Follies. (indirect: addresses a
before component)
c. Did you know that Auster wrote The Brooklyn Follies? (indirect:
addresses a before (component)
d. Do you now believe me that Auster wrote The Brooklyn Follies?
(indirect: addresses the after)
420 Panther
S ASSERTS P CORE:
ILL ACT
H BELIEVES P AFTER
S Speaker
H Hearer
P Proposition
Potentialmetonymic links
Figure 19.6. Scenario for assertive speech acts.
address the veracity of the proposition P. The verbs in the tags of (14a, 14b),
“know” and “hear,” are not verbatim resumptions of the host clause verbs;
nevertheless, they address an important before component of the assertive
scenario and their appearance is thus motivated.
Much longer and less felicitous are tags that evoke the relevance of the
asserted proposition for the hearer:
(15) a. ?Gore won the Nobel Peace Prize, do you care?
b. ?Gore won the Nobel Peace Prize, are you interested?
c. Gore won the Nobel Peace Prize, if you’re interested.
The appended expressions in 15 are increasingly clause-like (in comparison
with 13 and 14). Moreover, in 15c, the tag is conditional, not interrogative.
Conditionality is conceptually related to interrogativity (English if, which is
a cognate form of German ob, “whether,” can be used in indirect questions),
but the conditional clause in 15c does certainly not constitute a canonical tag.
Finally, the tag expressions in 15 are also syntactically less tightly connected
to their host clauses than in the canonical cases in 13. There are no anaphoric
ties at all between the host clause subject and predicate and the elements in
the tag.
The acceptability and canonicity of tags decreases even more drastically
when the before component “S believes P” and “there are good reasons for
believing P,” and the core component “S asserts P,” the result component “S is
regarded as being committed to P (as an effect of asserting P),” and the after
component “H believes P” are addressed. The tags become both longer and
more clause-like, and most of them are downright unacceptable.
(16) a. *Gore won the Nobel, do(n’t) I believe/think/assume so?
b. *Gore won the Nobel, are there good reasons for this claim?
c. *Gore won the Nobel, do(n’t) I claim/assert/say so?
d. *Gore won the Nobel, aren’t/am I committed to the truth of this?
e. Gore won the Nobel, (or) don’t you believe me?
There are good reasons for the unacceptability of 16a–d. Utterance 16a is com-
municatively (although not logically) inconsistent. Speakers are supposed
to have privileged access to their beliefs; to seek confirmation for what one
believes to be true is therefore pragmatically odd. As to 16b, there is a com-
municative principle that requires people to assert only propositions whose
truth they can back up with good arguments. To pose the question in the tag
whether such good reasons exist undermines the communicative function
of the host clause. Utterance 16c is unacceptable because it is pragmatically
paradoxical to assert something and at the same time question whether one’s
own act of assertion has actually been performed. Similarly, the utterance
422 Panther
of 16d is infelicitous because the assertion of the content of the host clause
creates the effect that the speaker is seriously committed to the truth of the
asserted proposition, but it is exactly this pragmatic effect that is challenged
in the tag. The only tag that is acceptable refers to the after component of the
speech act. The speaker’s goal in asserting something is usually to make the
hearer believe that the asserted proposition is true. This aim is, however, not
always achieved, and it is therefore quite natural for speakers to address the
after component. Nevertheless, despite the acceptability of 16e, the tag is for-
mally not canonical. First, it is rather long (clause-like), and, second, it is not
anaphorically linked to the preceding host; neither the subject of the tag nor
its verb anaphorically resumes formal elements of the host clause.
To conclude this section, a set of sentences is worth mentioning that seems
to behave erratically in not admitting canonical declarative question tags:
(17) a. *I promise to be on time, don’t I?
b. *I apologize for keeping you waiting, don’t I?
c. *Passengers are requested to board immediately, aren’t they?
(request to board a plane)
d. *I pronounce you man and wife, don’t I? (priest performing mar-
riage ceremony)
e. *You’re fired, aren’t you? (speaker fires hearer from job)
f. ?I believe Gore won the Nobel Prize, don’t I?
e. *I am glad you came to my party, aren’t I?
In grammatical terms, all of the above utterances are declarative sentences,
but they do not allow a tag that addresses the truth value of the proposi-
tion expressed in the host clause. The host clauses in 17a–d typically serve
as what Austin (1962) terms “explicit performative utterances.” The verb in
the superordinate clause self-referentially describes the speech act that the
speaker actually performs in uttering the sentence. In these cases, the host
clauses are not to be categorized in terms of truth but in terms of felicity (see
Austin, 1962). The utterances 17a–c constitute a promise, an apology, and a
request, respectively; the speaker cannot, in the same breath, question the
performance of these explicitly named illocutionary acts.
Utterances 17d and 17e are examples of linguistic acts that are grounded in
institutions. Institutionally legitimized speakers create new social, judicial,
and religious “facts” as a result of performing them. The utterance of the cor-
rect words, in the right circumstances, by the right speaker has the effect that
proposition P becomes “reality.” It is this feature that distinguishes what Searle
(1976) calls “declarations” from ordinary assertive declarative sentences,
which are descriptively either true or false. Similarly, explicit performative
Motivation in Language 423
Tagged imperatives
The number of tags that can be attached felicitously to imperative sentences is
much larger than those that co-occur with declarative clauses. Tagged imper-
atives have the canonical structure Modal Auxiliary (n’t) + you. Here are some
examples:
(18) a. Hand me that book, will/won’t/would you?
b. Open that door for me, can/can’t/could you?
The imperative tags in 18 are syntactically not as tightly linked with their host
clauses as canonical declarative tags are with their hosts. First, the subject of
an imperative tag (you) has no explicitly named antecedent in the host clause,
although it refers back to an understood addressee of the imperative sen-
tence. Second, imperative tags are not “pro-forms” for the verb phrase in the
host clause in the sense that the auxiliaries do/did are “pro-verb” forms for the
predicates in declaratives are. However, despite their looser syntactic ties to
the host clause, the appearance of modals such as can, could, will, and would
is, as argued below, are highly motivated by conceptual factors.
The standard function of imperative sentences is to perform directive
speech acts (i.e., they are used to perform orders, instructions, requests, rec-
ommendations, etc.). In order to understand what licenses or constrains the
appearance of imperative tags, it is necessary to consider the scenario for
directive speech acts. I consider a subtype of this scenario (viz. a conceptual
frame that represents requests for the transfer of an object from the hearer to
the speaker) (see Figure 19.7).
A glance at Figure 19.7 reveals that the tags in sentences 18a and 18b index
components of the directive speech-act scenario. Tagged imperatives com-
bine a direct speech act (the host clause) with a compacted indirect speech
act (the tag). For example, “can you?” in 18b is a condensed form of the
424 Panther
SUB-TYPE:
X EXISTS/IS AVAILABLE REQUEST THAT H GIVE X TO S
H HAS X S WANTS X
H CAN GIVE X TO S
S Speaker
H Hearer
potential metonymic links
Figure 19.7. Scenario for directive speech acts.
full-fledged indirect request “Can you open that door for me?” The latter is
called indirect because it can be used to achieve the same purpose as the cor-
responding direct request “Open that door for me.” A second important fea-
ture of well-formed imperative tags is that they are metonymically linked in
a part-whole relationship to the directive speech-act scenario. The tag selects
one aspect (component) of the speech-act scenario, which then metonymi-
cally evokes other parts of the speech-act scenario or the whole scenario.
It has often been observed that indirect speech acts are politer than direct
speech acts (Brown & Levinson, 1987; Searle, 1975), and many of the imper-
ative tags (although not all) serve the purpose of mitigating the impositive
force of the host clause.
The task remains to check which parts of the scenario can be verbalized as
imperative tags and why.
Before: availability, possession of x
(19) a. ?Pour me some Rioja, is there any?
b. ?Pour me some Rioja, do you have any?
The components “availability of x” and “possession of x” are not exploit-
able as “ideal” tags because they are clause-like (i.e., similar to interrogative
Motivation in Language 425
bizarre, given the goal of the speaker (compliance with the request). For com-
municative reasons, such a tag is completely unmotivated and will therefore
not appear.
Before: S wants H to give X to S
(22) *Pour me some Rioja, do I want you to/would I like you to?
The tags in 22 refer to what in speech act theory is known as a sincerity con-
dition. To question this component is pragmatically odd because speakers
should know their own wishes. An analogous constraint holds for assertive
tags that question the speaker’s belief in the proposition P (see Section 5.2).
Core: S asks H to give X to S
(23) *Pour me some Rioja, do(n’t) I ask you to?
As in the case of assertive tags (see Section 5.2), the illocutionary act, more
precisely, reference to the speaker and act of asking, cannot be compacted
into a well-formed tag. The reason is clear: such a tag creates an illocutionary
paradox because the speech act is accomplished in uttering the host clause,
and at the same time, questioned in the tag.
Resultant obligation: H is under an obligation to give X to S
(24) a. *Pour me some Rioja, must you?
b. *Pour me some Rioja, should you?
c. *Pour me some Rioja, mustn’t you?
d. Pour me some Rioja, shouldn’t you?
The positive tags in 24a and 24b are pragmatically odd because they create –
similar to the illocutionary tag in 23 – a paradoxical situation. In uttering
the host clause, the speaker introduces an obligation for the hearer, but the
immediately adjacent tag suspends this obligation. In contrast, utterance 24d
is felicitous. Here, the negative tag pragmatically implies the existence of a
host’s normally willingly undertaken social commitment (cf. “Shouldn’t you
pour me some Rioja” [as you’re the host]?). The negative form of the tag is
thus inferentially motivated. Yet 24c, with the negative tag “mustn’t you?”
seems less felicitous, if not infelicitous. The reason might be that, unlike
should, must often implies an externally imposed obligation complied with
only reluctantly, if not unwillingly.
