Mike Hawkins - Social Darwinism in European and American Thought, 1860-1945 - Nature As Model and Nature As Threat (1997)
Mike Hawkins - Social Darwinism in European and American Thought, 1860-1945 - Nature As Model and Nature As Threat (1997)
Mike Hawkins - Social Darwinism in European and American Thought, 1860-1945 - Nature As Model and Nature As Threat (1997)
Mike Hawkins
Kingston University
CAMBRIDGE
UNIVERSITY PRESS
PUBLISHED BY THE PRESS SYNDICATE OF THE UNIVERSITY OF CAMBRIDGE
The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge CB2 1RP, United Kingdom
CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS
The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge CB2 2RU, UK http://www.cup.cam.ac.uk
40 West 20th Street, New York, NY 10011-4211, USA http://www.cup.org
10 Stamford Road, Oakleigh, Melbourne 3166, Australia
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library
Acknowledgements page x
Bibliography 314
Index 335
Acknowledgements
This book has been a long time in the making, as a result of which I have
incurred many debts from friends, colleagues and family. Since it is
those closest to me who have borne the brunt of my absences and mood
swings, I would like to record my gratitude to Jacquie, Sarah and
Elizabeth for their support, encouragement and forbearance over many
years, and additionally for Jacquie's editing and proofreading skills. As
to friends and colleagues, special thanks are due to Steve Woodbridge
for his help in tracing sources, discussing ideas and reading drafts; to
Keith Reader, Steve Bastow and Andrea Hawkins for their assistance
with translations; and to Mike Giddy for enabling me to approach
matters from a different - if not always sober - angle. The following also
contributed ideas, criticisms and documents: Chris Alderman, Paul
Auerbach, Phylomena Badsey, Joe Bailey, Peter Beck (who suggested
the project in the first place), Gail Cunningham, Chris French, the late
Ivan Hannaford, John Ibbett, Simon Locke, Bill Pickering, Anne Poole,
Christine Pullen, Phil Spencer, Terry Sullivan, Marie Turner and Keith
Weightman. Thanks also to two anonymous readers for Cambridge
University Press, and to Richard Fisher, the Social Science Publishing
Director at Cambridge, for his encouragement and patience. The
Faculty of Human Sciences at Kingston University provided me with
two small research grants which enabled me to devote time to the book
at crucial stages in its development. None of the above are, of course,
responsible for the interpretations and any errors this book contains, but
without them it would not have been written.
Parti
Defining Social Darwinism
What is Social Darwinism, and what role has it played in the history of
social and political ideas? These questions, the point of departure for the
present study, are simple to formulate but, as the historiography of
Social Darwinism attests, difficult to answer. Anyone consulting the vast
literature on Social Darwinism in the hope of resolving them is likely to
experience confusion rather than enlightenment. What he or she will
encounter are heated controversies over a number of issues. First,
scholars dispute the definition of Social Darwinism and, as a conse-
quence, who is to count as a 'genuine' Social Darwinist. Second, they
disagree over the ideological functions of Social Darwinism with some
insisting on its conservative bias whereas others emphasise its reformist -
even radical - orientation. Third, there is controversy over the
significance of Social Darwinism, with positions ranging from the claim
that it was both widespread and influential, to the contrary view that its
importance has been grossly exaggerated by hostile commentators.
Finally, scholars contest the relationship between Social Darwinism and
Darwin himself, broadly dividing between those who see a connection
and those who insist on a radical difference between the work of the
English naturalist and the ideological uses to which his ideas were put.
This dissension has helped to define the aims and the contents of this
book. Indeed, it is my view that any attempt to understand the
emergence and history of Social Darwinism must first come to grips
with these disputes: appreciating the points at issue and the controversies
they have aroused is a first step towards a different approach to the
subject. For this reason, it is useful to review each of these areas of
disagreement in turn.
6
B. Kidd, Social Evolution (London: Macmillan, 1894), 245.
7
This is acknowledged by Jones, Social Darwinism, 122.
8
R. Williams, 'Social Darwinism', in J. Benthall, ed., The Limits of Human Nature
(London: Allen Lane, 1973), 117.
9
On the prevalence of notions of degeneration during this period, see J. Chamberlin and
S. Gilman, eds., Degeneration (New York: Columbia University Press, 1985); D. Pick,
Faces of Degeneration (Cambridge University Press, 1989).
10
C. Watts, A Preface to Conrad (London: Longman, 1982), 182-3. Watts discusses the
cultural impact of this nightmare, 86-8. See also G. Myers, 'Nineteenth Century
Popularizations of Thermodynamics and the Rhetoric of Social Prophesy', Victorian
Studies, 29(1985), 35-66.
11
G. Vacher de Lapouge, Les Selections sociales (Paris: Fontemoing, 1896), 446, 449;
Lapouge, UAryen (Paris: Fontemoing, 1899), vii, 512.
6 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
Focusing on the interrelationships and relative weighting of the different
ingredients of Social Darwinism produces a richer and more useful
understanding of it. This is not to say that all problems pertaining to the
classification of particular theorists are eliminated. Any definitional
framework is bound to encounter 'hard cases' - instances where it is
difficult to determine whether the relevant criteria have been satisfied.
The framework proposed in the next chapter is no exception in this
respect. But it has the advantage of discriminating between thinkers who
embrace the configuration as a whole, including the 'rules' for inter-
connecting its different components, and those who make use of some
of these components within a different, perhaps even antithetical, dis-
cursive framework. Social Darwinism must be seen as a network of inter-
linked ideas, subject to change over time - particularly with regard to the
relationships among these ideas - but retaining its overall identity
notwithstanding these modifications.
Some commentators have denned Social Darwinism as the explicit
endorsement of Darwin's theory of evolution, leaving open the issue of
the actual content of this theory.12 The problem with this approach is
that it includes theorists who, while seeking to legitimate their ideas by
claiming their provenance in Darwin, in fact propounded doctrines
which were at variance with the fundamental premisses of Darwinism.
This is true of much of what has been labelled 'reform Darwinism'. On
the other hand, this tactic would lead to the exclusion of Spencer who
objected to being referred to as a Darwinist because he had arrived at
this theory independently of Darwin's work.13 Defining Social Darwin-
ism in terms of an express commitment to Darwin's ideas in the context
of social theory is, therefore, unsatisfactory.
In an effort to introduce more specificity into the notion of Social
Darwinism, some historians have recommended equating it with
eugenics, or at least including the latter as part of the definition.14 The
problem with conflating Social Darwinism with eugenics, however, is
that it was possible to support one and not the other. Thus Benjamin
Kidd, though a Social Darwinist, was a severe critic of eugenics, while
12
J. R. Moore, 'Varieties of Social Darwinism', Open University Course A309, Conflict
and Stability in the Development of Modern Europe (Milton Keynes: Open University
Press, 1980), 37. See also A. Kelly, The Descent of Darwin (Chapel Hill: University of
North Carolina Press, 1981), 103.
13
See H. Spencer, 'Reponse a M. Emile de Laveleye', in E. Laveleye, Le Socialisme
contemporaine, fourth edn (Paris: Alcan, 1888), 409.
14
For the first tactic, see R. J. Halliday, 'Social Darwinism: A Definition', Victorian
Studies, 14(1971), 401; for the second, see D. P. Crook, 'Darwinism: The Political
Implications', History of European Ideas, 2(1981), 19. Not all historians, however, regard
eugenicists as bona fide Social Darwinists. See Bannister, Social Darwinism, 166;
C. Degler, In Search of Human Nature (Oxford University Press, 1991), 42.
The identity of Social Darwinism 7
George Bernard Shaw endorsed eugenics with enthusiasm but was
dismissive of Darwinism.15 Hence while there was often a very close
association between eugenics and Social Darwinism, it provides insuffi-
cient warrant for conflating them.
If this last approach is overly restrictive, then equating Social
Darwinism with a belief in the beneficial effects of warfare sins in the
opposite direction. This connection was made at the start of the present
century by the Russian-born businessman and sociologist, Jacques
Novicow (1849-1912), who proclaimed Social Darwinism to be a
doctrine which believed human progress had occurred through 'collec-
tive homicide'.16 He then proceeded to label as Social Darwinist
anybody who proffered a positive assessment of warfare irrespective of
the basis upon which this assessment was made. As a result Novicow
included many writers who were manifestly not Darwinists, in addition
to misrepresenting the views of genuine Social Darwinists who were
explicitly opposed to warfare between civilised nations - Spencer being a
notable but by no means the only example.17 The result of this type of
procedure is to deprive the notion of Social Darwinism of any specific
content and hence of any value in the analysis of ideas.
These disagreements over the intention of the term Social Darwinism
are not trivial matters of academic hair-splitting, for, as we shall see, they
have important ramifications for other areas of controversy.
29
Kelly, Descent, 101; Bannister, Social Darwinism, 9, and 'Survival of the Fittest', 398.
Crook, while critical of the revisionists, nevertheless agrees that 'There were no schools
of Social Darwinists': Darwinism, War and History, 204.
30
For Haeckel, see Kelly, Descent, 113; on Sumner, see R. Bannister, 'William Graham
Sumner's Social Darwinism: A Reconsideration', History of Political Economy, 4(1973),
89-109.
31
Leeds, 'Darwinian and "Darwinian" Evolutionism', 4 3 7 - 8 .
32
Bannister, Social Darwinism, 231.
The identity of Social Darwinism 11
Darwinism certainly played a formative role in the development of
psychology.33 Darwin's own attempts to derive human mental traits
from an animal origin were an important influence on the work of the
British psychologist George Romanes. 34 This influence is also evident in
the social psychology of the American William James (1842-1910), who
sought evolutionary explanations for such human instincts as acquisi-
tiveness, fear, play and pugnacity, and repeatedly cited Darwin's
authority.35 The impact of Darwinism is equally discernible in the
emerging disciplines of sexology, psychiatry and psychoanalysis. In the
latter instance, one historian has described the work of Sigmund Freud
(1856-1939) as a 'psychobiology of mind' in which Darwinism supplied
a framework for the investigation not only of mental pathologies but also
of the origins of morality and civilisation.36
It is more difficult to assess the legacy of Social Darwinism in
anthropology, sociology and political science, due to the absence of
detailed studies of certain key contributors. Some theorists were overtly
hostile to Darwinism, like Gaetano Mosca (1858-1931), who, in his
efforts to establish a science of politics, denied any role to natural
selection and the struggle for existence. 37 Vilfredo Pareto (1848-1923)
was likewise critical of Social Darwinism which, he believed, required
'considerable modification' if it was to be of service to the social
sciences. 38 Nevertheless, Pareto accepted the existence of adaptation
and the struggle for survival in social life, suggesting a more complex
(and perhaps ambivalent) stance vis-d-vis Darwinism on his part which
would repay closer investigation.39
The position of the German sociologist Max Weber (1864-1920) is
also a complex one. Weber's inaugural address of 1895 at the University
of Freiburg contained strong echoes of Social Darwinism. Referring to
relations between Germans and Poles in East Prussia, Weber remarked
that 'the free play of the forces of selection does not always operate in
33
E. Boring, A History of Experimental Psychology, second edn ( N e w York: Appleton-
Century-Crofts, 1950), 7 4 3 .
34
See the comments by Romanes in the preface to his Animal Intelligence, sixth edn
(London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Triibner, 1895), vi, xi.
35
William James, The Principles of Psychology, 2 vols. [1890] (London: Constable and C o . ,
1950), especially II, chaps. 2 4 - 8 .
36
F. J. Sulloway, Freud, Biologist of the Mind (London: Fontana, 1980), 275 and chap. 10.
See also C. Badcock, Psycho-Darwinism (London: HarperCollins, 1994).
37
G. Mosca, The Ruling Class, tr. H. Kahn ( N e w York: McGraw-Hill, 1939), 2 8 - 3 1 ,
121-3.
38
S. E. Finer, ed., Vilfredo Pareto: Sociological Writings, tr. D . Mirfin (Oxford: Blackwell,
1966), 213.
39
Ibid., 102, 1 1 3 - 1 4 . There is a discussion of the role of Social Darwinism in Pareto's
work in T . Parsons, The Structure of Social Action, 2 vols. (London: Collier-Macmillan,
1968), I, 2 1 9 - 2 8 .
12 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
favour of the nationality which is economically the more highly
developed or better endowed'. He went on to attack optimists who
imagined 'anything other than the hard struggle of man with man can
create any elbow room in this earthly life', and urged acceptance of cthe
eternal struggle to preserve and raise the quality of our national species'.40
Yet Weber was subsequently to express considerable scepticism over the
utility of Social Darwinism. He undoubtedly saw conflict as a constant
and multi-dimensional facet of social reality, and occasionally made use
of terms like 'the material struggle for existence'.41 But he explicitly
eschewed Darwinian accounts of the collapse of ancient civilisations and
was critical of the transfer of the concept of adaptation from biology to
sociology.42 Weber perhaps furnishes an example of an attempt to
emancipate sociology from the influence of pervasive biological models
of social relationships.
This would certainly be a valid assessment of the work of the French
sociologist, Emile Durkheim (1858-1917). In his first major publication
in 1893 Durkheim explicitly made use of the struggle for existence
among conspecifics to explain the high levels of occupational specialisa-
tion found in civilised societies.43 This is no mere passing reference
since Durkheim's argumentation made extensive use of Darwinism and
relied upon parallels between the growth of the social division of labour
and zoological processes.44 But thereafter, while retaining an interest in
evolutionary themes in his work on pedagogy and penal law, Durkheim
did not make use of Darwinism. On the contrary, his remarks on
Darwinism were dismissive and his attitude to Social Darwinists was
invariably hostile.45 This is not difficult to understand in the light of
Durkheim's mission to establish sociology as an autonomous science,
not to mention the sensitivity of a Jew and a Dreyfusard to the racialist
possibilities of biological reductionism in the highly charged ideological
40
M . Weber, ' T h e Nation State and Economic Policy', in Weber, Political Writings, ed.
P. Lassman and R. Speirs (Cambridge University Press, 1994), 1 1 , 14, 17, original
emphasis. See Weikart, ' T h e Origins of Social Darwinism in Germany', 482; H . Gerth
and C. Wright Mills, eds., 'Introduction' to From Max Weber (London: Routledge and
K e g a n P a u l , 1948), 1 1 .
41
F o r example, in M . Weber, The Methodology of the Social Sciences, tr. E. Shils and H . A.
Finch (New York: T h e Free Press, 1949), 2 6 - 7 .
42
M. Weber, The Agrarian Sociology of Ancient Civilisations, tr. R. Frank (London: NLB,
1976), 390, 408; Weber, Methodology, 2 5 - 6 .
43
E. Durkheim, The Division of Labour in Society, tr. W. Halls (London: Macmillan,
1984), Book II, chaps. 2 - 4 .
44
Ibid., 277. There is a detailed analysis of Durkheim's use of Social Darwinism in this
text in M . Hawkins, 'Durkheim, the Division of Labour and Social Darwinism', History
of European Ideas, 22(1996) 19-31.
45
Hawkins, *ta*.
The identity of Social Darwinism 13
atmosphere of the Third Republic.46 But the fact that even a theorist like
Durkheim was tempted to make use of Social Darwinism is surely
indicative of a pervasive and prestigious theoretical presence. That this
presence also existed in the United States is evidenced by the work of
the sociologist Lester Frank Ward (1841-1913). Ward was critical of the
use made of Darwinism by apologists for laissez-faire and unrestrained
economic competition, whom he accused of ignoring the role of
invention in social evolution, the effect of which was 'the reduction of
competition in the struggle for existence and the protection of the
weaker members'.47 Nevertheless, Ward's own theoretical writings
made considerable use of Darwinism. Ward depicted the struggle for
existence as acting primarily upon social structures rather than upon
individuals, races or societies, although he believed racial struggle
through warfare had played a vital role in progress.48 Furthermore,
Ward was one of the few social theorists to endorse sexual selection,
which he used to account for the differentiation of the sexes and the
subordination of women.49
I am not claiming that Pareto, Weber, Ward or Durkheim were Social
Darwinists. But the fact that all of them utilised Darwinism at certain
points in their careers surely suggests that Social Darwinism cannot be
dismissed as marginal or as the construct of later historians and social
critics. On the contrary, these examples indicate that Social Darwinism
was an omnipresent reality for the practitioners of the social sciences
during this period. Even when not adopting it as such, theorists
sometimes found it difficult to avoid (or resist) the language of selection
and survival of the fittest.50 To designate Social Darwinism as a 'straw
46
Although he repudiated biological reductionism, Durkheim remained ambivalent over
the social significance of biology. This is apparent in his treatment of suicide and
gender, and in his eventual endorsement of a homo-duplex model of human nature in
which the psyche is divided between a pre-social and a social component. O n the first
point see H. Kushner, 'Suicide, Gender and the Fear of Modernity in Nineteenth
Century Medical and Social Thought', Journal of Social History, 2 6 ( 1 9 9 3 ) , 472; on the
second, M . J. Hawkins, 'A Re-examination of Durkheim's Theory of H u m a n Nature',
Sociological Review, 2 5 ( 1 9 7 7 ) , 2 2 9 - 5 2 .
47
L. F. Ward, 'Mind as a Social Factor', in D . A. Hollinger and C. Capper, eds., The
American Intellectual Tradition, 2 vols., second edn ( N e w York: Oxford University Press,
1993), II, 47.
48
L. F. Ward, Pure Sociology ( N e w York: Macmillan, 1903), 184, 2 3 8 - 4 0 .
49
Ibid., 3 2 3 et seq. Ward's ambivalence towards Darwinism has been noted by Lewis
Coser, 'American Trends', in T . Bottomore and R. A. Nisbet, eds., A History of
Sociological Analysis (London: Heinemann, 1979), 2 9 8 - 3 0 0 .
50
This is the case with Edward Tylor, whose non-Darwinian stage-theory of social
evolution occasionally referred to selection, struggle and survival of the fittest. See his
Anthropology (London: Macmillan, 1892), 6, 55, 4 1 2 - 1 3 , 4 2 7 . T h e contexts suggest
that Tylor largely confined struggle to primitive phases of evolution, to be replaced by
'peaceful and profitable intercourse' among civilised nations (286).
14 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
man' is, therefore, to misinterpret the intellectual context in which the
social and psychological sciences were forged and developed.51
55
Examples of this perspective can be found in J. C. Greene, Science, Ideology and World
View (Berkeley, CA: University of Berkeley Press, 1981); R. M. Young, Darwin's
Metaphor (Cambridge University Press, 1985); Young, 'Darwinism is Social', in
D . Kohn, ed., The Darwinian Heritage (Princeton University Press, 1985), 609-38;
G. Jones, 'The Social History of Darwin's Descent of Man\ Economy and Society,
7(1978), 1-23. The most sustained effort to locate Darwin's work within his intellectual
and social milieu is A. Desmond and J. Moore, Darwin (London: Faber and Faber,
1991).
56
Greene, Science, Ideology and World View, 134, 140. See also Greene, Darwin and the
Modern World View (Baton Rouge, LA: Mentor, 1963), 8 4 - 9 .
57
R. M. Young, 'Malthus and the Evolutionists: The Common Context of Biological and
Social Theory', Past and Present, 43(1969), 111-12. See also B. Gale, 'Darwin and the
Concept of Struggle for Existence: A Study in the Extrascientific Origins of Scientific
Ideas', Isis, 63(1972 ), 321-44.
58
P. Q. Hirst, Social Evolution and Sociological Categories (London: Allen and Unwin,
1976), 19-22.
59
Bannister, Social Darwinism, 25; Crook, Darwinism, War and History, 17. Bowler
maintains that while Malthus did focus on intrasocial struggle, he confined this to
primitive rather than modern European societies. See P. Bowler, 'Malthus, Darwin,
and the Concept ofStruggle', Journal ofthe History of Ideas, 37(1976), 636.
16 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
allowed Darwin to see was 'the third and most important aspect of
struggle - that between closely related members of the same species'. 60
This last controversy is connected to the debates over the definition of
Social Darwinism in that often disagreements derive from different
understandings of the discursive entities under consideration - Darwin-
ism, Malthusianism and Social Darwinism. Once again, it underscores
the need for a conceptualisation of Darwinism which relates a notion
like 'struggle for existence' to other components in the overall configur-
ation. As I stated above, this procedure will not eliminate disagreement
and different readings; but it will facilitate a fuller understanding of the
configuration in question and the extent to which, if at all, its various
elements are comparable to those contained in other discursive entities.
60
P. Vorzimmer, 'Darwin, Malthus and the Theory of Natural Selection', Journal of the
History of Ideas, 3 0 ( 1 9 6 9 ) , 540. See also S. Herbert, 'Darwin, Malthus and Selection',
Journal of the History of Biology, 4 ( 1 9 7 1 ) , 2 0 9 - 1 7 .
61
P. Bowler, 'Social Darwinism', Sunday Correspondent, 13 May 1990.
62
T h e following examples, appearing in the British national press around the time Bowler
published his comments, made extensive use of Darwinian terminology in the context
of international economic competition and the policies of the Thatcher governments
respectively: Guy de Jonquieres, 'The Survival of the Fittest', Financial Times, 10 May
1990; T o n y Cole, 'Surplice to Requirements', New Statesman and Society, 4 May 1990.
63
R. Dawkins, The Selfish Gene, second edn (Oxford University Press, 1989), chap. 11.
The identity of Social Darwinism 17
term 'Social Darwinism'. This alone would furnish sufficient justifica-
tion for seeking a better grasp of the ideas and images in question. But I
have an additional reason: to show that the term is capable of being
constructed and used in a way that is invaluable for an understanding of
certain features of both historical and contemporary socio-political
discourse.
The first step towards realising this goal is to conceptualise Social
Darwinism. This is the task of the next chapter, which reconstructs the
set of assumptions that underpinned Darwin's theory of evolution. My
thesis is that this network represents a world view - an abstract
configuration of interlinked ideas about time, nature, human nature and
social reality. It is this world view, rather than a discrete ideology, which
constitutes Social Darwinism, and Darwin himself was a major (though
by no means the only) contributor to its elaboration and dissemination.
The specific attributes of this world view are then illustrated through a
comparison between it and Lamarckism, followed by an assessment of
the historical uniqueness of Social Darwinism.
Of crucial importance to the development of my argument is the
contention that, as a world view, Darwinism is a powerful rhetorical
instrument. Its persuasive and flexible rhetorical resources derive from
the existence of indeterminacies within the world view itself, i.e. open-
endedness and even ambiguity over the precise meaning either of certain
key terms or over how they are to be related to other terms. However,
two series of events have consequences for these indeterminacies. The
first comprises developments within the theory of organic evolution
which 'close up' some of the original indeterminacies while at the same
time opening up others. The second derives from the very processes of
argumentation and ideological conflict through which the rhetorical and
ideological limits of Social Darwinism are realised. Both processes
interact to engender modifications of the original world view, in some
instances leading to the emergence of different world views - something
that happened, I shall argue, with certain versions of 'reform Darwin-
ism'.
The work of the social psychologist Michael Billig and his collabora-
tors on the rhetorical features of ideologies, and the inevitability of what
they refer to as dilemmas, is very suggestive for exploring the rhetorical
implications of Social Darwinism. Billig maintains that ideologies are
never closed systems of thought but languages within which any
proposition can be countered by contrary assertions, requiring delibera-
tion and the assessment of competing values.64 I have already proposed
64
See M. Billig, Arguing and Thinking (Cambridge University Press, 1987). See also Billig
etaly Ideological Dilemmas (London: Sage, 1988), 23, 163.
18 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
that Social Darwinism contains a series of indeterminacies which
provide a rich source for different rhetorical uses and interpretations.
But these always take place within a specific ideological context: Social
Darwinism, as a world view, was deployed as the background to different
ideological positions. Now it is precisely at the intersections between the
world view and the content of the ideology that some of the most
interesting and important dilemmas were encountered. In particular,
various ideologists discovered a persistent property of the world view,
namely that nature was janiform. It could appear both as a model to be
emulated by social practices and institutions and as a threat whose
processes and laws were to be feared and counteracted by the
appropriate actions. Of particular significance is the manner in which
this dual aspect of nature was manifested not simply in the competing
claims of rival ideologies or in different interpretations within the same
ideology, but often within the ideas of the same thinker, and sometimes
within the same text.
This janiform quality of Social Darwinist discourse will be explored in
part II of this study through an examination of some of the pioneers in
the construction, application and popularisation of the world view.
Certain of these thinkers are well known and their ideas have been
subjected to considerable scrutiny in the scholarly literature. My reason
for including them is that the definition of Social Darwinism used here,
and the focus upon the duality of nature as model and threat, allows
these writers to be examined in a new light, uncovering implications and
tensions that have received little or no attention in the historiography to
date but which are, I shall argue, fundamental to an understanding of
Social Darwinism. I shall also be including less well-known figures who
either exerted considerable influence in their time or else exemplified
features which typify in some manner a particular discursive tactic or
structure.
Part III comprises a series of case studies intended to illustrate the
role of Social Darwinism in different ideological contexts. The choice, in
addition to being constrained by considerations of time and space,
reflects a personal estimation about which of the many areas of social
and political controversy during the last century or so are significant or
interesting. Inevitably, not everybody will be satisfied with my selection,
and some may feel that certain topics, such as Fascism, have already
received a great deal of attention in the specialist literature. My purpose,
however, in examining any particular topic, is to understand the role of
Social Darwinism within it, and this is something which, though often
assumed in the specialist literature, is rarely subjected to any detailed
analysis.
The identity of Social Darwinism 19
The subject matter has been restricted in two ways. First, I have
concentrated on social and political thought and have not explored the
role of Social Darwinism in other contexts such as literature, the media
or the popular culture of different social strata. This undertaking is
beyond my resources and competence and, moreover, is dependent
upon the exercise attempted in this study, namely the clarification of the
nature and roles of Social Darwinism within its locus of origin - socio-
political thought. Second, I have taken the bulk of my material from the
period 1860-1945. These are the years during which Social Darwinism
appeared and developed and probably enjoyed its most widespread
appeal. Thereafter the topic would require a study in its own right,
especially in the light of the transformations that occurred within the
Darwinian theory of organic evolution, first with the 'Modern Synthesis'
of the 1930s and 1940s and then with the discovery of the structure of
DNA in 1953. There is, however, a concluding chapter on Social
Darwinism and sociobiology. This is included partly in order to test the
robustness of the conceptualisation of Social Darwinism in a very
different historical context. But it also derives from the specific features
of the controversies surrounding sociobiology which resonate some
interesting continuities, as well as exhibiting some differences, with the
earlier period. Again the hope is that this discussion of modern Social
Darwinism will stimulate further inquiry.
It will be apparent from these comments that this is not a history of
Social Darwinism in the conventional sense, i.e. it is not a narrative
which traces in detail the trajectory of the world view step by step
through time. In my view, this approach would be inappropriate at the
present time. This study is both more limited and yet more comprehen-
sive in scope. It is limited by its focus on a number of themes and
thinkers because I consider it essential to grasp the character of Social
Darwinism as a configuration of interlinked propositions and ideas and
to examine how this configuration was used in ideological debate. This
requires a detailed textual examination of the thinkers under discussion,
and such detail precludes extending the analysis to cover all the relevant
contributions. Some readers may well find the textual exegeses exces-
sive. But the understanding of Social Darwinism has been obscured by
the manner in which it has been treated in the majority of commentaries
- a cursory definition accompanied by the occasional citation from a
particular thinker. If the concern is with how ideas are interlinked and
with how they function in discursive practice then a more detailed
presentation of the texts under consideration is absolutely essential.
If this exercise necessitates a restriction of the number of texts under
examination, then the comparative features of the study add a degree of
20 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
breadth and generality to the conclusions which would be lacking had it
been confined to a specific country. Drawing upon material from
Europe and the USA opens up new possibilities for understanding and
interpretation, and allows for a fuller appreciation of what Social
Darwinism is and was, its different manifestations, and its importance in
Western culture.
1 Defining Social Darwinism
12
Greene, Science, Ideology and World View, 129; R. Korey, ed., The Essential Darwin
(Boston: Little, Brown, 1984), 243-4; D. Rochowiak, 'Darwin's Psychological
Theorising: Triangulating on Habit', Studies in History and Philosophy of Science,
19(1988), 238-9.
13
C. Darwin, Tlie Descent of Man, second edn (London: Murray, 1896), 91-2.
Defining Social Darwinism 27
action of the environment; now there is a large body of evidence.' 14 This
raises the issue of the relationship between the theories of Darwin and
Lamarck, which I shall discuss in the next chapter. For the moment I
simply want to make the point that any differentiation between the two
theories must be based upon more than the presence or absence of the
inheritance of acquired characters, since this mechanism occurs in both.
For this reason it is quite inappropriate to classify a theory as non-
Darwinian just because it accepts the inheritance of acquired characters.
Not only did Darwin grant a role to this mechanism, but it was endorsed
by many of his most fervent admirers, such as Ernst Haeckel in
Germany. As Greene has argued, the 'Lamarckian' principle of the
inheritance of acquired characters was not seen as a rival to natural
selection, but rather as a complementary process in evolution. 15
The theory of sexual selection was developed in the Descent. Here
Darwin agreed that many physical and behavioural traits of humans and
animals (such as the differences between races among the former) could
not be adequately explained by natural selection. On the contrary, some
features, like the ostentatious plumage of the peacock, would seem to
reduce the survival probabilities of the organism in question. Equally,
such traits were inexplicable by the direct action of the environment or
the inherited effects of use and disuse. In order to account for such
characteristics Darwin invoked another mechanism, sexual selection, or
the competition for sexual partners and the opportunity for procre-
ation. 16 This took place either through conflict between males for access
to large numbers of females (e.g. among stags in deer herds), or else
competition between males to attract females by means of display,
courtship patterns, etc. (as in the case of the peacock). The most
combative or attractive males, therefore, were able to reproduce at the
expense of their less successful conspecifics.
Despite concessions to use and disuse and to the inheritance of
acquired characters and his innovative model of sexual selection,
Darwin continued to make natural selection the touchstone of his theory
of evolution. This is evident in his treatment of human evolution.
Darwin avoided this topic in the Origin, which concluded with the vague
14
Darwin to M. Wagner, 13 October 1876, in F. Darwin, ed., Charles Darwin, second
edn (London: Murray, 1902), 278.
15
Greene, Science, Ideology and World View, 121. The accuracy of Greene's assessment is
borne out by the example of scientists who saw no difficulty in synthesising natural
selection and the inheritance of acquired characters. For a British example see Raphael
Meldola, Evolution: Darwinian and Spencerian (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1910), 31.
For the USA, see L. H. Bailey, 'Neo-Lamarckism and Neo-Darwinism', The American
Naturalist, 28(1894), 677-8.
16
Darwin, Descent, 305-8. For a discussion of Darwin's notion of sexual selection see
J. M. Smith, 'Sexual Selection' in Barnett, Century of Darwin, 231-44.
28 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
statement: 'Psychology will be based on a new foundation, that of the
necessary acquirement of each mental power and capacity by gradation.
Light will be thrown on the origin of man and his history' (458). But it is
clear from Darwin's notebooks that from the earliest period of his
theoretical development between 1836 and 1839 he had desired an
understanding of human evolution. He excluded it from the Origin in
order to avoid jeopardising the acceptance of his theory by dealing with
such a controversial notion.17 In a letter to the co-discoverer of natural
selection, Alfred Russel Wallace (1823-1913), written just before the
publication of the Origin, Darwin stated: 'You ask whether I shall
discuss "man". I think I shall avoid the whole subject, as so surrounded
with prejudices; though I fully admit it is the highest and most
interesting problem for the naturalist.'18
This omission was rectified in the Descent, although by then a number
of other theorists had already extended the principle of natural selection
to human evolution. Still, from the very outset of this text, Darwin made
explicit his conviction 'that man must be included with other organic
beings in any general conclusion respecting his manner of appearance
on this earth' (1). He contended that only arrogance and prejudice can
sustain the belief in the separate creation of mankind, arguing that
humans have descended from a non-human ancestry which they share
with the apes. He insisted on the continuities between humans and
animals, claiming that differences are quantitative rather than qualita-
tive, and this not just with respect to physical traits but also with regard
to language, reason, imagination and morality.19
The issue of the origin of the moral faculty was a very important one
for Darwin, as indeed it has proved to be throughout the entire history of
Darwinian theory. For many of his contemporaries morality was some-
thing unique to humans. Darwin argued that this was not so. The moral
faculty derived from the 'social instincts', the most primitive manifesta-
tion of which was the parental instinct, which humans shared with other
social creatures. Since man is a social animal, Darwin asserted, 'it is
almost certain that he would inherit a tendency to be faithful to his
comrades, and obedient to the leader of the tribe; for these qualities are
common to most social animals' (167). Qualities such as altruism and
courage, however, were problematic, for while individuals who pos-
17
For Darwin's early interest in human evolution, see H. E. Gruber, Darwin on Man
(New York: Dutton, 1974); Greene, Science, Ideology and World View, 97-101;
Desmond and Moore, Darwin, chaps. 14-17.
18
Darwin to Wallace, 1 May 1857, in F. Darwin, Charles Darwin, 183.
19
The study of animal behaviour played an important part in Darwin's theory of human
evolution. See R. W. Burkhardt, 'Darwin on Animal Behaviour and Evolution', in
D. Kohn, The Darwinian Heritage, 327-65.
Defining Social Darwinism 29
sessed these attributes would unquestionably benefit their tribe, they
would expose themselves to increased risk of death. Hence they would
be unlikely to reproduce themselves in sufficient numbers for their type
to thrive (200). The difficulty here was one of explaining how a process -
natural selection - that acted upon individuals produced an outcome
with collective benefits in the form of moral sensibilities which were
potentially lethal for the individuals who possessed them. Theoretically,
survival and reproductive success should fall to cowards and egoists.
Darwin provided two answers. The first - one now favoured by the
majority of biologists - was to stress the self-regarding consequences of
altruistic actions: helping others would increase the likelihood of aid to
oneself in times of need. Darwin additionally stressed the importance to
the individual of the praise and blame of neighbours in stimulating
virtuous behaviour (201). But occasionally Darwin's language suggested
a very different explanation, namely that selfless individual behaviour
aided group survival. For example, he argued: 'A tribe including many
members who, from possessing in a high degree the spirit of patriotism,
fidelity, obedience, courage, and sympathy, were always ready to aid one
another, and to sacrifice themselves for the common good, would be
victorious over most other tribes; and this would be natural selection'
(203).20 I shall argue below that this ambiguity over group versus
individual selection is an important component of Darwinism.