Resultant willingness: H is willing to give X to S
(25) Pour me some Rioja, would you like to/be willing to/mind?
The tags in 25 are acceptable (but not canonical) because they are more clause-
like and thus do not abide by the principle of economical coding.
Motivation in Language 427
INFERENCES
Directionality of motivation
coding.11 The content of the host clause has an impact on the content of the
tag in that the tag metonymically selects one suitable conceptual compo-
nent from the speech-act scenario of the preceding host. The tag functions
as a condensed indirect speech act in imperative tags, and it focuses on the
truth of the proposition in declarative tags. Routinized inferential processes
are involved in the interpretation of, for example, negative tags such as “can’t
you?” and “won’t you?” The tags are preferably coded as economically as
possible.
Motivation in Language 429
Conclusions
In this chapter, I hope to have made the case for motivation as a key concept
in linguistic theorizing. In particular, I have tried to substantiate Saussure’s
claim that although elementary linguistic signs are – with notable excep-
tions – arbitrary, language as an instrument of expressing thoughts and per-
forming communicative acts must, to a certain extent, be motivated. I have
shown that grammatical phenomena – question tags attached to declara-
tive and imperative sentences – are licensed and constrained by a variety of
motivating factors. Tags are found in many other languages, but what kinds
of tags appear in a specific language cannot be predicted. It is a fact about
English that it has motivated canonical tags such as “did she?” “can you?” or
“will your?” and their negated counterparts. It is also a fact that German and
French lack literal equivalents of these English tags.
A final problem remains to be addressed very briefly. Why are linguistic
structures often only partially, or in Saussurean terms, relatively motivated?
Ariel (2008, p. 123) proposes an interesting answer. She points out that moti-
vation is, in logical terms, not a transitive relation. If some source x motivates
a target y, and y serves in turn as a source for motivating z, the result of this
chaining is not necessarily a recognizable motivational relationship between
x and z. Motivated chains of this sort are very common in the history of lan-
guages, and the results of such diachronic processes often, from a synchronic
perspective, appear to be unmotivated linguistic phenomena.
Notes
1. The conventionalist theory of linguistic signs is also propounded by Aristotle in
his treatise De Interpretatione. Aristotle holds that the relation between a linguistic
expression and its content is conventional; that is, “no name exists by nature, but
only by becoming a symbol” (quoted in Crystal, 1997, p. 408).
2. For example, in a recent discussion of Adele Goldberg’s book Constructions at Work
(2006), which explicitly embraces the thesis that grammatical constructions are
partially motivated, Borsley and Newmeyer (2009) argue that purely formal syntac-
tic generalizations exist, one of them being the rule of “Auxiliary–Subject Inversion.”
The authors argue that the constructions that undergo this rule are semantically
heterogeneous (e.g., interrogatives, exclamative sentences, counterfactual condi-
tionals) but they all fall formally under the same generalization (i.e., the auxiliary is
placed before the subject).
3. Langacker (e.g., 2008), the leading figure in the branch of cognitive linguistics
referred to as Cognitive Grammar, assumes throughout his work that linguistic
signs (simple and complex) exhibit a symbolic relationship between the semantic
pole and the phonological pole. Syntax and morphology are not considered to be
independent levels of linguistic organization.
430 Panther
4. Radden and Panther (2004, p. 10) suggest that the use of “give” as a grammati-
cal category “benefactive” in Ewe can be accounted for as the result of abductive
reasoning.
5. The Saussurean term synchronic refers to the linguistic system “at one point in time”
and is opposed to diachronic – “the evolution of language through time.”
6. Throughout the Cours de linguistique générale Saussure uses the term sémiologie,
whereas in English the term semiotics (introduced by the American philosopher C.
S. Peirce) is preferred.
7. Parts of this section originated in talks that were prepared and delivered with Linda
Thornburg at conferences at Josip Strossmayer University in Osijek, Croatia, and the
University of Bielsko-Biała, Poland, in September 2007 and October 2008, respec-
tively. My sincere thanks go to Professors Mario Brdar and Bogusław Bierwiaczonek
for their kind invitations and hospitality. Suggestions and constructive criticism
from the audiences at these conferences are gratefully acknowledged.
8. Grice (1975) lists “Be brief ” as one of the conversational maxims subsumed under
the Cooperative Principle that guides rational communication.
9. The term “illocutionary act” (what is done “in speaking”) was coined by the Oxford
philosopher John L. Austin in the 1960s, and further developed by the American
philosopher John Searle (1969). It is the latter’s notion of illocutionary act that is
assumed here. In what follows, I use the terms “speech act” and “illocutionary act”
interchangeably.
10. See Panther and Thornburg (2006) for the motivated behavior of manner scales
such as <can, be able to, have the ability>.
11. On the role of metonymy as a motivating factor of grammar, see the collection of
articles in Panther, Thornburg, and Barcelona (2009).
References
Ariel, M. (2008). Pragmatics and grammar. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Austin, J. L. (1962). How to do things with words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Bolinger, D. (1989). Intonation and its uses. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Borsley, R. D., & Newmeyer, F. J. (2009). On subject-auxiliary inversion and the notion
“purely formal generalization.” Cognitive Linguistics, 20, 135–145.
Brown, P., & Levinson, S. C. (1987). Politeness: Some universals in language use.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Cruse, A. (2006). A glossary of semantics and pragmatics. Edinburgh: Edinburgh
University Press.
Crystal, D. (1997). The Cambridge encyclopedia of language. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Goldberg, A. (2006). Constructions at work. Oxford, NY: Oxford University Press.
(2009). The nature of generalization in language. Cognitive Linguistics, 20, 93–127.
Grice, H. P. (1975). Logic and conversation. In P. Cole & J. L. Morgan (Eds.), Speech acts
(Syntax and Semantics 3) (pp. 41–58). New York: Academic Press.
Haiman, J. (1985). Natural syntax: Iconicity and erosion. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Motivation in Language 431
Hamilton, E., & Cairns, H. (Eds.), (1961). The collected dialogues of Plato including the
letters. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Heine, B. (1997). Cognitive foundations of grammar. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Heine, B., & Kuteva, T. (2002). World lexicon of grammaticalization. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Huddleston, R., & Pullum, G. K. (2002). The Cambridge grammar of the English lan-
guage. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Katamba, F. (2005). English words. London: Routledge.
Lakoff, G. (1987). Women, fire, and dangerous things: What categories reveal about the
mind. Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press.
Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1999). Philosophy in the flesh: The embodied mind and its chal-
lenge to Western thought. New York: Basic Books.
Langacker, R. (2008). Cognitive grammar: A basic introduction. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Newmeyer, F. J. (1983). Grammatical theory: Its limits and its possibilities. Chicago, IL:
The University of Chicago Press.
(2000). Language form and language function. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Panther, K.-U. (2008). Conceptual and pragmatic motivation as an explanatory concept
in linguistics. Journal of Foreign Languages, 315, 2–19.
Panther, K.-U., & Thornburg, L. L. (1998). A cognitive approach to inferencing in con-
versation. Journal of Pragmatics, 30, 755–769.
(1999). The potentiality for actuality metonymy in English and Hungarian. In K.-U.
Panther & G. Radden (Eds.), Metonymy in language and thought (Human Cognitive
Processing 4) (pp. 333–357). Amsterdam & Philadelphia: Benjamins.
(2003). Metonymies as natural inference and activation schemas: The case of depen-
dent clauses as independent speech acts. In K.-U. Panther, & L. L. Thornburg
(Eds.), Metonymy and pragmatic inferencing (Pragmatics & Beyond New Series 113)
(pp. 127–147). Amsterdam and Philadelphia: Benjamins.
(2006). Metonymy and the way we speak. In R. Benczes & S. Csábi (Eds.), The
metaphors of sixty: Papers presented on the occasion of the 60th birthday of Zoltán
Kövecses (pp. 183–195). Budapest: Eötvös Loránd University, Department of
American Studies.
(2007). Metonymy. In Geeraerts, Dirk, and Hubert Cuyckens, (Eds.), Handbook of
Cognitive Linguistics (pp. 236–263). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Panther, K.-U., Thornburg, L. L., & Barcelona, A. (Eds.), (2009). Metonymy and meta-
phor in grammar (Human Cognitive Processing 25). Amsterdam and Philadelphia:
Benjamins.
Radden, G., & Panther, K.-U. (2004). Introduction: Reflections on motivation. In
G. Radden, & K.-U. Panther (Eds.), Studies in linguistic motivation (Cognitive
Linguistics Research 28) (pp. 1–46). Berlin and New York: Mouton de Gruyter.
Radford, A. (1988). Transformational grammar: A first course. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
(1997). Syntax: A minimalist introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Saussure, F. de. (1968). Course in general linguistics. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Saussure, F. de. (1995). Cours de linguistique générale. Paris: Payot.
Searle, J. R. (1969). Speech acts: An essay in the philosophy of language. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
432 Panther
(1975). Indirect speech acts. In P. Cole & J. L. Morgan (Eds.), Speech acts (Syntax and
Semantics 3) (pp. 59–82). New York: Academic Press.
(1976). A classification of illocutionary acts. Language in Society, 5, 1–23.
Sedley, D. (2003). Plato’s Cratylus. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Thornburg, L. L., & Panther, K.-U. (1997). Speech act metonymies. In W.-A. Liebert, G.
Redeker, & L. Waugh (Eds.), Discourse and perspective in cognitive linguistics (pp.
205–219). Amsterdam and Philadelphia: Benjamins.
Wong, J. (2008). Anglo English and Singapore English tags: Their meanings and cultural
significance. Pragmatics and Cognition, 16, 88–117.
20
Edward F. Zigler
433
434 Zigler
past or present for referring to individuals at the lower end include “mental
retardation,” “mental deficiency,” “mental challenge,” “intellectual disabil-
ity,” “developmental disability,” or “developmental delay.” Terms of this kind
represent the attempt to describe a phenomenon without falling into the
trap of using pejorative descriptors. Currently, mental retardation is defined
as intelligence test performance two or more standard deviations below the
mean, namely, below the score of 70, accompanied by limitations in adap-
tive functioning (Robinson, Zigler, & Gallagher, 2000), with onset prior to
the age of 18 years (APA, 1980). Thus, IQ in the range of 50–69 is sometimes
viewed as mild mental retardation, IQ in the range of 35–49 as moderate
mental retardation, and lower than 35 as severe. It should, however, be evi-
dent that mental retardation is largely a matter of definition. The arbitrary
nature of the diagnostic criteria is clear from the fact that in recent years
the cutoff IQ score for mental retardation has fluctuated between 85 (APA,
1966) and 70 (APA, 1980). Furthermore, as emphasized by Zigler (1986), the
important point may not be the precise IQ but the divergence between the
chronological age and the mental age, whereby in the retarded the former is
higher than the latter. Whatever the cutoff point of the IQ is, it disregards
another highly important distinction among individuals in this domain of
disability, which is that between cultural-familial (nonorganic) etiologies
and organic etiologies that has been emphasized and studied by Zigler and
his students (Burack, 1990).
The situation is not much simpler in regard to the higher end of the IQ
curve. Usual terms that are used include “giftedness,” “talent,” “high ability,”
“excellence in performance,” or “high levels of accomplishment when com-
pared with others of their age, experience or environment” (Ross, 1993, p.
26). Here again there do not exist any accepted definitions or consensual
IQ cutoff points. Common distinctions refer to children scoring 115–129 as
bright, those scoring 130–144 as moderately gifted, 145–159 as highly gifted,
160–174 as exceptionally gifted, and those scoring above 175 as profoundly
gifted (Gross, 2004, p. 7; Newman, 2008). However, it is widely accepted that
most IQ tests are not very sensitive in distinguishing between degrees of gift-
edness at the higher levels (Pfeiffer & Blei, 2008). Furthermore, similar to the
asynchrony between age and mental age in the retarded, in the gifted there
is a parallel “asynchrony gap” between the chronological age and the men-
tal age, whereby the former is lower than the latter. In fact, giftedness has
been defined as “asynchronous development” resulting in advanced cognitive
abilities coupled with performance and inner experiences and awareness that
are qualitatively different from the norm characterizing the chronological age
(Morelock, 1992).
Intelligence and Cognitive Exceptionality 435
encouragement in the form of praise and rewards (Amabile, 1998; Dorst &
Cross, 2001; Nonaka, 1991; Sullivan & Harper, 2009).
Personality and behavioral factors. A large body of data presents informa-
tion about personality tendencies and behaviors characteristic of the gifted.
We will briefly describe some of the major ones, mentioned in multiple stud-
ies, grouped into clusters (Coleman & Cross, 2008; Friedman-Nimz & Skyba,
2009; Jackson, Moyle, & Piechowski, 2009; Lens & Rand, 2008; Sekowski,
Siekanska, & Klinkosz, 2009).
(a) curiosity, inquisitiveness, childlike sense of wonder, desire to know,
openness to experience and a broad range of interests; perceptiveness,
good sense of observation, sensitivity to small changes in the environ-
ment, awareness of things that others do not perceive, and perceiving
the world differently than others; heightened sensory awareness that
may take the form of overexcitabilities or supersensitivities in one
or more of the following domains: psychomotor, sensual, emotional,
intellectual, and imaginational;
(b) tolerance for ambiguity and complexity, considering situations from
many points of view;
(c) independence, nonconformity, autonomy, questioning rules or
authority;
(d) perfectionism, setting high standards for self and others, high achieve-
ment drive, being critical of oneself;
(e) feeling different from others, sometimes out of step with others, but
compassionate and interested in others and their problems;.
(f) passionate, having intense feelings;
(g) tendency for risk-taking;
(h) need sometimes to withdraw, need for solitude and periods of
contemplation;
(i) having high moral standards, being disturbed by inequity, exploitation,
corruption, and needless human suffering.
This list, even though it is partial, shows that the personality tendencies char-
acteristic for the gifted serve to enhance the likelihood of exceptional products
by the gifted. Their curiosity, attentiveness to the environment, achievement
motivation, independence, and moral standards are guarantees that the gift-
edness will be manifested in original, creative, and useful outputs.
However, it has been noted that some of the personality tendencies of the
gifted may be manifested in forms that will not be conducive to excellence
or may even hinder it. For example, the broad range of interests may lead to
losing focus and dealing with too many projects; the nonconformism may
Intelligence and Cognitive Exceptionality 443
General Conclusions
This chapter dealt with the effects of motivation on cognitive functioning in
two groups of individuals extreme in regard to intellectual ability. The reason
for focusing on these two groups is the common assumption that in view of
the evident status of intelligence in the retarded and in the gifted, motivation
appears to be of little consequence, if at all. The evidence provided in this
chapter about the role of motivation precisely in regard to these two groups
provides a strong argument in support of the dependence of cognitive func-
tioning on motivation.
Notably, the factors that were reviewed as impacting motivation were
of three kinds: environmental circumstances, personality tendencies, and
cognitive-motivational correlates. It was found that the same groups of
factors influence cognitive performance in the two groups of individuals.
Furthermore, in some cases, it became evident that motivational factors
depressing performance in the retarded or promoting it in the gifted were
contrasts, such as outerdirectedness in the former and innerdirectedness in
the latter group.
Observations of this kind indicate that one of the next steps in the study
of the interactions of cognition and motivation could be the development of
a theory of motivation that would be comprehensive both in its structure –
including environmental, personality, and cognitive factors – and its applica-
tion – to individuals at all levels of ability.
References
Amabile, T. M. (1998). How to kill creativity: Keep doing what you’re doing. Or, if you
want to spark innovation, rethink how you motivate, reward, and assign work to
people. Harvard Business Review (September–October), 77–87.
American Psychiatric Association (APA) (1966). Diagnostic and statistical manual (2nd
ed.). Washington, DC.
(1980). Diagnostic and statistical manual (3nd ed.). Washington, DC.
Balla, D., Butterfield, E., & Zigler, E. (1974). Effects of institutionalization on retarded
children: A longitudinal, cross-institutional investigation. American Journal of
Mental Deficiency, 78, 530–549.
Balla, D., & Zigler, E. (1975). Preinstitutional social deprivation and IQ changes among
institutionalized retarded children. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 75, 83–89.
Bennett-Gates, D., & Kreitler, S. (1999). Expectancy of success in individuals with mental
retardation. In E. Zigler & D. Bennett-Gates (Eds.), Personality development in indi-
viduals with mental retardation (pp. 130–144). NY: Cambridge University Press.
Bennett-Gates, D., & Zigler, E. (1999). Effectance motivation and the performance
of individuals with mental retardation. In E. Zigler & D. Bennett-Gates (Eds.),
446 Zigler
Harter, S. (1967). Mental age, IQ, and motivational factors in the discrimination learning
set performance of normal and retarded children. Journal of Experimental Child
Psychology, 5, 123–141.
Harter, S., & Zigler, E. (1974). The assessment of effectance motivation in normal and
retarded children. Developmental Psychology, 10, 169–180.
Hodapp, R. M., Burack, J. A., & Zigler, E. (1990). Issues in the developmental approach to
mental retardation. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Hodapp, R. M., & Fidler, D. J. (1999). Parenting, etiology, and personality-motivational
functioning in children with mental retardation. In E. Zigler & D. Bennett-Gates
(Eds.), Personality development in individuals with mental retardation (pp. 226–
248). NY: Cambridge University Press.
Jackson, P. S., Moyle, V. F., & Piechowski, M. M. (2009). Emotional life and psycho-
therapy of the gifted in light of Dabrowski’s theory. In L. Shavinina, R. Persson, L.
Kreger-Silverman, S. M. Reis, D. K. Simonton, N. Colangelo, & J. VanTassel-Baska
(Eds.), International handbook on giftedness (pp. 437–465). New York: Springer.
Kounin, J. (1941a). Experimental studies of rigidity: I. The measurement of rigidity in
normal and feeble-minded persons. Character and Personality, 9, 251–272.
(1941b). The explanatory power of the concept of rigidity as applied in feebleminded-
ness. Character and Personality, 9, 273–282.
Kreitler, S. (2004). The cognitive guidance of behavior. In J. T. Jost, M. R. Banaji, & P.
A. Prentice (Eds.), Perspectivism in social psychology: The Yin and Yang of scientific
progress (pp. 113–126).Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.
Kreitler, S., & Casakin, H. (2009). Motivation for creativity in design students. Creativity
Research Journal, 21, 282–293.