The above quotation does, though, indicate Darwin's conviction that
natural selection operated in human evolution. Humans exhibited
variations in body and mind and for him these 'variations are induced,
either directly or indirectly, by the same general causes, and obey the
same general laws, as with the lower animals'. As our early ancestors
must at times have increased beyond their means of subsistence, 'they
must, therefore, occasionally have been exposed to a struggle for
existence, and consequently to the rigid law of natural selection' (70-1).
Darwin believed that this struggle was mitigated within advanced
civilised societies although there is some ambivalence in his evaluation
of this. The growth of the instinct of sympathy had resulted in the
proliferation of welfare and charity schemes which not only supported
the mentally and physically incapable but enabled them to proliferate.
The struggle for existence was thus attenuated in 'highly civilised
nations', with the result that the biological value of their populations was
in danger of being reduced (205-6). Yet we could not check this
sympathy for the unfortunate 'without deterioration in the noblest part
of our nature' (206), and Darwin assured his readers that there was
20
For a discussion of the role of individual versus group selection in Darwin's thought,
see M. Ruse, The Darwinian Paradigm (London: Routledge, 1989), 34-54.
30 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
reason to believe that far from diminishing, the social instincts and the
virtues derived from them would be enhanced in the future (192).
Nevertheless, the struggle for existence seemed only to be mitigated
within civilised nations. The latter would, so Darwin argued, in the
future exterminate 'the savage races throughout the world' as well as the
'anthropomorphous apes' (241-2). He was emphatic that without
natural selection the heights of achievement exhibited by civilised
nations would never have been attained. Indeed, Darwin even suggested
that when one considered the vast tracts of fertile land populated only by
wandering savages, one could not help but wonder whether the struggle
for existence had been sufficiently severe (219).
The portrait of nature which emerges from Darwin's writings is thus
one in which change is paramount. Though very gradual and requiring
vast time scales for their realisation, selective pressures rendered
unviable the notion that species were permanent. In the Origin Darwin
wrote: CI am fully convinced that species are not immutable' (69). He
went on to suggest that the conceptual categories employed by
taxonomists to identify species were matters of convention, the products
of a consensus within the scientific community (104). Darwinism,
therefore, represents another source of difficulty for the belief in 'species
essentialism'21 and hence, by implication, for the notion of a universal
human nature. It contributed to the intellectual and moral crisis in mid-
century Western culture already referred to; it also, as I will argue, could
be employed as a means of resolving that crisis.
23
The theory of natural selection can, however, be reformulated as a deductive structure.
See A. Flew, Darwinian Evolution (London: Paladin, 1984), 36-40. There is an
illuminating presentation of Darwin's theory which underlines the looseness of its
deductive inferences in M. Ruse, Darwinism Defended (Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley,
1982), 47, fig. 2.10.
32 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
Similarly, the struggle for existence is in turn predicated on the
discrepant ratio of population growth to available resources. It is this
total configuration and the relationship among its elements which is
specific to Social Darwinism. The individual elements have a history of
their own, independent of Social Darwinism. What constitutes the latter
is the manner in which these elements are articulated and connected to
form a striking conception of the causes and dynamics of social change.
By referring to Social Darwinism as a world view I am making a claim
about its discursive role. This is that Social Darwinism is not, in itself, a
social or political theory. Rather, it consists of a series of connected
assumptions and propositions about nature, time and how humanity is
situated within both. What it does not possess is any concrete specifi-
cation of human social and mental development, nor any particular
vision of the optimal conditions for human social and spiritual existence.
In other words, the ideological component of a theory is absent from
Social Darwinism. This is not to argue that Darwin himself was
personally free of ideological interests or that these were unimportant to
his formulation of the world view. What I am claiming is that the world
view is separable from whatever religious, political or ethical perspectives
Darwin may have professed. Indeed, the success of Social Darwinism
lies in this very flexibility, in the possibilities it contained for transference
to a whole spectrum of ideological positions.
Why this flexibility? The answer is to be found in a feature of the
world view that has already been touched upon, namely the existence of
a series of indeterminacies surrounding some of its elements -
indeterminacies evidenced by Darwin's own hesitancies and ambigu-
ities. Even in his own writings, 'Darwinism' was not a fixed entity, but
more a set of models of evolutionary transformation which received
different emphases at different points in his scientific career.24 These
indeterminacies are therefore crucial to an understanding of the different
ideological contexts in which Social Darwinism could be deployed.
The first of these concerns the mechanisms of evolutionary change.
Natural selection, use and disuse of organs, acquired characters, sexual
selection - all of these formed part of the Darwinian lexicon, and
different theorists could, and did, emphasise different ones. Sexual
selection tended to fall into abeyance after Darwin, although it has been
very much revised in modern versions, as I will show in the final chapter
of this study. The inheritance of acquired characters was stressed by
many eminent popularisers of Social Darwinism. This gave rise to
another indeterminacy, namely the cause of organic and behavioural
24
E. Mayr, 'Darwin's Five Theories of Evolution', in Kohn, Darwinian Heritage, 755-72;
D. Hull, Darwinism as a Historical Entity', in Kohn, Darwinian Heritage, 810.
Defining Social Darwinism 33
variations. Advocates of the inheritance of acquired characters could
posit environmental changes as a source of such variations (rather than
innate mutations), a position which could legitimate agendas of political
and social reform. The compatibility of the inheritance of acquired
characters with natural selection was, nonetheless, put into question by
the work of the German biologist August Weismann (1834-1914).
Weismann theorised the existence of a 'germ-plasm' which determined
somatic traits. Whereas the latter could be influenced by environmental
conditions, the germ-plasm could not be so influenced. The upshot of
this was that any somatic modifications induced in an organism during
its lifetime could not be transmitted to its offspring. This encouraged a
neo-Darwinism which espoused a 'hard hereditarianism', insisting that
natural selection of innate organic variations was the only mechanism of
evolution. Yet although this version became increasingly widespread
during the first half of the twentieth century, the inheritance of acquired
characters continued to stimulate a great deal of research in biology
between the 1870s and the 1920s.25 It gradually lost favour during the
period of the evolutionary synthesis, more as a result of becoming an
unnecessary hypothesis through the general acceptance of natural
selection than through falsification.26 The struggle for existence was also
a concept open to a number of interpretations by social theorists. It
could be equated with violent struggle and warfare, or - in keeping with
Darwin's suggestions about the attenuation of struggle in civilised
nations - warfare could be confined to primitive stages of social
evolution, to be replaced by industrial competition or perhaps the battle
of ideas as civilisation progressed. Hence the possibility of being both a
Social Darwinist and a pacifist. Another very important area of
indeterminacy related to the unit of evolution upon which natural
selection acted. We have noted how Darwin tended to see this as the
individual organism but sometimes presented the group as the evolu-
tionary unit. This opened up the possibility of variable interpretations of
the unit of selection - individual, species, tribe, nation, race were some
of the candidates that were put forward between 1860 and 1945
(compared to the 'selfish gene' of modern Darwinism). Hence the world
25
E. Mayr, 'Prologue' in Mayr and Provine, Evolutionary Synthesis, 15. It is interesting to
note that Weismann himself came to admit the possibility that the germ-plasm could be
directly affected by the environment. Cf. E. Mayr, One Long Argument, 1 2 5 - 6 .
26
R. W. Burkhardt, 'Lamarckism in Britain and the United States', in Mayr and Provine,
Evolutionary Synthesis, 347. T h e inheritance of acquired characters has never been
completely abandoned by biologists. S o m e modern geneticists believe it possible for an
organism to alter its genes through environmental modification of the D N A molecule,
and to then transmit this alteration to its offspring. See N . Schoon, 'Genes "Heresy"
May Revolutionise Evolutionary Theory', The Independent, 14 December 1989.
34 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
view possessed great flexibility over what units were engaged in the
struggle for existence, in addition to flexibility with regard to how the
struggle was conducted.
Two other indeterminacies relate to the rate and the direction of
evolutionary change. First, Darwin saw the rate of change as inevitably
gradual, building upon minute variations. It was, however, possible to
be a Darwinist and believe change to be more uneven, with long periods
of stability juxtaposed with periods of relatively dramatic change, a view
held by one of Darwin's most formidable champions, T. H. Huxley
(1825-95). 27 Second, the Darwinian world view did not entail a
commitment to a particular direction for evolutionary change, and
theories of degeneration were as prolific as theories of progress.
Certainly many Social Darwinists did believe that evolution entailed
progress, a view endorsed by Darwin himself, as I shall argue below. But
belief in progress forms part of the ideological aspect of a theory, and the
Darwinian world view was equally compatible with a quite antithetical
perspective.
One final area of indeterminacy - and an extremely important one -
derives not from the meaning of particular terms but from the
articulation between the fifth element and the remainder of the world
view. It was especially pronounced for those whose interest was in social
evolution. Two broad strategies were available to theorists. They could
be completely reductionist and argue that social evolution was depen-
dent on the biological properties of humans, or they could argue that
social evolution, while not reducible to biology, nonetheless took place
through analogous processes of adaptation, selection and inheritance. In
practice the two approaches were not always kept distinct, with some
theorists adopting both. But whatever strategy was opted for, there was a
need to show that the social order in some way mirrored the natural
order. This created a potential for the production of a whole range of
equivalences, analogies, images and metaphors: that societies are
equivalent to biological organisms or that races represent biological
species; individuals are akin to cells; that war is a manifestation of the
struggle for existence; that women and children occupy the same
position as 'savages' in the scale of evolution, and so on. Metaphors and
images were thus central to any Social Darwinist enterprise, whatever its
27
For Huxley's saltationism, see M. Di Gregorio, T. H Huxley's Place in Natural Science
(New Haven/London: Yale University Press, 1984), 66; A. Desmond, Huxley (London:
Michael Joseph, 1994), 256, 262. A modern version is the theory of 'punctuated
equilibrium' propounded by Stephen Jay Gould and his co-workers. This theory has,
however, met with a great deal of criticism. For a critical overview of the literature see
E. O. Wilson, The Diversity of Life (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1994), 80-1, 344; J. M.
Smith, Did Darwin Get it Right? (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1993), chaps. 16-17.
Defining Social Darwinism 35
scientific pretensions, necessitated by the need to link the first four
elements of the world view with the fifth and to show how human
culture was governed by inexorable laws of nature.
These indeterminacies do not mean that the world view was so
abstract as to be indistinguishable from others, or so bland that it could
go with anything. It embraces scientific materialism, the rejection of
supernatural forces in natural explanation, and a view of humans as
having evolved from non-human life-forms and as susceptible to change
over time. As for its indeterminacies, these undoubtedly make for
adaptability, but not ideological licence. Despite its flexibility and the
depth of its rhetorical resources, there were boundaries to both. My
point is that these boundaries cannot be arbitrarily specified but must be
discovered by an examination of its actual discursive uses. From the fact
of somebody being a Social Darwinist it is not possible - or rather, it
would be extremely unwise - to deduce his or her position on warfare,
capitalism, race, imperialism or the social status of women. The
indeterminacies within the world view allow for the taking up of quite
antithetical positions on all these, and other, issues.
There is, however, one feature of the world view - one that was to be
discovered in the course of its deployment in ideological debates - which
was to mark most of Social Darwinist theorising, irrespective of its
ideological bent. This is the Janus-like picture of nature that it presents.
Hints of this are discernible in Darwin's own writings, for example when
he highlights the deleterious consequences of the diminution of the
struggle for survival within civilised societies but then asserts the
impossibility of counteracting these without violating some of our most
exalted values. Here we see the laws of nature as both beneficent and
malign, as something to be emulated and as a force to be feared, as both
a model and a threat. If the indeterminacies within Social Darwinism
provided a veritable quarry of rhetorical materials, then the janiform
visage of nature it also contained constituted a source of dilemmas
which at times threatened the coherence of the theories in question. But
again, neither the rhetorical potential nor the dilemmatics of Social
Darwinism can be identified prior to the investigation of the texts in
which they appeared.
39
40 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
late eighteenth-century French philosophers dedicated to the creation of
a science of mankind.3 Lamarck extended their project by insisting that
humans were part of nature and subject to its laws. Far from constituting
a special creation, people differed only quantitatively from other
creatures in that they possessed more complex faculties than animals but
nothing uniquely human, including the ability to reason.
In his Zoological Philosophy of 1809,4 Lamarck asserted the existence
of an evolutionary progression from the simplest to the most complex
forms of biological organisation. He observed that 'in ascending the
animal scale, starting from the most imperfect animals, organisation
gradually increases in complexity in an extremely remarkable manner'
(1). This progression was a consequence of organic transformations
impelled by environmental changes. Lamarck proposed as a general law
that 'variations in the environment induce changes in the needs, habits
and mode of life of living beings; and that these changes give rise to
modifications or developments in their organs and the shape of their
parts' (45). The impact of environmental change on the animal was not
direct: rather, in striving to adapt to new conditions, an animal's needs
were altered. If these became permanent then organic transformations
were made possible either through the development of new organs or by
the modification of existing structures (107). The features of the milieu
considered critical in causing these modifications were climate, tempera-
ture, habits and 'the means of self-preservation, the mode of life and the
methods of defence and multiplication' (114).
On the basis of these considerations Lamarck postulated two laws of
development. The first asserted that in any animal that had 'not passed
the limits of its development', increased frequency in the use of an organ
or faculty would augment or enlarge it, while prolonged disuse would
cause it to atrophy. The second claimed that any losses or acquisitions
brought about by use or disuse or through adaptation to changing
conditions would be 'preserved by reproduction to the new individuals
which arise, provided that the acquired modifications are common to
both sexes, or at least to the individuals which produce the young' (113).
Lamarck concluded from these laws that new species evolved very slowly
from existing species through the accretion of these modifications.
Hence there were no fixed and immutable entities in nature, while
species 'shade gradually into some other neighbouring species', making
it difficult to establish clear-cut species boundaries (36-7).
These laws applied to humanity whose ancestors, having acquired the
facility of standing and walking in an upright position, developed new
3
Jordanova, Lamarck, 77-80.
4
Tr. H. Elliot (London: Macmillan, 1914).
The distinctiveness of Social Darwinism 41
needs to which they adapted and thus not only left the other animals
behind in terms of development, but gained mastery over them as well.
With the extension of needs and ideas, the necessity for communication
intensified, leading to the formation of the organs of speech and
language (170-3).
This brief survey reveals some points in common between the theories
of Lamarck and Darwin. In both there is an assertion of the universality
of evolution which occurs gradually through the accumulation of small
changes. Both consider species to be mutable, which makes possible the
emergence of new species, although Lamarck's reference to 'limits of
development' implies the existence of some constraints on this process.
Both endorse the thesis that humans evolved from animal life-forms.
Where Lamarck and Darwin differed was, first, in their characterisation
of evolution, with Lamarck describing a linear process from the simple
to the complex in contrast to Darwin's branching notion; and second, in
their respective explanations of these transformations. Lamarck was
certainly attuned to the existence of competition and predation
throughout nature (including mankind), which has prompted some
commentators to credit him with advocating the struggle for existence as
a selective device.5 Careful attention to the contexts in which his
remarks on this topic are made show this not to be so.
Lamarck argued that the fecundity and rapid multiplication of
organisms, particularly those low in the scale of complexity, posed a
threat to the preservation and perfectibility of the higher species by
crowding them out of existence. Predation corrected this imbalance and
preserved the natural equilibrium:
The multiplication of the small species of animals is so great, and the succession
of generations is so rapid, that these small species would render the globe
uninhabitable to any others if nature had not set a limit to their prodigious
multiplication. But since they serve as a prey to a multitude of other animals,
and since the duration of their life is very short and they are killed by any fall of
temperature, their numbers are always maintained in the proper proportions for
the preservation of their own and other races.
As to the larger and stronger animals, they might well become dominant and
have bad effects upon the preservation of many other races if they could multiply
in too large proportions; but their races devour one another, and they only
multiply slowly and a few at a time, and this maintains in their case also the kind
of equilibrium that should exist (54).
Human beings might, at first glance, seem to be exceptions to this rule
because their intelligence and other abilities protected them from the
5
For example, G. Himmelfarb, Darwin and the Darwinian Revolution (New York:
Norton, 1962), 177-8.
42 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
predation of other animals. But nature had endowed humans with many
passions and these, through the warfare they engendered, checked
population growth. Thus mankind regulated itself through the unin-
tended consequences of its powers and passions.
By these wise precautions, everything is thus preserved in the established order;
the continual changes and renewals which are observed in that order are kept
within limits that they cannot pass; all the races of living bodies continue to exist
in spite of their variations; none of the progress made towards perfection of
organisation is lost; what appears to be disorder, confusion, anomaly, incessantly
passes again into the general order, and even contributes to it; everywhere and
always, the will of the Sublime Author of nature and of everything that exists is
invariably carried out (55).
From these arguments and the language in which they are couched it
is evident that Lamarck had a different view of nature to that exhibited
in Darwin's writings. While they shared a number of assumptions,
Darwin's advocacy of a creative role for struggle in bringing about
organic change was very different from Lamarck's remarks about the
effects of predation and warfare. For the French naturalist both were
conservative principles, serving to maintain an equilibrium in the natural
order. In this respect at least, Lamarck's philosophy of nature had its
roots in eighteenth-century conceptions of nature as a system of
harmony and perfectibility.6
Other differences over the nature of struggle are also discernible. In
contrast to Darwin, who considered the battle for life to be most acute
among conspecifics, Lamarck declared: 'individuals rarely eat others of
the same race as themselves; they make war on different races' (54). For
him predation was not a question of culling the weakest specimens
within a species: on the contrary, 'ill-fed, suffering or sickly individuals'
were capable of adaptation and modification and their descendants
would therefore move up a rung on the evolutionary ladder (108).
Jordanova has summarised the difference between the two naturalists
thus: where Darwin saw animals and plants compering for survival,
Lamarck saw a more harmonious process of mutual adaptation. 7
Lamarckism, then, cannot be reduced to a belief in the inheritance of
acquired characters as a mechanism of evolution. Rather it must be seen
as a world view in its own right in which change takes place from below
as inferior organisms strive to adapt, improve and progress. This
conception of a self-improving natural order, mediated through the
writings of the French anatomist Etienne Geoffroy Saint-Hilaire, was
6
There is a useful discussion of eighteenth-century conceptions of nature in B. Willey,
The Eighteenth Century Background (London: Chatto and Windus, 1965).
7
Jordanova, Lamarck, 106.
The distinctiveness of Social Darwinism 43
deployed in both France and Britain as the philosophical foundation of
early radical, republican and socialist political agendas. As Desmond has
demonstrated, Lamarckism provided these movements with a powerful
scientific rationale for doctrines of progress through 'development from
below5. For the radicals: 'Nature and society were congruent. Both were
improving and progressive: the moral evils of society were benevolent
dispensations favouring working-class improvement, while in the animal
kingdom the inferior organisms triumphantly progressed to escape their
lowly station.'8 These arguments appealed not only to radical and
socialist agitators, but also to the non-establishment medical schools of
Edinburgh and London that were challenging the hegemony of Oxbridge
and the medical corporations. 'Clearly', writes Desmond, 'Lamarckism
had some disreputable associations. It was being exploited by extremists
promoting the dissolution of Church and aristocracy, and calling for a
new economic system. These atheists and socialists supported a brand of
evolution quite unlike Darwin's.'9 He concludes that this ideological
context helps explain Darwin's tardiness in publishing his own theory.
Darwin had attended Edinburgh University for a time and had there met
some of the foremost radical Lamarckians. He was terrified of becoming
associated with the political uses to which they were putting their
transformist ideas. For, like them, Darwin also perceived nature to be
self-developing and courted the risk of having his own ideas pirated by
the radicals, notwithstanding his Malthusian, anti-Lamarckian view of
the causes of this development.10 Fortunately for Darwin the routing of
the radical Lamarckians during the late 1840s coupled with the relative
political quiescence of the following decade enabled him to avoid the
taint of radicalism, although his ideas did become part of the arsenal of
anti-establishment figures like Huxley and Spencer.
Darwinism and Lamarckism, therefore, though sharing some assump-
tions, diverged widely on others. In particular, they proposed different
explanations of organic change which in turn resonated discrepant
conceptions of the natural order. For Darwin, evolution was brought
about primarily through the selective consequences of struggle, an
explanation that was alien to Lamarckism. Yet the differences are more
than just a disagreement over the role of competition. This notion was
integral to Darwinism, intimately linked to the configuration of assump-
tions comprising the world view as a whole. Its absence (as a creative
8
A. Desmond, The Politics of Evolution (London: University of Chicago Press, 1989),
208.
9
Ibid., A.
10
Ibid., 412. Desmond describes how working-class audiences during the 1860s
interpreted Darwin for their own purposes in his Huxley, 292-3.
44 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
mechanism) in Lamarck likewise reflected the Frenchman's belief in
adaptation from below as the driving force in evolution and of nature as
a moving equilibrium. Darwinism additionally implied a much greater
stress on heredity than did Lamarckism. In the latter perspective,
heredity acts to ensure the transmission of successful adaptations,
whereas in the former it is itself a source of variations (although Darwin
was unsure how these occurred). Darwinism also contained the potential
for depicting heredity as a much more autonomous force, relatively
immune from environmental pressures, as in its Weismannian guise.
Hence the Darwinian conception of heredity is one that potentially lends
itself to a form of hereditarian determinism which is at odds with the
environmentalist focus of Lamarckism.
This last consideration points to a need for care in analysing the
writings of evolutionary thinkers who enlisted the inheritance of acquired
characters within Social Darwinist frameworks. This is especially true of
those who believed in progress. The inheritance of acquired characters
could be used to explain cumulative mental or social improvement. But
what clearly separates such theories from the Lamarckian view is that in
the former this is invariably accompanied by a commitment to the
struggle for survival made necessary for the elimination of the 'unfit'
who are incapable of improvement because of their hereditary disposi-
tion. Here we encounter another example of the way in which specific
terms need to be understood in the overall discursive context of which
they are a part. Struggle and heredity play different roles and have
different significations within the Darwinian and Lamarckian world
views. And it was precisely because the former possessed a stress on
heredity and on struggle that it could depict nature as at once both a
model and a threat.
Essay on the History of Civil Society ed. D. Forbes (Edinburgh University Press, 1966).
50 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
with public-spiritedness.18 Thus, notwithstanding his occasional praise
for warfare, Ferguson's ultimate commitment was to the morality of
community, anticipating a time when: cThe same maxim will apply
throughout every part of nature. To love is to enjoy pleasure: To hate is to be
in pain' (54, original emphasis).
Before leaving the eighteenth century it is useful to consider one of the
most uncompromising critics of the Enlightenment, Thomas Malthus
(1766-1834). His An Essay on the Principle of Population (1798), 19 which
was to exert such an influence on both Wallace and Darwin, was
directed against Enlightenment doctrines of progress and perfectibility.
Malthus argued that population always increased at a much faster rate
than food production and was held in check by natural disasters, plague
and warfare, and (as he subsequently conceded) sexual temperance. His
goal was to show that population growth, far from stimulating progress,
actually made such progress impossible. He allowed that 'the goad of
necessity' was certainly responsible for the improved conditions of
modern civilisation (47), and he also acknowledged the possibility of
improving animals and plants through selective breeding (53-4). But
such could occur only within the limits imposed by the essential nature
of the species concerned and these limits were particularly marked in the
case of mankind. 'In human life', Malthus asserted, 'though there are
great variations from different causes, it may be doubted whether, since
the world began, any organic improvement whatever of the human
frame can be clearly ascertained.' Small changes were no doubt possible
in theory but, since they would necessitate the celibacy of 'all the bad
specimens', extremely difficult to realise in practice (54). Although
familiar with the stage-theory of development, Malthus regarded this as
confirmation of the universality of his law of population and hence of the
impossibility of any radical alteration in the quality of life for the majority
of the population.20
Darwin and Wallace took over Malthus's thesis on the pressure
exerted by fecundity on resources and deployed it within a very different
outlook on nature and time - in fact as a cause of precisely those organic
transmutations which Malthus had deemed to be ruled out by this
thesis. Nevertheless, as will be evident in following chapters, the new
18
Ferguson deplored the pursuit of private gain at the expense of the public weal in
modern societies (19, 3 2 - 3 , 8 6 - 7 , 199). O n civic humanism, see J. G. A. Pocock, The
Machiavellian Moment (Princeton University Press, 1975); Pocock, Politics, Language
and Time (London: Methuen, 1972), chaps. 3 and 4.
19
Ed. D . Winch (Cambridge University Press, 1992). For a discussion of the political
context of Malthus's theory, see D . Wells, 'Resurrecting the Dismal Parson: Malthus,
Ecology and Political Thought', Political Studies, 3 0 ( 1 9 8 2 ) , 1-15.
20
O n this point, see Meek, Social Science, 2 2 3 .
The distinctiveness of Social Darwinism 51
world view of Social Darwinism could be enrolled in the same
ideological cause as the original Malthusian doctrine, i.e. to support free
markets and oppose doctrines of equality.
27
Schweber, however, has argued that Comte influenced Darwin's own thinking on
evolution. See S. S. Schweber, 'The Origin of the Origin Revisited', Journal of the
History of Biology, 10(1977), 2 1 9 - 3 1 6 .
28
London: Effingham Wilson, 1828.
The distinctiveness of Social Darwinism 55
similar to that suffered by all the lower animals, which are constantly
pressing against the bounds of subsistence' (107).
For Edmonds: 'Nature has laid down laws for the perpetual improve-
ment of the human race' (65), which it is 'not in the power of man to
prevent' (283). One of these is 'the law of the strongest, or war' which,
according to Edmonds, 'is one of the most benevolent institutions of
Nature . . . Beneficent providence has so ordained it that the powerful
are continually bringing the weak under their subjection' (199). This
subordination of the weak to the strong was advantageous because
knowledge equated to power and conquest disseminated knowledge
through compulsion, the only method which enabled rapid advances to
take place. Yet although subjected to inexorable laws of nature,
Edmonds thought it possible to improve mankind through something
very akin to eugenics. Signalling the way in which domestic breeds of
animals and vegetables could be improved by 'selective culture', he
suggested that such techniques could be applied to humans.
The bodies of a coming generation may be rendered superior in health, strength
and activity to the bodies of a present generation, by selecting for the purposes of
propagation the individuals of both sexes possessing the most healthy, vigorous
and active bodies, and not suffering weak and diseased people to transmit their
diseases and miseries to posterity. In similar manner, the minds of a people may
be improved by selecting for propagation those people who excel in the most
useful qualities of mind, as justice, judgement, imagination, benevolence, &c,
and not permitting ideots [sic] or madmen, or people approaching to such, to
propagate (269).
Striking though these passages are, Edmonds cannot be regarded as a
proto-Social Darwinist for a number of reasons. First, he maintained
that species were created and designed by God (34), who had likewise
created the separate races of mankind. He denied that the mental
differences between Europeans and negroes derived from accidental
variations and considered them immutable (187). Such argumentation
was inconsistent with any notion of the evolution of humans from ape-
like ancestors. Second, although Edmonds believed that population
growth was constrained by the availability of food supplies, he did not
argue that such growth was a cause of adaptation and specialisation. He
exempted mankind from this constraint anyway since all European
nations were populated to a level far below that which they were capable
of supporting (107-8). Although Edmonds sometimes adopted a
Malthusian stance, as when he claimed that 'pauperism is caused by
improvident propagation' (237), elsewhere he asserted pauperism to be
the effect of private property and the division of society into rich and
poor (107-8). Thus his 'law of the strongest' was not deduced from the
56 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
ratio of population increase to food production as a general law of nature
but derived from the lack of international justice due to the absence of
regular concourse among nations (235). His support for conquest was
couched in terms of the benefits to be gained from the diffusion of
knowledge rather than as a means of winnowing the unfit. Third,
Edmonds did not regard market competition as a selective device but
rather as an obstacle to the advance of the division of labour in that it
was not only injurious to the public interest but also to the firms involved
(75). In no sense, therefore, does his focus on adaptation, selective
breeding and the inheritance of acquired characters in a social context -
interesting though they are - represent a formulation of the Social
Darwinist world view.
The only likely case for a genuine formulation of Social Darwinism
prior to Darwin that I have encountered is the writing of a Scots fruit
farmer and aboriculturalist, Patrick Matthew (1790-1874), although the
evidence is equivocal. In 1860 Matthew claimed to have discovered the
principle of natural selection almost thirty years previously in his book
Naval Timber and Aboriculture.29 In an appendix to this text Matthew
wrote of a 'law universal in nature':
This law sustains the lion in his strength, the hare in her swiftness, and the fox in
his wiles. As Nature, in all her modifications of life, has a power of increase far
beyond what is needed to supply the place of what falls by Time's decay, those
individuals who possess not the requisite strength, swiftness, hardihood, or
cunning, fall prematurely without reproducing - either a prey to their natural
devourers, or sinking under disease, generally induced by want of nourishment,
their place being occupied by the more perfect of their kind, who are pressing on
the means of subsistence (98).
This is a succinct statement of the selective impact of competition
arising from the pressure of population on subsistence. Matthew stressed
the 'extreme fecundity of nature 5 and argued that: 'As the field of
existence is limited and preoccupied, it is only the hardier, more robust,
better suited to circumstance individuals, who are able to struggle
forward to maturity, these inhabiting only the situations to which they
have superior adaptation and greater power of occupancy than any other
kind; the weaker, less circumstance-suited, being prematurely destroyed'
(107-8). He suggested that an examination of the fossil record on the
29
Edinburgh: Adam Black, 1831. The most pertinent comments were contained in an
appendix which has been reproduced with other publications by Matthew in W. J.
Dempster, Patrick Matthew and Natural Selection (Edinburgh: Paul Harris, 1983), from
which the following exposition has been drawn. Darwin acknowledged Matthew's
priority in subsequent editions of the Origin. See Matthew's letter to The Gardeners*
Chronicle and Agricultural Gazette, 17 April 1860, and Darwin's letter to the same
chronicle, 21 April 1860, in Dempster, Patrick Matthew, 112-17.
The distinctiveness of Social Darwinism 57
extinction and emergence of species left the naturalist with a clear choice
between belief in 'a repeated miraculous creation' or in 'a power of
change' in nature which had the effect of blurring the distinction
between varieties and species (106).
Matthew applied these arguments to social arrangements, insisting
that hereditary nobility and primogeniture were 'an outrage on this law
of nature' and a debasement of the racial stock, since all aristocracies
required renovation by 'regular married alliance with wilder stocks' (98).
He was critical of the English Poor Laws for discouraging self-reliance
and effort among the unemployed and compared this situation with the
one in Scotland, where the absence of parish relief fostered indepen-
dence and a willingness to move to more promising circumstances
(103). Matthew was an ardent supporter of emigration and colonial
enterprise - his work on naval timber was motivated by the desire to
strengthen Britain's overseas power. He claimed that emigration
ensured that the mentally and physically ablest persons 'will be thrown
into their natural position as leaders' whereas the 'feebler or more
improvident varieties will generally sink under the incidental hardships'
(102). Faint hearts were a hindrance to successful overseas ventures:
Our milder moods, benevolence, gentleness, contemplation - our refinement in
sentiment ... have a negative weight on the balance of national strength. The
rougher excitement of hatred, ambition, pride, patriotism, and the more selfish
passions, is necessary to the full and strong development of our active powers.
That Britain is leaving the impress of her energy and morality on a considerable
portion of the world, is owing to her havingfirstbornefireand sword over these
countries ... (103).
However, these sentiments were not consistently adhered to, for
elsewhere in the same text Matthew looked forward to the obliteration of
national distinctions which would reduce the reasons for warfare and
'bring the European family closer into amity' (110). He suggested that
war and conquest should be confined to the annexation of land
inhabited by non-Europeans. These ambivalences pose problems for the
interpretation of Matthew's ideas. Some historians have seen his work as
a complete anticipation of Darwinism and Social Darwinism, while
others have rejected this and located his ideas in an older, Providential
and catastrophist outlook.30 Matthew himself seemed to have hesitated
over the universal application of natural selection, which is a funda-
mental assumption of the world view. Darwin's brother, Erasmus,
30
For the first interpretation, see Dempster, Patrick Matthew, the second is argued in
K. D. Wells, 'The Historical Context of Natural Selection: The Case of Patrick
Matthew', Journal of the History of Biology, 6(1973), 225-58.
58 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
chided Matthew for this, suggesting that Charles 'is more faithful to your
own original child than you are yourself'.31
In conclusion, then, it is evident that Social Darwinism did not
emerge until after 1859. All of its separate components had certainly
been articulated in one form or another as aspects of the natural and/or
social realms. But the overall configuration, with its particular inter-
connection of these various elements, was the work of Darwin and the
other pioneers who forged the world view. It is to some of these pioneers
that we now turn.
31
Erasmus Darwin to Matthew, 21 November 1863, in Dempster, Patrick Matthew•, 120.
Part II
Pioneers
The emergence of Social Darwinism
Introduction
Before Darwin published his Descent in 1871, Europeans and Americans
had already started to explore the social and psychological implications
of Darwinism. As a German enthusiast wrote: 'from the first appearance
of the Darwinian doctrine, every moderately logical thinker must have
regarded man as similarly modifiable, and as the result of the mutability
of species'.1 Though exaggerating the acceptance of Darwinism this
statement accurately conveys the realisation by many intellectuals that
this was a theory rich in implications for the study of human society.
Within a quarter of a century of the appearance of the Origin there had
emerged a literature devoted to exploring these implications in a wide
range of contexts: social and psychological development, class, race and
gender, religion and morality, war and peace, crime and destitution.
Well before the label itself, Social Darwinism was established as a rich
and versatile theoretical resource.
These pioneering examples of Social Darwinism are the focus of this
and the next three chapters. The intention is not to provide a
comprehensive account of the emergence of Social Darwinism, but
rather to investigate the manner in which the world view was deployed in
a variety of discursive contexts. This chapter deals with several very early
examples which appeared in the 1860s and 1870s in Europe and the
USA.
61
62 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
role of struggle and selection in human history and drew attention to the
'struggle for space5 between races. 2 In this struggle Rolle saw progress
attained through the elimination of the lower races. But other applica-
tions were possible, as demonstrated by the work of the American,
Charles Loring Brace (1826-90).
Brace published his theory of races in 1863, at the height of the
American Civil War. A passionate opponent of slavery, which he
described as an 'organised system of heathenism', 3 Brace sought to
undermine existing ethnological arguments in support of negro infer-
iority. This study took over a decade, during which time Brace was
heavily influenced by the Origin, which he read repeatedly. 4 He was
convinced that if Darwin's theory was true, then 'the law of natural
selection applies to all the moral history of mankind, as well as to the
physical'. 5 TJie Races of the Old World6 was an elaboration of this
principle.
Using linguistic evidence, Brace posited a common origin for all races
and argued that present racial differences were a consequence of the
interaction between environmental conditions, natural selection, inheri-
tance and variations. Although admitting to ignorance concerning the
cause of variations, Brace argued that those conferring advantages in the
form of 'the best chance of living and propagating' (351) would be
selected and spread through a population. In this way, Brace saw no
difficulty in 'accounting for the origin of the negro from the white man,
or from the brown, or from some other race' (390).