Kreitler, S., & Kreitler, H. (1988). The cognitive approach to motivation in retarded indi-
viduals. In N. W. Bray (Ed.), International review of research in mental retardation
(Vol. 15, pp. 81–123). San Diego, CA: Academic Press.
(1990). The cognitive foundations of personality traits. New York: Plenum.
Kreitler, S., & Zigler, E. (1990). Motivational determinants of children’s probability learn-
ing. Journal of Genetic Psychology, 151, 301–316.
Lens, W., & Rand, P. (2008). Motivation and cognition: Their role in the development
of giftedness. In S. I. Feiffer (Ed.), Handbook of giftedness in children (pp. 199–202).
New York: Elsevier.
Margaliot, A. (2005). A model for teaching the cognitive skill of melioration to pre-service
science teachers in a college for teachers. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Bar-Ilan
University, Ramat Gan, Israel.
Merighi, J., Edison, M., & Zigler, E. (1990). The role of motivational factors in the func-
tioning of mentally retarded individuals. In R. M. Hodapp, J. A. Burack, & E. Zigler
(Eds.), Issues in the developmental approach to mental retardation (pp. 114–134). NY:
Cambridge University Press.
Morelock, M. (1992). Giftedness: The view from within. Understanding Our Gifted, 1,
11–15.
Newman, T. M. (2008). Assessment of giftedness in school-age children using measures
of intelligence or cognitive abilities. In S. I. Feiffer (Ed.), Handbook of giftedness in
children: Psychoeducational theory, research and best practices (pp. 161–176). New
York: Springer.
448 Zigler
Nonaka, I. (1991). The knowledge creating company. Harvard Business Review, 69,
96–104.
Olszewski-Kubilius, P. (2008). The role of the family in talent development. In S. I.
Feiffer (Ed.), Handbook of giftedness in children: Psychoeducational theory, research
and best practices (pp.53–70). New York: Springer.
Pfeiffer, S. I., & Blei, S. (2008). Gifted identification beyond the IQ test: Rating scales
and other assessment procedures. In S. I. Feiffer (Ed.), Handbook of giftedness in
children: Psychoeducational theory, research and best practices (pp. 177–198). New
York: Springer.
Plucker, J. A., & Levy, J. J. (2001). The Downside of Being Talented (Electronic version).
American Psychologist, 56, 75–76.
Raber, S. M., & Weisz, J. R. (1981). Teacher feedback to mentally retarded and nonre-
tarded children. American Journal of Mental Deficiency, 86, 148–156.
Reis, S. M., & McCoach, D. B. (2002). Underachievement in gifted students. In M.
Neihart, S. M. Reis, N. M. Robinson, & S. M. Moon (Eds.), The social and emotional
development of gifted children (pp. 81–91). Waco, Texas: Prufrock Press.
Renzulli, J. (1978). What makes giftedness: Reexamining a definition. Phi Delta Kappan,
60, 180–184.
Reynolds, W. M., & Miller, K. L. (1985). Depression and learned helplessness in mentally
retarded and nonmentally retarded adolescents: An initial investigation. Applied
Research in Mental Retardation, 6, 295–306.
Richter, R. (2003). Cognitive orientation when creatively solving engineering and busi-
ness problems. Unpublished master’s thesis in Industrial Engineering, Tel Aviv
University, Tel-Aviv, Israel.
Rimm, S. (2008). Underachievement syndrome: A psychological defensive pattern.
In S. I. Feiffer (Ed.), Handbook of giftedness in children: Psychoeducational theory,
research and best practices (pp. 139–160). New York: Springer.
Robinson, N. M., Zigler, E., & Gallagher, J. J. (2000). Two tails of the normal curve:
Similarities and differences in the study of mental retardation and giftedness.
American Psychologist, 55, 1413–1424.
Ross, P. O. (1993). National excellence: A case for developing America’s talent.
Washington, DC: US Department of Education, Office of Educational Research
and Improvement.
Runco, M. A. (2007). Creativity: Theories and themes: Research, development and prac-
tice. NY: Elsevier
Sakar-DeLeeuw, N., (1999). Gifted preschoolers: Parent and teacher views on identifi-
cation, early admission and programming. US: Roeper School Article Review, 21,
174–179.
Schlanger, B. B. (1954). Environmental influences on the verbal output of mentally
retarded children. Journal of Speech and Hearing Disorders, 19, 339–343.
Schuler, P. (2002). Perfectionism in gifted children and adolescents. In M. Neihart, S. M.
Reis, N. M. Robinson, & S. M. Moon (Eds.), The social and emotional development
of gifted children (pp. 71–79). Waco, Texas: Prufrock Press.
Sekowski, A., Siekanska, M., & Klinkosz, W. (2009). On individual differences in gifted-
ness. In L. Shavinina, R. Persson, L. Kreger-Silverman, S. M. Reis, D. K. Simonton,
N. Colangelo, & J. VanTassel-Baska (Eds.), International handbook on giftedness
(pp. 467–485). New York: Springer.
Intelligence and Cognitive Exceptionality 449
Shonkoff, J. P., & Phillips, D. A. (Eds.) (2000). From neurons to neighborhoods: The sci-
ence of early childhood development. National Research Council and Institute of
Medicine – Committee on Integrating the Science of Early Childhood Development
Board on Children, Youth, and Families, Commission on Behavioral and Social
Sciences and Education. Washington, D.C.: National Academy Press.
Sternberg, R. J., & Davidson, J. E. (1986). Conceptions of giftedness: A map of the ter-
rain. In R. J. Sternberg & J. E. Janet (Eds.), Conceptions of giftedness (pp. 3–20). NY:
Cambridge University Press.
Sullivan, C., & Harper, G. (Eds.) (2009). Authors at work: The creative environment
Essays and Studies Collection, Vol. 62, The English Association, UK/DS Cambridge:
Brewer.
Swiatek, M. A. (1995). An empirical investigation of the social coping strategies used by
gifted adolescents. Gifted Child Quarterly, 39, 154–160.
Switzky, H. N. (1997). Individual differences in personality and motivational systems
in persons with mental retardation. In W. E. MacLean, Jr. (Ed.), Ellis’handbook of
mental deficiency, psychological theory and research, 3rd ed. (pp. 343–377). Mahwah,
NJ: Erlbaum.
Tannenbaum, A. J. (1986). Giftedness: A psychosocial approach. In R. J. Sternberg &
J. E. Janet (Eds.), Conceptions of giftedness (pp. 21–52). NY: Cambridge University
Press.
Weisz, J. R. (1981a). Effects of the “mentally retarded” label on adult judgments about
child failure. Journal of Abnormal Behavior, 90, 371–374.
(1981b). Learned helplessness in black and white children identified by their schools
as retarded and nonretarded: Performance deterioration in response to failure.
Developmental Psychology, 17, 499–508.
Zigler, E. (1958). Social deprivation and rigidity in the performance of feeble-minded chil-
dren. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, University of Texas.
(1971). The retarded child as a whole person. In H. E. Adams & W. K. Boardman (Eds.),
Advances in experimental clinical psychology (pp. 47–121). New York: Pergamon.
(1982). MA, IQ and the developmental-difference controversy. In E. Zigler & D. Balla
(Eds.), Mental retardation: The developmental-difference controversy (pp. 207–211).
Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
(1986). Intelligence: A developmental approach. In R. J. Sternberg & D. K. Detterman
(Eds.), What is intelligence? (pp. 149–152). Norwood, NJ: Ablex Publishing Co.
Zigler, E., Balla, D., & Butterfield, E. C. (1968). A longitudinal investigation of the rela-
tionship between preinstitutional social deprivation and social motivation in insti-
tutionalized retardates. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 10, 437–445.
Zigler, E., & Bennett-Gates, D. (Eds.) (1999). Personality development in individuals with
mental retardation. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Zigler, E., & Hodapp, R. M. (1986). Understanding mental retardation. New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Zigler, E., & Unell, E. (1962). Concept-switching in normal and feeble-minded chil-
dren as a function of reinforcement. American Journal of Mental Deficiency, 66,
651–657.
21
When William James laid out a vast agenda for a scientific discipline in his
grand two-volume Principles of Psychology of 1890 (James, 1950), he placed
chapters on consciousness and the self (Decartes’s je pense and je suis) toward
the very beginning of this work. Since then there have been several waves
of influence that have tended to cast consciousness or direct experience of
selfhood somewhat in the shadows. Freud and his clinical followers in psy-
choanalysis brought unconsciousness or thought and motivation without
awareness to the fore. Behaviorism, through developing highly sophisti-
cated experimental procedures for assessing learning and observable action
sequences, in effect ostracized consciousness and imagery for half a cen-
tury (Holt, 1964). Attention to consciousness began to re-emerge with the
“cognitive revolution” of the 1960s and opened avenues to studying human
awareness, ongoing thought, and private cognitive processing. The qualia of
experience now intrigue philosophers of the mind as well as behavioral sci-
entists and neurophysiologists (Buckner, Andrews-Hanna, & Schacter, 2008;
Ciba Foundation Symposium, 1993; J. L. Singer & Salovey, 1999; J. L. Singer &
Bonanno, 1990). Although new research in social cognition has also opened
the way for studying out-of-awareness attitude phenomena (Hassin, Uleman,
& Bargh, 2005), the importance of research on conscious thought is no longer
denied.