Brace was careful to emphasise that races were varieties, not species.
He insisted that there was no physiological evidence to support the latter
thesis, and differences among individuals of the same race were as great
as those between races on such measures (365). Furthermore, all races
could inter-breed, and Brace emphatically rejected the claim that racial
hybrids were infertile (376-7). In fact, Brace evinced a great deal of
sympathy for mulattos, blacks and Red Indians in the United States,
who he believed were dying out as the result of the destruction of their
health and habitats by the rapaciousness of the white races rather than
through any inherent inferiority (383-4). Negroes would benefit greatly
from freedom and integration with whites, partly at least because all
humans were capable of conscious, rational adaptation to new condi-
2
F. Rolle, Der Menschs Seine Abstammung und Gesittung im Lichte der DarwinHschen Lehre
(Frankfurt am Main: Germann'sche Verlagsbuchhandlung, 1866), 109.
3
Brace, letter to Washington Independent, 12 September 1861, in Emma Brace, ed., The
Life of Charles Loring Brace Chiefly Told in His Own Letters (London: Sampson, Low,
Marston and Co., 1894), 243.
4 5
Emma Brace, Life, 300. Brace, cited in Emma Brace, Life, 302.
6
London: John Murray, 1863.
The emergence of Social Darwinism 63
tions (372-4). This process was plainly in evidence among the European
settlers in North America, who were changing physically from their
ancestors. Initially this would result in the elimination of those who were
weaker or unable to adapt to the new conditions, but the stronger would
survive and pass their advantageous traits to their descendants 'until a
new type is formed, adapted to the country and climate' (375). The
lesson Brace drew from this was that the varieties of humanity were no
more immutable than those found in nature at large. He concluded that
'we do not regard the Races of men now existing as permanent. Their
lives converge into one another in the past, and they may meet again in
the future or they may cease altogether' (399-400).
This text is of interest for several reasons. The first is Brace's use of
Darwinism to attack belief in the fixity of racial differences. An example
of this mode of thought is furnished by a book published with the explicit
intent of demonstrating 'that the so-called slavery of the South was the
Negro's normal or natural condition'.7 The author, van Evrie, regarded
the boundaries between species as 'absolutely impassable',8 and the
white and black races as separate species of vastly different capabilities.
The blacks were hopelessly inferior to the whites, and nothing could
alter this condition:
The organism of the race - the species - whether human or animal, never
changes or variesfromthat eternal type fixedfromthe beginning by the hand of
God; and men, therefore, are now, in their natural capacities, what they always
have been and always will be, whatever the external9 circumstances that may
control or modify the development of these capacities.
The significance of this statement lies not in its creationism - for, as we
will see, Brace saw no contradiction between Darwinism and a belief in
God as creator - but in its static perception of species as immutable
essences. From it van Evrie concluded, in sharp contrast to the position
of Brace, that racial crossings were violations of nature and hence
abominations, while slavery was the natural condition of negroes. To
grant them independence was akin to forcing ten-year-old children to
fend for themselves: the result would be the extermination of the
negroes in America.10
The second notable feature of Brace's use of Darwinism consists in
his refusal to erect a hierarchy of races. Races were not species, there
were no insuperable boundaries between them, and their relationships
could not be conceived in terms of inferiority and superiority. Indeed,
he envisaged a time in the future when racial inter-mixture could result
7
J. H. van Evrie, White Supremacy and Negro Subordination, second edn (New York: Van
Evrie, Horton and Co., 1868), dedication to reader.
8 9 10
Ibid., 37. Ibid., 126. Ibid., 161, 309-10.
64 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
in a new and more perfect race (400). This contrasts not only with the
perspective of van Evrie - who was not a Social Darwinist - but with
other avowedly Darwinist accounts of race. Thus the German zoologist
Oskar Schmidt (1826-86) argued that human progress, though a fact of
history, was confined to a few nations only. Some inferior races, which
were distinct species, were capable of advancement, but for many
'destruction in the struggle for existence as a consequence of their
retardation . . . is the natural course of things'.11 While Brace believed
that in certain circumstances races could degenerate (cf. Races, 368-72),
he did not adhere to the doctrine of the inevitability of racial conflict and
extermination. He depicted the struggle for existence as occurring
between individuals and their environments rather than between
different races.
Third, Brace - who was a church minister - denied any incommensur-
ability between Darwinism and his religious beliefs. He wrote in 1866
that Darwinism 'furnishes what historians and philosophers have so long
sought for, a law of progress', which would result in the triumph of good
because good was a life-preserving force.12 He insisted that there was no
general tendency in nature to degeneration or imperfection, but only
one 'towards higher forms of life. Natural selection is a means of arriving
at the best.'13 The social significance of this was clarified in a subsequent
study, The Dangerous Classes of New York.1* These classes consisted of
destitute urban elements living in crime and vice. Brace admitted that
while such traits could become hereditary there was little chance of this
happening in New York. This was because geographical mobility and
the American values of self-improvement and equality prevented the
emergence of families with long criminal pedigrees, which in turn
reduced the hereditability of crime (47). Additionally, the laws of nature
worked in parallel fashion:
The action of the great law of 'Natural Selection', in regard to the human race, is
always towards temperance and virtue. That is, vice and extreme indulgence
weaken the physical powers and undermine the constitution; they impair the
faculties by which man struggles with adverse conditions and gets beyond the
reach of poverty and want. The vicious and sensual and drunken die earlier, or
they have fewer children, or their children are carried off by diseases more
frequently, or they themselves are unable to resist or prevent poverty and
suffering. As a consequence, in the lowest class, the more self-controlled and
virtuous tend constantly to survive, and to prevail in the 'struggle for existence',
11
Schmidt, Doctrine of Descent, 298.
12
Brace, letter to Lady Lyell, 23 December 1866, in Emma Brace, Life, 285.
13
Brace, Life, 302.
14
The Dangerous Classes of New York and Twenty Years Work Among Them (New York:
Wynkoop and Hallenback, 1872).
The emergence of Social Darwinism 65
over the vicious and ungoverned, and to transmit their progeny. The natural
drift among the poor is towards virtue (44-5).
Even in the worst families, the superior hereditary qualities of earlier
ancestors were latent within individuals, and could be nurtured by better
food and conditions, regular work and, above all, religion, all of which
would 'awaken these hidden tendencies to good' (45). The application
of Christian principles of charity was thus in harmony 'with natural and
economic laws' (441).
Finally, Brace's use of Darwinism contains tensions which are
instructive for a more general understanding of Social Darwinism. As
was noted above, the struggle for existence appears in his work as
something which operates between individuals and their natural and
social environments, but not between individuals themselves. As a
consequence, Brace did not explore the full implications of Darwinism,
namely that the struggle for life is at its most intense between members
of the same species. His hesitation in this respect undoubtedly derived
from his religious convictions and his commitment to racial integration
and social reform. Moreover, his correspondence reveals his belief in
Theism and in a Creator who could 'arrange forces on a general plan',
coupled with an admission that it was nonetheless difficult to recognise
the hand of God in the play of chance and natural selection.15 Brace's
writings, therefore, present nature as a model and evolution as an
ultimately benign force working towards progress and human perfection.
But they do so by playing down those features of Darwinism which
could pose problems for this view of nature, i.e. intra-specific competi-
tion and scientific determinism. In this respect, the pioneering Social
Darwinism of Brace is, as we shall see, paradigmatic.
21
Bagehot, Physics and Politics, 43; also 215. In the light of Bagehot's stress on the
selective role of warfare, particularly among 'savages', there seems no justification for
Himmelfarb's claim that Physics and Politics was 'a travesty of Darwinism' which sought
to repudiate the role of the struggle for existence during the early stage of human
evolution. See Himmelfarb, Darwin and the Darwinian Revolution, 426-30.
The emergence of Social Darwinism 73
colonialists and 'barbarians', with the latter reduced, through this
conflict, to a point where they were 'no longer so much as vanquished
competitors; they have ceased to compete at all'. 22 On other occasions,
though, he described warfare as largely confined to the preliminary age
and asserted that war had 'ceased to be a moving force in the
world...' 23 This could reflect an evolutionary perspective on the
struggle for existence, as for Biichner, but Bagehot did not elaborate
upon this point or discuss alternative methods of selection.
This vagueness on the status of struggle and warfare among advanced
nations was compounded by an implicit reinterpretation of struggle. For
Bagehot did not derive this from the relationship between fecundity and
resources. He was unquestionably aware of the overcrowding, poverty
and vice typical of the large cities, which he attributed to population
growth, and he explained this by the strength of the sexual instinct which
was a residue of early human nature, moulded at a time when rapid
multiplication was integral to military success. But he did not regard this
as a permanent trait, since he believed that this instinct was weakened in
proportion as the cerebral faculties grew. There was only so much
energy available to each individual, and the expansion of certain
activities had to be compensated by a contraction of others. 24 Bagehot
did not suggest that population pressures engendered the struggle for
existence among advanced nations, nor was it invoked as the cause of
warfare at early stages of evolution. War and struggle, therefore, appear
as facts of life in themselves, rather than as the effects of other processes.
Furthermore, Bagehot only used struggle as an explanation for the
formation of societies during the preliminary stage, attributing the
break-up of the stationary state in ancient, mediaeval and modern times
to the emergence of debate and a popular element in government.25 It
would be plausible to interpret discussion and argument as a mode of
struggle transported to the realm of ideas, something argued by other
Social Darwinists, but Bagehot did not do so. As a consequence, while
all the elements of the Darwinist world view can be easily discerned in
his writings, the interconnection between the elements was loosened and
the struggle for existence became detached from the remaining elements
to appear as part of the human condition, albeit a shadowy and
problematic one beyond certain levels of evolution.
22 23
Bagehot, Physics and Politics, 46. Ibid., 78.
24
Ibid., 195, 1 9 9 - 2 0 0 . It is significant that Bagehot wrote at a time when the birth-rate
had not yet declined among the 'higher ranks' in a manner that was later to alarm the
eugenicists.
25
Bagehot, Physics and Politics, 158, 175, 185.
74 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
26
W. Reade, The Martyrdom of Man (London: Watts, 1945), 312-3. A similar ambition
was expressed by Bagehot in Physics and Politics, 2 - 3 .
27
Pick, Faces of Degeneration; Jones, Social Darwinism, 103 et seq.\ N. Rose, The
Psychological Complex (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1985), 57 etseq.
28
See G. Himmelfarb, The Idea of Poverty (London: Faber and Faber, 1984), 3 2 4 - 5 .
The emergence of Social Darwinism 75
from the lower classes, especially, though not exclusively, in the towns
and cities.29
Cesare Lombroso (1835-1909) held various chairs in forensic
medicine, psychiatry and criminal anthropology at the universities of
Pavia and then Turin. His book L'Uomo Delinquente ('The Criminal
Man') reached a wide audience, expanding from 252 pages in its first
edition of 1876 to 1,203 pages (in three volumes) by the fifth edition of
1895. Here Lombroso elaborated the concept of the 'born criminal', a
man or woman who broke the law not through habit, or the pressure of
circumstances or temporary passions - all of which played a part in the
motives of other kinds of criminal - but by virtue of a hereditary
predisposition to evil.
Towards the end of his career Lombroso recalled how, in 1870, he
had been struck by the similarities between the skull of a brigand and
those of the 'inferior invertebrates'. He concluded from these observa-
tions that 'the characteristics of primitive man and of inferior animals
must be reproduced in our times'.30 How did Lombroso arrive at these
conclusions? In his Crime: Its Causes and Consequences he announced
himself to be a disciple of Darwin, convinced that social life 'was
governed by silent laws, which never fall into desuetude and rule society
much more surely than the laws inscribed in the codes' (369). One such
law was that 'the very progress of the organic world is entirely based
upon the struggle for existence', which was equally applicable to human
evolution (427). In pre-civilised stages of human development, this
struggle took the form of warfare, which was the source of 'immense
progress' by welding tribes into increasingly larger and more complex
societies. This had the effect of imposing social discipline upon the
naturally idle and capricious savage through the principles of hierarchy
and subordination that were vital to civilised existence (441). War,
however, was an evil when nations were civilised, although Lombroso
did not specify how the struggle for existence manifested itself in these
circumstances, despite his insistence on its omnipresence. Another
natural law was heredity, about which Lombroso was also rather vague.
He confidently asserted, nonetheless, that while heredity fixed the
'organic type', not all of its influences were apparent at any given
moment in the life-history of an organism, but often remained latent
29
For a discussion of homo criminalis see M. Foucault, Discipline and Punish, tr.
A. Sheridan (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1977), 1 0 1 - 2 , 2 7 5 - 6 .
30
C. Lombroso, opening address to the Sixth Congress of Criminal Anthropology, Turin,
April 1906. Cited by M . Parmelee, 'Introduction to the English Edition', of Lombroso,
Crime: Its Causes and Remedies, tr. from the French edition by H . P. Horton (Boston:
Little, Brown, 1911), xiv.
76 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
'and manifest themselves gradually throughout the whole period of
development' (174).31
Society was therefore subjected to the laws of heredity and the struggle
for survival, which interacted to cause evolutionary change. But progress
was uneven, and modern societies contained many persons whose
development was fixed at the level of savages or even animals. This was
the case with the born criminal. The physical features of the born
criminal were a low cranial capacity, retreating forehead, highly
developed frontal sinuses, a thick skull, large ears, protruding lower jaw,
tufted and crispy hair, and often included prominent canine teeth,
prehensile feet and left-handedness for good measure. Psychologically,
such a person was insensitive to pain, prone to sensual pleasures,
capable of only blunted affections, lazy, impulsive and incapable of
remorse. Since all of these attributes, physical and mental, were
observable among savages, and even among the anthropoid apes,
Lombroso's conclusion was that 'many of the characters presented by
savage races are very often found among born criminals', and when a
criminal 'lacks absolutely every trace of shame and pity', he 'may go
back far beyond the savages, even to the brutes themselves' (365-8).
The born criminal - responsible, according to Lombroso, for as much as
40 per cent of modern crime - was an atavistic throwback to the savage
and even animal ancestry of modern man, an alien and menacing
presence in the very interstices of a civilisation to which he was innately
inimical. This atavism was evident in many of the practices of born
criminals, for example tattooing (which was typical of savages) and the
use of slang: 'They talk differently from us because they do not feel in
the same way; they talk like savages because they are veritable savages in
the midst of this brilliant European civilisation.' 32
For Lombroso the physical traits of born criminals signifying their
innate criminality could be deciphered by someone with the appropriate
training. He gave several examples of the deployment of his own
expertise for this purpose. When six men were accused of violating a
three-and-a-half-year-old girl by the victim's mother - all of whom
denied the offence - Lombroso was called upon to interrogate the
suspects, and reported: 'I picked out immediately one among them who
had obscene tattooing upon his arm, a sinister physiognomy, irregula-
rities of the field of vision, and also traces of a recent attack of syphilis.
Later this individual confessed his crime' (437).
31
For Lombroso's knowledge of heredity, see Parmelee, 'Introduction', xxx. Parmelee
thinks it probable that Lombroso upheld the inheritance of acquired characters, xxxi.
32
Lombroso, UHomme criminel, 3 vols. (Paris: 1895), I, 497. Cited by Parmelee,
'Introduction', xx.
The emergence of Social Darwinism 77
Lombroso took his analysis beyond a comparison between the savage
and the born criminal. He conceptualised a syndrome of physical and
mental pathologies which brought within a common frame of reference
not only criminals, but 'moral imbeciles' and epileptics. In Criminal
Man he announced: 'The perversion of the affective sphere, the hate,
exaggerated and without motive, the absence or insufficiency of all
restraint, the multiple hereditary tendencies, are the source of irresistible
impulses in the moral imbecile as well as the born criminal and the
epileptic.'33 What linked these afflictions was their hereditary basis and
their primitive origins, that is, their derivation from the earliest phases of
the physical and mental evolution of humanity. In these periods, the
savage had existed in circumstances in which hatred and violence,
unrestrained passion and indifference to suffering, whether in himself in
or in others, were normal daily experiences, which explained the
proclivity of the modern savage for such practices as cannibalism and
infanticide. Civilisation removed these circumstances and repressed the
proclivities, but the latter reappeared in the psyche of the born criminal
and the 'instinctive animalism' of the epileptic.
A glimpse of this primitive heritage was afforded by observing
children. Lombroso was convinced that 'the most horrible crimes have
their origin in those animal instincts of which childhood gives us a pale
reflection'.34 In The Female Offender35 written by Lombroso and his
colleague Ferrero, criminal women were likened to children because in
the former 'their moral sense is deficient... they are revengeful, jealous,
inclined to vengeances of a refined cruelty' (151). The authors
speculated about the enormous potential for crime possessed by
children, only prevented from effective expression by their physical
weakness and undeveloped intelligence (152). In this manner, Lom-
broso combined evolution, recapitulation and heredity to construct a
developmental continuum. Pre-historic humans and modern savages
were closest to our animal forebears; criminals, lunatics and epileptics
were cases of arrested development - individuals stuck on the lowest
rungs of a phyletic ladder which every 'normal' child traversed in the
course of maturation. Or rather, every normal male child, since
Lombroso believed that women were at a considerably lower stage of
evolution than men.
In their study of women offenders Lombroso and Ferrero argued that
female born criminals were, like their male counterparts, typified by a
series of physical abnormalities reflecting their atavistic natures:
33
VHomme criminel, II, 125. Cited by Parmelee, 'Introduction', xxiii.
34
Lombroso, Crime, 3 6 8 .
35
C. Lombroso and W. Ferrero (no tr.), The Female Offender (London: Owen, 1959).
78 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
The criminal being only a reversion to the primitive type of his species, the
female criminal necessarily offers the two most salient characteristics of
primordial woman, namely, precocity and a minor degree of differentiation from
the male - this lesser differentiation manifesting itself in the stature, cranium,
brain, and in the muscular strength which she possesses to a degree so far in
advance of the modern female (112-13).
Here the authors ran into difficulties. Female born criminals were
supposed to be more masculine than non-delinquent women. Yet their
data actually revealed that delinquent females displayed significantly less
physical anomalies than their male counterparts, so much so that female
offenders seemed 'almost normal' in comparison to male criminals
(107). But if females were closer to the evolutionary origins of the species
than were males, then women offenders should exhibit more anomalous
features than men. Lombroso and Ferrero appealed to a number of
factors to explain this seeming contradiction. First, they insisted that
women were inherently more conservative than men, the primary cause
of which was 'the immobility of the ovule compared with the zoosperm'.
Second, the demands of childrearing exposed women to less varied
conditions of existence. Among vertebrates and even more so among
savages, the struggle for life devolved principally upon males, and this
caused variations and 'peculiar adaptations in functions and organs'. For
this reason, women were less exposed to 'transformation and deforma-
tion'. These causes were reinforced, finally, by sexual selection: 'Man
not only refused to marry a deformed female, but ate her, while, on the
other hand, preserving for his enjoyment the handsome woman who
gratified his peculiar instincts. In those days he was the stronger, and the
choice rested with him' (109, original emphasis). These arguments
combined popular perceptions (or, rather, misperceptions) of savage
societies, sexual stereotypes, recapitulation theory and Social Darwinism
in an account of the criminal psyche which, well before the endorsement
of germ-plasm theory, was heavily reductionist.
It has been suggested that in the latter part of his career Lombroso
came to place more stress on social determinants of criminal beha-
viour.36 If this was indeed the case he always assigned a preponderant
role to atavism in the cause of crime, even to the extent of attributing
tattooing and the use of slang to inheritance. His biological determinism
was clearly in evidence, for example, in his discussion of alcoholism,
when he wrote: 'The progeny of the alcoholic are blind, paralytic,
impotent. Even if they begin life with wealth, they must necessarily
become poor. If they are poor, they are incapable of working.' The
criminal was likewise driven to act as he did by innate predispositions
36
Parmelee, 'Introduction', xxviii.
The emergence of Social Darwinism 79
over which he had no control. Thus Lombroso saw in the criminal 'a
savage and at the same time a sick man'. 37 Despite this, Lombroso
cautioned against any undue sympathy for homo criminalis. If crime was
an inescapable feature of social life, so was punishment, for it was
pointless to try and reform the born criminal: the death penalty was part
of the incessant struggle for existence and was therefore 'inscribed in the
book of nature5. Lombroso reasoned: 'The fact that there exist such
beings as born criminals, organically fitted for evil, atavistic reproduc-
tions, not simply of savage men but even of the fiercest animals, far from
making us more compassionate towards them ... steels us against all
pity.' But Lombroso opposed the indiscriminate use of the death
penalty, preferring instead the isolation of born criminals to prevent
them reproducing, and he even toyed with the possibility of turning their
instincts to good use: 'If we try to apply the Darwinian law (according to
which only those organisms survive which have utility for the species) to
the fact that crime does not cease to increase ... we are driven to believe
that it must have, if not a function, at least a social utility.' So instead of
repressing criminals, the state should seek to harness their behaviour to
socially useful ends, and he recommended the army for murderers and
the police force or journalism for swindlers.38
Lombroso's methodology, which relied upon anthropometric mea-
surements for its data base, had come under increasing attack by the
beginning of the twentieth century. Nevertheless, the concept of the
born criminal was to remain an important one in debates about
criminality, especially in those emanating from eugenics and racial
hygiene. This held true even among persons possessing a sophisticated
knowledge of genetics, as is aptly illustrated by the eugenicist and
professor of racial hygiene, Fritz Lenz (1887-1976), writing in Germany
half a century after the Italian had first propounded his views. Lenz even
embraced a similar semiotic approach, claiming it possible to infer
mental constitution from physical traits. He argued:
there are close relationships between race and crime. I am inclined to think that
there is even a certain amount of truth in the doctrine formulated a good many
years ago by Lombroso, that the 'born criminal' belongs to a special and
primitive racial stock. Criminals very often exhibit characters which remind us of
Neanderthal man or of other primitive races, having prominent and massive
jaws, receding foreheads, etc.39
37
Lombroso, Crime, 89; Lombroso, UHomme criminel, II, 135, cited by Parmelee,
'Introduction', xxiv.
38
Lombroso, Crime, 4 2 6 , 4 2 7 , 4 4 0 , 4 4 7 .
39
F. Lenz, 'The Inheritance of Intellectual Gifts', in E. Bauer, E. Fischer and F. Lenz,
Human Heredity, tr. E. and C. Paul (London: Allen and U n w i n , 1931), 6 8 1 . This is a
translation of the third edition (1927) of the important textbook Grundriss der
80 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
Lenz speculated that when these early races had been extirpated some of
their blood had been preserved through inter-mixture with other races,
with the result that vestiges of early man probably 'remain scattered here
and there in the European population of today, and . . . the carriers of
this primitive hereditary equipment are peculiarly apt to come into
conflict with the demands of modern civilised life'. 40 In the case of Lenz
and his co-authors, familiarity with advances in modern genetics was
utilised to reconfirm the theory of criminal atavism advanced by the
'Italian' school of criminal anthropology, with, ultimately, inhuman
consequences, as will be shown in the chapter on Nazism.
Although I have pointed to the continuity between Lombroso's notion
of the born criminal and the ideas of Lenz and his co-authors, it would
be facile to interpret the Italian's work as a form of proto-Nazism. Gould
has emphasised the reformist and even socialist proclivities of many of
the leaders of criminal anthropology, who were committed to a more
rational order.41 As Pick has shown, Lombroso's criminal science was
part of an attempt to understand the foundations of political instability
and social stagnation in the post-unification era in Italy, and he was
'typically perceived at the time as a progressive figure .. .' 42 To see
criminality and other forms of 'anti-social' behaviour as having a
hereditary basis was commonplace at this time. What Lombroso and his
co-workers did was to posit an explanation for crime that was to become
an important model of Social Darwinist reasoning even after its
methodological foundations had been undermined.
Conclusion
The theorists discussed in this chapter were by no means the only
notable pioneers in the application of Darwinism to social and political
subjects. Clemence Royer in France, Ernst Haeckel in Germany, and
Herbert Spencer in England were all creative and influential participants
in this development, and their contributions will be surveyed in later
chapters.43 From these early examples, however, it is possible to arrive at
menschlichen Erblichkeitslehre und Rassenhygiene. The second edition (1923) of this text
was apparently read by Hitler during his imprisonment in Landsberg fortress. See
R. Lerner, Final Solutions (Pennsylvania State University Press, 1992), 70.
40 41
Lenz,'Inheritance', 681. Gould, Ever Since Darwin, 227.
42
Pick, Faces of Degeneration, 122. Chapter 5 of Pick's study provides a detailed
assessment of Lombroso's work and its context.
43
The quality of these pioneering efforts makes it impossible to concur with D . Bellomy's
assertion that the 'earliest applications of Darwinism by social scientists were cavalier
and imprecise': ' "Social Darwinism" Revisited', 39. The writings of Brace, Royer and
Spencer were highly detailed and imaginative applications of Darwinism, as was
Bagehot's contribution, even if his Darwinism was looser than that of the others.
The emergence of Social Darwinism 81
some general inferences concerning the nature and discursive functions
of Social Darwinism.
First, the writings of Bagehot and Lombroso established a set of
identities and differences located along an evolutionary continuum in
which the presumed attributes of pre-historic people designated the
starting point of evolution. Various other categories could then be
equated with primitive people if they were deemed to exhibit these
characteristics. Modern 'savages', children, women, criminals, the
insane, epileptics - sometimes even entire classes in the case of Bagehot
- could be assigned inferior positions and substituted for one another on
the evolutionary ladder. This tactic did not originate with Social
Darwinism, as was pointed out above. But Social Darwinism increased
its plausibility and provide the value judgements implicit in these
categorisations with a scientific mantle. As the example of Lenz
indicates, and subsequent chapters will confirm, it is a constantly
recurring feature of much Social Darwinist theorising.
Second, the theorists discussed above already indicate the flexibility of
Social Darwinism, which underwrote the conservatism of Bagehot, the
atheistic materialism and political radicalism of Biichner, the Christian
humanism of Brace and the criminal anthropology of Lombroso. In all
instances the elements comprising the world view were clearly discern-
ible, though in some cases their interconnections were modified. Finally,
all the writers displayed ambiguities and tensions in their use of Social
Darwinism. These aporias derive from the dilemmas exposed by the
rhetorical appropriation of Social Darwinism: they occur even in
theorists dedicated to the construction of a comprehensive evolutionary
philosophy of nature and society, such as Herbert Spencer, the subject
of the next chapter.
Herbert Spencer and cosmic evolution
Introduction
For many people the name of the English philosopher Herbert Spencer
(1820-1903) would be virtually synonymous with Social Darwinism.
Not only did Spencer coin the expression 'the survival of the fittest' and
apply it to social evolution, he was also instrumental in popularising the
term 'evolution' in its modern sense.1 Although his influence waned in
the twentieth century, during the last three decades of the nineteenth
century he enjoyed a world-wide reputation: his books were translated
into many languages and at times there were over a million copies in
print.2 Spencer appears to be not only a quintessential Social Darwinist,
therefore, but also a highly influential one.
As was noted in the introduction, however, this identification of
Spencer with Social Darwinism has been questioned by modern
historians who have denied the existence of specifically Darwinian
elements in Spencer's thought.3 Some commentators have gone so far as
to suggest that to interpret Spencer as a Social Darwinist is to
misrepresent and even to caricature his work.4 Others focus upon
Spencer's political theory and pay less attention to his evolutionary
arguments.5 Contrary to both these tendencies, I am going to argue,
first, that Spencer was a Social Darwinist; and second, that the relation-
1
P. J. Bowler, 'The Changing Meaning of Evolution', Journal of the History of Ideas,
36(1975), 106-9.
2
R. M. Young, 'Herbert Spencer and Inevitable Progress', History Today, 37(1987), 18.
It is important not to exaggerate Spencer's decline for he continued to exert an
influence throughout the twentieth century. See, for example, C. W. Saleeby, Evolution,
the Master Key (London: Harper, 1906), which hints at 'hero-worship' (v); Meldola,
Evolution; Sir E. Benn, The State the Enemy (London: Benn, 1953).
3
J. D. Y. Peel, Herbert Spencer: The Evolution of a Sociologist (London: Heinemann,
1971), 147; Bannister, Social Darwinism, 55; P. J. Bowler, Evolution, 267-72.
4
J. H. Turner, Herbert Spencer: A Renewed Appreciation (Beverly Hills/London: Sage,
1985), 11.
5
For examples, see W. L. Miller, 'Herbert Spencer's Theory of Welfare and Public
Policy', History of Political Economy, 4(1972), 207-31; and the essays devoted to
Spencer's political ideas in History of Political Thought, 2(1981).
82
Herbert Spencer and cosmic evolution 83
ship between Spencer's evolutionary and political thought is funda-
mental for an understanding of this latter aspect of his work.6
At the age of sixteen, Spencer published a defence of the new Poor
Laws in which he invoked scriptural authority for his assertion that the
idle and improvident should not be allowed to prosper at the expense of
the thrifty and diligent.7 This stance reflected the values of radical
individualism and self-help which Spencer had imbibed from his
family.8 During his subsequent career as a railway engineer, journalist
and writer, his allegiance to these values was unwavering; what was to
change was the basis upon which they were validated. As an adult,
Spencer abandoned religion in favour of an all-embracing Synthetic
Philosophy, the central tenet of which was the idea of'cosmic evolution'.
Cosmic evolution
Spencer's notion of evolution was derived from the principle of the
conservation of energy or, as he preferred, the 'persistence of force'.
Throughout the universe, matter and motion were constantly redistrib-
uted. Evolutionary change consisted in the simultaneous integration of
matter and dissipation of motion, whereas dissolution involved the
disintegration of matter and the absorption of motion. Nature was in a
state of constant evolution because of the 'instability of the homoge-
neous'; the differential impact of persistent force on a homogeneous
body induced changes within it, hence the progressive development of
all phenomena from simple and incoherent states to conditions of
structural complexity through the differentiation and integration of
parts. 'Not only is all progress from the homogeneous to the hetero-
geneous, but, at the same time, it is from the indefinite to the definite.' 9
6
A recent study has argued that, starting from a conception that was neither Darwinian
nor Lamarckian, Spencer sought to synthesise features of both biological theories. See
M. Taylor, Men Versus the State (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), chaps. 2 and 3.
Although providing an excellent contextualisation of Spencer's thought and an
illuminating account of his evolutionary ideas, I believe Taylor underplays the
congruence between Darwin and Spencer. The same charge could be levelled against
Spencer's American disciple and populariser, E. L. Youmans, who insisted that, unlike
Spencer, Darwin was not concerned with elucidating 'the general laws of Evolution'.
See his 'Herbert Spencer and the Doctrine of Evolution' (1874), in J. Fiske, Life and
Letters of Edward Livingstone Youmans (London: Chapman and Hall, 1894), 526-43.
7
Reproduced in J. Offer, ed., Herbert Spencer: Political Writings (Cambridge University
Press, 1994). See D. Wiltshire, The Social and Political Thought of Herbert Spencer
(Oxford University Press, 1978), 21 etseq.
8
See Spencer's description of the character traits of his father and uncles in his
Autobiography, 2 vols. (London: Williams and Norgate, 1904), I, 42; II, 441.
9
Herbert Spencer, 'The Social Organism', in Spencer, The Man Versus the State, with
Four Essays on Politics and Society, ed. D. Macrae (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1969),
215. Spencer's general theory of evolution was set out in 1860 in his First Principles,
84 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
With regard to organic nature, Spencer claimed that each organism
struggled to maintain an equilibrium between itself and its environment.
Because the latter was constantly changing, adjustments were also
continuous, producing moving equilibria until the organism either failed
to adapt or eventually succumbed to the processes of dissolution and
death. Spencer distinguished two forms of 'equilibration'. The first he
named 'direct equilibration' consisting of 'certain changes of function
and structure that are directly consequent on changes in the incident
forces - inner changes by which the outer changes are balanced and the
equilibrium restored'. 10 This direct adaptation by the organism to its
environment was accompanied by 'indirect equilibration' in the form of
natural selection, or survival of the fittest, a process which 'has always
been going on, is going on now, and must ever continue to go on'. 11
There were, however, two facets of natural selection. The first he
designated as a self-evident truth, namely that 'the average vigour of any
race would be diminished did the diseased and feeble habitually survive
and propagate; and that the destruction of such, through failure to fulfil
some of the conditions to life, leaves behind those who are able to fulfil
the conditions to life, and thus keeps up the average fitness to the
conditions of life . . . > 1 2 This aspect of the survival of the fittest Spencer
regarded as well established, having himself drawn attention to its role in
maintaining the average fitness of a population in 1852.13 What Spencer
did not recognise until the publication of the work of Darwin and
Wallace was the part played by natural selection in producing fitness
through its action on the variations which occurred between organ-
isms.14 He wrote in his Autobiography: 'At that time I ascribed all
modifications to direct adaptation to changing conditions; and was
unconscious that in the absence of that indirect adaptation effected by
the natural selection of favourable variations, the explanation left the
large part of the facts unaccounted for.' 15 It was Darwin's achievement
to have discovered and demonstrated this process.
sixth edn (London: Williams and Norgate, 1922), Part II. For a detailed account of this
theory, see Taylor, Men Versus the State, 76-85.
10
Spencer, Principles of Biology, 2 vols., revised edn (New York: Appleton and Co., 1898),
I, 528.
11
Ibid., I, 531.
12
Ibid. By 'race' Spencer here means a biological sub-species or variety.
13
Spencer, 'A Theory of Population Deduced from the General Law of Animal Fertility',
Westminster Review, 1(1852), 468-501. Spencer was correct to insist on the widespread
acceptance of this notion of selection, which had often been employed by naturalists as
evidence of the impossibility of evolutionary transmutation. See S. J. Gould, An Urchin
in the Storm (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1990), chap. 3.
14
Spencer, Principles of Biology, I, 532-3.
15
Spencer, Autobiography, I, 502. See also II, 50.
Herbert Spencer and cosmic evolution 85
The stimulus to the struggle for existence was provided by population
pressure, which had always been the 'proximate cause of progress'.16
This struggle was both inter- and intra-specific. The relationship
between predators and prey was an incessant cause of mutual adaptation
which produced improvements in senses and organs.17 Successful modi-
fications were inherited by subsequent generations, leading to cumu-
lative and progressive development.18 This struggle was augmented by
another which occurred within each species. 'The stronger often carries
off by force the prey which the weaker has caught. Monopolising certain
hunting grounds, the more ferocious drive others of their kind into less
favourable places. With plant-eating animals, too, the like holds.'19 The
struggle for resources was thus a ubiquitous selective process: 'Placed in
competition with members of its own species and in antagonism with
members of other species, it [the organism] dwindles and gets killed off,
or thrives and propagates, according as it is ill-endowed or well-
endowed.'20 Moreover, Spencer deemed rivalry over resources to occur
even within each individual organism. Organs appropriated blood and
nutrients from a common stock: 'So that though the welfare of each is
indirectly bound up with that of the rest; yet directly, each is antagonistic
to the rest.' This inter-organic competition stimulated the growth and
development of organs.21
Like all organisms, humans were governed by the mechanisms of
direct and indirect equilibration. Despite their relatively low rate of
reproduction, humans were subjected to an ineluctable pressure of
population on the means of subsistence, stimulating their faculties and
engendering competition. Families and races which failed to adapt to
this pressure were liable to extinction. This harsh discipline had enabled
humanity to advance to its present level of development, thus ensuring
'a constant progress towards a higher degree of skill, intelligence, and
self-regulation - a better coordination of actions - a more complete
life'.22
Warfare was the human analogue of predation, and produced similar
consequences: 'Warfare among men, like warfare among animals, has
had a large share in raising their organisations to a higher stage.' Warfare
produced the survival of the fittest groups whose successful traits would
Human nature was not static: as with all of nature, it changed over
time, albeit very slowly and in accordance with evolutionary laws.
Spencer eschewed the notions of either a fixed or a malleable human
nature in favour of a 'conception of human nature that is changed in the
slow succession of generations by discipline'. 46 Now a society was a
system of cooperative interactions which allowed members to increase
their welfare and adapt and compete more effectively than was possible
through their unaided efforts. But the ability of people to cooperate, and
hence the mode of cooperation adopted, depended upon their level of
intellectual and moral development. 47 The evolution of human nature,
therefore, held the key to social evolution, and this was the sense in
which Spencer's approach can be described as individualistic. Despite
his deference to the dialectic of whole/part interactions, human nature
provided the ultimate explanation of social change.
Spencer constructed two models of social organisation - the militant
and industrial - which expressed two very different modes of coopera-
tion that in turn derived from different stages of the evolution of human
nature. The militant type was typical of the earliest phases of evolution,
and evidence for the intellectual and moral proclivities of people during
these phases could be derived from a number of sources. One was the
institutions and behaviour of the members of contemporary hunter-
43
Spencer, The Study of Sociology, 5 1 .
44
For example, Principles of Psychology, 2 vols., third edn (London: Williams and Norgate,
1890), II, 535; Spencer, Facts and Comments (London: Williams and Norgate, 1902),
9 4 - 6 ; Spencer, Data of Ethics, 3; Spencer, Study of Sociology, 337.
45
Spencer, Education: Intellectual, Moral and Physical (London: Williams and Norgate,
1906), 4 4 .
46 47
Spencer, Study of Sociology, 145. Spencer, Principles of Psychology, II, 508.
Herbert Spencer and cosmic evolution 91
gatherer societies, or 'savages'. Another was those members of advanced
societies who, like savages, remained fixed at primitive evolutionary
levels, such as the 'less cultivated', especially women from 'inferior
ranks'. 48 Finally, because he endorsed a 'recapitulation' theory of
human development according to which advanced organisms repro-
duced the various stages of their evolutionary ancestry during their
maturation, 49 Spencer was able to deduce the physical and behavioural
traits of primitive people from the corresponding traits of modern
children, a deduction that was equally unflattering to both:
During early childhood every civilised man passes through that phase of
character exhibited by the barbarous race from which he is descended. As the
child's features - flat nose, forward-opening nostrils, large lips, wide-apart eyes,
absent frontal sinus, etc. - resemble those of the savage, so too, do his instincts.
Hence the tendency to cruelty, to thieving, to lying, so general among
children.50
62
Spencer, 'Specialised Administration', 2 8 8 - 9 0 ; Spencer, 'Representative Government:
What is it G o o d For?', Man Versus the State, 2 6 5 - 7 0 .
63
T . H . Huxley, Critiques and Addresses (London: Macmillan, 1873), 1 8 - 1 9 . See also
D . G. Ritchie, The Principles of State Interference (London: Swan Sonnenschein, 1891),
17-27.
64
W. M. Simon, 'Herbert Spencer and the*Social Organismn', Journal of the History of
Ideas, 21(1960), 294-9; E. F. Paul, 'Herbert Spencer: The Historicist as Failed
Prophet', Journal of the History of Ideas, 44(1983), 619-38; T. S. Gray, 'Herbert
Spencer: Individualist or Organicist?', Political Studies, 33(1985), 236-53; E. F. Paul,
'liberalism, Unintended Orders and Evolutionism', Political Studies, 36(1988), 251-72;
M. Taylor, 'The Errors of an Evolutionist', Political Studies, 37(1989), 4 3 6 - 4 2 ; E. F.
Paul, 'Herbert Spencer - Second Thoughts', Political Studies, 37(1989), 4 4 5 - 8 ; Taylor,
Men Versus the State, chap. 4.
Herbert Spencer and cosmic evolution 95
the risk of extinction. One of the tasks of sociology was to expose the
folly of political intervention in the working of natural laws by shattering
the widespread and dangerous illusion that 'societies arise by manufac-
ture, instead of arising, as they do, by evolution'. 65
It is important to bear in mind precisely what was Social Darwinian in
Spencer's arguments. He was vehemently opposed to publicly funded
welfare schemes because he believed them to have the effect of
preserving - indeed, often multiplying - the numbers of the unfit. His
attitude to the latter is graphically displayed in the following description
of London's 'undeserving poor':
'They have no work', you say. Say rather that they either refuse work or quickly
turn themselves out of it. They are simply good-for-nothings, who in one way or
another live on the good-for-somethings - vagrants and sots, criminals and those
on the way to crime, youths who are burdens on hard-worked parents, men who
appropriate the wages of their wives, fellows who share the gains of prostitutes;
and then less visible and less numerous, there is a corresponding class of
women.66
73 74
Spencer, Man Versus the State, 1 0 8 - 9 . Spencer, Study of Sociology, 2 5 0 , 2 5 3 .
75
Spencer, Man Versus the State, 143; Study of Sociology, 213; see also Spencer's essays
'Imperialism and Slavery', 'Re-Barbarisation' and 'Regimentation' in Facts and
Comments.
76
Spencer's critique of militarism was utilised by the anti-war feminists in Britain in their
opposition to the First World War. See M. S. Florence, C. Marshall and C. K. Ogden,
Militarism Versus Feminism, ed. M. Kemester and J. Vellacott (London: Virago, 1987),
8 5 , 1 0 5 - 6 . (I am grateful to Phylomena Badsey for providing m e with this reference.)
77
See, for example, Spencer's criticism of certain features of capitalism in 'From
98 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
liberalism generally, fighting a battle on two fronts - against aristocratic
privilege on the one hand and the demands of the organised working
class on the other. For Spencer, to modify liberalism in order to
accommodate the latter was tantamount to a betrayal of the historic
mission of liberalism. Hence: 'The function of Liberalism in the past
was that of putting a limit to the power of kings. The function of true
Liberalism in the future will be that of putting a limit to the powers of
Parliament.'78 In the light of the recrudescence of neo-liberalism and
support for laissez-faire in Britain and the USA in the 1970s, this
prediction has proved remarkably prescient.
Introduction
When Darwin published the Origin Americans were preoccupied with
slavery, the future of their nation, and the likelihood of war: indeed, the
Civil War may have impeded the reception of Darwinism during the
1860s. By this time, however, the United States was experiencing many
of the social and political problems besetting Britain, in addition to the
divisive issue of slavery, which made race a more immediate domestic
concern and one, moreover, that was to be constantly fuelled by
successive waves of immigration. This provided a fertile context for
'scientific' approaches to and resolutions of these problems, and
Darwinism was soon enlisted to these ends, as is evident from Brace's
writings on race and class.
Thanks to the efforts of Darwin's supporters, Darwinism had become
well established by the 1870s, although not all American scientists were
prepared to endorse natural selection fully, and neo-Lamarckism
remained influential throughout the century.1 The position of the
distinguished palaeontologist Edward Drinker Cope (1840-97) exempli-
fies both the continued hold of Lamarck on American naturalists and
the powerful fascination exercised by Darwinism. Cope conceded that
natural selection performed a culling action upon organic variations but
insisted it was unable to account for the variations themselves. These he
explained as the consequence of growth forces which increasingly came
under the control of 'intelligent choice' as one ascended the animal
scale.2 Despite this refusal to grant natural selection a wider role, Cope
was profoundly affected by Darwinism. Prior to the publication of the
See E. J. Pfeifer, 'The United States', in Glick, Comparative Reception. Pfeifer (199)
estimates that neo-Lamarckians outnumbered Darwinists among American scientists
by the end of the century.
E. D. Cope, The Origin of the Fittest: Essays on Evolution (London/New York:
Macmillan, 1887), 16, 40; Cope, 'The Energy of Evolution', American Naturalist,
18(1894), 205-19.
104
Social Darwinism in the USA 105
Ascent he had signalled his hostility to natural selection as a cause of
progress while simultaneously perceiving the relevance of Darwinism to
human evolution. He accepted the simian ancestry of humans, endorsed
a racial hierarchy defined by 'greater or less approximation to the apes',
speculated about the evolution of human intelligence, speech, morality
and social organisation, and described sexual differences as the products
of evolution.3 He also indulged in a tortured attempt to reconcile these
positions with divine creation and biblical accounts of human develop-
ment - an attempt which he subsequently admitted was unsuccessful.4
Even for a convinced neo-Lamarckian like Cope, then, Social Darwin-
ism constituted an authoritative - not to say seductive - body of ideas.
Spencer's writings furnished another influential source of evolutionary
theory. In a series of articles published in the New York Herald in 1870 -
the same year she declared her intention of standing for the Presidency -
the feminist Victoria Woodhull (1838-1927) reinterpreted the history of
civilisation in evolutionary terms. Although these essays did not make
use of natural selection and the survival of the fittest, they did insist on
the relevance of biological evolution to the study of society, declaring:
'The same laws that govern the growth and multiply the plant also
govern society and multiply it. The same laws that bring fruit to
perfection and dissolution perfect and dissolve societies. The same laws
that produce and control the units of the animal kingdom produce and
control the units of society.'5 In later years this assumption would
underpin Woodhull's campaigns for eugenics and the elimination of the
unfit.6
Woodhull's essays exhibit the influence of Spencer's doctrine that
evolution and dissolution were derivatives of the persistence of force. In
this she typified the tremendous popularity among Americans enjoyed
by Spencer during the nineteenth century.7 The enthusiasm for Spencer
is captured in a letter to the Englishman by one of his most fervent
admirers and popularisers in the United States, Edward Livingstone
Youmans (1821-87). Youmans wrote: 'I am an ultra and thoroughgoing
American. I believe there is great work to be done here for civilisation.
What we want are ideas - large, organising ideas - and I believe there is
3
Cope, On the Hypothesis of Evolution: Physical and Metaphysical (New Haven: Chatfield
and Co., 1870), 29, 31, 35, 54-5.
4
Ibid., 33-4, 63-70. For the admission that this reconciliation was unsuccessful see the
Preface to Origin of the Fittest, vii. Cope still included an amended version of this essay
in this volume.
5
V. Woodhull, The Origin, Tendencies and Principles of Government (New York: Woodhull,
Claflin, 1871), 48.
6
Woodhull's eugenics are discussed below in chapter 9.
7
Hofstadter, Social Darwinism, 33-5.
106 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
no other man whose thoughts are so valuable to our needs as yours are.'8
Though not himself an original thinker, Youmans zealously publicised
Spencer's philosophy in the United States. According to Fiske, in
Youmans Spencer found someone always alert to 'the slightest chances
to promote his interests and those of his system of thought'.9 But
however congenial American Social Darwinists found Spencer, they
were never slavish imitators or uncritical disciples, and they modified his
ideas to suit their own intellectual and ideological requirements. The
Social Darwinist world view remained intact throughout these modifica-
tions and constituted a significant factor not only in the political
controversies of the nineteenth century, but also in the development of
the social sciences and philosophy. This significance requires emphasis
because revisionist historiography has contributed to a serious misrepre-
sentation of the role of Social Darwinism in American thought.
This chapter focuses upon the work of three leading American
intellectuals: Sumner, James and Fiske. The latter, with Youmans, was
one of the most important early American popularisers of Darwin and
Spencer, and his philosophy graphically illustrates both the potential and
the dilemmas contained in Social Darwinism.
17
New York: Harper.
18
'The Forgotten Man' in Persons, Social Darwinism, 133.
112 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
In the text on classes, Sumner maintained that unskilled workers in
the United States were in a favourable position due to the shortage of
labour, needing only to be freed from the parasites who lived off them.
Freedom was in fact an essential condition, and being 'an affair of laws
and institutions which bring rights and duties into equilibrium', it was a
consequence of modern social developments (33). Liberty, then, had
nothing to do with issues such as democracy and universal suffrage.
History disclosed 'a tiresome repetition of one story', namely the
appropriation of the state by a class for the purpose of living in luxury.
The causes of this lay deep in human nature and were not peculiar to
any particular class, so irrespective of which class governed, there was a
need to protect individuals from the abuse of state power (30-2). Civil
liberty consisted of ca status created for the individual by laws and
institutions, the effect of which is that each man is guaranteed the use of all his
own powers exclusively for all his own welfare' (34, original emphasis).
Equality was incompatible with liberty (16), and any interference in
society and economy through political engineering was doomed to be
counter-productive:
Whatever we gain ... will be by growth, never in the world by any reconstruction
of society on the plan of some enthusiastic social architect. The latter is only
repeating the old error over again and postponing all our real chances of real
improvement. Society needs first of all to befreedfromthese medlars [sic] - that
is, to be left alone. Here we are, then, once more back at the old doctrine -
Laissez-faire. Let us translate it into blunt English, and it will read, Mind your
own business (120).
Sumner was adamant that the appearance of capital - which was
simply stored and accumulated labour, i.e. human energy (62) -
represented a great advance for civilisation by providing people with
some insurance against the 'sport of Nature' (59). Capitalism, based
upon private property, civil liberty and contract, he described as a 'great
social cooperation. It is automatic and instinctive in its operation' (66).
This spontaneity should not be subverted by socialistic schemes for
redistributing property which failed to understand that the irksome
necessity of labour was induced by the struggle for existence, not by the
machinations of capitalists. Sumner certainly considered 'plutocracy' -
the domination of the state by capitalists - to be a real danger in the
United States (106-7). Nor was he opposed to trade unions: although
critical of the abuses to which they were liable (94, 130) he considered
them quite legitimate instruments in the conflict between employers and
labourers, and even urged that they should assume responsibility for the
industrial regulatory functions currently exercised by government
(93-5). What Sumner desired was that no class should be able to use the
Social Darwinism in the USA 113
state to despoil another. Good government was confined to the provision
of'peace, order, liberty, security, justice, and equality before the law'. 19
These activities established the social framework within which industrial
activities could flourish; thereafter, it was the responsibility of each
individual to provide for his or her wants. 'The State gives equal rights
and equal chances just because it does not mean to give anything else'
(41). In other texts Sumner concluded that conservatism was the only
sound political position, which he defined as the belief that 'the only
possible good for society must come of evolution not of revolution'.20
This being so, then it was 'a matter of patriotism and civic duty to resist
the extension of State interference'.21
In his assault on collective welfare Sumner did not level the charge
made by Spencer, i.e. that it represented an evolutionary regression to
the militant type of society. For Sumner, militancy and industrialism
were psychological propensities arising from outgroup aggression and
ingroup solidarity respectively. He tended to conceptualise the extremes
of evolutionary development in terms of 'barbarism' and 'civilisation',
but, like the English philosopher, he believed that the advance from one
state to the other had been very uneven. Not only did mankind represent
every grade of civilisation, from the most barbarous to the most
advanced, but these levels were reproduced within the most civilised
states. As Sumner pointed out in his essay on classes, this was especially
true of large cities 'where the highest triumphs of culture' coexisted with
'survival of every form of barbarism and lower civilisation' (70). Civil
liberty and laissez-faire therefore constituted the foundations for future
development by placing the onus of adaptation exclusively on the
individual: 'The penalty of ceasing an aggressive behaviour towards the
hardships of life on the part of mankind is, that we go backward. We
cannot stand still' (73). Sumner's evolutionary sociology thus exhibited
many of the features of Spencer's theory: development as a consequence
of unceasing struggle which, being a law of nature, was ineluctable; an
uneven social advance from a primitive to a civilised condition, with the
distinct possibility of stagnation if current political trends were not
reversed; the construction of a category of the unfit, largely on the basis
of a moral evaluation ('loafers', the 'silly', etc.) whose parasitic behaviour
threatened future evolution; and laissez-faire elevated to the status of a
natural law, creating the appropriate social milieu within which selection
could occur.
19
Sumner, Collected Essays in Political and Social Science (New York: Henry Holt, 1885),
99.
20
'The N e w Social Issue', in Persons, Social Darwinism, 163.
21
'State Interference', in Persons, Social Darwinism, 108.
114 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
Sumner's sociology differed from that of Spencer, however, on a
number of points. 22 For example, Sumner made far less use of analogies
from the animal kingdom, and was sceptical about the alleged
inheritance of instincts from an animal ancestry.23 Even more significant
is their different interpretations of militancy and warfare. Spencer's
evolutionary perspective on the impact of natural selection on human
societies allowed for a transformation of the struggle from violent to
peaceful means. Sumner's position was more static: ingroup selection
was peaceful, but militancy remained important between states. Uni-
versal peace was impossible because war derived from the competition
for life and was therefore an inevitable feature of the human condition.
This argument expresses Sumner's qualified acceptance of progress.
Societies became larger and more complex through time, leading to
increased specialisation, advances in the arts and sciences and in
economic productivity, and the emergence of civil liberty. But the
optimism of both Spencer and Fiske was absent from the pages of
Sumner's publications. The very circumstances of advancement appear
to coexist with an unalterable condition of effort and abstinence:
'Labour and self-denial, to work yet abstain from enjoying, to earn a
product yet work on as if one possessed nothing, have been the condition
of advance for the human race from the beginning, and they continue to
be such still.'24 This struggle for welfare 'constitutes history, or the life
of the human race on earth'.25 Nature for Sumner unquestionably acted
as a model for social relations, as for Spencer and Fiske. But it was a
much harsher one in that, unlike the other two men, Sumner did not
seek to soften what he saw as the realities of the natural order by erecting
a vision of a future world in which these realities were transcended or
even mitigated. He approved of peace and repudiated militancy and
violence, yet the laws of nature indicated no possibility of mankind's
emancipation from either. Spencer and Fiske counselled patience in the
face of the laws of progress; Sumner offered stoical acceptance of the
need for ceaseless struggle.
22
These differences, and their significance, render inappropriate the description of
Sumner's sociology as 'Spencerianism in American dress'. See the essay of that title by
H. E. Barnes in Barnes, ed., An Introduction to the History of Sociology, abridged edn
(London: University of Chicago Press, 1966), chap. 17.
23
Sumner, in Folkways ( N e w York: Ginn, 1906), argued that this inheritance was possible
but unproven (2). Later he drew parallels between human and organic heredity and
variation but insisted that these had n o value (84). Sumner was not consistent in this,
however, and occasionally likened humans to 'other animals' (4).
24
Sumner, Collected Essays, 4 0 .
25
Sumner, 'Sociology', 24.
Social Darwinism in the USA 115
Every civilised society has to carry below the lowest section of the masses a dead
weight of ignorance, poverty, crime, and disease. Every such society has, in the
great central section of the masses, a great body which is neutral in all the policy
of society. It lives by routine and tradition. It is not brutal, but it is shallow,
27
Persons, 'Introduction', Social Darwinism, 3; Bannister, 'William Graham Sumner's
Social Darwinism', 97.
28
Sumner, What Social Classes Owe To Each Other, 75.
Social Darwinism in the USA 117
narrow-minded, and prejudiced. Nevertheless it is harmless. It lacks initiative
and cannot give an impulse for good or bad. It produces few criminals. It can
sometimes be moved by appeals to itsfixedideas and prejudices. It is affected in
its mores by contagionfromthe classes above it (50).
As this citation makes plain, the masses initiated nothing: creativity was
the prerogative of the few. 'Only the elite of any society, in any age,
think ...'(206).
Sumner repeated his earlier conviction that no class could be trusted
to rule society impartially and hence the task of constitutional govern-
ment was to devise means for preventing the abuse of state power. At the
same time, he was convinced of the inevitability of a ruling class. 'In
every societal system or order', affirmed Sumner, 'there must be a ruling
class or classes; in other words, a class gets control of any society and
determines its political form or system. The ruling class, therefore, has
the power' (169). This meant that ultimately all controversies over rights
were resolved by force, although he used this latter term in a broad
sense. 'Nothing but might has ever made right, and if we include in
might (as we ought to) elections and the decisions of courts, nothing but
might makes right now' (65). All disputes have to end, and they are
terminated by force: the aggrieved parties invariably complain of violated
rights, but they are ultimately 'overborne by force of some kind.
Therefore might has made all the right which ever has existed or exists
now' (66).
In Folkways, then, Social Darwinism functions as an organising
narrative. In the earlier essays, while this function was discernible it was
secondary to the rhetorical use of Darwinian concepts to support
Sumner's political and moral views. This use appears in the later text as
well, for instance in Sumner's strictures on the notion of wage-slavery
(178-9). But the main thrust of this book was to catalogue various
folkways and to show how they arose through and were modified by the
struggle for existence and the competition of life. Indeed, by focusing
upon the sources of social variation and by including a chapter on
'Societal Selection', Sumner was more strictly Social Darwinist in
Folkways than in his earlier publications. In this he may have been
influenced by the uncompromising versions of Social Darwinism
associated with European theorists such as Westermarck, Vacher de
Lapouge, Ratzel, Gumplowicz, Ammon and Galton, who appear in his
notes and bibliography. Yet Sumner did not explicitly assign a
preponderant role to heredity as did many of these authors; for him,
social evolution was analogous to, rather than derivative from, organic
evolution, and he sought to explicate the sources of variation and
conservation and the cultural mechanisms through which competition
118 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
and selection took place. He was thus a determinist because for him
evolutionary laws were inexorable and unavoidable, but he was not a
biological reductionist in that the laws in question operated in and
through social beliefs, practices and institutions.
Conclusion
By the beginning of the 1880s Darwinism had been put to a variety of
theoretical usages by American intellectuals. Brace made it the basis of a
science of racial development; Fiske and Sumner employed it to show
34
The sociobiologist Wilson proclaims that the combination of genes responsible for any
particular gifted person is unlikely to appear in the same family more than once. 'So if
genius is to any extent hereditary, it winks on and off through the gene pool in a way
that would be difficult to measure or predict.' E. O. Wilson, On Human Nature
(London: Harvard University Press, 1978), 198.
Social Darwinism in the USA 121
that social change was refractory to political and legislative engineering;
James extolled the evolutionary significance of genius. Sumner's adapta-
tions achieved the greatest notoriety and his name, along with Spencer's,
has become synonymous with Social Darwinism. But Brace and James
were every bit as committed to the world view as Sumner and Spencer,
as indeed they were to the idea of individual liberty. Having different
conceptions of how the latter was realised, and different evaluations of
the status quo with respect to this realisation, Brace and James differed
from Sumner and Spencer on the ideological implications of Darwinism.
Moreover, James re-interpreted the world view itself. But the compo-
nents of the world view and their interconnections were clearly
discernible in all these instances.
The American situation affords a vivid illustration of both the diversity
of contexts in which Social Darwinism could be employed and the
impossibility of deducing a theorist's ideological position from the fact
of being a Social Darwinist. Brace and Fiske both believed Darwinism to
substantiate progress as a historical law; Sumner was at best sceptical
about the existence of any such law. Brace, Fiske and James explicitly
argued for the compatibility of Darwinism and religious belief, while
Sumner's views on warfare differed from those of Fiske (at least when
the latter was in his optimist mode). In all instances, nature was assigned
normative status as a guide for the social sciences and/or as a model for
social action. The world view itself, however, with its indeterminacies,
allowed for radically different perceptions of nature and its laws. It also
promoted hesitancies, ambivalences and inconsistencies within the same
thinker as he sought to come to terms with the social ramifications of
these laws.
This feature has already been commented upon in the work of Fiske
and Sumner, but it is also evident in James's writings. For example, in
his book on psychology James dismissed the claim that habits were
inherited. Habit undoubtedly represented the 'enormous flywheel of
society, its most precious conservative agent'.35 But its heritage was
social rather than biological, since it was not inscribed in the constitution
of the mind. It was precisely because habits were not inherited in this
way that men could think anew, recombine ideas and innovate. This is
why man was, above all, 'the educable animal'.36 Instincts, on the other
hand, were inherited, and James sometimes depicted their influences in
ways which contradicted his strictures against scientific certainty as well
as placing severe limits on the educability of humans. Aggression and
warfare, deriving from the circumstances of primitive tribal existence,
35 36
James, Principles of Psychology, I, 121. Ibid., II, 368, original emphasis.
122 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
were instances of the instinctive heritage of human nature. 'If evolution
and the survival of the fittest be true at all, the destruction of prey and
of human rivals must have been among the most important of man's
primitive functions, the fighting and the chasing instincts must have
become ingrained.'37 Whatever pacific virtues men professed, these
'smouldering and sinister traits' remained part of their psychological
make-up. 'It is just because human bloodthirstiness is such a primitive
part of us', continued James, 'that it is so hard to eradicate, especially
where a fight or a hunt is promised as part of the fun.' 38 Likewise with
women: totally formed in character by the age of twenty, they possessed
brains that were less efficient than those of men, rendering them
unreceptive to thoughts that were inaccessible to their 'direct
intuition'.39
These claims were highly deterministic and placed boundaries to the
efficacy of education. In making them James appears to be guilty of
espousing the rigid determinism of which he was elsewhere so critical.
What they reflect, in part at least, is the ambivalence of someone who on
the one hand wished to develop a science of psychology along Darwinist
lines, which involved the linking of human and animal behaviour via the
doctrine of descent, and on the other wanted to acknowledge the
importance of individual creativity and freedom. Social Darwinism
served both causes, but not in ways that were always commensurable.
37 38 39
Ibid., II, 412, original emphases. Ibid. Ibid., II, 368-9.
Social Darwinism in France and Germany
Introduction
When Darwin published the Origin, France and Germany were in the
throes of socio-economic change and political conflict. In France the
legacy of the Revolution was one of cleavage and political confrontation
expressed in the episodes of insurrection, restoration and coup which
occurred until the formation of the Third Republic. Born from the
trauma of military defeat and civil war, the Republic was itself a
precarious compromise that was to be riven by crises during its seventy-
year history. Class divisions, provincial loyalties and the dislocative
impacts of rapid industrialisation and urbanisation were compounded
by an embittered antagonism between the Catholic Church and the
forces of anti-clericalism. Small wonder, then, that French philosophers
and social theorists were continually preoccupied with what Comte had
designated the 'seventh science': la morale. Their aim, whatever their
political predilections, was to discover an authoritative body of beliefs
capable of uniting the nation around an ethical consensus. The
achievements of the natural sciences ensured that many theorists would
seek to emulate these disciplines in the search for models and methods
that could assist in the construction of this moral concordance.
After the abortive revolution of 1848, Germany also experienced
political division against a background of brisk economic growth and
social change. After national unification under Bismarck, the new Reich
was fraught with continuing regional differences and enmities, com-
pounded by hostility between Protestants and a sizeable Catholic
minority. Abrasive class divisions were reflected in the emergence of the
largest socialist party in Europe, in addition to a sharp differentiation
between rural/agrarian and urban/industrial sub-cultures. Tensions with
rival nationalities added to these difficulties, and in the neighbouring
Austro-Hungarian Empire these tensions between Germans and other
ethnic groups were such as to encourage some of the former to
contemplate an expansion of the Reich that would include all German
123
124 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
nationals within its boundaries. To the pressures wrought by industria-
lisation, urbanisation, nationalism and democratisation were added
conflicts between religious orthodoxy and a critical and rationalist
temper exemplified by a new spirit of biblical criticism and the growth of
science, particularly in the field of biology.
Both national contexts, therefore, provided fertile conditions for the
reception and development of the Social Darwinist world view. As we
have seen in the cases of Britain and the USA, the world view offered the
promise of new certainties that could be inferred from the processes
which regulated both history and human nature, namely adaptation,
selection and heredity. The theorists who represent the main focus of
this chapter - Clemence Royer and Ernst Haeckel - were quick to
exploit this promise in France and Germany respectively.
8
Royer, 'Preface', lxiv. Royer, 'Preface, lxi; Origine, 531-2.
128 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
competition here taking a peaceful form, although she did not elaborate
on this point.
Royer, therefore, endorsed all the elements of the Darwinist world
view, which she applied to questions concerning the origins and develop-
ment of humans and their social arrangements. She also forcefully raised
what she saw to be the political and ethical implications of this world
view.
9
See Royer's defiant reassertion of these views in her 'Avant Propos' of 1866, vii.
Social Darwinism in France and Germany 129
with evolution. Since nature had decreed the unequal value of
individuals, liberty allowed each one to realise his or her own worth, and
competition weeded out the unsuccessful. Egalitarian policies stifled
initiative and reduced the rewards accruing to effort and success (583-
4). 'The formula for the highest social prosperity is therefore equality of
initial liberty for each member of the national group, and the free play of
individual capabilities [forces] and initiatives' (585). One of the objectives
of science must be the exposure of the absurdity of egalitarian creeds
and the demonstration that 'equality of liberty and progress through
inequality is the law of equity and the road to happiness for all...' (587).
Royer looked to Darwinism to provide a naturalist foundation for
ethics. In her view, it established an absolute criterion for distinguishing
between right and wrong because 'the moral rule for every species is that
which tends to its conservation, to its multiplication, to its progress,
relative to place and time'.10 This was the rationale for Royer's
swingeing attack on misguided public and private charity, i.e. charity
which, by evolutionary standards, had the consequence of sacrificing the
good to the bad:
What is the result of this exclusive and unintelligent protection accorded to the
weak, the infirm, the incurable, the wicked, to all those who are ill-favoured by
nature? It is that the ills which have afflicted them tend to be perpetuated and
multiplied indefinitely; that evil is increased instead of diminishing, and tends to
grow at the expense of good.11
The targets of this diatribe were the losers in the struggle for existence
whose hereditary defects would be perpetuated and increased by
charitable actions aimed at their protection and welfare. In the light of
these sentiments it is ironic (or perhaps poetic justice) that Royer,
although achieving some belated public recognition and financial
security by the end of her life, at one time fell into indigence and was
obliged to enter a retirement home. 12
We have already encountered Royer's assertion that social inequalities
invariably had a biological foundation. There was, though, an exception
to this rule: the subordinate position of women in modern societies.
This arose with the appearance of warrior societies which provided the
opportunity for male domination to replace the equal relationships
between the sexes that had prevailed hitherto. Royer repudiated the idea
that patriarchal relations had any natural or biological foundation. She
considered them to be an interregnum in the otherwise co-equal
development of the sexes, and responsible for an unbalanced evolution
10
Royer, 'Preface', lxiii. Royer developed her ideas on ethics in her Le Bien et la lot morale
(Paris: Guillaumin, 1881).
11 12
Ibid., lvi. Harvey,' "Doubly Revolutionary"', 256.
130 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
of the mental faculties and social roles of men and women. Hence 'it
follows from these considerations that there is nothing inevitable,
nothing absolute, about the differences in aptitudes and functions which
exist today among the two halves of humanity'. Races which failed to
recognise this and adapt to modern conditions by allowing women
freedom to participate in intellectual progress would succumb to more
enlightened rivals in the struggle for life, and vanish from the face of the
earth.13
Royer was in a good position to appreciate the workings of
patriarchalism, since her failure to secure an academic post was probably
a result of her gender. Her feminism, therefore, resonated her experi-
ences as well as her convictions, and was conveyed with passion in her
writings. Yet its relationship to her hereditarian determinism is highly
problematic, and it is difficult to resist the impression of intellectual and
political opportunism in her insistence that the position of females
represented an exception to the general rule that social inequalities
reflected biological differences. To argue for the social determination of
sex roles is therefore an aporia in her writings, a switch in the mode of
argumentation stemming from certain ideological motives that led her to
contradict the assumptions that grounded her work.
In assessing Royer's Social Darwinism it is tempting to focus on those
facets of her 'Preface' which had so shocked her contemporaries, i.e. her
feminism, anti-clericalism and her critique of charity for the 'unfit'. But
to do so would be to understate in some respects the importance of her
ideas. She never achieved the readership and popularity of Haeckel and
Spencer, but her projected 'semiotics of nature' should be seen as one of
the earliest attempts to locate Darwinism within a wider philosophical
framework - one that was systematically formulated and explicitly linked
to socio-political issues. It was a framework proposed as an alternative to
religion through a comprehensive account of humanity - its origins, its
history, its relationship to the rest of nature, and its future. It was, in
short, an attempt to discover a naturalistic basis for la morale - one that
was capable of dealing with the inescapable fact of humanity's location
in time and hence with the historicity and seeming contingency of its
institutions and beliefs, of those very attributes by which it had, in
various cultural contexts, defined itself as human. Royer's efforts
confronted these issues by elaborating what she took to be the
13
Royer, Origine, 391; 'Preface', lx. For discussions of Royer's feminism, see Harvey,
' "Doubly Revolutionary"'; and Harvey, ' "Strangers to Each Other": Male and
Female Relationships in the life and Work of Clemence Royer', in P. Abir-Am and
D. Outra, eds., Uneasy Careers and Intimate Lives (New Brunswick: Rutgers University
Press, 1987).
Social Darwinism in France and Germany 131
philosophical, ethical and political implications of the Darwinian
revolution in biological science.
Royer was not alone in France in her efforts to enlist Darwinism in the
service of liberalism. A Belgian-born economist, Gustave de Molinari
(b. 1818), was a prolific publicist of the doctrines of political economy
which he readily assimilated to Darwinism. His L'Evolution economique,14
for example, applied Darwinian concepts to the development of what he
designated as the modern 'economic state', i.e. an international system
of production and exchange. This state, and its continual progress,
comprised a regime of 'unlimited competition' in which the penalty for
remaining stationary for industries and nations was inevitable destruc-
tion (77). Molinari distinguished between la petite Industrie in which
production was principally achieved through physical labour, and la
grande industrie where mechanical force dominated production. Since
the birth of civilisation (i.e. the appearance of agriculture), the second
type had gradually superseded the first, while the individual entrepre-
neur had in turn given way to industrial society and the current
international system (43). Throughout this development, the motor of
change was the struggle for existence.
In early phases of this evolution, struggle took the form of warfare.