450
Conscious Thought, Imagination, and Fantasy 451
the basic emotions that have now been shown to exist across human species
in the research of Ekman and Izard are motivating human beings in doz-
ens of different situations independent of presumed drive pressures. Human
beings seek – as Tomkins has proposed – to reconstruct, in overt action or in
thought, situations that evoke the positive emotions of interest-excitement or
joy. They seek to avoid in action or thought those situations that have evoked
specific negative emotions of anger, fear-terror, sadness-distress (weeping),
or the complexes of shame-humiliation-guilt. Human beings are further
“wired-up” to express emotions as fully as possible and finally to control
emotional expression where social experience suggests such control is nec-
essary, either for safety or to avoid humiliation. Situations that permit expe-
rience and expression of positive emotions or that allow appropriate control
of negative emotion are intrinsically positively reinforcing. Those situations
that are more likely to evoke negative emotions – such as fear, anger, distress,
or shame – or that have blocked the expression of socially adaptive control of
emotions may be experienced as inherently punishing or negatively reinforc-
ing (Singer, 1974b; Tomkins, 1962, 1981).
Memory and anticipation become central features related to emotional
experience. Identifying, labeling, and gradually organizing new information
into mental representations that are technically labeled as schemas accom-
plishes this. These structures include schemas about persons or physical
objects, schemas about self and others, and scripts about action sequence
or prototypes that become means for encapsulating a variety of common
features of situations and persons into one fuzzy concept (Mandler, 1984;
Mandler, 1988; J. L. Singer & Salovey, 1991).
The avoidance of negative affects, seeking to maximize the positive effects
of joy and excitement-curiosity, expressing of emotions and yet also manag-
ing to control emotions may reflect the overarching link of affects to cogni-
tion. We must, however, also call attention to the two major human polarities
of community and agency because these, in varied expressions, form much of
the content of our conscious thought. A wide range of research of psychopa-
thology, healthy behaviors, and interpersonal interactions support the notion
that humans throughout life are seeking a balance between personal inti-
macy and group affiliation, on the one hand, and autonomy or self-actualized
individuality, on the other (Blatt, 2008; Bonanno & Singer, 1990). Whether
expressed as memories (Singer & Salovey 1993), intrusive thoughts about
self and others (Singer, 2006), or current concerns and wishes (Klinger 1999,
Singer, 2002), our conscious mentation largely represents content involving
our affiliative or agency needs.
456 Singer & Singer
assimilated into the as-yet limited number of schemas the child has at its
command. The startle responses or terror evoked in a toddler by the size and
noise of a huge passing truck may be gradually transformed into curiosity
and interest as the child attempts to reproduce the noises and movements of
the truck through creating its own sound effects and manipulating blocks or
toy trucks. Imaginative play may thus be understood as a means by which
the uncontrollable qualities and complexity of one’s physical and social envi-
ronment can be gradually miniaturized and manipulated. In effect, we can
see that much of human thought involves a similar effort to create, at least
temporarily, a world one can control through replaying memories or antic-
ipation and fantasy. Indeed, it can be argued that the very act of rehearsal
and anticipation or even of elaborating possible future events in somewhat
more bizarre fantasies may gradually approximate possible situations we do
encounter. Such mental rehearsal may leave us better prepared to handle
these, or at least be less frightened by them when they do occur (Singer &
Singer, 2005).
With the conceptual framework of the agency-autonomy or Blatt’s rela-
tional versus self-representation dialectic, the child’s make-believe world is
one that represents a continuous working out of the tension between the
need for closeness and affiliation and the need for privacy with its concom-
itant experience of personal power and individuality. Indeed, the very act of
beginning to form individualized images, memories, and anticipatory fanta-
sies becomes, in our crowded and sensory-bombarded world, the last refuge
for an experience of individuality and personal privacy. For the developing
child seeking the “story line,” it can simulate sustained relationships with par-
ents and others. It can also create private games by floor play or enacting a
relationship with a personally possessed stuffed animal or even an invisible
playmate, thus establishing that experience of individuation that also seems
so necessary in our human condition.
In view of this persistent human attachment-individuation tension, the
emergence of an increasingly complex imaginative dimension subject to
reasonable control (a kind of cognitive skill in itself) sustains the need for
self-definition, a sense of uniqueness, and private power. The child must learn
gradually to establish priorities in the direction of attention, whether toward
the environment or material recurring from memory or forming itself into
fantasies. Our practical survival may well demand that we assign a some-
what higher priority to the processing of externally generated stimulation.
Our affective development must also involve reflection, introspection, the
capacity to enjoy private experiences, gradually shape and direct them, to
plan and also create stories, and mentally to manipulate the range of future
458 Singer & Singer
possibilities. For young children with limited motor and linguistic capacities
and a smaller and less differentiated range of stored schemas and scripts, the
balancing of such priorities may be reflected in the varying amounts of physi-
cal, rule-oriented, or social and imaginative play in which they engage.
Of special importance is the conception of transformation or the emer-
gence through play of what Alan Leslie (1987) in a fine paper has called a
metarepresentational mode of thought. Leslie’s argument is that a major step
in development involves the “decoupling” of the direct representations we
sustain of objects, persons, or situations from their perceptual images into a
new set of metarepresentations that are symbolic or mental representations
of the same original set of objects, but now treated as part of an entire sys-
tem of thought that one can modify, manipulate, analogize, or transform to
metaphor. With the help to some extent of adults, but also on the basis of an
inherent capacity in the child, the ability merges to create a frame in which
otherwise very stable objects can be transformed into representations that
bear only a tenuous link with their original shapes.
Leslie’s conception of the theory of mind implies that human beings have
available a domain of metarepresentations they can manipulate to make
inferences about causes, predictions about future events, recognize the conse-
quences of ignorance, distinguish reality from fantasy, acquire a language of
words and phrases depicting mental experiences or states, and infer motiva-
tions. As Leslie puts it, “Pretend play is thus one of the earliest manifestations
of the ability to characterize and manipulate one’s own and other’s cognitive
relations to information” (Leslie, 1987, p. 422).
It may well be the case that preschool children practicing imaginative play
may also be more likely to move naturally into adopting a metarepresen-
tational orientation. They may show an ability to demonstrate a “theory of
mind”; that is, an ability to be aware of their own thoughts as distinct from
others. In a series of studies under our direction (Rosen, Schwebel, & Singer,
1997; Schwebel, Rosen, & Singer, 1999), it has been demonstrated that pre-
school children who play more imaginatively (on observation by raters on
several occasions) may actually perform better on the reality-fantasy and
false-belief measures used as estimates of theory of mind. As a matter of fact,
even when age and other factors are taken out in multiple regression analyses,
the scores on make-believe play still predict theory of mind results.
What we are proposing, then, is that imaginative play in childhood emerges
almost necessarily as the child’s cognitive capacities unfold through height-
ened brain development and inevitable social experiences. At the same time,
this metarepresentational mode makes it possible for increasing complexity
of play to occur. Such play provides pleasures for the children by allowing
Conscious Thought, Imagination, and Fantasy 459
dubious evidence and relative untestability. At the same time, cognitive sci-
ence has provided support for the present view that much of our information
processing and our uses of schemas, scripts, prototypes, or attitudes operates
relatively automatically or without conscious awareness (Banaji, 2001; Hassin
et al., 2005; Kihlstrom, 1987; J. L. Singer & Salovey, 1991). Is the theater of con-
sciousness simply an epiphenomenon or does it contribute a special potency
to our intentions toward action?
The position we are proposing is that the brain (except when traumati-
cally disabled as in our first definition of consciousness) is almost contin-
uously active. Materials from long-term memory recur sometimes almost
randomly (as may be especially the case in night dreaming), but also as a
function of recurrent, unfinished tasks, unfulfilled intentions, or current
concerns (Klinger, 1999). These current concerns may be aroused by asso-
ciations to environmental signals such as pictures of food, odors from food
vendor’s stands, or erotic images on TV and in magazines. Antrobus (1999)
has outlined with precision these circumstances from controlled research
that identify the likely awareness of TUITS (Giambra, 1995). Recent brain
imaging (MRI) research seems consistent with the laboratory evidence that
during those intervals when individuals are not processing externally gener-
ated task information (with parietal and occipital areas activated), they revert
to frontal-lobe activity, which may well reflect recurrent working memory or
future-oriented mentation (Antrobus, 1993, 1999; Courtney, 1997). As Klinger
summarizes recent research, “It is now clear that up to perhaps one half of
waking thought takes one form or another of daydreaming . . . thoughts are,
like more overt behavior, organized entities that . . . pertain to the goals to
which people commit themselves and are steered by emotional response to
goal related cues” (Klinger, 1999, p. 46). We concur with Klinger’s conclusion
that such mentation may well play a role in all cognitive processing from
simpler stimulus responses (see Johnson, 1997) to more complex forms of
problem-solving and creative thinking. Our human ability to project images,
self-representations, or even to carry on internal monologues or imagined
dialogues establishes a meaningful (S. Kreitler, 1999) stage or workspace
(Baars, 1997) that often motivates us to action much in the same manner as
sight or smell from the food vendor’s stand.
The research support for our position derives from a variety of experimen-
tal, psychometric, and clinical sources (J. L. Singer & Bonanno, 1990; J. A.