War, or its threat, encouraged invention, eliminated the least capable
individuals and nations, and constrained the winners to cultivate their
powers in order to maintain their dominance (86-8). But with the
development of industry, war ceased to be advantageous in the struggle,
and was replaced by economic competition. This Molinari considered to
be even more effective as a goad to progress than warfare because whereas
the latter was confined to the ruling classes, the former was universal in its
scope (88). Competition eliminated the less intelligent, industrious and
moral races. Within each society, evolution raised the general level of
ability, and the least capable individuals slipped to the bottom of the
social hierarchy, although even here there was no refuge from the brutal
selective pressure of competition (94). Nor could one look forward to a
golden age of repose in the future: 'No! competition is struggle, it is the
civilised form of war, which it is destined to abolish ...' (85).
Like Royer, Molinari was fervently opposed to either monarchical
reaction or socialistic utopianism (136). He was aware that coincident
with the production of great wealth there had occurred an equally great
multiplication of pauperism which neither public nor private charity
seemed capable of reducing (102). This he ascribed to the transitional
status of modern societies and to defects in human nature: moral and
14
G. de Molinari, UEvolution economique du dix-neuvieme siecle: theorie du progres (Paris:
Reinwald, 1880).
132 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
intellectual evolution had not kept pace with economic change. The
solution was not to be found in social reconstruction, but in moral
progress as a precondition for increased wealth and its more equitable
distribution (125, 134). Here one detects an ambivalence on Molinari's
part with regard to the implication of economic evolution. On the one
hand, the trend was towards an equilibrium between production and
consumption which represented 'an evolution towards order and justice'
(84). On the other hand, competition was inescapable and entailed the
expropriation and eventual destruction of the weak by the strong (90,
94). Molinari did not explain how moral evolution of any sort could
overcome this dilemma.
15
For the history of Darwinism in Germany, see W. M. Montgomery, 'Germany' in
Glick, Comparative Reception.
16
Schmidt, The Doctrine of Descent and Darwinism, 140.
17
E. Haeckel, The History of Creation, 2 vols., tr. E. R. Lankester (London: King, 1876), I,
161; I, 4.
Social Darwinism in France and Germany 133
quently did it become appropriated by racists and militarists, and then
never exclusively so. 18 But German liberalism differed from Spencerian
individualism in that while it extolled the virtues of private property,
economic competition, freedom of speech and association, and secular
education, it also endorsed a strong nation-state and the vigorous
assertion of German national interests.19 These features of German
liberalism are important to an understanding of the work of Ernst
Haeckel.
Haeckel was not only a creative naturalist in his own right but an
indefatigable advocate for evolutionary theory in particular and for
scientific education in general. His popular studies went through
numerous editions and were translated into several languages. 20 For
Haeckel and his followers, commitment to a scientific appreciation of
man and nature carried with it the responsibility of challenging super-
natural explanations, and they accused religious authorities - especially
the Roman Catholic Church - of obfuscating the pursuit of scientific
knowledge and perverting education. These attacks made Haeckel a
controversial figure during the nineteenth century, and this continues to
be the case in the present day, for modern scholars disagree over how his
work should be interpreted. Some regard him as a thorough-going
Social Darwinist, eugenicist, Aryan supremacist and anti-Semite who
recommended racial and national conflicts as essential to progress. In
these respects, Haeckel is deemed to be a forerunner of and contributor
to National Socialism, all the more influential because his scientific
credentials lent authenticity to his racism and bellicosity. 21 Other
historians have argued that the incidence of Social Darwinism in
Haeckel's writings has been greatly exaggerated and have objected to
18
P. J. Weindling, Darwinism and Social Darwinism in Imperial Germany (Stuttgart: Gustav
Fischer, 1991), 16. See also R. Weikart, 'The Origins of Social Darwinism in
Germany*; T. Benton, 'Social Darwinism and Socialist Darwinism in Germany: 1860-
1900', Rivista diFilosofia, 73(1982), 79-121.
19
For a discussion of German liberalism in the context of social theory, see W. D. Smith,
Politics and the Science of Culture in Germany, 1840-1920 (Oxford University Press,
1991). There is an illuminating discussion of the different political contexts of
Darwinism in Britain and Germany in Weindling, Darwinism and Social Darwinism,
chap.1.
20
Kelly, The Descent of Darwin, 25, describes The History of Creation (1868) as the chief
source for Darwinism in Germany until 1900, by which time it had gone through nine
editions. Another book, The Riddle of the Universe (1899) was translated into twenty
languages and by 1914 had sold over 300,000 copies in Germany alone. See H.-G.
Zmarlik, 'Social Darwinism in Germany Seen as a Historical Problem', in H. Holborn,
ed., Republic to Reich: The Making of the Nazi Revolution, tr. R. Manheim (New York:
Pantheon, 1972), 452.
21
D. Gasman, The Scientific Origins of National Socialism (London: Macdonald, 1970);
J. Moore, 'Varieties of Social Darwinism'; G. J. Stein, 'Biological Science and the
Roots of Nazism', American Scientist, 76(1988), 50-8; Lerner, Final Solutions, chap. 2.
134 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
treating his ideas as a 'theoretical rehearsal for Nazism5, and instead
located the German populariser within a secular and rationalist critical
tradition.22 The following account is not directly concerned with the
relationship between HaeckePs ideas and those of National Socialism,
but in evaluating the extent to which his ideas can be legitimately
described as Social Darwinist it is possible to arrive at an assessment of
their ideological import.
Haeckel perceived a close relationship between philosophy and
science. For him, the former was a synthesising activity which inter-
preted the results of science and coordinated all knowledge into 'one
grand and harmonious whole'. 23 HaeckePs own philosophical system
was 'monism', which asserted 'the unity of all nature, the animating of
all matter, the inseparability of mental power and corporeal substance'.
Monism repudiated supernatural or teleological explanations on the
grounds that 'all phenomena are due solely to mechanical or efficient
causes .. .' 24 Nature in its entirety must be approached from the
standpoint of a unified descriptive and explanatory framework.
The framework in question was evolution. Organisms, arising from
inorganic matter by 'spontaneous generation', underwent a continuous
process of diversification and perfection. This was the 'law of progressive
development', according to which species were modified over time to
produce new species. Evidence for this development and the descent of
all living beings from earlier life-forms was furnished by embryology:
'The history of the foetus is a recapitulation of the human race.' This
was encapsulated in HaeckePs famous Biogenetic Law to the effect that
ontogeny recapitulated philogeny.25
Haeckel was a devotee of the principle of the inheritance of acquired
characters, dismissing Weismann's theory of the germ-plasm as mere
metaphysical speculation. In this he considered himself to be faithful to
the heritage of Lamarck and Darwin, insisting that the transmission of
acquired characters was attested to by an enormous body of evidence
and was 'an indispensable foundation of the theory of evolution'.26
Darwin's specific contribution to evolutionary science was his theory of
natural selection. The Englishman's meticulous marshalling of evidence
revealed the struggle for life to be the impersonal regulator of the
22
Kelly, Descent of Darwin, 8, 101, 114. Kelly maintains (113) that any hints of Social
Darwinism in Haeckel's popular writings 'are minor asides and do not affect the general
tone or substance of his work'.
23
Haeckel, Freedom in Science and Teaching (no tr.) (London: Kegan Paul, 1879), 79;
History of Creation, II, 349.
24
Haeckel, History of Creation, I, 22; Haeckel, The Evolution of Man, tr. J. M c C a b e , 2 vols.
(London: Watts, 1910), II, 748.
25 26
Haeckel, Evolution of Man, I, 4. Ibid., II, 736.
Social Darwinism in France and Germany 135
'reciprocal action of heredity and adaptation in the gradual transforma-
tion of species'. Nature did not unfold in accordance with God's design,
for its changes were 'merely the inevitable outcome of the struggle for
existence, the blind controller .. ,' 27 Haeckel preferred the expression
'competition for the means of subsistence' to 'struggle for existence',28
but his portrayal of this process was graphic and he was uncompromising
in the inferences he drew from its universality. The objective contempla-
tion of nature, he argued, gave no warrant for any belief in peaceful
coexistence:
We shall ratherfindeverywhere a pitiless, most embittered Struggle of All against
All, Nowhere in nature, no matter where we turn our eyes, does that idyllic
peace, celebrated by the poets, exist; wefindeverywhere a struggle and a striving
to annihilate neighbours and competitors. Passion and selfishness - conscious or
unconscious - is everywhere the motive force of life ... 29 Man in this respect
certainly forms no exception to the rest of the animal world.
There was no justification for crediting nature with a moral order. 'We
can only see a "moral order" and "design" in it when we ignore the
triumph of immoral force and the aimless features of the organism.
Might goes before right as long as organic life exists.'30 Yet it was
through this 'purposeless drama' that progress occurred. The struggle
for existence, particularly among organisms closely resembling one
another, engendered adaptive pressures which induced specialisation,
diversification and perfection. These benefits were equally apparent in
the free competition of labourers: 'The greater or more general the
competition, the more quickly improvements are made in the branch of
labour, and the higher is the grade of perfection of the labourers
themselves.'31 Haeckel was somewhat vague, however, on why this
struggle took place, and did not deduce its necessity from the ratio
between population growth and resources. The competition for the
means of subsistence appears as an existential datum, an inescapable
feature of nature and of society.32
Haeckel tirelessly reminded his readers that human beings were
governed by the same laws that ruled the rest of the natural order. He
castigated the anthropocentric claim that man was the centre of the
universe, insisting that 'as our mother-earth is a mere speck in the
sunbeam of the illimitable universe, so man himself is but a grain of
27
Haeckel, The Riddle of the Universe, tr. J. McCabe (London: Watts, 1900), 269, 275.
28 29
Haeckel, History of Creation, I, 161. Ibid., I, 19-20, original emphasis.
30 31
Haeckel, Evolution of Man, I, 72. Haeckel, History of Creation, I, 164.
32
Such is also the case with a popular account of human evolution published by Haeckel's
disciple, Boelsche, which omits any mention of population in its discussion of natural
selection. Cf. W. Boelsche, The Descent of Man (no. tr.) (London: Simpkin, Marshall,
1926), 8 6 - 9 1 .
136 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
protoplasm in the perishable framework of organic nature'. 33 Because
humans were merely highly developed vertebrates, all of their character-
istics were prefigured in the animal kingdom. Indeed, it was apparent in
the ontogenesis of each individual that the first few weeks in the womb
recapitulated a genealogy reaching beyond our vertebrate ancestry to
even more primitive life-forms.34 In order to combat Christian pride in
the uniqueness of humanity - which he saw as an obstacle to scientific
progress - Haeckel was particularly fond of stressing the continuity
between humans and the primates. Every organ in the human body had
been inherited from the apes, and the same was true of mental faculties,
with the differences between man and the apes being quantitative rather
than qualitative in nature. Even the maternal instinct stemmed from 'the
instinct which is found in its extreme form in the exaggerated tenderness
of the mother-ape'. Neither speech nor reason could be legitimately
regarded as the exclusive prerogative of man, while social duties 'are
merely higher evolutionary stages of the social instincts which we find in
all social animals .. .' 35
Haeckel's insistence on human subordination to the empire of natural
laws often assumed the form of biological reductionism. For example,
he claimed: 'We can only arrive at a correct knowledge of the social
body, the State, through a scientific knowledge of the structure and life
of the individuals who compose it, and the cells of which they are in turn
composed.'36 Likewise, he referred to social phenomena as the outcome
of the laws of inheritance, adaptation and natural selection, from which
had evolved the social division of labour, just as specialisation and
differentiation had occurred in plants and animals. In fact, it was
precisely due to the operation of these laws that progress was made
possible, that 'the history of man is the history of his progressive
development*.37 The struggle for existence was very much a feature of this
development. 'The ferocious conflict of interests in human society',
observed Haeckel, 'is only a feeble image of the existence of the combat,
incessant and cruel, which reigns throughout the living world.' 38 He
concluded that the 'whole history of nations, or what is called "Universal
History", must therefore be explicable by means of "natural selection" -
33
Haeckel, Riddle of the Universe, 15. Cf. Haeckel, History of Creation, II, 264.
34
Haeckel, History of Creation, I, 170; Haeckel, Evolution of Man, II, 4 0 4 .
35
Haeckel, Evolution of Man, II, 738; Haeckel, Riddle of the Universe, 5 1 , 128, 359. There
are similarities here with Darwin's comparison between humans and apes. See
D e s m o n d and Moore, Darwin, 2 4 4 .
36
Haeckel, Riddle of the Universe, 8.
37
Haeckel, History of Creation, I, 2 7 1 - 9 , 2 8 2 , original emphasis.
38
Haeckel, Le Monisme: lien entre la religion et la science, tr. G. Vacher de Lapouge (Paris:
Schleicher, 1902), 33.
Social Darwinism in France and Germany 137
must be a physico-chemical process, depending on the action of
Adaptation and Inheritance in the struggle for life. And this is actually
the case.'39 Thus the fate of nations and races 'is determined by the
same "eternal laws of iron" as the history of the whole organic world',
while the destiny of individuals was likewise governed 'with an iron
necessity' by mechanical causes.40 These facts occasionally prompted
Haeckel to deny the existence of free will: 'The will of the animal, as well
as that of man, is never free.' This assertion, made in Haeckel's first
popular book, was repeated over three decades later: 'The human will
has no more freedom than that of the higher animals, from which it
differs only in degree, not in kind.'41 There is a tension at the heart of
Haeckel's system between this reductionism and determinism on the
one hand, and his commitment to ethical values and ideals on the other.
This commitment was plainly articulated in Haeckel's insistence that
scientific materialism did not imply ethical materialism, which he
rejected for its ascription of no other motive to human conduct than
sensory gratification and for ignoring the role of ethical forces in human
conduct.42
Before examining the ideological implications of Haeckel's Darwin-
ismus, it is pertinent to underline the fact that Haeckel quite clearly was a
Social Darwinist. All the components of the Darwinian world view were
articulated in his writings and their relevance to the study of humans
steadfastly maintained. Haeckel also went further than merely proposing
the relevance of Darwinism to the study of humans, by insisting that
nature supplied humans with a model capable of guiding moral and
political actions. Although he described natural selection as a 'blind
controller', Haeckel did not perceive history as a dimension of chance
and accident or the future as unpredictable. Despite his objections to
arguments from design and Creation, he still perceived the existence of
an order in nature and advocated 'a complete and honest return to
Nature and to natural relations'. The order in question consisted of
biological laws and people must recognise their subjection to these laws
and the need to live in conformity with them. This recognition would
facilitate the rearrangement of social institutions such as the family and
the state 'not according to the laws of distant centuries, but according to
the rational principles deduced from knowledge of nature. Politics,
morals, and the principles of justice, which are still drawn from all
possible sources, will have to be formed in accordance with natural laws
only.'43
39 40
Haeckel, History of Creation, I, 170. Haeckel, Riddle of the Universe, 277-8.
41
Haeckel, History of Creation, I, 237; Haeckel, Riddle of the Universe, 133.
42 43
Haeckel, History of Creation, I, 36-7. Ibid., II, 368.
138 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
Haeckel was not only a highly influential populariser of Social
Darwinism, but wrote at a time when the application of Darwinism to
psychological and social phenomena was still in its infancy. Further-
more, although Haeckel once warned of the dangers inherent in the
unqualified transfer of scientific theories to the political domain, and
described his own occasional ventures in this area as of 'no objective
value',44 he was a vigorous polemicist on behalf of secularism and
educational reform, in addition to other causes. As he pointed out in the
very text in which he made this disclaimer: 'Every great and comprehen-
sive theory which affects the foundations of human science, and which,
consequently, influences the systems of philosophy, will, in the first
place not only further our theoretical view of the universe, but will also
react on practical philosophy, ethics, and the correlated provinces of
religion and politics.'45 It is precisely Haeckel's adventures in these
'correlated provinces' which are the basis of controversies over the
ideological import of his ideas. What was this ideological import, and
how did it relate to Haeckel's Social Darwinism?
47
Ibid., 93, original emphasis.
48
Bannister (Social Darwinism, 267) claims Haeckel made these statements tongue in
cheek.
49
Haeckel, History of Creation, I, 228, 232, 281.
140 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
affirmed that all 'woolly-haired' peoples 'are on the whole at a much
lower stage of development, and more like apes' than straight-haired
races. The former were 'incapable of a true inner culture and a higher
mental development' even when they inhabited a civilised milieu like the
USA. The Mediterranean species, in contrast, had always been the most
physically and mentally advanced type, and, with the exception of the
Mongolians, the only one with a history and a civilisation. The English
and Germans were the best representatives of this species, and were
laying the basis for a new era of even higher mental development.50 His
views on inequality were summed up as follows: 'The most primitive
races, such as the Veddahs of Ceylon, or the Australian natives, are very
little above the mental life of the anthropoid apes. From the highest
savages we pass by a complete gradation of stages to the most civilised
races. But what a gulf there is, even here, between the genius of a
Goethe, a Darwin, or a Lamarck, and an ordinary philistine or a third-
rate official.'51
Haeckel believed racial inequalities to be biologically determined, and
he denied any possibility of reducing them through education or other
'artificial methods'. It was futile to try and civilise the lower races
because the necessary precondition for human culture, 'the perfecting of
the brain', had not taken place; any contact with civilisation accelerated
their extinction rather than their improvement. Haeckel was adamant
that all the inferior races 'will sooner or later completely succumb in the
struggle for existence to the superiority of the Mediterranean races'. 52
While the Europeans were destined to spread across the globe, the lower
races were doomed to perish. 'Even if these races were to propagate
more abundantly than the white Europeans', proclaimed Haeckel, 'yet
they would sooner or later succumb to the latter in the struggle for
life.'53
The anti-egalitarian sentiments expressed in Haeckel's defence of
Darwinism against the charge of socialism were not, therefore, off-the-
cuff remarks but part of a system of beliefs about the unequal value of
human beings brought about by the operation of biological laws. Closely
connected to these beliefs were others that anticipated the eugenic
programmes of some later Social Darwinists. Haeckel approved of the
elimination of weak and sickly infants among the ancient Spartans and
the American Indians, and lamented the preservation of inferior babies
at the expense of strong and healthy children in modern states. He
50
Ibid., II, 303-10, 3 2 1 - 3 , 332.
51
Haeckel, Last Words on Evolution: A Popular Retrospect and Summary, tr. J. McCabe
(London: Owen, 1906), 1 0 0 - 1 .
52 53
Haeckel, History of Creation, II, 3 6 3 , 325. Ibid., I, 256.
Social Darwinism in France and Germany 141
accused militarists of proposing to squander the best of the younger
generation in needless wars, leaving the unfit and infirm safe at home to
breed, thus perpetuating their disabilities and diluting the biological
value of the population. This value was additionally under threat from
medical practitioners who kept alive the chronically sick and insane long
enough for them to reproduce, and by a judicial failure to make adequate
use of the death penalty. The latter sanction was required not just in the
interests of justice, but for 'weeding out' incorrigible criminals among
the population. This weeding process eased the struggle for existence
among 'the better portion of mankind' and prevented the transmission
of criminality to the offspring of these 'degenerate outcasts'. He warned
that these examples of 'artificial selection' were responsible for the
currently poor mental and physical condition of most individuals and
the scarcity of healthy and 'free and independent spirits'. 54
In spite of these degenerative tendencies, Haeckel remained confident
that their effects would ultimately be counteracted by the irresistible
action of natural selection in maintaining and enhancing the progress of
civilisation:
The result of the struggle for life is that, in the long run, that which is better,
because more perfect, conquers that which is weaker and more imperfect. In
human life, however, this struggle for life will ever become more and more of an
intellectual struggle, not a struggle with weapons of murder. The organ which,
above all others, in man becomes more perfect by the ennobling influence of
natural selection is the brain. The man with the most perfect understanding, not
the man with the best revolver, will in the long run be victorious; he will transmit
to his descendants the qualities of the brain which assisted him in the victory.
Thus then we may justly hope, in spite of all the efforts of the retrograde forces,
that the progress of mankind towards freedom, and thus to the utmost
perfection, will, by the happy influence of natural selection, become more and
more certain.55
Haeckel's disparaging assessment of the intellectual capabilities of
non-whites and his dismissal of their cultures, his attitude to the sick and
the insane and his desire to weed out criminals, appear to lend credence
to the thesis of his complicity in the elaboration of a proto-Nazi ideology.
The fact is, as will become only too evident in subsequent chapters,
these ideas were quite unexceptional by the standards of the time and
were widespread throughout European and American society. We have
already encountered similar notions in the work of Darwin, Spencer,
Royer and Sumner, who were all liberals. Furthermore, Haeckel, like
these thinkers, was equally ready to utilise Social Darwinism to attack
established institutions and traditions as well as to uphold existing
54 55
Ibid., I, 170-1, 173-4, 172. Ibid., I, 174, original emphasis.
142 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
conventions and values. He bemoaned the lack of biological and
anthropological training among judges and politicians, which he held
responsible for their numerous blunders and inadequacies. He derided
the political and cultural pretensions of the hereditary nobility, whose
inbreeding, aloofness and 'unnatural' education he despised. He was
critical of conservative governments and political reactionaries in
Germany who aligned themselves with repressive clerical forces in order
to curtail the spread of science and enlightenment and stifle academic
freedom.56 Above all, Haeckel condemned the prevailing German
educational system for its excessive focus on the classics and religious
indoctrination at the expense of science. I f the modern state gives every
citizen a vote', reasoned Haeckel, 'it should also give him the means of
developing his reason by a proper education, in order to make a rational
use of his vote for the common weal.' 57
What connected these disparate themes in Haeckel's discourse was
their location within an allegedly scientific account of the world and of
human nature. For him these political positions were matters of fact and
reason, not of faith or Utopian idealism. The main obstacles to the public
recognition of this were the Church (especially the Roman Catholic
Church) and Christianity in general. They represented rival systems of
knowledge and thus were the prime targets of his polemical use of Social
Darwinism. Haeckel insisted that all public issues were secondary to the
question of the relationship between the state and organised religion:
'Whether a Monarchy or Republic be preferable, whether the constitu-
tion should be aristocratic or democratic, are subordinate questions in
comparison with the supreme question: Shall the modern civilised state
be spiritual or secular?'58 It is worth exploring Haeckel's anti-clericalism
in more detail, for it reveals the major ideological thrust of his writings
and illuminates the role played by Social Darwinism in his arguments.
Haeckel pronounced an irreconcilable antagonism between science
and religion: 'Where faith commences, science ends.' 59 This was
because they reposed upon incompatible claims to knowledge; respec-
tively, reason and revelation. Only knowledge of nature could constitute
genuine revelation, and this was founded on rational, scientific methods.
The obtuseness of religious authorities on the thesis of man's ape-like
ancestry was typical of the way in which religion impeded scientific
knowledge. In language reminiscent of that used by Huxley in his
famous encounter with Bishop Wilberforce, Haeckel declared it prefer-
56
Haeckel, Riddle of the Universe, 6-9; Haeckel, History of Creation, I, 181; Haeckel, Last
Words, 102-3, 110.
57 58
Haeckel, Riddle of the Universe, 372. Ibid., 9.
59
Haeckel, History of Creation, I, 9.
Social Darwinism in France and Germany 143
able to be the 'advanced offspring of a simian ancestor' who had evolved
through struggle 'than the degenerate descendant of a god-like being,
made from a clod, and fallen, for his sins, and an Eve created from one
of his ribs'.60 This led Haeckel into an often impassioned denunciation
of religious influences in German culture. He despised what he saw as
the narrow-mindedness and bigotry of German Catholicism and
excoriated the 'eel-like sophistry' of the Jesuits in the belief that 'the
charlatan of the Vatican is the deadly enemy of free science and free
teaching'. The practices of priestly celibacy, confession and the sale of
indulgences he stigmatised as immoral and/or prejudicial to family life.
Haeckel's most intemperate invective, however, was directed against the
Papacy, which he referred to as 'the greatest swindle the world has ever
submitted to', while its doctrines were 'an unscrupulous tissue of lying
and deceit' employed in the service of 'mental despotism and secular
power'.61
Haeckel's objections to religion went beyond Catholicism to the
fundamentals of Christianity itself. The truly valuable part of Christian
teaching - the Golden Rule to love one's neighbour - was as old as
civilisation and had its roots in the social practices of many animals. The
same was also true of the kernel of Christianity adopted by monism, i.e.
love, the equality of men before God, charitable conduct towards the
poor and the wretched, all of which were 'merely higher evolutionary
stages of the social instincts, which we find in all higher social
animals.. .' 62 Other features of Christianity were totally objectionable.
Its anthropocentrism encouraged a disdainful contempt towards the rest
of nature, whereas Darwinism, by demonstrating man's links with the
animals, taught us to regard the latter as our brothers, though Haeckel
evidently did not wish to extend this fraternity to the 'lower' races.
Christ reinforced the Asian undervaluation of women who were
stigmatised as unclean, whereas in reality 'men and women are two
different organisms, equal in worth, each having its characteristic virtues
and defects'. Even the injunction to love one's neighbour was exagger-
ated by Christians to the detriment of egoism, a vital factor in self-
preservation and creativity in the advance of civilisation. Its extension to
one's enemies was downright unnatural, implying that the theft of a
German colony by the English should be met by the renunciation of the
remainder of Germany's overseas possessions. 63 Finally, to this cata-
logue of sins must be added the doctrine of the immortality of the soul.
60
Haeckel, Evolution of Man, II, 7 4 2 .
61
Haeckel, Last Words, 4 3 , 4 7 , 106, 125; Haeckel, Riddle of the Universe, 3 3 3 .
62
Haeckel, Riddle of the Universe, 3 5 8 - 6 0 , 3 5 9 . See also Haeckel, Freedom in Science, 9 6 .
63
Haeckel, Riddle of the Universe, 3 6 1 - 6 .
144 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
'Death puts an end, in man as in any other Vertebrate, to the
physiological function of the cerebral neurone, the countless micro-
scopic ganglionic cells, the collective activity of which is known as the
"soul".' 64
Convicted of so many egregious violations of the discoveries of
evolutionary science, Christianity had to be replaced by a new religion:
monism. This was pantheistic, upholding the existence of an impersonal
God resident in every atom.65 Haeckel often waxed lyrical on the
religious dimension of monism: "The will of God is at work in every
falling drop of rain and every growing crystal, in the scent of the rose and
the spirit of man.'66 God and the world were one, since God was
equivalent to nature or substance, which meant that, as far as Haeckel
was concerned 'pantheism is the world system of the modern scientist'.61
Haeckel's professed scientific materialism was juxtaposed with a mystical
adulation of nature derived from the influence of German Naturphiloso-
phie on his thought.68 But Haeckel quite plainly regarded monism and
Christianity as competing belief-systems, equally comprehensive in
scope but based upon incompatible knowledge claims, and Social
Darwinism was central to his attempt to buttress the authority of the
former and undermine that of the latter.
Haeckel's Social Darwinism, therefore, acted as a comprehensive
framework within which the mysteries of nature and society could be
investigated. Contemporary German society might be conflictual and
fragmented, but political difficulties, like scientific problems, were
resolvable through the application of reason and science and by the
realisation of a philosophical project which revealed the interconnection
of all these different areas and their governance by universal laws of
nature.
Haeckel's personal political trajectory mirrored the development of
German liberalism in general, which had lost its revolutionary and
emancipatory character by the end of the nineteenth century and
assumed a more stridently nationalist and authoritarian posture.69
Notwithstanding his polemics against the establishment and Prussian
militarism, Haeckel admired the authoritarian Bismarck as a 'great
64 65
Haeckel, Evolution of Man, II, 578. Haeckel, LeMonisme, 3 4 - 5 .
66
Haeckel, Last Words, 112.
67
Haeckel, Riddle of the Universe, 296, original emphasis.
68
For the impact of Naturphilosophie on Haeckel, see Gasman, Scientific Origins, xvii-xx;
Kelly, Descent of Darwin, 24, 28.
69
There are excellent assessments of the influence and political direction of Haeckel's
work in P. Corsi and P. Weindling, 'Darwinism in Germany, France and Italy', in
Kohn, Darwinian Heritage, 6 8 5 - 9 8 , and Weindling, Health, Race and German Politics
Between Unification and Nazism, 1870-1945 (Cambridge University Press, 1989), 4 0 - 8 .
Social Darwinism in France and Germany 145
statesman'.70 Becoming disillusioned with Germany's political leader-
ship in his later years, he joined ultra-nationalist organisations such as
the Pan German League, which contributed to the political culture in
which National Socialism was spawned. As with German liberalism, too,
he upheld an organic rather than an atomistic conception of social
reality, believing that in complex systems the individual parts were, 'like
good citizens', subordinated to the welfare of the whole.71 All of these
features of his thought are commensurable with the content and
development of liberalism in Germany, and it is to this context that
Haeckel should be assigned rather than some form of proto-Nazism.
Haeckel directed his polemical energies and rhetorical skills primarily
against the opponents of evolutionism, secularisation and scientific
freedom. At the same time, the significance of his views on inequality,
race and eugenics should not be minimised. Their importance does not
consist in their links with Nazism, but rather in their wide acceptance
among the European and American intelligentsia. Haeckel's denigration
of 'lower races', paupers, criminals and people suffering from congenital
mental and physical illness did not differ from the views expressed by
Royer and Spencer. All thinkers buttressed these opinions with Social
Darwinism: but Haeckel's views surely derived an added authenticity
from his status as a gifted and eminent naturalist.
Conclusion
It is now appropriate to make some general observations about the
pioneering examples examined in the last four chapters. First, all of the
theorists examined so far made selection, adaptation and heredity
fundamental processes in their accounts of social and psychological
change. Competition was the cause of adaptation and eliminated the
unfit. It occurred both within and between societies, in peaceful and
violent manifestations, although the majority of thinkers upheld an
evolution of struggle itself, from warfare to industrial competition or the
selection of ideas. This proved to be a troublesome concept, however,
with Sumner and Fiske equivocating over the future of warfare, and
70
Haeckel, Riddle of the Universe, 342. See Gasman, Scientific Origins, 128. For an analysis
of the Pan German League and its relationship to the German right, see G. Eley,
Reshaping the German Right (London: Yale University Press, 1980); R. Chickering, We
Men Who Feel Most German (London: Allen and Unwin, 1984).
71
Haeckel, Freedom in Science, 58. On this aspect of Haeckel's thought, see P. Weindling,
'Theories of the Cell State in Imperial Germany', in C. Webster, ed., Biology, Medicine
and Society 1840-1940 (Cambridge University Press, 1981), 119. On the coexistence of
individualism and collectivism in German liberalism, see Weikart, 'The Origins of
Social Darwinism in Germany', 471.
146 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
Royer and Haeckel approving of bellicose relationships between races at
different stages of evolution. The overwhelming tendency was to depict
the struggle for existence as taking place between individuals and
groups, although the German geologist Rolle focused almost exclusively
on the latter, while Brace focused on the former. An important
consequence of this treatment of competition was that social conflict (at
least in certain guises) could be presented, not as a symptom of social
instability and decline, but as the motor of progress.
Progress was a second salient feature of these pioneering efforts,
although here Sumner would constitute an exception. This does not
mean that these theorists were oblivious to the possibility of stagnation
or even regression. Even Spencer, who is normally perceived as an
unwavering apostle of progress, was fully aware of these possibilities.72
With this qualification in mind, it is still true that evolution was on the
whole progressive and humanity was the highest point of development.
Regression was always possible and vigilance was required to ensure that
the laws of nature were not infringed by ignorant politicians and
reformers. In addition, even the most advanced societies contained
survivals from previous evolutionary phases which were responsible for
social pathologies. But all thinkers seemed confident that Western
civilisation would continue to advance in the future.
A third facet of these pioneering theorists was their deterministic
conception of natural law. None adopted Peirce's probabilistic represen-
tation of natural selection except James, and even he failed to do so
consistently in his text on psychology. Dewey's characterisation of
eighteenth-century social thought is thus equally applicable to the
theories studied so far: 'Change was working on the side of man but only
because of fixed laws which governed the changes that take place. There
was hope in change just because the laws that govern it do not change.
The locus of the immutable was shifted to scientific natural law .. ,' 73
This made for excellent rhetoric when attacking misguided policies but
was inherently problematic, as we have seen, when a theorist came to
make positive policy proposals, some of which implied the emancipation
of humanity from the inexorability of natural laws.
Fourth, the theorists so far studied upheld biological reductionism to
varying degrees. Culture certainly acted as an environment to which
individuals must adapt, but usually successful adaptations became
hereditary. This position possessed considerable rhetorical potential for
72
R. N y e , 'Sociology and Degeneration: T h e Irony of Progress', in Chamberlin and
Gilman, eds., Degeneration, 5 5 - 9 .
73
J. D e w e y , 'Time and Individuality', in John Dewey: The Essential Writings, ed.
D . Sidorsky ( N e w York: Harper Torchbooks, 1977), 136, original emphasis.
Social Darwinism in France and Germany 147
the defence of inequalities or for denigrating attempts at social
engineering, but encountered difficulties if the theorists wished to
modify behaviour or institutions, which, since they were predominantly
liberal in outlook, they sometimes wished to do. As we noted with Royer
and her stance on the subordination of women, this required recourse to
cultural rather than biological explanations. More generally, theorists
elaborated a notion of 'social selection', describing social practices and
values which had a selective impact upon members of society. Some-
times social selection worked in conjunction with its natural counterpart;
more often it was perceived to run counter to the requirements of the
'natural order'. This argumentation was discernible in Darwin's Descent
and was evident in the work of Spencer, Royer, Lombroso, Haeckel and
Sumner and assumed considerable importance in later Social Darwinist
theories, as we shall see. Social selection represents social processes
which, particularly if opposed to the workings of natural selection, are
very powerful. Their existence poses problems for biological deter-
minism - how are they to be explained? - as well as to the health and
potential survival of the societies in which they occur. Thus nature
provided the social scientist with a means of explaining the structures
and dynamics of social systems, but it also acted as a normative reference
point, an ideal to be emulated, when these systems were threatened by
'unnatural' cultural forces.
Fifth, there emerges from Social Darwinist discourse a rather
nebulous but ubiquitous category: the 'unfit'. It includes the indigent,
the sick, criminals, the urban underclass and varying ethnic and racial
groups. This category is not an artefact of Social Darwinism but derives
from social and political values and prejudices that pre-exist the world
view. Nor is the substitutability of these groups, i.e. the extent to which
the description of one can be transferred to another, a product of Social
Darwinism. Race, class and, as we shall see, sometimes gender as well,
furnished a reservoir of interchangeable judgements, concepts and
metaphors. What Social Darwinists did was locate these judgements,
concepts and metaphors within an evolutionary continuum which
explained, through selection and heredity, why the persons to whom
they were applied were losers in the battle for life. In this way, not only
the categorisation, but also the treatment of these persons was validated
by science.