Singer & Salovey, 1999). For example, direct inquiry through questionnaires
makes clear the ubiquity of daydreaming and related ongoing conscious activ-
ities and their extensive personality correlates. Laboratory research, in which
participants engaging in vigilance or signal-detection tasks are periodically
Conscious Thought, Imagination, and Fantasy 463
Self-Representation
An awareness of self as reflected in interior monologues (Hamlet’s “O what
a rogue and peasant slave am I”) or images of oneself in future interactions
(Hamlet’s “The play’s the thing/wherein I’ll catch the conscience of the king!”)
is a recurrent feature of ongoing conscious thought. Beliefs about oneself in
relation to significant others such as parents and authorities or about one’s
“actual self ” as compared to one’s “ideal,” “ought,” or “dreaded self ” have
increasingly been carefully and extensively studied (Higgins, 1987; Hart et al.,
1997; J. L. Singer, 2006).
The valuable work by Higgins and his various collaborators has outlined
with strong experimental evidence how discrepancies between Actual and
Ideal or Actual and Ought self-beliefs may be associated with depressive or
agitated-anxious moods, respectively. We have carried this work further to
show that such self-beliefs are related not only to self-esteem measures and
mood or emotional states but are reflected in participants’ ongoing thought
as sampled by pager interruptions seven times a day over a week’s time.
Arousing participants’ awareness of actual-ideal or actual-ought discrepan-
cies increased conscious recurrence of self-thought and heightened negative
affects (J. L. Singer, 2006). The examination of samples of ongoing waking
thought about self may be a fruitful field, not only for further research but
also for clinical application.
In summary, we have sought to show that although a great deal of human
information may well run off out-of-awareness, there remains a narrower but
vivid stage of conscious thought, on which we re-enact memories, reshape
schemas, play out scripts for alternative futures, and even try out relatively
bizarre or fantastic adventures. Recent research on the Brain’s Default System
supports the findings from purely psychological studies to suggest that when
464 Singer & Singer
References
Antrobus, J. A. (1993). Thinking away and ahead. In H. Morowitz & J. L. Singer, (Eds.),
The mind, the brain, and complex adaptive systems (pp. 155–174). New York:
Addison–Wesley.
(1999). Towards a neurocognitive processing model of imaginal thought. In J. A.
Singer & P. A. Salovey (Eds.), At play in the fields of consciousness (pp. 3–28).
Mahwah, New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Baars, B. (1997). A cognitive theory of consciousness. Cambridge, England: Cambridge
University Press.
Bakan, D. (1966). The duality of human existence. Chicago: Rand McNally.
Banaji, Mahzarin R. (2001). Implicit attitudes can be measured. In H. L. Roediger III, J.
S. Nairne, I. Neath, & A. M. Surprenant (Eds.), The nature of remembering: Essays
in honor of Robert G. Crowder (pp. 117–150). Washington, DC: APA.
Blatt, S. J. (2008). Polarities of experience: Relatedness and self-definition in personality
development, psychopathology, and therapeutic process. Washington, DC: American
Psychological Association.
Bonanno, G. A., & Singer, J. L. (1990). Repressive personality style: Theoretical and meth-
odological implications for health and pathology. In J. L. Singer (Ed.), Repression
and dissociation (pp. 435–470). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Bruner, J. (1986). Actual minds, possible worlds. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Buckner, R., Andrews-Hanna. J., & Schacter, D. (2008). The brain’s default network:
Anatomy, function and relevance to disease. Annals of the New York Academy of
Sciences, 1124(1), 1–38.
Ciba Foundation Symposium 174. (1993). Experimental and theoretical studies of con-
sciousness. Chichester, England: Wiley.
Courtney, S. (1997, February). Functional MRI studies of visual perception and work-
ing memory. Paper presented at the 22nd Annual Interdisciplinary Conference,
Jackson Hole, Wyoming.
Demos, E.V. (Ed.) (1995). Exploring affect: The selected writings of Silvan S. Tomkins. New
York: Cambridge University Press.
Ekman, P. (1973). Darwin and facial expressions: A century of research in reviews. New
York: Academic Press.
Ekman, P., Friesen, W. V., Ellsworth, P. C. (1982). Emotion in the human face: Guidelines
for research and an integration of findings. Rev ed. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge
University Press.
Conscious Thought, Imagination, and Fantasy 465
Spurgeon, C. (1961). Shakespeare’s imagery. New York and London: Cambridge University
Press.
Taylor, M. (1999). Imaginary companions and the children who create them. New York:
Oxford University Press.
Taylor, S. (1989). Positive delusions: Creative self-deceptions and the healthy mind. New
York: Basic Books.
Tomkins, S. S. (1962). Affect, imagery and consciousness. Vol. 1. New York: Springer.
(1981). The quest for primary motives: Biography and autobiography of an idea.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 41, 306–329.
22
468
Creativity and Motivation 469
higher than her figure of 30 percent for a matched control group from other
occupations. The finding is so remarkable that it is important to note that
Andreasen’s diagnostic methods were more rigorous than in any previous
study.
Jamison (1997) questioned 47 award-winning British, Irish, or Common
wealth writers. Thirty-eight percent reported having sought treatment for
mood disorders, as compared to 6 percent in the general population.
Piirto (1998) examined the lives of 80 women writers using questionnaires
and published material. She found one of the themes was the incidence of
self-destructive acts and depression. The exact prevalence of this characteris-
tic is not clear; presumably, it was observed mostly in the confidential ques-
tionnaires because Piirto recorded only six writers for whom it was identified
by literature analysis.
Rivers-Norton (2002) noted that although studies of eminent writers
emphasized their distress, dysfunction, and mood disorders, they did not
focus primarily on the effects of childhood abuse. Analyzing autobiographi-
cal and biographical material as well as literary narratives by four randomly
selected eminent writers who had reported such abuse, she evaluated inter
alia whether these writers created narratives to acknowledge, engage, inte-
grate, and transcend their lived experiencing of this abuse. In all cases, she
found that early abuse led to existential crises that were reflected in literary
content and form.
Kaufman and Baer (2002) pointed out that most studies in this area have
focused predominantly, or even exclusively, on male writers, and that this
may limit the generalizability of the findings. There is, however, evidence that
mental illness is prevalent among successful women writers. In a historio-
metric study of 1,629 writers, Kaufman (2001) found that female poets were
significantly more likely to suffer mental illness than female fiction writers
or male writers of any type. A subsequent study of 520 eminent American
women found that poets were more likely to have mental illnesses and to
experience personal tragedy than journalists, visual artists, politicians, and
actresses (Kaufman, 2001).
The relationship between creativity and psychopathology may reflect the
fact that disturbances can be motivating. That is one way to interpret Freud’s
theory. Simplifying some, an individual may have a problem and use creative
work to explore or even relieve the disturbance. An alternative is suggested by
the findings of an association of creativity with alcohol and other substance
use. Ludwig’s (1995) study, mentioned previously, showed that creative writ-
ers were more likely than members of less creative professions to have alcohol
and drug problems. One explanation for this was offered by the novelist John
470 Runco & McGarva
Cheever. He suggested that his capacity to tap uncensored material led him
to drink – and gave him creative insight.
Humanistic Views
The motive to creative does not always originate in disturbance. This is
especially clear in the framework of what is often labeled the Humanistic
perspective. It posits that creativity can be motivated by the drive for
self-actualization and the fulfillment of potential. Note here that creativity
can therefore be tied to psychological health and well-being. Rogers (1961),
for instance, felt that creativity can flourish only when motivation comes
from within the creator and not when there is an expectation of being eval-
uated. Maslow (1968) viewed creative behavior as part of self-actualization,
and therefore placed it at the top of his hierarchy of needs, to be addressed
only when the more basic needs were met. A questionnaire-based study has
confirmed the relationship between creativity and self-actualization (Runco,
Ebersole, & Mraz, 1997).
Maslow (1968) acknowledged that self-actualizing creativity (which he dis-
tinguished from special-talent creativity), rather than conforming fully to the
hierarchical model, might be observed in innately creative people even when
they were unsatisfied, unhappy, or hungry. Rhodes (1961) pointed out that
creative behavior may result from either “deficiency” or “being” needs, in the
same way in which Maslow (1968) described two kinds of love: “D-love” and
“B-love.” When creative behavior is successful as a response to deficiencies
in one’s basic needs in an emotionally repressive or deprived environment, it
may allow subsequent access to higher levels of creativity. The deliberate and
conscious working through of underlying conflicts has also been shown to
have health benefits (Pennebaker, Kiecolt-Glaser, & Glaser, 1997).
One interesting part of the Humanistic perspective is the claim that cre-
ativity originates from within the individual. This is interesting because a
parallel view is very apparent in creative studies. We are referring to the
emphasis placed on intrinsic motivation in studies of creativity (Amabile,
1990; Eisenberger & Shanock, 2003; Runco, 1993). Intrinsic motivation
was tied to creative talent in some of the very first empirical investigations
reported at the Institute for Personality Assessment and Research (IPAR)
(Barron, 1963, 1972; MacKinnon, 1965, 1970, 1983). Intrinsic motivation was,
at that point, a core characteristic and viewed much more as a general ten-
dency, much as a personality trait. Other core characteristics included wide
interests (which is itself a reflection of motivation), unconventionality, and,
of course, originality.
Creativity and Motivation 471
Individuals who have invested a large amount into one style or perspective (e.g., a
scientist who has spent years developing one theory or model) will be motivated
to justify its usage. If his or her pet model was replaced, the scientist’s investment
(temporal and psychic) would depreciate. Note that it is essentially linear: the
more of an investment, the higher the motivation to avoid depreciation. Experts
would thus be highly motivated in a particular fashion, as would anyone who has
devoted years to a topic or model or perspective. (Runco, 2003)
Amabile (1996) described how extrinsic motivation can have a positive influ-
ence if it is synergistic – informational or enabling – rather than controlling.
The positive effect is especially likely when high intrinsic motivation is already
present. Thus, her theory allows for internal and external motivations to
co-occur. To test this, Ruscio, Whitney, and Amabile (1998) asked 151 univer-
sity students to write Haiku meeting stated requirements of form and content.
They had previously tested the participants’ stable, domain-specific motiva-
tion. The poems were rated for creativity and other qualities by English grad-
uate students. Stable intrinsic motivation significantly predicted creativity.
In a collage experiment with elementary school students in the United
States and Saudi Arabia, Hennessey (2000) found that, as usual, subsequent
reported interest in the task was undermined by the promise of a reward.
However, the Saudi children showed a smaller, in fact insignificant, effect.
Explaining this in terms of cultural differences, she went on to suggest that
Deci and Ryan’s (1995) self-determination theory may be of wider application
than a simplistic intrinsic motivation principle.
Heinzen (1994) has also divided creative behaviors into the intrinsically and
extrinsically motivated, associating the former with positive affect and spread-
ing cognitive activation, in which multiple ideas, consequences, and benefits are
quickly surveyed and assessed. This theoretical approach accounts for the supe-
rior creativity of intrinsically motivated behaviors. Clearly, speed is not essen-
tial to creativity. Another effect of personal interest in a project may be that the
creator is willing to work on it over a longer period, and it may be allowed to
mature in an unconscious “incubation” (Wallas, 1926) phase where unexpected
associations can occur. More exactly, it may be that equally good associations
are made both consciously and unconsciously, but that the latter are more
accessible when needed later (Zhong, Dijksterhuis, & Galinsky, 2008).
Ochse (1990) argued that the intrinsic motivation principle may apply
better in the laboratory than in the real world. Extrinsic rewards offered by
experimenters are merely short-term satisfactions such as praise and privi-
leges, and the subjects are usually unexceptional people who engage in the
research for extrinsic reasons. Ochse cautions that one should be wary of
using the conclusions to explain the stubborn labor of habitual creators.
Creativity and Motivation 473
The operant approach is in direct contrast to the view that there is an innate
talent. It also has difficulty explaining how people create their first works with
minimal encouragement (Abra, 1988). Skinner himself suggested that there
may be a reinforcement history that can explain why a “starving artist” con-
tinues to create even when rewards are seemingly absent. Skinner (1972) also
acknowledged that individuals can give themselves intrinsic reinforcement
(such as by thinking approving thoughts), provided that this itself is a trained
response.
Epstein (1990) investigated the possibility that reinforcement can restrict
one’s range of behavior rather than foster variation. He attempted to explain
how mutations occur. His Generativity Theory suggests that new behav-
iors always emerge from the interconnection or integration of old ones, in
ways which can be predicted, manipulated, and taught (Epstein, 1991). In a
recent study (Epstein, Schmidt, & Warfel, 2008), training such competencies
improved test scores and led to a significant increase in creative output.
Personal Creativity
Much of the research cited above examined creative products. This is actu-
ally true of the entire field of creative studies; as of late, there is a tendency to
focus on products and relegate creative processes. When college students are
employed in research, products such as poems or collages are assessed. When
unambiguously creative persons are studied, their productivity (e.g., inven-
tions, paintings, publications) are counted. This all makes for highly objective
research, but it means that findings – including those concerning motivation
and creativity – may not apply to everyday creativity and creative efforts that
do not lead to a product.
There is good reason to postulate a strong tie between the creative process
and intrinsic motivation. This follows most recently from Runco’s (1995, 1996,
2011a) theory of personal creativity and older theories of cognitive develop-
ment (Piaget, 1970). The theory of personal creativity was in fact proposed in
response to the same product bias that was just described. It posits that cre-
ative products, be they everyday insights and solutions or world class break-
throughs, must begin with an original interpretation of experience. This is
something each of us can do, and we do it regularly. We do not, however,
construct original interpretations unless we need to do so. It is easier, and
often entirely effective, to rely on experience, assumption, and routine, and
thus to use the same old solution or interpretation we always have. We can,
however, if motivated to do so, put the effort into constructing a new inter-
pretation. In fact, it may be that this is a critical individual difference that
Creativity and Motivation 475
might predict creative accomplishment; some people may be more likely than
others to construct original interpretations.
Two of the claims above are quite important. The first is that everyone
shares the capacity to construct original interpretations. This in turn implies
that the capacity for personal creativity is widely distributed; it is not some-
thing only the highly talented possess. The second claim is that the capacity
for creativity – again, the capacity to construct original interpretations – is
not used unless the individual is motivated to do so. This is where cognitive
developmental theory comes in. Piaget (1970), for example, put great weight
on the importance of assimilation. It works along with accommodation when
an individual adapts to his or her environment. Assimilation occurs when
information is altered, as needed, in order to fit with existing structures and
understandings. Accommodation, on the other hand, occurs when structures
change in order to take new information into account. Accommodation may
be at work when there is an a-ha moment or insight; as such, it may play a role
in some creative accomplishment (Gruber, 1981). Assimilation, on the other
hand, plays a large role in imagination. It allows the person to transcend real-
ity, even if briefly. It is also a synonym for personal interpretation.
What is most relevant is Piaget’s idea (1976, 1981) that humans are biolog-
ically predisposed to understand their experiences – to develop and adapt.
His theory was best labeled genetic epistemology precisely for this reason.
Further, he argued that we are motivated to adapt, to understand. For Piaget,
intrinsic motivation is a natural by-product or interaction with the environ-
ment. Whenever an individual encounters something he or she does not
understand, there is an interest in assimilating, then accommodating, and in
developing a new understanding.
What we have, then, is an explanation for why individuals person might be
intrinsically interested in constructing new interpretations. They are simply
reacting to situations that allow or even call for adaptation. That adaptation
may benefit from assimilation – that is, interpretation – and the interpreta-
tion may be original.
Creativity is not synonymous with adaptability. I touched on this elsewhere:
Many human behaviors–and especially those of older and mature individuals – are
directed towards the conservation of resources (e.g., energy), and thus towards effi-
ciency. We develop routines, for example, to make our lives easier. Creative behav-
ior is typically very different. Frequently creative inventions make our lives easier,
but the discovery of the necessary technologies may require a huge amount of effort
and avoidance of routine. Creative behavior is not necessarily efficient behavior, nor
even always adaptive . . . and the motivations to act in a creative fashion or develop
competencies for creative work are similarly unique. (Runco, 2005b)
476 Runco & McGarva
Indeed, sometimes it is most adaptive to conform and sit into some social situ-
ation, rather than impose an original action. Further, creative behavior is some-
times clearly maladaptive, at least for the individual. Consider in this regard the
costs to creativity, health, or social acceptance. (Ludwig, 1995)
One thing may not have jumped out of the review presented above: moti-
vation is not simply an affective influence on creativity. It is more than emo-
tion. It is also related to thinking and cognition. This may be clearest in the
theory of personal creativity. Recall that the intrinsic motivation to construct
original interpretations resulted from the inborn drive to understand as well
as the lack of understanding. Ideas and insights, in this light, are constructed
to facilitate adaptation. Some of them might be elaborated and eventually
creative. What is most relevant here is that the motivation is a result of the
cognitive predicament. There is, in that light, a process that requires both
affect and cognition. Admittedly, there is some debate over which comes first,
the affect or the cognition (Lazarus, 1991a, 1991b; Zajonc, 1980), but to us it
seems most realistic to accept the fact that humans are complicated; we have
emotions and thoughts. We might attempt to delineate them and argue which
is first, but in fact they work together. They are both a part of what it means
to be human, and they both play a role in creative efforts.
References
Abra, J. (1988). Assaulting Parnassus Theoretical views of creativity. Lanham, MD:.
University Press of America.
Albert, R. S., & Runco, M. A. (2006). Parents’ personality and the creative potential of
exceptionally gifted boys. Creativity Research Journal, 17, 355–367.
Amabile, T. M. (1990). Within you, without you: Towards a social psychology of creativity
and beyond. In M. A. Runco & R. S. Albert (Eds.), Theories of creativity (pp. 61–91).
Newbury Park, CA: Sage Publications.
Amabile, T. (1996). Creativity in context. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Andreasen, N. (1997). Creativity and mental illness: Prevalence rates in writers and
their first-degree relatives. In M. A. Runco & R. Richards (Eds.), Eminent creativity,
everyday creativity, and health (pp. 7–18). Norwood, NJ: Ablex.
Barron, F. (1963). The need for order and for disorder as motives in creative activity. In
C. W. Taylor & F. Barron (Eds.), Scientific creativity: Its recognition and development
(pp. 153–160). New York: Wiley.
(1972). Artists in the making. New York: Seminar Press.
(1995). No rootless flower: An ecology of creativity. Cresskill, NJ: Hampton Press.
Campbell, D. (1960). Blind variation and selective retention in creative thought as in
other knowledge processes. Psychological Review, 67, 380–400.
Chown, S. M. (1961). Age and the rigidities. Journal of Gerontology, 16, 353–362.
Cox, C. M. (1926). Genetic studies of genius. Vol. 2: The early mental traits of three hun-
dred geniuses. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Csikszentmihalyi, M. (1975). Beyond boredom and anxiety. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.
(1988). The dangers of originality: Creativity and the artistic process. In M. M. Gedo
(Ed.), Psychoanalytic perspectives on art (pp. 213–224). Hillsdale, NJ: Analytic
Press.