Sixth, the ideological orientation of pioneering Social Darwinism was
overwhelmingly liberal when due consideration is given to the differing
national connotations of this term. 74 Early European Social Darwinists,
74
These connotations are explored in detail by Bellamy in Liberalism and Modern Society.
148 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
therefore, were never conservative in the sense that they were uncritical
champions of the status quo. like all liberals, they faced a double
challenge from the entrenched forces of reaction and the reformist and
sometimes revolutionary demands of the underprivileged. That is why
their arguments sometimes appear as emancipatory (e.g. when opposing
militarism, clericalism and aristocratic privilege), sometimes as con-
servative (e.g. when opposing welfare legislation). The United States
lacked a feudal legacy and hence this Janus-faced aspect of liberalism is
less evident there. But the liberal orientation of American Social
Darwinists seems quite evident. Sumner, though a vociferous opponent
of increased democratisation and welfare schemes, was an equally
pungent critic of plutocracy and a supporter of trade unions. Brace, one
of the earliest pioneers in the use of Social Darwinism, held progressive
views on race and devoted his life to improving the conditions and
educating the minds of the 'dangerous classes'. One major difference
between European and American Social Darwinists, however, concerns
religion. Spencer, Huxley, Biichner, Haeckel and Royer were ardently
anti-clerical in sentiment, whereas Americans like Brace, Fiske and
James perceived Darwinism and religion to be commensurable. A liberal
disposition, then, provides no basis for inferring a thinker's position on
specific issues: Spencer opposed imperialism, Royer endorsed colonial
expansion.
The pioneers discussed so far disseminated the world view and
explored some of its social implications. Their efforts are instructive
because they highlight problems implicit in the world view which were to
figure markedly in the subsequent history of Social Darwinism. But this
history is one in which the world view was to be enlisted in other causes,
some of which were antithetical to the liberal values endorsed by the
majority of the pioneers.
Part III
Case studies
Reform Darwinism
Introduction
There is a sense in which many of the theorists discussed thus far could
be regarded as 'reform Darwinists'. A. R. Wallace was a socialist;
Lombroso, Brace, Haeckel, Royer and Biichner advocated considerable
social and political change; and even Spencer and Sumner could be
highly critical of contemporary values and institutions. With the
extension of democracy during the nineteenth and early twentieth
centuries, though, there came an intensification of debates over universal
suffrage, equality, the emancipation of women, welfare provision and
international fraternity. Darwinism was enlisted by protagonists on all
sides of these debates: the concern of this chapter is with theorists
supportive of socio-political change in the direction of greater equality,
public welfare, and democracy. They ranged from Marxist revolution-
aries through to democratic socialists and 'New Liberals' - all sharing a
commitment to the use of state power in order to achieve their goals -
but also included anarchists desirous of radical change but opposed to
the state in any form.
The purpose of this examination is two-fold. The first is to argue that
although there was a genre of reformist and socialist Darwinism, some of
what has been subsumed under this label was actually opposed to
Darwinism as defined in this study. The second aim is to explore the
discursive limits of the world view. No matter how polysemous the
elements of Social Darwinism were, their integration into a systematic
whole acted as a constraint upon their appropriation by any and every
ideological and theoretical enterprise. We have already encountered
examples of how such constraints generated tensions within theories
which presented peaceful cooperation as an ultimate social objective.
The investigation of reform Darwinism allows for a richer analysis of
such constraints and tensions.
151
152 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
Socialism, declared Ferri, would only abolish the evils of the current
system, while preserving its real achievements in the arts, sciences and
technology, and in the cultivation of personal liberty. Everything, in
society as in nature, progressed through often imperceptible changes.
When evolution reached a certain threshold, then a revolution took
place which completed the process of transformation. Like Bernstein in
Germany and the Fabians in Britain, Ferri advocated the gradual
conquest of political power and the winning of concessions by the
proletariat, so that a point would be reached when the final socialist
'revolution' would be bloodless (120-4, 134-5).
Ferri's difficulty in accommodating revolutionary praxis to the notion
of the gradual processes of evolutionary change prompted him to opt for
a reformist and democratic brand of socialism. But Ferri conceded a
158 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
great deal to hereditarian thinking in his views on women, inequality and
criminality, blurring the boundaries between sociological and biological
explanations in a way which compromised the coherence of his theory of
social change. For example, he defended the concept of the 'born
criminal', arguing that while socialism would eliminate crimes caused by
miserable social conditions and poverty, it would be unable to eradicate
those deriving from the abnormal organic constitution of the criminal.
Thus 'what will not disappear are outrages on chastity through sexual
pathological inversion, murders committed by epileptics, robberies
caused by psycho-pathological degeneracy, etc' (33). 8 His debt to
biological determinism was equally evident in the thesis that mutual aid
and cooperation were laws of nature. As with Bebel, explanation shifted
from biological to sociological causes and back again without any
theoretical rationale for the change, although there was, of course, a
transparent ideological reason for the shift. But Fern's text attests to the
hold of biological and hereditarian thinking on socialist intellectuals.
This hold is graphically illustrated by a very different synthesis of
socialism and Darwinism undertaken by the German, Ludwig Wolt-
mann (1871-1907), a holder of doctorates in philosophy and medicine
and a Social Democratic Party activist during the 1890s. 9 Woltmann
eschewed revolution in favour of the gradual evolution of socialism
advocated by his compatriot Eduard Bernstein (1850-1932) in the
latter's Evolutionary Socialism of 1899. 10 However, Woltmann was also
convinced of the superiority of the Aryan race and started a journal,
Politische-Anthropologische Revue, for the promulgation of racial theories.
For him, anthropology demonstrated that the 'intellectual power of the
white races is without doubt higher than that of all the other races'. 11
Because organic transformations took place over a very long period, the
characteristics of the different races had remained unchanged through-
out human history and pre-history.
Woltmann contended that the emergence of human culture had
transformed the struggle for existence from one hitherto directed
8
These arguments were not uncommon among socialists of the period. See, for example,
Lawrence Small, Darwinism and Socialism (London: Independent Labour Party, 1907/
8). The author argued that the social and moral instincts had been fixed by natural
selection, and proposed eugenics programmes to check the propagation of the diseased,
deformed and criminal (12-13).
9
For details of Woltmann's background and political views, see Weindling, Health, Race
and German Politics, 119-20, 129-30.
10
Although Bernstein was influenced by the British Fabians, several of whom embraced
Social Darwinism, there is no evidence of Darwinism in this text, despite its title. See
E. Bernstein, Evolutionary Socialism (New York: Shocken, 1961).
11
L. Woltmann, Die Darwinische Theorie und der Sozialismus (Dusseldorf: Michels, 1899),
305.
Reform Darwinism 159
primarily against natural conditions and other creatures into a racial
conflict over territory, food and power: 'New and more violent conflicts
of interest arose in mankind's struggle amongst themselves. Races
trampled on one another as if they were different species. The process of
selection was repeated on a narrower but higher sphere of existence, in
the struggle of man against man.' 12 Arguing that society itself was an
organic entity, Woltmann attempted to convince German workers that
they would benefit from national solidarity in the struggle for existence
against other nations. In this context, socialism for Woltmann signified
increased possibilities for technical and intellectual advance brought
about through domestic cooperation. It entailed substituting conscious
control and direction for the laws of fate and chance, emancipation from
the superstitions and myths of religion, and a healthy enjoyment of work
and earthly existence. This required a genuine harmonisation with
'Mother Nature', and hence, as with Bebel, nature afforded a model to
be emulated by a healthy social organism: 'In this respect, socialism is a
true return to nature.' 13
In the race theory proposed by Woltmann, the extensiveness of
evolutionary time was invoked as a justification for what amounted to a
form of essentialism. Human nature varied in accordance with race, but
racial characteristics remained unchanged for millennia and could be
taken as fixed. For Woltmann, evolutionary time, far from problema-
tising the idea of a fixed human nature, allowed for a differentiation of
mankind into races, the various attributes of which were stable; having
been formed very gradually they were refractory to any rapid transmuta-
tions, save through miscegenation.
12 13
Ibid., 301. Ibid., 397.
14
'Social Darwinism, eugenics and Fabianism could have been made for each other.'
This is the verdict of Shaw in 'Eliminating the Yahoo', 43. In contrast, Searle, pointing
to the environmentalism inherent in Fabianism, describes its relationship to eugenics as
a flirtation. G. R. Searle, 'Eugenics and Class' in Webster, Biology, Medicine and Society,
231 and 240-2.
160 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
is beyond the scope of this study, it is possible to analyse the use of
Social Darwinism by some Fabian theorists.
An important figure during the formative years of Fabianism was the
philosopher David. G. Ritchie (1853-1903), who was a member of the
Fabian Society from 1889 to 1893. His Darwinism and Politics,15
published in 1889, sought to dissociate Darwinism from what Ritchie
alleged was its monopoly by conservative apologists, while admitting
that the language of natural selection did lend itself to the legitimation of
laissez-faire and racial, sexual and class inequalities (12).
Ritchie endorsed an objective elucidation of the laws governing social
relations, but argued that once established, these laws, being simply
generalisation from experience, had no claims 'upon our reverence'
(33). In his view, social evolution showed how conscious and deliberate
adaptation among humans was analogous to the 'spontaneous variation'
among animals and plants in the struggle for existence, although he
appreciated the difficulty of deciding the boundaries between biological
inheritance and cultural transmission in human affairs (40-1, 53).
Ritchie described war as the 'primitive form of the struggle between
races and nations' (29) but, contra Spencer, he designated economic
competition as more primitive still, as 'only a phase of the oldest form of
the struggle for existence - the struggle between individuals for subsist-
ence, and that . . . therefore belongs to a lower type than the struggles
between organised communities, where a strict organisation mitigates
the internal strife' (45).
Complementing this social evolution was another in which inherited
instincts were gradually replaced by imitation and education in intelli-
gent behaviour, facilitated by the greater size of the brain and the
prolongation of infancy in humans. For Ritchie this showed human
inheritance to be more a matter of moral and intellectual culture than of
biology. His conclusion was:
From the fact that human societies, like natural organisms, grow and are not
made, we have certainly to learn that every evil cannot be remedied in a day. But
from the other, at least equally important fact, that human societies do not
merely grow but are consciously altered by human effort, we have also to learn
that every evil is not to be accepted as inevitable (68).
Ritchie applied this reasoning to a number of contemporary issues. He
recognised a real danger of population growth outstripping food supplies
and proposed birth control as a remedy. This measure would reduce
excess population, especially among those who were currently going
overseas with missionary and colonial zeal and enslaving, demoralising
15
London: Swan Sonnenschein.
Reform Darwinism 161
and destroying the 'lower races' (96-7). Fewer children would mean
healthier children, but birth control was intimately linked to the position
of women in society, and Ritchie was strongly in favour of equality for
women and their full participation in political and economic life instead
of their restriction to maternal and domestic roles (99). He rejected
patriarchy and its rationalisation in terms of the presumed inferiority of
women, which - assuming it to have any basis in fact at all - he believed
would be eliminated in the course of evolution once equality was
instigated (82). like J. S. Mill before him, he argued that womanhood
was largely a social construct, and concluded: 'It is hypocritical to deny
the political capacity of women, simply because their political mcapacity
has through long centuries been so diligently cultivated . . . ' (86, original
emphasis).
If these arguments hinted at a limited commitment to Social
Darwinism, this impression was dispelled by a second edition.16 In two
additional chapters Ritchie attacked the claim by A. R. Wallace that
natural selection was incapable of explaining the emergence and
development of cognitive, moral and aesthetic properties. In doing so he
clarified his views on the evolution of the struggle for existence: 'Natural
selection operates in the highest types of human society as well as in the
rest of the organic realm; but it passes into a higher form of itself, in
which the conflict of ideas and institutions takes the place of the struggle
for existence between individuals and races' (106). Thus struggle
evolved from one between individuals to a conflict between aggregates
of individuals in the form of races and nations, and then to the conflict
of ideas. It was this progression which made socialism a realistic prospect
and at the same time enabled Ritchie to reaffirm his allegiance to Social
Darwinism: 'Progress comes only by struggle, though the struggle in its
highest form may go on within the individual soul and may cause no
death but the death of partial truths that have become errors and of
customs that have outlived their use' (141). Moreover, as he had
reminded his readers in the first edition, there was always one aspect of
this struggle which could never be eliminated, i.e. 'the struggle against
nature, including the blind forces of human passion' (100, original
emphasis). With these arguments Ritchie both affirmed the importance
of cultural and social conditions in human development, and retained
the struggle for existence as the principle of change. This type of
synthesis of Social Darwinism and socialism was to prove popular
among the Fabians. However, as is apparent from Ritchie's thesis that
social reforms would rapidly produce organic transformations in
16
London: Swan Sonnenschein, 1891.
162 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
women, it was one which subordinated biological to sociological
explanation to such a degree that the former was virtually eliminated as a
factor in social change.
There is an equally discernible hesitancy over the respective roles of
heredity and environment in the publications of Graham Wallas (1858-
1932) who, in the application of Darwinism to the investigation of
human nature, sought a means of strengthening democracy by providing
the latter with a scientific foundation. Wallas, one of the original
members of the Fabian Society, became disillusioned with the elitism
and authoritarianism of some of its leaders, notably the Webbs. 17 For
him, democracy was not simply a matter of environmental engineering,
but involved active citizenship and the living of a 'good' life.
Wallas came to the conclusion that any vision of the good life must, in
the manner of Aristotle, concern itself with the nature of those who were
to live it, a concern he found to be lamentably absent in contemporary
political thinking. The theories of human nature found in current -
particularly liberal and utilitarian - discourses were woefully impover-
ished, with their over-intellectualised conceptions of people as rational,
calculating, self-interested beings. The solution was to turn to scientific
psychology for an understanding of human nature, and here Wallas
believed Darwin had provided a critical direction with his investigations
of human descent. Darwinism allowed for the possibility of an objective
grasp of human psychology within a comparative framework that
included animals; this would facilitate a more realistic basis for demo-
cratic theory and practice. As Wallas observed: 'Unless he is prepared to
study undismayed the nature of man as evolution has for the moment
left it, the reformer who is also a politician will find his life one of
constant and cruel disillusion.'18
In his Human Nature and Politics (1908) and subsequent publications,
Wallas sketched the main features of human psychology. In the slow
course of evolution people had, through adaptation and selection, come
to possess an inherited constitution which exhibited little variation from
the Stone Age to the present day.19 Of paramount importance were
inherited predispositions, or instincts, the products of an interaction
between individual and environment established through natural selec-
tion. Biologically speaking, human nature was, to all intents and
17
Wallas contributed an essay on 'Property Under Socialism' to the Fabian Essays of
1889. For details of Wallas's break with the Fabians, see M. J. Wiener, Between Two
Worlds (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1971), 52-3; T. H. Quaker, Graham Wallas and the
Great Society (London: Macmillan, 1980), chap. 2.
18
G. Wallas, 'Darwinism and Social Motive' (1906), in Wallas, Men and Ideas (London:
Allen and Unwin, 1940), 93.
19
G. Wallas, Human Nature in Politics, third edn (London: Constable, 1927), 25.
Reform Darwinism 163
purposes, fixed. Wallas was an anti-Lamarckian, believing that the
results of personal experience and achievements, while they could
modify the habits and proclivities of individuals (as was apparent even
among animals), could not be inherited. Each new generation started
'not where their fathers left off, but where their fathers began'. 20
Furthermore, this instinctual apparatus was a very powerful factor in
shaping a person's behaviour: 'Things that are nearer sense, nearer to
our more ancient evolutionary past, produce a readier inference as well
as a more compelling impulse.'21 Wallas developed an analysis of the
way in which images and symbols in election campaigns were used to
appeal to this ancient instinctual apparatus, which included affection,
inquisitiveness, self-preservation, competitiveness, fear and curiosity.
Intelligence was also an inherited disposition, and it was to this that
Wallas looked in order to guide personal conduct and social organisa-
tion. 'Thought', he argued, 'may be late in evolution, it may be
deplorably weak in driving power, but without its guidance no man or
organisation can find a safe path amid the vast impersonal complexities
of the universe as we have learnt to see it.' 22 Although the different
dispositions of the human psyche could be analysed separately, in
actuality they were all part of a complex and interrelated whole: 'The
mind of man is like a harp, all of whose strings throb together; so that
emotion, impulse, inference, and the special kind of inference called
reasoning, are often simultaneous and intermingled aspects of a single
mental experience.'23
If human psychology was largely the product of natural selection,
what role did the struggle for existence play in the modern world? Here
Wallas was vague. He accused those believing that war and imperial
conflict were manifestations of the struggle for survival of misunder-
standing the doctrine of natural selection. Darwinism demonstrated that
the human race was a biological whole, and that we should have 'love for
that infinitely varying multitude'. It was a great 'intellectual tragedy' of
the nineteenth century 'that the discovery of organic evolution, instead
of stimulating such a general love of humanity, seemed at first to show
that it was forever impossible'. Modern warfare was completely dysgenic
in its consequences, and Wallas was convinced of the need to destroy
the belief that progress was only possible through conflict between
peoples.24 He pointed out that individualists such as Spencer had once
20
G. Wallas, The Great Society (New York: Macmillan, 1920), 8.
21 22
Wallas, Human Nature, 106. Wallas, Great Society, 45.
23
Wallas, Human Nature, 99.
24
Wallas, Human Nature, 286-92; Wallas, Great Society, 164-5. Wallas, 'Comment on Dr
Jack's Article "The Peacefulness of Being at War"', Men and Ideas, 96-8.
164 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
35
Published in the 1948 edition of Fabian Essays.
168 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
evolutionary progress. Thus the relationship between Social Darwinism
and Fabianism was a complex one defying any straightforward general-
isation. In the case of Webb, Ritchie and Graham Wallas the relationship
was close and the world view undoubtedly furnished the scaffolding for
their political ideals and policy proposals. It must be recognised, though,
that these proposals varied considerably between, for instance, those of
the technocratic and elitist Webb and the much more democratic
Ritchie and Wallas. In the case of Shaw, the connection was absent,
while in some other one-time Fabians it was highly complex.36
50
Ibid., 116, 146, 342-3, 350-1.
Reform Darwinism 175
directly from nature. The overt denial of the legitimacy of such
derivations usually constituted the prolegomena to the construction of a
moral ontology, as we saw with Huxley, Stephen and Kidd.
The interpretation of Darwinism by the American philosopher, John
Dewey, offers a sharp contrast to these theories. Though explicitly
interested in Darwinism,51 Dewey would probably not be regarded as a
Social Darwinist by most commentators. In my view he was, and even in
texts where his Darwinism was not particularly salient it provided a set
of crucial background assumptions. Since Dewey's understanding of
Darwinism differed in important respects from that of most of his
contemporaries, it is interesting to explore the moral and political
conclusions he derived from it.
Dewey proposed that 'the evolution of living and thinking beings out of
a state of things in which life and thought were not found is a fact which
must be recognised in any metaphysical inquiry into the irreducible traits
of the world. For evolution appears to be just one of those traits.'52
Dewey accepted the Darwinian account of evolution through selection of
adaptive variations in the struggle for existence, but he departed from
conventional representations of Darwinism in a number of ways.
First, following Peirce, Dewey perceived the law of natural selection
to be statistical in form and thus incapable of making statements about
individuals. Hence: 'Laws do not "govern" the activity of individuals.
They are a formulation of the frequency distributions of the behaviour of
large number [sic] of individuals engaged in interactions with one
another.'53 Second, nature was variable, changing, the site of accident
and the unforeseen. The implication of this was that:
It is the fate of a living creature ... that it cannot secure what belongs to it
without an adventure in a world that as a whole it does not own and to which it
has no native title. Whenever the organic impulse exceeds the limit of the body,
itfindsitself in a strange world and commits in some measure the fortune of the
self to external circumstance.54
This notion of the 'fortune of the self was a central feature of Dewey's
thinking about human existence. 'Man', he wrote, 'lives in an aleatory
world; his existence involves, to put it baldly, a gamble. The world is a
scene of risk; it is uncertain, unstable, uncannily unstable. Its dangers
are irregular, inconstant, not to be counted upon as to their times and
seasons. Although persistent, they are sporadic, episodic.'55
51
There is an illuminating analysis of Dewey's interest in Darwinism in David Sidorsky's
'Introduction' to John Dewey: The Essential Writings, xx-xxviii.
52 53
D e w e y , John Dewey: The Essential Writings, 109. Ibid., 143.
54
Ibid., 267.
55
D e w e y , Experience and Nature [1925] (La Salle, IL: Open Court, 1971), 38.
176 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
Third, Dewey was adamant that morals must commence with the
recognition that humans were part of nature, thereby linking 'ethics with
physics and biology'.56 Plainly, Dewey believed that the study of nature
was a foundation for ethics. But because he perceived nature as a realm
of change and chance as well as uniformity and necessity, he concluded
that human nature was not fixed. In fact, human instincts were alterable
whereas social institutions and practices were invariably resistant to
change.57 What interested Dewey, then, was not the persistence of some
human essence through time, but the interactions between a changing
human nature on the one hand, and social values and practices on the
other.
Human existence - as with all organic life - took place within an
environment which could be favourable or unfavourable to life activities.
Humans were therefore obliged to struggle in order to enlist the support
of the environment and effect changes to it. 58 Any interactive equi-
librium between organism and environment was inclined to be short-
lived on account of the changes emanating from the latter. Furthermore,
these changes were:
so opposed in direction that we must choose. We must take theriskof casting in
our lot with one movement or the other. Nothing can eliminate all risk, all
adventure; the one thing doomed to failure is to try to keep even with the whole
environment at once - that is to say, to maintain the happy moment when all
things go our way.59
Knowledge played a fundamental role in this process by assisting
individuals to cope with the crises of life and to adapt to change. But for
knowledge to be instrumental required creative rather than routine
intelligence, an ability which Dewey insisted was available to all people
and 'not an aesthetic appreciation carried on by a refined class or a
capitalistic possession of a few learned specialists, whether men of
science or of philosophy'.60
Dewey was highly critical of laissez-faire individualism for identifying
liberty with the actions of the entrepreneur, and was also aware of the
ways in which Darwinism had been used to justify these and other
exploitative actions.61 He advocated instead 'humane liberalism', com-
mitted to radical reform of the prevailing social system and its inequal-
ities, though a reform which was achieved democratically and not
through coercion. This required the acceptance of two principles. The
first was that individuality is 'nothing fixed, given, ready-made', but an
achievement made possible by and through social institutions and
56
Dewey, Human Nature and Conduct (London: Allen and Unwin, 1922), 12.
57 58 59
Ibid., 106-9. Dewey, Essential Writings, 72. Ibid., 73.
60 61
Ibid., 93. Ibid., 200; Dewey, Human Nature, 301.
Reform Darwinism 177
62
interactions. The second was that of 'historic relativity', i.e. that the
content and meaning of individuality and freedom changed over time.
'Time signifies change' affirmed Dewey, and it was this feature of
human existence which the enemies of freedom negated. Dictatorships
and totalitarian states were 'ways of denying the realities of time and the
creativeness of the individual. Freedom of thought and of expression are
not mere rights to be claimed. They have their roots deep in the
existence of individuals as developing careers in time.' 63
Here Dewey utilised a distinctive conception of nature in order to
authorise his ethical and political vision. What is of interest is the
conception of nature itself, in which 'qualities and relations, individual-
ities and conformities, finalities and efficacies, contingencies and
necessities are inextricably bound together'. 64 This view, with its stress
on change, contingency and choice, represented an interpretation of
Darwinism which was unusual for its time and, as we shall see, still
contrasts sharply with the reductionism and determinism typical of
modern versions of Social Darwinism. It enabled Dewey to advocate
liberty, democracy and rational political action as practices that were in
tune with the realities of nature as well as pre-conditions for future
evolutionary progress.
during the early 1890s, was an impressive and influential example of this
genre. 66 As a naturalist Kropotkin was well aware of the severity of the
struggle of animals to survive in the harsh conditions imposed by nature,
but his own observations had failed to find evidence of any struggle
between animals of the same species. Furthermore, the struggle against
nature was so exhausting that he questioned whether this could act as an
impetus for progressive change. What he did find was the widespread
existence of mutual assistance and cooperation among the social
animals. From this he concluded not only that mutual aid was 'as much
a law of animal life as mutual struggle', but that the former was of more
importance than the latter for the 'maintenance and further development
of the species' (30-1). Kropotkin admitted that struggle was a fact of life
in which the fittest survived, but he denied that convincing evidence had
been adduced to support the actuality of intra-species competition, and
he emphasised instead the significance of mutual aid in eliminating
struggle and promoting progress.
'Don't compete! - competition is always injurious to the species, and you have
plenty of resources to avoid it!' That is the tendency of nature, not always realised
in full, but always present. That is the watchword which comes to us from the
bush, the forest, theriver,the ocean. 'Therefore combine - practice mutual aid!
That is the surest means for giving to each and to all the greatest safety, the best
guarantee of existence and progress, bodily, intellectual and moral5 (81-2,
original emphasis).
66
The edition used here was edited by P. Avrich (London: Allen Lane, 1972).
Reform Darwinism 179
not natural selection. For Kropotkin, struggle was relegated to the wings
of evolution, responsible for exhaustion and waste rather than for
cumulative change. Mutual aid rather than struggle provided the
impetus for change and progress. True, the often adverse conditions
imposed by nature were an incentive for solidarity and cooperation, but
the battle of life had only a minor part in the drama of evolution.
Kropotkin was not oblivious to the pernicious influences of militarism,
exploitation, and unbridled individualism in modern societies, but
against these he drew attention to cooperatives, friendly societies and
trade unions in the towns, and the prevalence of village communities
among millions of European country folk. The reality of mutual
solidarity in the daily lives of ordinary people was unsurprising, 'because
this feeling has been nurtured by thousands of years of human social life
and hundreds of thousands of years of pre-human life in societies' (234).
The biological determinism in Kropotkin's analysis posed problems
for the coherence of his theory. Some social phenomena - those
involving solidarity - were derived from innate tendencies, while others
- war, exploitation, political oppression - were attributed to perverse
social conditions. But the outcome was hardly a synthesis of anarchism
and Social Darwinism. Many Social Darwinists recognised the signifi-
cance of group solidarity in social evolution, but they did so in order to
accentuate its function in the struggle for survival against other groups.
As an anarcho-communist Kropotkin rejected the notion of a 'cosmic
code' of inevitable inter-group competition, and in his effort to
demonstrate the reality of solidarity and mutualism he propounded a
world view that differed on crucial details from Social Darwinism.
Mutual aid was not, for him, a consequence of natural selection as it was
for the Darwinists, but an independent process constituting the principal
force behind evolutionary progress.
The appellation 'reform Darwinism' is equally problematic when
applied to the French solidarity movement of the late nineteenth and
early twentieth centuries. This doctrine attempted to synthesise individ-
ualism and collectivism by a programme of legislation aimed at
ameliorating the condition of the urban proletariat while still respecting
the claims of private property and avoiding the implementation of state
socialism. Its most influential spokesman was the Radical deputy and
minister, Leon Bourgeois (1851-1925), whose book, Solidarite (1896)
achieved a remarkable degree of popularity and influence.67
67
L. Bourgeois, Solidarite (Paris: Armand Colin, 1896). On Bourgeois and solidarism, see
J. A. Scott, Republican Ideas and the Liberal Tradition in France, 1870-1914 (New York:
Octagon, 1966); J. E. S. Hayward, 'Solidarity: The Social History of an Idea in
Nineteenth Century France', International Review of Social History, 4(1959), 261-84;
180 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
Bourgeois asserted that morality must be grounded in truth, which in
turn was established by science. Economic and social phenomena, like
physical, chemical and biological phenomena, obeyed ineluctable causal
laws ascertainable through scientific inquiry. Biology showed that man
was the product of a continuing evolution. The struggle for existence,
undoubtedly a fact of life, coexisted with another biological law,
solidarity. Just as each person was composed of mutually interacting
elements, so was he or she inextricably linked with other members of
society, both spatially and temporally. Individuals were culturally bound
to their predecessors, and through specialisation and the division of
labour, to their contemporaries. 'The laws of the species - laws of
heredity, adaptation, selection, the laws of integration and disintegration
- are only diverse aspects of the same general law of reciprocal
dependence, that is to say, solidarity, of the elements of universal life'
(45).
Mutual reciprocity did not contradict, but complemented, the
struggle for existence. The latter was undoubtedly essential to evolu-
tionary progress, but if left unchecked it would lead to harmful
consequences for the social body as well as for the individual. The
components of the social organism had to be organised, as did the
multiple cells comprising each organism. This was achieved by force in
authoritarian regimes and by consent in regimes founded upon liberty.
Bourgeois argued that the brutal struggle for existence was the point of
departure for human evolution (in contrast to the peaceful state of
nature hypothesised by Rousseau), and that as mankind developed
intelligence and morality the idea of voluntary association gradually
became paramount. This paved the way for a pacific contractual social
system which replaced the former state of war. Bourgeois regarded
liberty - the opportunity for individuals to realise their full potential - as
the primary condition of this form of social organisation. But people
were not isolated beings and, accordingly, had to recognise a social debt,
the fulfilment of which enabled society to ameliorate inequalities which
arose, not from natural differences in aptitudes, but from adverse social
circumstances and injustices (114).
This thesis portrayed solidarity as less the complement of the struggle
for existence than its replacement as society evolved greater levels of
harmony and reciprocity. Hence Bourgeois and Kropotkin both pro-
posed models of social organisation which they claimed were validated
by principles of biological science but in which natural selection played a
minimal role. The biological models upon which they both drew - and
Hayward, 'The Official Social Philosophy of the French Third Republic: Leon
Bourgeois and Solidarism', International Review of Social History, 6(1961), 19-48.
Reform Darwinism 181
there were a number of such models in contemporary French thought68
- depicted organisms as mutually harmonious systems, the multiple
parts of which were interdependent and equilibrated. While this perspec-
tive on organic structure was compatible with Darwinist accounts of
organic change, it could also be, and was, deployed as a counterweight
to the Darwinian stress on competition in nature.69 Rather than being
labelled as examples of 'reform Darwinism', then, the theories of
Kropotkin and Bourgeois should be seen as critiques of Social
Darwinism which perceived nature as a model for social relations but
drew upon alternative theories of nature and evolution. Nor was this
simply a case of exploiting the indeterminate and ambiguous features of
the Darwinian world view; for though these theorists tried to legitimate
their position by invoking the authority of Darwin, they in fact proposed
a totally different account of change in which natural selection was either
minimised or eradicated.
A better candidate for the designation of reform Darwinist would be
the Frenchman J.-L. de Lanessan (1843-1919), a theorist of French
republicanism and a politician - he was for many years a deputy to the
National Assembly and governor-general of Indo-China from 1891 to
1895. In 1881 Lanessan published a short tract on Darwinism which
showed a firm grasp of the theory of natural selection.70 Lanessan took
issue with Darwin, though, on the role of the struggle for existence
between the organism and its milieu, which he considered to play a
negligible role in selection. The most important forms of struggle were
between organisms and others of a different nature, and with conspe-
cifics. The first led to the emergence of cooperation and association
among animals, which often enabled weaker individuals to survive; the
second (along with sexual selection) did produce the survival of the
fittest and was the primary cause of the progressive development and
transmutation of species (45-6).
Lanessan then argued that the struggle for existence applied equally to
humans (66). As in the animal kingdom, the struggle between people
and their milieu did not make for progressive selection but its opposite,
since it was often the hardiest and ablest individuals who bore the brunt
of environmentally imposed hardships (68). The struggle against other
creatures motivated human association and cooperation, which in turn
stimulated intelligence. But the growth of both society and intelligence
had implications for the struggle for existence. Among animals, the
68
See W. Schneider, Quality and Quantity (Cambridge University Press, 1990), 2 8 - 3 2 .
69
In Germany the concept of the cell-state was used in this manner. See Weindling,
Darwinism and Social Darwinism in Germany.
70
J.-L. Lanessan, Etude sur la doctrine du Darwin (Paris: Octave D o i n , 1881).
182 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
struggle with conspecifics produced the survival of the fittest. Within
human societies, 'this struggle has created kings, nobles, priests,
exploiters of all kinds' and stifled the growth of intelligence through war
and poverty (78-9). Similarly, sexual selection did not make for progress
because the existence of inequalities of wealth encouraged women to sell
themselves to the richest men (who were often the weakest), and
ensured their maintenance in conditions of ignorance and servitude
(79).
Lanessan was highly critical of theorists who used Darwinism to
present social inequalities as reflections of the survival of the fittest. like
Kidd, he proposed the equalisation of rights, universal education and
the abolition of hereditary wealth, in order to make the struggle for
existence within society congruent with the 'true' nature of the struggle
for existence and sexual selection (80), themes which were to be
developed in his subsequent publications.71 In their attempt to harmo-
nise the struggle of conspecifics in society with its counterpart in nature,
Lanessan's publications represent a genuine effort to construct a reform
Darwinism, geared to the support of French republicanism.
Conclusion
This analysis of reform Darwinism has highlighted a number of contra-
dictory features that are important for an appreciation of the discursive
boundaries of Social Darwinism. These features are connected to the
goals pursued by the majority of socialists, anarchists and liberal
reformers, namely social harmony, individual fulfilment and the eradica-
tion of poverty and oppression. The logic of reformism involved
ascribing conflict and inequality to social conditions that could be
altered through appropriate policies. But if struggle and selection were
ineluctable laws of nature, then the relationship between the natural and
social orders could prove problematic. One response was to deny the
relevance of biology to an understanding of society, and assert the
methodological autonomy of the social sciences - the strategy adopted
by Marx and Durkheim.72 Another was to reinterpret the struggle for
71
See J.-L. Lanessan, La Luttepour ^existence et revolution des societes (Paris: Alcan, 1903);
Lanessan, La Concurrence sociale et les devoirs sociaux (Paris: Alcan, 1904).
72
Although, as argued in the introduction, Durkheim never fully emancipated his
sociology from biologically grounded assumptions. Even theorists who explicitly
denounced biological reductionism, therefore, sometimes succumbed to it. This is
noticeable in Anton Pannakoek's Marxism and Darwinism, tr. N . Weiser (Chicago:
Kerr, 1912; German edition, 1909). After claiming that Darwinism and Marxism were
separate sciences (35), the author went on to depict cooperation and altruism as laws
governing all social animals ( 3 6 - 4 2 ) .