Creativity and Motivation 479
(1990). The domain of creativity. In M. A. Runco & R. S. Albert (Eds.), Theories of cre-
ativity (pp. 190–212). Newbury Park, CA: Sage Publications.
(1996). Creativity: Flow and the psychology of discovery and invention. New York:
HarperCollins.
Davis, G. (1999). Barriers to creativity and creative attitudes. In M. A. Runco & S. Pritzker
(Eds.), Encyclopedia of creativity (pp. 165–174). San Diego, CA: Academic Press.
Deci, R. L., & Ryan, R. M. (1985). Intrinsic motivation and self-determination in human
behavior. New York: Plenum.
Díaz de Chumaceiro, C. L. (2004). Serendipity and Pseudo-Serendipity in Career Paths of
Successful Women: Orchestra Conductors. Creativity Research Journal, 16, 345–356.
Dudek, S. Z., & Hall W. (1991). Personality consistency: Eminent architects 25 years later.
Creativity Research Journal, 4, 213–232.
Eisenberger, R., & Shanock, L. (2003). Reward, intrinsic motivation, and creativity: A
case study of conceptual and methodological isolation. Creativity Research Journal,
15, 121–130.
Eisenman, R. (1997). Creativity, preference for complexity, and physical and mental
health. In M. A. Runco & R. Richards (Eds.), Eminent creativity, everyday creativity,
and health (pp. 99–106). Norwood, NJ: Ablex.
Elliot, A. J. (1997). Integrating “classic” and “contemporary” approaches to achievement
motivation: A hierarchical model of approach and avoidance achievement moti-
vation. In P. Pintrich & M. Maehr (Eds.), Advances in motivation and achievement
(vol. 10, pp. 143–179). Greenwich, CT: JAI Press.
(1999). Approach and avoidance motivation and achievement goals. Educational
Psychologist, 34, 149–169.
Elliot, A. J., & McGregor, H. A. (2001). A 2 x 2 achievement goal framework. Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology, 80, 501–519.
Epstein, E., Schmidt, S. M., & Warfel, R. (2008). Measuring and Training Creativity
Competencies: Validation of a New Test. Creativity Research Journal, 20, 7–12.
Epstein, R. (1990). Generativity theory as a theory of creativity. In M. A. Runco & R. S.
Albert (Eds.), Theories of creativity (pp. 116–140). Newbury Park, CA: Sage.
Finke, R., 1990. Creative imagery: Discoveries and inventions in visualization. Hillsdale,
NJ: Erlbaum.
Freud, S. (1966). The standard edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund
Freud. London: Hoarth.
Galton, F. (1869). Hereditary genius. New York: MacMillan.
Goetz, E. M., & Baer, D. M. (1973). Social control of form diversity and the emergence
of new forms in children’s blockbuilding. Journal of Applied Behavior Analysis, 6,
209–217.
Gough, H. G., & Bradley, P. (1999). Manual for the California Psychological Inventory, 3rd
ed. Palo Alto, CA: Consulting Psychologists Press.
Gruber, H. E. (1981). On the relation between ‘a ha’ experiences and the construction of
ideas. History of Science, 19, 41–59.
(1988). The evolving systems approach to creative work. Creativity Research Journal,
1, 27–51.
Hayes, J. R. (1978). Cognitive psychology. Homewood, IL: Dorsey.
Heinzen, T. (1994). Situational affect: Proactive and reactive creativity. In M. A. Runco &
M. Shaw (Eds.), Creativity and affect (pp. 127–146). Norwood, NJ: Ablex.
480 Runco & McGarva
Richards (Eds.), Eminent creativity, everyday creativity, and health (pp. 287–392).
Norwood, NJ: Ablex.
Perry, S. (1999). Writing in flow. New York: Writer’s Digest Books.
Piaget, J. (1970). Piaget’s theory. In P. H. Mussen (Ed.), Carmichael’s handbook of child
psychology (3rd ed., pp. 703–732). New York: Wiley
(1976). To understand is to invent. New York: Penguin.
(1981). Foreword. In H. E. Gruber (Ed.), Darwin on man: A psychological study of sci-
entific creativity. Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press.
Piirto, J. (1998). Understanding those who create. 2nd Ed. Scottsdale, AZ: Gifted
Psychology Press
Pryor, K. W., Hoag, R., & O’Reilly, J. (1969).The creative porpoise: Training for novel
behavior. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 12, 653–662.
Rhodes, M. (1961). An analysis of creativity. Phi Delta Kappan, 42, 305–310.
Richards, R. (1999). The subtle attraction: Beauty as a force in awareness, creativity and
survival. In S. W. Russ (Ed.), Affect, creative experience and psychological adjust-
ment (pp.195–219). Philadelphia: Brunner/Mazel.
Rivers-Norton, J. (2002). Creativity as an agent of change: Transforming childhood
adversity through literary regeneration and the poser of place. The International
Journal of Environmental, Cultural, Economic and Social Sustainability, 1, 31–38.
Rogers, C. R. (1961). On becoming a person. Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin.
Root-Bernstein, R. (1988). Discovering. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Rothenberg, A. (1990). Creativity, mental health, and alcoholism. Creativity Research
Journal, 3, 179–201.
Rubenson, D. L., & Runco, M. A. (1992). The psychoeconomic approach to creativity.
New Ideas in Psychology, 10, 131–147.
(1995). The psychoeconomic view of creative work in groups and organizations.
Creativity and Innovation Management, 4, 232–241.
Runco, M. A. (1987). The generality of creative performance in gifted and nongifted chil-
dren. Gifted Child Quarterly, 31, 121–25.
(1993). Operant theories of insight, originality, and creativity. American Behavioral
Scientist, 37, 59–74.
(1994a). Creativity and its discontents. In M. P. Shaw & M. A. Runco (Eds.), Creativity
and affect (pp. 102–123). Norwood, NJ: Ablex.
Runco, M. A. (Ed.) (1994b). Problem finding, problem solving, and creativity. Norwood,
NJ: Ablex.
Runco, M. A. (1995). Insight for creativity, expression for impact. Creativity Research
Journal, 8, 377–390.
(1996). Personal creativity: Definition and developmental issues. New Directions for
Child Development, No. 72 (Summer), pp. 3–30.
(2011a). Personal creativity. In M. A. Runco & S. Pritzker (Eds.), Encyclopedia of crea-
tivity (2nd ed., pp. ). San Diego, CA: Academic Press.
(2011b). Tactics and strategies for creativity. In M. A. Runco & S. Pritzker (Eds.),
Encyclopedia of creativity (2nd ed., pp. 423–426). San Diego, CA: Academic Press.
(2003). Creativity, cognition, and their educational implications. In J. C. Houtz (Ed.),
The educational psychology of creativity (pp. 25–56). Cresskill, NJ: Hampton Press.
(2005a). Creative giftedness. In R. S. Sternberg & J. E. Davidson (Eds.), Conceptions of
giftedness (rev. ed.) (pp. 295–311). New York: Cambridge University Press.
482 Runco & McGarva
483
484 Index
need for cognitive closure. 16. See also need for object constancy, 150–151
closure; closure motivation perceptual illusions, 291
negotiation behavior, 22, See negotiation perceptual systems, 290
nervous system, 140, 145, 183 signal detection, 461
central nervous system, 181, 215 social perception, 161
neurons, 182 three dimensional construction of
plasticity, 225 space, 184
nervous systems, 181, 187 perceptual defense, 69
neural networks, 87 period of enlightment, 175
neural systems, 77, 113 person representations
neurobiology, 137 relative accessibility, 161
neurochemistries, 120 personality, 1, 33, 35, 50, 62, 64, 70, 96
neurological disorders, 85 anxious and explosive personality, 203
neurophysiology, 137 dispositions, 161
nigrostriatal pathways extraversion, 225
movements, 122 five factor model of personality (FFM), 227
norm representation individual differences, 311
norm of cooperation, 165 introverts, 225
norms, 63 neuroticism, 226
personal attributes, 161
octopamine, 124 self esteem, 297
onomatopoeia, 415 sense of SELF, 121
ontogeny, 138, 141 the self, 160
optimism, 162 traits, 203
organisms, 174–176, 178–179, 182, 184–186, 188 value system, 308
autonomous organisms, 188 personality cognition overlap, 66
biological organisms, 174 personality disorders, 64
constructional constraints, 180 personality traits, 56–57, 62–66, 68, 70–73,
emancipation, 187 79, 85
energy converters, 179 agreeableness, 65
excitations and irritations, 183 conscientiousness, 65
head capsules, 187 introversion/extroversion, 65
hydraulic systems, 180 meaning variables, 56
inner spaces, 187 neuroticism, 65
locomotor apparatus, 183 P-FIT model
machines, 175 processing of sensory information, 221
motorium, 181 solutions to a given problem, 221
musculature, 181 structural symbolism, 221
organismic autonomy, 186 philosophy, 173
organismic complexity, 187 analytical philosophy, 339
organismic constructions, 181–182, 184 constructivism, 187
rhythmical activity, 180, 183 natural philosophy, 188
sensorium, 181 polarity, 175
sensory organs, 184 Whitehead’s concepts, 188
vertebrate eyes, 183 phylogenetic approach, 138, 141
orienting response, 39 phylogenetic perspective, 138
out group behaviors, 21 phylogeny. See phylogenetic approach
physical health, 33, 198
perception, 78, 80, 142–143 physics, 111, 327, 331
background, 159 physiological homeostasis, 141
focal objects, 159–160 physiological processes, 138
network of perceptions, 186 plants, 130–131
Index 503