Reform Darwinism 183
existence in order to consign violent struggle to the evolutionary past
and portray market competition, or the conflict of ideas, as the social
analogues of the struggle for existence. This strategy was adopted by a
number of liberals and socialists, but the resultant theories were not
always coherent, often containing an ambivalent representation of
nature. Nature could appear both as a remorseless, impersonal process
of change and destruction and as a benign force - often personified as a
female, as in Bebel's image of nature as an instructress - which was
paradigmatic for the future organisation of society. One way out of this
dilemma - the one followed by Dewey - was to insist on the statistical
character of scientific laws and to stress the aleatory features of the
Darwinian view of nature, thereby opening up the possibility of a
rationally inspired democratic politics. This mode of Social Darwinist
theorising has not, however, found many disciples.
Another strategy consisted of elevating mutual aid to the status of a
natural law, and marginalising or denying the importance of the struggle
for existence. These theories, although invariably insisting upon their
Darwinian lineage, were actually opposed to Social Darwinism. They
amounted to an alternative interpretation, a different world view that
rejected the Darwinian explanatory focus on adaptation through
struggle. Biologically inspired theories of this ilk were influential. For
example, they helped substantiate a significant form of pacifism which
Crook has termed 'peace biology'. 73 Their existence attests to the
persisting importance of biological models in social and political
thought, but the model of nature they espoused was antithetical to that
contained in Social Darwinism.
73
Crook, Darwinism, War and History, which contains an extensive analysis of such
theories. Examples are W. Trotter, Instincts of the Herd in Peace and War (London:
Fisher Unwin, 1916); J. Novicow, 'The Mechanism and Limits of Human Association:
The Foundations of a Sociology of Peace', tr. S. H. Otis, American Journal of Sociology,
23(1917), 289-349.
8 RaceSj nations and the struggle for existence
Introduction
Although several reform Darwinists were pacifists opposed to inter-
national armed conflict, most of them still believed that some form of
competition - usually economic - would continue to govern inter-state
relationships. What distinguishes the thinkers to be examined in this
chapter is that, first, they made conflict between nations and races the
central focus of their publications, and second, they regarded this conflict
as ultimately violent, carrying the threat of national or racial extermina-
tion. Given the salience of the notion of 'race' in these texts, it is
necessary to examine briefly some of its connotations.
Race was a widely used concept by the middle of the nineteenth
century. It could designate an organic sub-species or variety, as in the
sub-title of the Origin^ or a human group. In instances of the second
usage, it could be applied to humanity as a whole or to a combination of
nationalities (e.g. the 'European race'), or to an individual nation (e.g.
the 'English race'). Additionally, race was used to describe a group
characterised by distinctive physical (and, invariably, psychological)
traits, as in 'Celtic' 'Aryan' or 'Negroid' races. Such groups were often
hierarchically arranged according to a scale of physical, mental or moral
value. In some theories, those forming the subject of this chapter, the
'fact' that certain races were superior to others meant that relations
between races assumed vital importance to an understanding of history
and culture. In many cases, theorists tended to use the terms 'nation'
and 'race' as broadly interchangeable, or to regard nations as embodi-
ments of distinctive racial (i.e. physical and psychological) attributes.
For example, the Scots physician and anatomist, Robert Knox (1793-
1862), published a systematic treatise on race in 1850 entitled The Races
of Man.1 Knox, while sympathetic to the 'darker races' and critical of
1
This is the Robert Knox associated with the Burke and Hare bodysnatching scandal of
1828. For an account of the life and work of Knox, see H. Lonsdale, A Sketch of the Life
and Writings of Robert Knox the Anatomist (London: Macmillan, 1870).
184
Races, nations and the struggle for existence 185
colonialism, argued that racial inter-breeding led to the corruption and
collapse of civilisations.2 This theme was the central argument of the
Frenchman, Arthur de Gobineau (1816-82) in his four-volume Essay on
the Inequality of the Human Races (1853-5), in which he foretold the
future of humanity in terms of 'its waning and inevitable decline'
through miscegenation.3 The Aryans, of whom the Germanic peoples
were the last remnants, were creators of modern civilisation but had
become enfeebled through inter-breeding with inferior races and were
threatened by extinction. This thesis received its most comprehensive
elaboration by a Germanised Briton, Houston Stewart Chamberlain
(1855-1927) in his famous The Foundations of the Nineteenth Century
(1899). Chamberlain portrayed the history of the West as an incessant
conflict between the spiritual and culture-creating Aryans and the
mercenary and materialistic Jews. Western civilisation had declined,
although Chamberlain believed the situation could be retrieved by
decisive intervention, and came to regard Hitler as a potential saviour.4
None of these theorists drew upon Darwinism for their arguments.
The work of Knox preceded Darwinism, and de Gobineau was hostile to
Darwin, whom he accused of plagiarising his ideas.5 Chamberlain has
been associated with Social Darwinism, but although he was familiar
with the biological thought of his day, he repudiated natural selection
and embraced a vitalist conception of organic growth.6 The relevance of
these thinkers to an understanding of Social Darwinism lies in their
popularisations of the idea that racial struggle was fundamental to a
'scientific' understanding of history and culture. Their theories made
explicit something that was implicit in much racial thinking, i.e. that
race was an intrinsically hierarchical and evaluative term, mingling
phenomenological description with moral judgement. In this it was
similar to the concept of class: indeed, descriptions and judgements
were often interchanged between the two notions.7
2
See S. Collinson, 'Robert Knox Anatomy of Race', History Today, 40(1990), 44-9.
3
De Gobineau, Essay, in M. Biddiss, ed., Gobineau: Selected Political Writings (London:
Jonathan Cape, 1970), 175.
4
For an analysis of Chamberlain's ideas in The Foundations, see G. Field, Evangelist of
Race (New York: Columbia University Press, 1981), chap. 5; R. Stackelberg, Idealism
Debased (Ohio: Kent University Press, 1981), Part III.
5
De Gobineau, foreword to second edition of Essay, Selected Political Writings, 232.
6
M. Burleigh and W. Wipperman charge Chamberlain with fusing Social Darwinism
with anti-Semitism in The Racial State (Cambridge University Press, 1991), 36. For an
analysis of Chamberlain's racial ideas which stresses their anti-Darwinian orientation,
see M. Woodroffe, 'Racial Theories of History and Politics: the Example of Houston
Stewart Chamberlain', in P. Kennedy and A. Nicholls, eds., Nationalist and Racist
Movements in Britain and Germany Before 1914 (London: Macmillan, 1981), 143-53.
7
D. Lorimer, Colour, Class and the Victorians (Leicester University Press, 1978), 60-2,
77,80-1.
186 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
In Darwinism it was possible to conceive groups as the units of
evolutionary change. In the light of the importance of both race and
nationalism in nineteenth-century social thought, it is understandable
why Darwinists very quickly showed interest in racial attributes and
inter-ethnic relationships. Both A. R. Wallace and Charles Loring Brace
produced evolutionary accounts of racial differences, while Haeckel,
Royer, Rolle and Bagehot made racial and/or national conflict an
important factor in social evolution. The theorists discussed below went
further than this in making national and racial struggles the primary
focus of their interpretations of socio-historical change.
23
Lapouge, Selections, 1, 11, 5, 8.
24
Lapouge, "The Fundamental Laws of Anthropo-sociology', tr. C. Closson, Journal of
Political Economy, 6 ( 1 8 9 8 ) , 56.
25 26 27
Lapouge, UAryen, 369. Lapouge, Selections, 67. Ibid., 7.
28 29
Lapouge, UAryen, 369. Ibid., 3 5 1 , 5 1 1 .
Races, nations and the struggle for existence 193
escape their racial heritage: the belief that inferior races were improvable
through contacts with more advanced races was contrary to the lessons
of science.30
According to Lapouge, useful variations of a physical or psychological
nature allowed some individuals to survive and reproduce while others
died out. 31 But because man was a social animal, the struggle for
existence became modified into a conflict between different groups 'in
which the individuals found themselves united against the common
enemy'. 32 This transformation was of momentous consequence for the
course of human evolution. 'The struggle of man against man through
war has not ceased, but it has acquired a social character .. ,' 3 3 As social
solidarity grew, natural selection diminished in importance and was
replaced by social selection, a form of struggle no less murderous than its
natural counterpart but one producing very different results. In fact,
social selection perverted evolution by eliminating the best individuals
and allowing inferior specimens to survive and propagate their kind.
This was how the great civilisations of antiquity had perished and a
similar fate now threatened modern Europe. 34
Lapouge argued that Europe was populated by three major racial
groups. The first was Homo Europaeus - tall, pale-skinned, blue-eyed
and long-skulled. Lapouge considered the 'cephalic index' afforded a
good measure of racial type, and Homo Europaeus was dolichocephalous,
with an index of 75 or less.35 This race had become popularly referred to
as 'Aryan', a term Lapouge found acceptable on condition that the
anthropo-sociologist bore in mind its zoological rather than linguistic
connotations. The second race was Homo Alpinus, smaller and darker
complexioned than the Aryan, with black hair, brown eyes and
brachycephalous heads (i.e. short skulls with an index of over 80). This
race was a product of inter-breeding with several others. The third race
was the Mediterranean type, long-headed but possessing the darker skin
and shorter stature of Alpinus. Lapouge was primarily concerned with
the first two races.
Psychological differences augmented the physical distinctions
between the Aryan and Alpinus. The former was a natural leader and
30 31
Ibid., 3 5 2 - 3 , 4 0 5 . Lapouge, Selections, 8 2 .
32
Lapouge, L'Aryen, 3 7 4 . Lapouge, Selections, 60.
34
Ibid., chap. 7 and 4 4 3 - 4 ; Lapouge, VAryen, 5 1 2 , 4 0 6 .
35
T h e cephalic index is obtained by dividing the width of the skull by its length and
multiplying the result by 100. However, anthropologists disagreed over the respective
virtues of dolichocephaly and brachycephaly, and many, contra Lapouge, were of the
opinion that brachycephaly was a sign of superiority. See Schneider, Quality and
Quantity, 2 5 1 ; Haller, Outcasts From Evolution, 3 8 . Havelock Ellis associated dolichoce-
phaly with degeneration in his Man and Woman, eighth edn (London: Heinemann,
1934), 186.
194 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
innovator, excelling in intellectual work, whether in science, letters or
the arts, as well as in the business world. This made the Aryan 'a great
promoter of progress', a natural conqueror, robust, intelligent, possessed
of boundless energy, though of a sad and cold disposition.36 In all these
respects, he contrasted sharply with the brachycephalous Alpinus;
Lapouge even considered the greater tendency of Aryans to ride bicycles
a mark of superiority.37 He speculated that Alpinus had originally 'lived
in forests and mountains in an almost simian state, and had been enticed
out of their lairs only to serve as slaves to the dolichocephals'.38 This had
generated an innate desire for a master: 'The instinct of servitude is so
anchored in the psychology of the brachycephal that immediately he is
free, he is compelled to seek a master who will guarantee his security.'
These psychological differences were reflected in a 'natural division of
labour' in which the Aryans occupied the most important social
positions while the brachycephals performed menial tasks and manual
labour.39
In spite of their natural inferiority - indeed, because of it - the
brachycephals were becoming the dominant race in Europe. Homo
Alpinus was seemingly indestructible: 'He is inert, he is mediocre, but he
multiplies.'40 Since the Middle Ages the brachycephals had increased at
the expense of the dolichocephals because the social milieu progressively
favoured servility and mediocrity, subverting the natural division of
labour throughout Europe. Social selection was destroying the most
eugenic families and leaving in its wake a racial debris incapable of
resisting the challenge of new conquerors.
Lapouge identified several forms of social selection. First, there was
political selection, functioning through civil wars, exile and persecution.
The French Revolution was an important instance of this, marking the
violent transfer of power from one race - the Aryans - to another,
Alpinus, who maintained this dominance through the device of democ-
racy.41 Lapouge regarded democracy as an unmitigated disaster in
France, where it failed to express French racial realities in the way that a
parliamentary system did in Britain and the USA (where the Aryans
were still numerous). Though weak and vacillating due to the mutual
paralysis of the executive and legislature, this regime continued to
oppress individuals left unprotected after first the absolute monarchy
and then the Revolution had destroyed the institutional life of France
and created a 'human dust' of atomised individuals. Yet the brachyce-
36 37
Lapouge, VAryen, 399, 151. Lapouge, 'The Fundamental Laws', 63.
38 39
Lapouge, VAryen, 236. Lapouge, Selections, 76; VAryen, 238.
40
Lapouge, VAryen, 481; see also Selections, 67.
41
Lapouge, Selections, 251; L 'Aryen, 464.
Races, nations and the struggle for existence 195
phal thrived in this environment: 'He is the perfect slave, the ideal serf,
the model subject, and in a republic like our own, the best-regarded
citizen, as he tolerates every abuse.'42
Modern warfare also had a deleterious selective impact. Among
primitives and barbarians, war was beneficial because it eliminated weak
individuals. With the advent of civilisation it became a veritable scourge,
ensuring that the bravest and strongest were exposed to death while the
lunatics, criminals and misfits were protected. War had been virtually
eliminated within societies, but at the international level it was as fierce
and relentless as ever, making the proposal for a United States of Europe
an empty Utopia. 'War is the essential and necessary mode of
international selection, and it appears to augment rather than diminish
in intensity.' The decline of the militaristic Aryan spelled disaster for
European nations in the forthcoming conflicts which, for Lapouge, were
unavoidable. 'The struggle of large nations is a natural necessity.'43
Religion exerted another adverse selective influence, especially Cath-
olicism, where celibacy among the priesthood reduced the ranks of the
most ardent, and hence usually better, individuals. Worse still was the
fact that Christianity encouraged moral conformity and intolerance,
which worked against the independently minded Aryans.44 Lapouge was
convinced that society had need of a shared system of values which
could act as a moral bond because selection had produced in man a
biological need to believe in such values which made them as necessary
as bread, but the religion he endorsed was Haeckel's monism rather
than Christianity.45
Closely linked to religion was moral selection, in which prudish norms
and prohibitions hindered reproductive activities and forced people to
wear too much clothing, which restricted the ability of the skin to
breathe and caused diseases like tuberculosis. Charitable endeavours
were equally regressive, 'protecting from the effects of selection those
elements which cannot and will not work, and multiplying them in an
artificial manner'.46 This allowed racial degeneration to become the
norm in modern societies 'where the incompetent, far from being
eliminated, can live at the expense of others and multiply the more so as
they are psychically closer to animality'. Humanitarian concern for the
criminal had also created a form of legal selection. Lapouge insisted that
the criminal should not be allowed to reproduce because all of his
42
Lapouge, UAryen, 2 3 3 ; also 3 7 6 - 8 , 3 8 1 .
43
Lapouge, Selections, 224; L'Aryen, 5 0 1 .
Lapouge, Selections, 2 6 4 - 6 , 2 8 1 .
45
Lapouge, 'Preface' to Haeckel, Le Monisme, 1, 8; L'Aryen, vi.
46
Lapouge, Selections, 3 1 2 - 1 7 , 318.
196 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
progeny would carry the germ of criminality. Imprisonment he decried
as both ineffectual and expensive: the most certain, selective and
economical penal sanction was the death penalty. 47
Finally, there existed a mode of economic selection which was helping
to destroy the Aryan who, while eminently suited to entrepreneurial and
even speculative activities, was disadvantaged by the untrammelled
egoism of the modern world. This favoured an aristocracy whose wealth
was based upon chance rather than upon merit, one which became
softened and corrupted by success, lazy and decadent.
All these forces, along with the emigration of the best Aryan stock to
the New World and the degenerative consequences of cross-breeding,
combined to reduce the number of dolichocephals in Europe, particu-
larly in France, Spain and Southern Germany. Hence Lapouge's
writings were punctuated with jeremiads prophesying the imminent
destruction of European civilisation. Europe was finished, and in the
forthcoming global confrontation he foresaw the triumph of Russia and
the implementation of a bureaucratic regime congenial to the brachy-
cephals, although it was just conceivable that victory could go to the
Aryan United States. 48 Sometimes Lapouge predicted the total eclipse
of civilisation in a tone which came close to the subsequent Nazi rhetoric
of apocalypse:
The final times will see men emancipated from all civilisation, returned to their
elementary liberty, ensconced in caves, borrowing their coats from the denizens
of the forest, begging their repast from wild boars and wolves. One will no longer
see any inequality among men, except one, the inequality between he who is on
the spit and he who turns it. Dies irael ['Day of wrath!']49
Lapouge did offer some hope of salvation if nations could harness the
immensely powerful forces of heredity to work in favour of their eugenic
elements. 'Systematic selection appears to be the only means possible to
escape from the coming mediocrity and the final fall.' 50 Public opinion
must be educated about the effects of racial mixing and of the urgent
need for eugenic policies. Polygamy, abortion and even incest he
approved as eugenically sound practices, and Lapouge suggested that
the provision of free alcohol to the worst social types might encourage
them to kill themselves off in their inevitable excesses. 51 His ideal was a
society in which the superior racial elements were in complete control
47 48
Ibid., 119, 321-4. Lapouge, UAryen, 492, 495, 502.
49
L a p o u g e , 'Dies irael La fin d u m o n d e civilise', Revue Europe (1923), cited in C o l o m b a t ,
La Fin du monde civilise, 219. Statements like this, c o m m o n t h r o u g h o u t L a p o u g e ' s
publications, caused h i m to b e c o m e associated with pessimistic a n d iconoclastic
versions of Social Darwinism. See C. Fages, ' L ' E v o l u t i o n d u darwinisme sociologique',
UHumanite nouvelle, 3 ( 1 8 9 9 ) , 3 0 , 3 2 - 4 , 3 6 - 7 .
50 51
L a p o u g e , Selections, 4 8 9 . Ibid., 4 8 6 .
Races, nations and the struggle for existence 197
and remained strictly segregated from the remainder of the population.
"The system of closed, specialised castes, artificial sub-species, is the last
word in evolution.'52
Though Lapouge was marginalised in his own country and played a
limited role in the French eugenics movement, it would be too simple
to explain this by reference to the sentiments outlined above. 53 First,
Lapouge's ideas were not qualitatively different from those of his
contemporaries, even if somewhat less tactfully presented. Second,
Lapouge did enjoy a considerable reputation in the wider international
eugenics movement, and even in France his status improved somewhat
with the development of a more racially oriented eugenics during the
1930s and 1940s. 54 Third, Lapouge's ideas on race were also unremark-
able by the standards of his time and were hence unlikely to have been
responsible for his lack of popularity among his countrymen. Lapouge
described the Jews as an ethnic group rather than a zoological race - one
founded upon religion and with a psychic identity forged over centuries
of selection. They were everywhere the same: intelligent, ruthless, gifted
money-makers, arrogant in success and servile in defeat, and congeni-
tally odious, as evinced by their history of persecution, which antedated
the birth of Christ by several centuries. In the leadership vacuum
created by the decline of the Aryans, the Jews would undoubtedly
become prominent, perhaps even to the extent of taking over Europe,
but they were unable to reproduce themselves sufficiently rapidly to
become a master race, and were likely to remain a powerful but detested
caste.55
Arguments of this nature would have been offensive to many French
citizens in the highly charged atmosphere surrounding the Dreyfus
case, but they were mild by comparison with the anti-Semitic rhetoric
of the radical, nationalistic right.56 Yet Lapouge does not appear to
have found an audience among these groups. The reason surely lies in
52
Ibid., 484.
53
For details of Lapouge's reception in France, see Clark, Social Darwinism in France,
143-54, 158; Clark, 'Le Darwinisme social en France', 197-8; W. Schneider, Quality
and Quantity, 61.
54
See Schneider, Quality and Quantity, 251. Schneider underlines the originality of
Lapouge's ideas on eugenics at their time of publication, 61. Lapouge was cited in
books on heredity, as well as by social theorists. See J. A. Thomson, Heredity (London:
Murray, 1908), 562, 593; Sumner Folkways, 42; T. Veblen, in M. Lerner, ed., The
Portable Veblen (New York: Viking Press, 1948), 215; C. Spiess, Imperialismes (Paris:
Eugene Figuiere, 1917); C. Closson, 'Social Selection', Journal of Political Economy,
4(1896), 4 4 9 - 6 6 .
55
Lapouge, UAryen, 4 6 5 - 8 , 4 7 4 .
56
See, for example, Campagne nationaliste, 1899—1901 (Paris: Imprimerie de la Cour
d'Appel, 1902) by Jules Soury (a Social Darwinist), which contains numerous
pejorative references to Jews, including fantasies about sticking them like pigs (91).
198 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
the overwhelming thrust of his publications, which was directed against
not only the political institutions of the Third Republic - dislike of
which he shared with the nationalist right - but against contemporary
French culture in general. Like de Gobineau, who also had few
French disciples, Lapouge located the cause of French decline and
decadence in the racial composition of the nation. His anthropo-
sociology was not focused upon the relationships between whites and
non-whites, which was the case with much of the literature on race,
but with relationships within the national community. His unflattering
description of the brachycephals, especially his derogatory assessments
of their character and capabilities, was aimed at the mass of the
French population. Even to those who repudiated the values and
institutions of republicanism, Lapouge must have appeared to have
relegated the vast majority of the French nation to the status of
permanent and irremediable worthlessness.
In effect, Lapouge went beyond a critique of the Third Republic to
challenge the entire heritage of the Enlightenment and the Revolution.
His assertion that the individual was 'crushed by his race' controverted
the universalist claim of autonomous, enlightened reason to chart the
course of human destiny. To the formula 'liberty, Equality and
Fraternity5 Lapouge opposed the slogan 'Determinism, Inequality,
Selection'. 57 He was unequivocal in his condemnation of democracy,
progress and pacifism. Science demonstrated the accidental, contingent
nature of life and was inimical to any ideal of progress. 58 The notion of
individual rights was ludicrous, for there could be no question of rights
against force; on the contrary, rights were created and maintained by
force. Finally, Lapouge poured scorn on the goal of fraternity: 'Let there
be fraternity, but woe to the vanquished! Life maintains itself only
through death.'59
Lapouge's ambition was to achieve a 'scientific explanation of the
historical development of civilisations by showing them to depend upon
the processes of biological evolution'. 60 In this he had a great deal in
common with Otto Ammon (1842-1915) in Germany. Both theorists
sought to quantify physical racial differences and to correlate these with
psychological traits, and both used their results to oppose those political
and social tendencies in their countries of which they disapproved. 61
Darwinism held out the hope of a genuine science of society and politics,
57 58
Lapouge, 'Preface' to Le Monisme, 2. Lapouge, Selections, 451; L'Aryen, ix.
59 60
Lapouge, L'Aryen, 512. Lapouge, 'The Fundamental Laws', 54.
61
See Ammon's critique of socialism in his Der Darwinismus Gegen die Sozialdemokratie
(Hamburg: Verlagstalt und Druckerei, 1891). For a discussion of Ammon, see Stark,
'Natural and Social Selection'; Bellomy,' "Social Darwinism" Revisited', 109-13.
Races, nations and the struggle for existence 199
and the task of anthropo-sociology was to communicate the importance
of race for an understanding of history and to measure and explain the
course of racial degeneration in Europe.
However, Lapouge's methodology, which, like that of Lombroso,
relied upon cranial measurements as indices of racial type, waned in
popularity during the twentieth century. The dubiousness of the attempt
to correlate intelligence and other mental attributes with the cephalic
index was apparent from Lapouge's own data. He alleged that the
dolichocephals made up the bulk of the intelligentsia and the high-status
professions, but his statistics actually showed the intellectual classes to
have a mean cephalic index that was higher than the average for the
population as a whole. The implications of this were evaded by invoking
the absence of large numbers of brachycephals in the populations
concerned.62
Lapouge was also unable to maintain a consistent explanation of
social and political phenomena by means of the biological reductionism
he espoused. The point of his work was to show that modern nations
were amalgams of different races, and the obvious inference to be
drawn from this was that nation-states were artificial units within which
racial conflicts were endemic. Many of Lapouge's strictures against the
racial pollution caused by the brachycephals, including his interpreta-
tion of the French Revolution, drew precisely this inference. But he also
argued on occasions that a nation was an immense family within a
certain geographical area, linked to its dead by traditions which would
in turn be bequeathed to its posterity. This implies a much more
harmonious (and traditionalist) conception of nationality stressing the
role of cultural bonds in cementing a people into a community.63 Yet
this perspective was contradicted by his critique of the idea of
naturalisation, which he labelled biological nonsense; hoping to turn a
foreigner into a national was akin to wanting to change a man into a
woman. 'Nations are as real as races, they are biological entities',
subject to a common selection which fused their various racial
components.64 But this thesis - that racial inter-breeding established
the basis for national identity - contradicts the repeated attacks on
racial crossings for causing the appearance of 'racial pariahs', people
pulled in different directions by plural hereditary forces, biologically
incoherent specimens doomed to extinction.65
62
Lapouge, 'The Fundamental Laws', 9 0 - 1 . Lapouge sometimes grouped mesocephals -
people with a cranial index of 7 5 - 9 - with dolichocephals in order to obtain a sufficient
contrast between the latter and brachycephals. See 'The Fundamental Laws', 8 2 - 3 .
63 64 65
Lapouge, L'Aryen, 367. Lapouge, Selections, 2 2 5 . Ibid., 161, 184.
200 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
There is a paradox at the centre of Lapouge's theory of social
selection, namely that biological forces, alleged to be inexorable causal
processes at work in human history, were implicitly acknowledged to be
powerless against countervailing social factors. Previous civilisations
were supposed to have declined due to race-mixing; modern civilisation
was, in addition, threatened by social dynamics which perverted the
course of 'natural evolution'. There is a great deal of intellectual
opportunism here. Phenomena were explained in either biological or
cultural terms depending on how they were evaluated. The psycho-
logical attributes of the Aryans which fitted them for mastery and
creativity, as well as the corresponding traits of the brachycephals which
rendered them suitable for servility and drudgery, were ascribed to
immutable biological laws. The factors responsible for the decline of the
Aryans and the numerical ascendancy of Alpinus, however, derived from
social processes which gave the latter an 'unfair' advantage, and should
therefore be checked.
This inconsistency of argument derived in part from the way in which
ideological considerations dominated the underlying world view, and
partly from the enterprise of trying to construct an account of culture
upon the presumed workings of nature. In the case of Lapouge, it is
ironic that the outcome of his efforts was a view of evolution in which
natural selection actually played very little part in bringing about change^
and instead functioned to preserve the dominance of the blue-eyed, long-
headed, bicycle-riding Aryan. In short, nature in his work provided less
a model of how social change actually took place than a normative
model of how society should be ordered. In this framework, the struggle
for existence was as potent a force as ever, but its consequences had little
to do with changing the physical and mental properties of races. Thus,
contrary to a constant emphasis on the ubiquity of change, Lapouge
adopted an essentialist position on race: for him, racial traits were, for all
intents and purposes, fixed. Transformation was possible, but only as
corruption and decadence.
68
Sumner, Collected Essays, 130.
Races, nations and the struggle for existence 203
by persons who did not believe that races were equivalent to species.
Thus the geologist Nathaniel Southgate Shaler (1841-1906) wrote that
humans belonged to a single species and races were 'mere varieties of
the same stock'.69 These varieties were nonetheless exposed to the
struggle for survival, and Shaler claimed that the frequency of Indian
and French place names in the United States was 'a startling suggestive-
ness of the incapacity of certain peoples to hold their places in the
struggle for existence'.70 As for the situation of blacks, Shaler insisted
that both sides in the Civil War had been motivated by honourable
considerations, and that while slavery was an evil, blacks had flourished
under its regimen and their masters had been humane. 71 Racial
prejudice he attacked as unwarranted in educated people; but he
asserted that it had once functioned to keep 'kinds' separate in order to
avoid race mixing, which Shaler deemed to be a cause of degeneracy,
despite his insistence that humans were one species.72
It must be stressed that one did not need to be a Social Darwinist in
order to adhere to this position on race. As Haller has argued, different
perceptions of the course of evolution had little impact on racist
doctrines.73 What Social Darwinism contributed to race theory was an
apparently scientific rationale for racial hierarchy and a mechanism - the
struggle for survival - for legitimating the predicted fate of blacks and
the actual fate of native Americans.
Imperialism
During the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries the imperialist
policies pursued by the great powers were often perceived in terms of
racial conflict. This provided a context in which Social Darwinism could
be harnessed to the explanation and justification of imperialist policies,
and historians have indeed argued that this ideological linkage was an
intimate one.74 In fact there is a dearth of detailed investigations of the
role of Social Darwinism in imperialist thought and practice, a lacuna
particularly marked with regard to the soldiers, entrepreneurs and
administrators who were actively engaged in colonialism.
69
N . S. Shaler, The Citizen: A Study of the Individual and Government ( N e w York: Barnes,
1904), 13.
70 71 72
Ibid., 5 3 . Ibid., 60,318. Ibid., 2 3 4 - 5 , 3 1 9 - 2 0 .
73
Haller, Outcasts From Evolution, 210.
74
Williams, 'Social Darwinism,' 122; Young, 'Malthus and the Evolutionists', 1 3 7 - 8 ;
Moore, 'Varieties of Social Darwinism', 36; Jones, Social Darwinism, 1 4 9 - 5 3 ; J. Joll,
Europe After 1870 (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1983), 1 0 1 - 5 ; B. Semmel, Imperialism
and Social Reform (London: Allen and U n w i n , 1960); H. W. Koch, 'Social Darwinism
as a Factor in the " N e w Imperialism"', in Koch, ed., The Origins of the First World War,
second edn (London: Macmillan, 1984), 3 1 9 - 4 2 .
204 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
Two additional points need underlining. First, it is evident from some
of the figures already discussed that there was no single Social Darwinist
perspective on imperialism: to Woltmann's and Royer's endorsement
must be contrasted the hostility evinced by Sumner and Spencer.
Second, one could be an enthusiastic imperialist without being a Social
Darwinist. The German explorer and adventurer in East Africa, Carl
Peters, was convinced of the civilising mission of the Anglo-Saxons. By
opening up Africa, Europe would not only become enriched but would
realise a great duty, 'namely, to elevate a race from a lower plane, and to
draw it into the stream of the active development of mankind'. 75 On a
less elevated level, he was equally set on the aggrandisement of the
German Reich in the face of what he saw as the British ambition of
world hegemony.76 In neither cause did he resort to Social Darwinism;
when he lapsed into a philosophical register it was to stress the
importance of the will in overcoming obstacles and the need for stoical
acceptance of the mysterious workings of Providence.77
As with its associations with laissez-faire and racial conflict, then,
Social Darwinism's connections with imperialist ideology were complex,
and neither entailed the other. This being so, there were nevertheless
Social Darwinist rationalisations of imperialism. An excellent example is
furnished by the publications of the adventurer, hunter and busi-
nessman, Frederick Courtney Selous (1852-1917). In 1889, Selous
christened a mountain in South-East Africa Mount Darwin 'after that
illustrious Englishman whose far-reaching theories ... have revolution-
ised modern thought, and destroyed for ever many old beliefs that had
held men's minds in thrall for centuries'.78 Selous was deeply involved
in the annexation of what was to become Rhodesia, which entailed some
bloody confrontations with the warlike Matabele. In his description and
rationalisation of these conflicts, Selous drew heavily upon Social
Darwinism.
Selous defied his readers to judge his actions in the Matabele Wars
according to the dictates of conventional morality. He admitted to
shooting at fleeing blacks 'with as little compunction as though they
were a pack of wild dogs'.79 But he maintained that human beings,
75
Carl Peters, The Future of Africa (London: Waterlow, 1897), 15.
76
See Peters, England and the English (London: Hurst and Blacken, 1904), chap. 10.
Peters' efforts in East Africa were actually an embarrassment to the German
government which was lukewarm about colonial expansion in this area.
77
Peters, New Light on Dark Africa, tr. H. W. Dulken (London: Ward Locke, 1891), 9 1 .
78
F. C. Selous, Travel and Adventure in South-East Africa (London: Rowland, Ward,
1893), 286. For a discussion of Selous and his views o n empire, see K. Tidrick, Empire
and the English Character (London: Taurus, 1990), chap. 2.
79
Selous, Sunshine and Storm in Rhodesia (London: Rowland, Ward, 1896), 64.
Races, nations and the struggle for existence 205
including the civilised inhabitants of Western Europe, were initially
descended from wild beasts and then from the equally savage peoples of
pre-historic times. Hence even with civilised persons it was not necessary
to scratch very deep 'in order to discover the savage ancestors from
whom they are descended'. 80 In the context of the Matabele Wars, the
horrors of the natural environment, the fear of insurrection and the
spectacle of massacred white women and children, were responsible for
awakening the 'slumbering fiend5 which lies latent within us all:
in the smooth and easy course of civilised existence it is possible for a man to live
a long life without ever becoming aware that somewhere deep down below the
polished surface of conventionality there exists in him an ineradicable leaven of
innate ferocity, which, although it may never show itself except under the most
exceptional circumstances, must and ever will be there - the cruel instinct which,
given sufficient provocation, prompts the meekest nature to kill his enemy - the
instinct which forms the connecting link between the nature of man and that of
the beast.81
As far as the indigenous peoples of south-east Africa were concerned,
Selous was convinced of their inferiority relative to the white colonisers.
The latter despised the blacks and regarded them as occupying a lower
scale of humanity. Empathy between the races was out of the question,
and Selous proclaimed it to be 'impossible for a European to understand
the workings of a native's mind'. 82 History showed that when a civilised
race tried to govern a savage race, the latter rebelled. The conquest of
the savage race was therefore a pre-requisite for the development of
civilisation, even though this undoubtedly involved bloodshed and
injustice against the primitive race.
Therefore Matabeleland is doomed by what seems a law of nature to be ruled by
the white man, and the black man must go, or conform to the white man's laws,
or die in resisting them. It seems a hard and cruel fate for the black man, but it is
a destiny which the broadest philanthropy cannot avert, whilst the British
colonist is but the irresponsible atom employed in carrying out a preordained
law - the law which has ruled upon this planet ever since, in the far-off misty
depths of time, organic life wasfirstevolved upon the earth - the inexorable law
which Darwin has aptly termed the 'Survival of the Fittest'.83
Here a Darwinist perspective on the animal origins of mankind and
the role of struggle in evolution is appealed to as a vindication of white
colonial policies in Africa. Selous made the love of hunting, adventure
and colonisation criteria of national fitness. When youths no longer
wished to leave the comfort of their homes to seek their fortunes in 'wild
80 81
Ibid., 193-4. Ibid.,\93.
82
Ibid., 25. See also Selous, Travel and Adventure, 9-10, 135.
83
Selous, Sunshine and Storm, 67.
206 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
and distant lands', 'then will the decadence of England have set in. As a
nation we are probably already past our prime; but that we still possess a
vast fund of vigour and energy there can be no doubt.' 84 Selous certainly
practised what he preached: he was killed in action against German
forces in Tanganyika in 1917.
88
K. H. Metz, 'The Politics of Conflict: Heinrich von Treitschke and the Idea of
Realpolitik\ History of Political Thought, 3 ( 1 9 8 2 ) , 276.
89
Heinrich von Treitschke, Politics, 2 vols., tr. B. Dugdale and Torben de Bille (London:
Constable, 1916).
90
I. Berlin, Against the Current (Oxford University Press, 1981), 338.
208 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
international warfare was written by the German general, Friedrich von
Bernhardi. His Germany and the Next War (1912) 91 sold well and was
translated into several languages. In it Bernhardi deplored the opposi-
tion to warfare mounted by people who were devoted to personal
comfort at the expense of national values and interests. Such sentiments
were symptomatic of moral decay, of a turning against nature's laws and
the 'biological necessity' of war:
The struggle for existence is, in the life of Nature, the basis of all healthy
development. All existing things show themselves to be the result of contesting
forces. So in the life of man the struggle is not merely the destructive, but the
life-giving principle ... The law of the stronger holds good everywhere. Those
forms survive which are able to procure themselves the most favourable
conditions of life, and to assert themselves in the universal economy of Nature.
The weaker succumb. This struggle is regulated and restrained by the
unconscious sway of biological laws and by the interplay of opposite forces
(10-11).
Bernhardi maintained that all the laws of nature reduced to one: the law
of struggle. This had a dual aspect: intm-social, which occurred in every-
day life within a society, in the realm of science, thoughts and wishes as
well as that of actions; and super-social, consisting of violent clashes
between nations. Struggle and war were not identical therefore, since the
former could be peaceful, as in the case of intra-social conflict, where
laws and the state established limits and controls. But no power existed
capable of arbitrating the interactions among states, which inevitably
resulted in warfare (11-13).
Bernhardi, in orthodox Darwinian fashion, inferred the inevitability of
conflict from the pressure of population on resources. Healthy nations
had a tendency to expand their populations. Since the globe was now
almost entirely inhabited, this growth could be accommodated only
through conquest, emigration and colonisation. If the last two options
were foreclosed, as they were to Germany, then 'the instinct of self
preservation leads inevitably to war, and the conquest of foreign soil'
(15). To the pressures created by population growth as motives for war,
Bernhardi added the need for foreign markets as an outlet for German
goods, and the imperative of protecting the domestic market from
foreign imports. His conclusion was: 'The knowledge, therefore, that
war depends on biological laws leads to the conclusion that every
attempt to exclude it from international relations must be demonstrably
untenable. But it is not only a biological law, but a moral obligation,
and, as such, an indispensable factor in civilisation' (17).
91
Trans. A. H. Powles (London: Arnold, 1912). See Crook, Darwinism, War and History,
82-3.
Races, nations and the struggle for existence 209
The moral imperatives of the nation entailed the subordination of
individual rights to national duties (17-18, 41, 59), and meant that the
actions of the state could not be assessed in accordance with the
standards of personal morality. Bernhardi proclaimed that in the arena
of international relations: 'Might is at once the supreme right, and the
dispute as to what is right is decided by the arbitrament of war. War
gives a biologically just decision, since its decisions rest on the very
nature of things' (57).
There are strong echoes of Treitschke's doctrine of Machtpolitik in
these arguments, which has prompted some commentators to downplay
the general's Social Darwinism, relegating it to a marginal role in the
text, or seeing it as a mere gloss of 'disconnected catchwords'. 92 These
judgements underestimate both the coherence and the rhetorical
significance of Bernhardi's Darwinism. The world view was clearly
formulated and invoked at those points in his arguments where
Bernhardi went beyond Treitschke to argue that the interests of the
nation-state had to be understood within the context of biological
imperatives. The pressure of population on resources made struggle 'a
universal law of nature', a law which grounded the interactions among
states and which justified the subordination of the individual to the
nation. This materialist rationale for power politics and reason of state
would have been anathema to Treitschke.
There is another reason for taking Bernhardi's Social Darwinism
seriously, namely that his thesis that nations struggled for space and
resources resonated, and indeed may have been influenced by, the
Lebensraum theory of the zoologist-turned-geographer, Friedrich Ratzel
(1844-1904). Ratzel argued that all organisms were engaged in a Kampf
um Raum - a struggle for space - in which the strongest sought to expel
or eliminate the weakest. This struggle for Lebensraum (living space) was
extended to humans, and Ratzel made it clear that nations were
inevitably engaged in the struggle to expand their living space if they
wished to avoid decline.93 Thus Bernhardi's own use of Social
Darwinism was hardly eccentric but echoed an established tradition
among respectable academic thinkers in Germany.
Furthermore, very similar rationalisations of war were produced by
thinkers outside of Germany. 'God's Test by War' was published in an
2
For the first interpretation see Crook, Darwinism, War and History, 83, 117; for the
second, see Zmarlik, 'Social Darwinism in Germany', 455-6.
93
For analyses of Ratzel's theories and their relationship to Social Darwinism, see Smith,
Politics and the Sciences of Culture, 142-7, 219-30; Weikart, 'The Origins of Social
Darwinism in Germany', 485-6.
210 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
influential British journal in 1911 by Harold F. Wyatt.94 It opened with
the assertion that 'the biological law of competition still rules the
destinies of nations as of individual men'. The author then enquired of
England: 'Is the heart that once was hers still strong to dare and to
resolve and to endure? How shall we know? By the test. What test? That
which God has given for the trial of peoples - the test of war' (591-2).
According to Wyatt nations, which now constituted the main divisions
of the human race, were analogous to individual organisms. Every
healthy organism 'feels the same impulse to grow and to compete with
its rivals for increased means of subsistence' (595). Since nations were
part of nature, they too were subjected to the struggle for existence, with
victory going to the strongest and most efficient organism. Without
death the world would be rapidly overpopulated, and among humans
war was the 'scythe' that brought death. But it was also the 'condition of
human advance', something ignored by those who stigmatised warfare
as a relic from mankind's barbarous past:
Defeat in war is thefruitof naval and military inefficiency, and that inefficiency
is the inevitable sequel to moral decay. Victory in war is the method by which, in
the economy of God's providence, the sound nation supersedes the unsound,
because in our time such victory is the direct offspring of a higher efficiency, and
the higher efficiency is the logical outcome of the higher morale (595).
Unless human nature was radically transformed, the absence of
warfare would produce stagnation rather than progress 'because the
terrific punishment which war provides for human degeneracy would be
removed' (597). Wyatt was adamant that in war the morally righteous
win, so that 'victory is the crown of moral quality', and 'the "survival of
the fittest" means the survival of the ethically best'. War was the enemy
of sloth, apathy and decadence, and the test of a nation's fitness and
moral worth was decided before 'the Court of God, which is war' (599,
602). The author lambasted the Anglo-Saxons for the absence of the
'spirit of self-sacrifice' which he saw manifest in the refusal of their
women to bear children and their menfolk to bear arms, in contrast to
the Japanese and Germans (600).
Despite Wyatt's resort to religious metaphors and the language of sin
and retribution, Social Darwinism provided the intellectual scaffolding
for his argumentation. Societies were assimilated to the laws regulating
biological organisms, and struggle derived from superfecundity and was
made the motor of evolution and progress. This essay was not merely a
reflection of jingoistic fervour, therefore, but resonated a number of
94
H. F. Wyatt, 'God's Test by War', The Nineteenth Century and After, 69(1911),
591-606.
Races, nations and the struggle for existence 211
well-established themes in Social Darwinist discourse, both in Britain
and elsewhere.
The notion that, in the polity of nature, warfare acted as the ultimate
test of a nation's fitness was also articulated by the Frenchman, George
Valois (1876-1945). Valois pursued a veritable ideological pilgrimage
across the entire political spectrum, from anarchism through monar-
chism, to Fascism and finally socialism, a journey that finally ended in a
Nazi concentration camp. Throughout these peregrinations, Valois
sought the same goal: a united France, organised for the purpose of
industrial efficiency, and bound together by a moral consensus. While
he changed his mind about the optimal socio-political framework within
which this goal could be achieved, the view of the world and human
nature which underpinned it was first adumbrated in L'Homme qui vient>
published just prior to his joining the extreme nationalist and pro-
monarchist Action Franchise in 1906. 95
Valois was influenced by a recent study by a French biologist, Rene
Quinton, entitled L'Eau de mer, milieu organique (1904). Quinton
proposed that the earth had been slowly cooling since its formation. This
forced each organism to struggle to maintain the temperature of its
'internal milieu', i.e. the biochemical conditions of its physiological
existence. A contemporary commentator summarised Quinton's re-
search as a demonstration that life should not be seen as unstable and
ruled by caprice and accident, because the external adaptations of an
organism acted to preserve its internal milieu. 96 For Valois, Quinton's
book facilitated a reworking of Darwinism in which progress and
conservation could both be shown to be part of nature's law. Each
organism struggled incessantly to augment its protection against a
hostile environment. Among animals, this was achieved through organic
modifications; in humans, by work and the organisation of work.
Unfortunately, humans were, by nature, disinclined to labour.
Civilisation commenced when energetic individuals coerced their
fellows into organised efforts, meaning that the need for leadership and
authority was universal and perpetual: 'The domination of the man with
the whip is eternal' (27). Even after centuries of civilisation, human
nature had not changed: 'The beast of yore is still within us, ready at any
moment to lead us back to the forest' (14). The coercive and
95
G Valois, L'Homme qui vient: philosophie de Vautorite, second edn (Paris: Nouvelle
librairie Nationale, 1909). According to Y. Guchet, Georges Valois (Paris: Edition
Albatros, 1975), 4 4 - 5 , 2 0 5 , this text was the best known and most philosophical of
Valois' books, and he remained faithful to the world view sketched therein until at least
1930.
96
J. Weber, 'Les Theories biologiques de M . Rene Quinton', Revue de metaphysique et de
morale, 13(1905), 138.
212 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
organisational abilities of the man with the whip were constantly
required to prevent human nature from reasserting its primeval slothful-
ness. What motivated him was the struggle for survival. The very success
of the dominant individual was an incentive for others to take his place.
Thus the master had to be constantly vigilant: 'There is the fear of the
other aristocrat who had armed himself in order to take his slaves and
the wealth he accumulates in his house; there is the fear of the slave who
would like to take his place . . . ' (12-13). This worked to the benefit of
the species, for the aristocrat could only maintain his position of
dominance if he continued to perform the functions of discipline and
organisation.
The need for authority was eternal, but the forms of constraint,
domination and social coordination evolved over time. Valois believed
that with the emergence of industrial civilisation, the intra-social form of
the struggle for existence was transformed. In the modern world, the
industrialist and businessman, motivated by the spirit of struggle and
risk and subject to the selective pressures of economic competition,
complemented the activities of the warrior, while among ordinary people
poverty acted as a spur to effort and a punishment for degeneracy and
idleness (86). But this did not imply that war became dysfunctional
during the industrial era. On the contrary, it was still a 'law of the world'
(132), but one that now applied to nations rather than to individuals.
Industrial activities required domestic stability which was achieved
within the framework of the nation-state. But each nation was in a state
of nature vis-d-vis its neighbours, so that 'war between nations is a
fortunate necessity for civilisation5 (175). It was fortunate because
armed conflict or its threat prevented laziness and decadence and forced
each country to improve its industrial, and hence military, capacity, to
the full. Selection, which had formerly operated upon individuals, now
acted upon nations. Weak nations, like weak individuals, were inclined
to whine about justice and self-determination, but rights could only be
established by submission to the ultimate 'tribunal of the Field of Battle'
(181). Valois admonished nations to halt their clamour for peace and to
prepare for war if they wished to survive. Nature recognised only one
form of justice, 'the decline, the death of every living being which
abdicates, which renounces, effort' (188). He additionally proposed that
a victorious nation ought to replace the work-force of a defeated nation
with its own rather than attempt to incorporate the vanquished since this
was more beneficial to the species. The victors, by extending their own
brave and diligent race and eliminating weak, idle and lax races,
contributed to the creation of an ever higher humanity (194-5).
This text is an eclectic one and a number of influences are discernible,
Races, nations and the struggle for existence 213
especially Nietzsche, from whom Valois borrowed a number of expres-
sions and ideas. But the Darwinian world view is no mere gloss, for it
once again provided a set of background assumptions that were brought
to the fore when Valois required a scientific counter to liberal and
socialist celebrations of individual freedom, egalitarianism, emancipa-
tion from labour and peace. As with Bernhardi and Wyatt, group
selection through warfare, presented as a biological law, established the
rationale for the supremacy of the state and the nation over the
individual.
My final case study was written during World War II by Sir Arthur
Keith (1866-1955), a distinguished British anatomist and physical
anthropologist. Interestingly, in his Essays on Human Evolution91 Keith
confessed that until the war of 1914-18 he had subscribed to the view
that modern warfare was dysgenic, depriving a nation of its fittest
members and thus rendering it less capable of conducting the struggle
for existence. Thereafter he came to believe that war 'is part of the
machinery which has determined, and is now determining, the fate of
nations and of races' (129). In light of the use then being made of Social
Darwinism by Nazi theoreticians it is interesting to examine Keith's
arguments in some detail.
The foundation of Keith's theory was the premise that among social
animals struggle took place between relatively isolated groups, whether
of the same or dissimilar species. This required unity and cooperation
within the group but resistance to any amalgamation with other groups.
Thus intra-group solidarity was complemented by hostility and aggres-
sion towards other groups. Since man was a social animal, this held true
of the most basic form of association, the 'tribe', which was a specific
assortment of genetic material. In biological terms, a tribe was a success
if it managed to maintain its genetic integrity over time; if it failed to do
so by a slackening of parental and other social bonds, or lack of courage
and skill in defence, or by inter-breeding with neighbouring tribes, it was
an evolutionary failure (5).
In these conditions, tribesmen evolved a 'dual mentality' consisting of
two codes of conduct, the 'ethical' and the 'cosmicaP. The former was
oriented to the group and stressed altruism, cooperation and solidarity,
while the latter stressed antagonism and violence against other tribes and
inevitably entailed warfare. The pacifists and the militarists were there-
fore both correct in their assessment of human nature, but they each
concentrated on only one of its facets: the truth was that man was
97
Sir A. Keith, Essays on Human Evolution (London: Scientific Book Club). These essays
have no date of publication, but according to the author's testimony they were written
between 1942 and 1944, and published towards the end of 1944. See vi-vii, 92.
214 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
instinctually fitted for both peace and war. 'Human nature was fashioned
or evolved just to secure these two conditions - continuity through time
and separation in space. Hence the duality of man's nature - the good,
social, or virtuous traits serving intra-tribal economy; the evil, vicious, or
anti-social qualities serving the inter-tribal economy and the policy of
keeping its genes apart' (23).
The breaking up of tribal communities by the formation of city-states
and then nations had been a vital step in the progress of civilisation,
allowing the rule of law to replace that of custom, and nurturing
individual liberty and independence. But there were limits to this
process. First, the dual code was so deeply entrenched in human nature
'that it cannot be rooted out; by effort and education the individual may
control the cosmical side of his nature, but he cannot annihilate it'
(123). Second, 'nations are in the scheme of evolution, the lineal
successors of tribes' (146). As a consequence, individuals simply
transferred their allegiance from the tribe to the nation-state. 'Free
peoples value their liberties above all else save one thing: that one
exception is the integrity and independence of the tribe or nation of
which they form part...' (35). This explained the nature and the cause
of war: 'any threat of injury to the life or integrity of a nation, any attack
on its homeland or on its means of supply, calls forth the old defensive
mechanism which Nature has implanted for the protection and
perpetuation of her evolutionary units. War is indeed a factor, and a very
powerful one, in the evolution of mankind' (133).
Keith derived several moral and political inferences from this theory.
He apparently saw no possibility of social evolution beyond the modern
nation-state, and regarded universal brotherhood as an impossibility
because of the tribal foundations of human nature and the ineradicability
of the cosmic code. Christianity was doomed to failure because it sought
to apply the ethical code to the whole of humanity, hence 'its methods
are discordant with human nature, and are therefore anti-evolutionary.
Nationalism, on the other hand, is a growing force because it is in
harmony with human nature, and is therefore pro-evolutionary' (68).
People had to recognise the existence of the dual code within
themselves. Those who sought to regulate their lives according to only
one code - the ethical - would be prone to unhappiness, such as was the
case with conscientious objectors (195). Moreover, Keith did not regard
civilisation as a force capable of eliminating the cosmic ethos. On the
contrary, some of the most civilised modern states were also the most
ferocious, cruel and warlike, e.g. the Japanese, Western Europeans and
North Americans (38-9).
Keith acknowledged the dysgenic impact of modern warfare on a
Races, nations and the struggle for existence 215
nation's population but insisted that the effects of war had to be
measured in national rather than in individual terms. 'War, particularly
war as now waged, is the ultimate test, not only of armies, but also of
nations. The whole national fabric is tested' (193). War was a powerful
factor in national integration, producing a strengthening of the ethical
code and the bonds of fellowship and altruism even if the cosmic code of
hatred was also reinforced (106). But Keith's position was not without
its difficulties. Nazi Germany he presented as a nation that had
succumbed to tribalism, although he praised Hitler for understanding
the laws of evolution and applying them to the German people (8-11).
In fact Keith found it difficult to condemn Nazi Germany for its
belligerence since he described nationalism as the successor of tribalism,
and regarded nations as incipient species (140). He also celebrated the
rejuvenating effects of war on a nation's sense of identity and solidarity
and proposed that 'if mankind is to be vigorous in mind and progressive
in its spirit, its division into nations and races must be maintained'
(175). His paradoxical recipe for peace in Europe was 'each nation being
prepared for war and ready to give its blood and its treasure to maintain
peace' (206). Finally, although he praised the expansion of individual
freedom in countries such as Britain, he considered these liberties
dangerous in times of war when they should be abrogated in order to
achieve unity of action. He even suggested that periodic outbreaks of
war were required in order to prevent individualism from corroding
group solidarity: 'When individual selfishness eats into this capital of
altruism, then the pyramid of civilisation begins to crumble.' War, by
comparison may 'damage a civilisation, but cannot destroy it' (84, 113).
Keith's ideas were remarkably close to Hitler's pronouncements on
war and individualism (which are discussed in chapter 11), as well as
exhibiting continuity with those of Wyatt, Bernhardi and, earlier,
Lapouge and Gumplowicz. The linking of a hereditarian, group
selectionist version of Social Darwinism to positions in which national
interests assumed moral paramountcy, and ethnic characteristics were
virtually timeless, had taken place well before the end of the nineteenth
century and had been reinforced by the eugenics movements of the early
twentieth. The use of Social Darwinism to construct a moral celebration
of international and inter-racial war was not, therefore, a marginal or
perverse ideological activity, but rather an important instance of how the
world view could be adapted to the perceived moral and political
imperatives of the moment.
The eugenic conscience
Introduction
The story of the various national eugenics and racial hygiene movements
has been told many times, and it is not my intention to reproduce these
histories here. 1 My interest is in the relationship between these move-
ments and Social Darwinism. As I argued in the introduction, eugenics
and Social Darwinism should not be conflated for it was possible to
endorse one and not the other. Nevertheless, Darwin himself prefigured
the concerns of the eugenics movements. In his Descent Darwin signalled
his anxiety about the possibility of biological decline caused by social
practices that cushioned the unfit from the impact of natural selection.
Whereas among 'savages' mentally and physically defective individuals
were quickly eliminated, in civilised societies such persons were
sustained by various medical and charitable practices:
Thus the weak members of civilised society propagate their kind. No one who
has attended to the breeding of domestic animals will doubt that this must be
highly injurious to the race of man. It is surprising how soon a want of care, or
care wrongly directed, leads to the degeneration of a domestic race; but
excepting in the case of man himself, hardly any one is so ignorant as to allow his
worst animals to breed (205-6).
1
The most recent studies are: for Britain, G. Jones, Social Hygiene in Twentieth Century
Britain (London: Croom Helm, 1986); R. Soloway, Demography and Degeneration
(London: University of North Carolina Press, 1989); P. M. H. Mazumdar, Eugenics,
Human Genetics and Human Failures (London: Routledge, 1992); for Britain and the
USA, D. Kevles, In the Name of Eugenics (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1986); the USA,
M. H. Haller, Eugenics (New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press, 1984); for
France, Schneider, Quality and Quantity; for Germany, Weindling, Health, Race and
German Politics. Material on France and Germany is also contained in M. Adams, ed.,
The Wellborn Science (New York: Oxford University Press, 1990), which also includes
essays on Brazil and Russia. There is an excellent history of various attempts to
measure intelligence in S. J. Gould, The Mismeasure of Man (Harmondsworth: Penguin,
1992). For investigations of other national eugenics movements, see M. Nash, 'Social
Eugenics and Nationalist Race Hygiene in Early Twentieth Century Spain', History of
European Ideas, 15(1992), 741-8; N. L. Stepan, 'Race, Gender and Nation in
Argentina: The Influence of Italian Eugenics', History of European Ideas, 15(1992),
749-56.
216
The eugenic conscience 217
In the closing pages of the book Darwin returned to this topic to suggest
that 'all ought to refrain from marriage who cannot avoid abject poverty
for their children', pointing out that 'if the prudent avoid marriage whilst
the reckless marry, the inferior members tend to supplant the better
members of society5. Darwin underlined the role played by natural
selection in human evolution, and claimed that man must remain
subject to a severe struggle for existence: 'Otherwise he would sink into
indolence, and the more girted men would not be more successful in the
battle of life than the less gifted. Hence our natural rate of increase,
though leading to many and obvious evils, must not be greatly
diminished by any means' (945).
There were a number of assumptions in these arguments which
reappeared in, and indeed structured, subsequent discourses on eu-
genics and racial hygiene. There was, first, the supposition that
'inferiority' and 'superiority' could be objectively ascertained. Second,
there was the assumption that the factors responsible for this distinction
were mainly due to heredity rather than to social conditions. Third,
there was a presumption of the appropriateness of the analogy between
stockbreeding and human reproduction - a presumption that was
widespread throughout Europe at the time.2 Finally, there was the
proposition that the beneficial action of natural selection had been
replaced by social mechanisms facilitating the propagation of inferior
specimens. There was a potential dilemma within this proposition,
however, because concern for the unfit derived from the strengthening
of social sentiments which themselves were the products of natural
selection. Natural forces were hence ambivalent in their social out-
comes.
These themes were central to the work of Darwin's cousin Francis
Galton (1822-1911). In 1883 Galton proposed the 'science' of eugenics
in the belief that it was objectively possible to recognise the undesirable
elements in a population and reduce their numbers through relevant
social controls - negative eugenics - while at the same time encouraging
the reproduction of the better elements - positive eugenics.3 These
suggestions were not initially influential, but by the early twentieth
2
On the importance of animal breeding in furnishing models for the breeding, control
and elimination of humans, see E. U. Da Cal, 'The Influence of Animal Breeding on
Political Racism', History of European Ideas, 15(1992), 717-25.
3
For a full elaboration of his ideas on the eve of the formation of eugenics movements
across the world, see F. Galton, 'Eugenics: Its Definition, Scope and Aims', American
Journal of Sociology, 10(1904), 1-25. For a discussion of Galton's work, see Kevles, In
the Name of Eugenics, chap. 1; Soloway, Demography and Degeneration, chaps. 2-6. For
Galton's influence on contemporary anthropology see D. Lorimer, 'Theoretical Racism
in Late Victorian Anthropology', Victorian Studies, 31(1988), 430.
218 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
century they acquired considerable currency as the various eugenics
movements urged government action to prevent national and racial
decline. The German Race Hygiene Society was founded in 1905,
followed by the Eugenics Education Society in England (1907), and the
French Eugenics Society (1912). A similar body was established in the
USA in 1910, and the First International Eugenics Congress was held in
London in 1912. The reasons for this transition from the laissez-faire
stance of Royer and Spencer to the demand for government action
typical of the eugenics and racial hygiene movements are complex, but
important to an understanding of the role of Social Darwinism in these
movements.
Perhaps the most direct impact was the discovery that after a period
of steady population increase the trend was reversed, with all Euro-
pean nations experiencing a sharp fall in birth-rates.4 Moreover, this
decline was not socially uniform but mainly confined to the middle and
upper classes, thus fuelling anxieties about the future quality of the
nation. Statistics also revealed increases in crime and prostitution, the
incidence of diseases like tuberculosis, and the numbers of feebleminded
persons. The worthless appeared to be thriving at the expense of the
worthy.
There were other factors at work as well. Historians have shown how
eugenics and social hygiene programmes in some countries served the
interests of the practitioners in the various branches of medicine and
related professions in their efforts to achieve professional status and
public recognition.5 Urbanisation and industrialisation created social
conditions in which ill-health, poverty and crime could thrive, providing
opportunities for experts of various descriptions to supply services to a
state apparatus increasingly concerned with monitoring and controlling
its subjects.6 The tensions brought about through class and ethnic
conflicts and the demands of organised labour and feminists helped
establish a climate in which these social conditions could become the
focus of political controversy. Reformers advocated programmes of
environmental engineering aimed at removing what they saw as the
social causes of crime, poverty and disease. But those who believed that
4
Soloway, Demography and Degeneration, xii.
5
Weindling, Race, Health and German Polities', Schneider, Quality and Quantity. Jones
does not regard these motives to have been significant in the formation of the British
social hygiene movement, though she believes they may have subsequently come to play
this role; Jones, Social Hygiene, 52. Although physicians played an important role in
British eugenics, the majority of the British medical profession appear to have been
opposed to eugenics. See D. Porter,' "Enemies of the Race": Biologism, Environment-
alism and Public Health in Edwardian England', Victorian Studies, 34(1991), 160-78.
6
See J. Donzelot, The Policing of Families (London: Hutchinson, 1980).
The eugenic conscience 219
the environment exerted a negligible impact on the formation of
character and physique demanded policies which placed the emphasis
on heredity. Not that the two political agendas were mutually exclusive;
some reformers like Wallas were able to combine a commitment to
social change with a belief in the importance of eugenics. But the
increasingly hereditarian bias of eugenics and social medicine during the
course of the twentieth century encouraged the promotion of action
aimed at elevating the biological quality of the population rather than
restructuring the social system in ways that would redistribute opportu-
nities and rewards in favour of the disadvantaged.
Another factor was the concern of many intellectuals with something
mentioned in the above citation from Darwin's Descent - degeneration.
Fiction, medicine and social thought were replete with data, images and
explanations concerning the degenerative consequences of modernity.
Urbanisation and industrialisation produced a fascination with mental
and physical disease, with suicide and crime, prostitution and sexual
deviance. In some versions, degeneracy was vested with a wider
significance as the manifestation of a deep-seated malaise, endemic to
Western culture and morality.7 This was the thesis of the physician and
Jewish nationalist, Max Nordau (1849-1923), the pseudonym of Max
Simon Siidfeld. In his widely read Degeneration of 1892, 8 Nordau wrote
of 'a severe mental epidemic; a sort of black death of degeneracy and
hysteria . . . ' (537). Degeneracy was a pathological condition, a deviation
from normalcy that was hereditary and hence transmissible to descen-
dants. It was manifested in a number of physical stigmata - squint eyes,
imperfect ears, stunted growth - but above all in a series of mental
morbidities, such as hysteria, exaggerated egoism, pessimism, apathy,
impulsiveness, emotionalism, mysticism, and a complete absence of any
sense of right and wrong (18-22).
Although Nordau's text was important for popularising the notion of
degeneracy, it differed from later eugenics literature on two points. First,
the main target of his attacks was not the 'lower classes' as was so often
the case for eugenicists. For Nordau, the peasantry and the majority of
the working class and bourgeoisie were untainted by degeneracy, which
was confined the aristocracy and the urban intelligentsia - to the 'upper
ten thousand' (2). Second, Nordau did not advocate political inter-
vention as a remedy for degeneracy. The latter was a condition brought
7
Pick, Faces of Degeneration', Chamberlin and Gilman, eds., Degeneration.
8
Published in German as Die Entartung. The text I have used is the English translation of
the second German edition (London: Heinemann, 1895). For a more detailed account
of Nordau's views on degeneracy, see S. E. Aschheim, 'Max Nordau, Friedrich
Nietzsche and Degeneration*3 Journal of Contemporary History, 28(1993), 643-57.
220 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
about by the failure of the human organism to adapt to the enormous
changes in the conditions of life experienced during the past half century
or so. During this period, lives had been dramatically altered by steam,
electricity, the railways and newspapers. This new lifestyle incurred a
tremendous increase in 'organic expenditure', leading to nervous
exhaustion (39). It was, though, precisely through the agencies of
adaptation and the struggle for existence that the problem of degeneracy
would be eventually resolved, since degenerates were incapable of
adaptation (540). Their elimination was hastened if they were sur-
rounded by normal, healthy people, for in such a case the former 'have
to fight in the struggle for existence, and there is no leisure for them to
perish in a slow decay by their own incapacity for work' (540-1). Hence
Nordau was fairly optimistic about the future of civilisation. Normal
people would either adapt to the changing circumstances of civilisation
or else, if this proved too difficult, abandon the innovations responsible
for undue stress. As for the degenerates, their sterility and dysfunction-
ality doomed them to elimination: 'They can neither adapt themselves to
the conditions of Nature and civilisation, nor maintain themselves in the
struggle for existence against the healthy' (541).
Nordau's account of degeneracy, therefore, reproduced the optimism
of the early pioneers of Social Darwinism insofar as he believed that the
course of evolution was ultimately progressive.9 By the end of the
nineteenth century, however, Darwinian theory had itself been reinter-
preted in ways that made degeneracy an evolutionary possibility. This
was the overt thesis of the eminent British naturalist E. R. Lankester in
his Degeneration: A Chapter in Darwinism (1880).10 Warning his readers
against a complacent faith in the benignity of future evolution, Lankester
asserted that natural selection could have one of three possible outcomes
for an organism: the maintenance of a balance between it and its milieu;
organic development; or degeneration. The last of these outcomes he
defined as a gradual change in structure by means of which an organism
became adapted to a less varied and complex form of life (32). Its causes
- and human relevance - were clarified thus:
Any new set of conditions occurring to an animal which renders its food and
safety very easily attained, seem to lead as a rule to Degeneration; just as an
active healthy man sometimes degenerates when he becomes suddenly possessed
of a fortune; or as Rome degenerated when possessed of therichesof the ancient
9
Nordau retained this optimism in his later publications. Despite the carnage of World
War I, he maintained that war would eventually be eliminated through the taming of
the 'wolfish instincts' within humans. See Nordau, Morals and the Evolution of Man, tr.
M. A. Lewenz (London: Cassell, 1922), 183, 246.
10
London: Macmillan.
The eugenic conscience 221
world. The habit of parasitism clearly acts upon animal organisation in this way
(33).
Indeed, the moral implications of this conception of degeneracy were
never very far beneath the surface of Lankester's arguments. He
reminded his readers that 'we are subject to the general laws of
evolution, and are as likely to degenerate as to progress' (60). Such a fate
had befallen civilisations in the past, and was possible once more due to
the prevalence of 'a contented life of material enjoyment accompanied
by ignorance and superstition' (61). He looked to science to enable
people to avoid this fate: 'The full and earnest cultivation of Science -
the Knowledge of Causes - is that to which we have to look for the
protection of our race - even of this English branch of it - from relapse
and degeneration' (62).
Lankester elevated degeneracy to the status of a natural process by
demonstrating how it could occur in nature as a consequence of
evolutionary dynamics. Two points are noteworthy about his presenta-
tion of this issue. The first has already been remarked upon: the moral
judgements implicit in the criteria proposed for deciding when an
organism was degenerating. The fact that degeneration could only be
inferred from the existence of these alleged criteria gave the theorist a
great deal of latitude for interpreting change and discriminating between
elaboration, stasis or decay. The second point concerns the prescribed
role of the scientist in detecting and remedying degeneracy. If the course
of evolution was such that pathological outcomes were not only possible
but probable, then the scientist, social scientist or physician, possessed
expertise relevant to diagnosis and cure. The ground was prepared for
intervention and redirection in social affairs on the basis of scientific
expertise in order to ensure that the course of evolution remained
wholesome. Lankester himself was to underline this point in subsequent
publications in which he insisted that only scientific knowledge of
heredity and breeding could avert the potentially disastrous conse-
quences of overpopulation.11 This was exactly the message of eugenics.
Eugenics was a convenient framework for thinking about these issues.
It brought together a configuration of phenomena - crime, mental and
physical illness, poverty, moral depravity, childcare, parenthood, the
structure and functions of the family, abortion, birth control, and the
respective powers and responsibilities of public and private agencies. It
allowed these problems to be addressed either within a cosmopolitan
perspective stressing concern for the future of the entire human species
11
E. Ray Lankester, The Kingdom of Man (London: Watts and Co., 1911), 32, 35, 40-1,
53.
222 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
or, much more commonly, within a context of national or racial
consciousness in which the survival of the community was deemed
paramount. This chapter examines samples of this reasoning within four
national contexts.
Eugenics in Britain
One of the earliest calls for eugenics policies in Britain was made by a
professor of physiology, John Berry Haycraft (1857-1922) in his
Darwinism and Race Progress.12 Haycraft represented a shift towards the
more exclusive hereditarianism heralded by Weismann's theories,
rejecting any significant role for environmental factors in racial improve-
ment in favour of selection acting through the death or non-reproduc-
tion of inferior specimens, falsely claiming that Darwin himself had
gradually come to favour selection over the inheritance of acquired
characters (28). He drew attention to differential fertility rates within
advanced societies and raised the spectre of the 'swamping' of the
capable by the incapable (150). But the main thrust of his work was to
highlight the beneficial effects of fatal diseases such as smallpox,
whooping cough, tuberculosis and leprosy, which were 'friends to
humanity' because they carried off the weaker members of society.
Modern medicine and social policies, however, were eradicating these
diseases, allowing large numbers of the unfit to survive and reproduce
(50-1). It being a law of nature that the world would be dominated by
the producers of the largest number of progeny, Haycraft insisted: 'Let
us be sure that in our own nation it shall not be the offspring of the
deteriorated ...' (153). This entailed replacing 'the selection of the
microbes by the selection of human forethought' (58).
Haycraft dissociated himself from any desire to deprive individuals of
the benefits of modern medicine, but he argued that there were
additional considerations to be borne in mind, including the ramifica-
tions of medical care for the health of the race. He took heart from what
he perceived to be a diminution in the 'clamorous appeals for personal
rights' in favour of a 'growing sense of obligation and a desire to further
the interests of others' (156).
Haycraft's recommendations were for the prevention of marriage and
reproduction among those with innate criminal tendencies, and among
the 'undeserving poor' who were capable of work and should therefore
be treated as criminals (98-102). Those suffering from hereditary
defects should be segregated - though well treated - because such
12
London: Swan Sonnenschein, 1895. A translation was published in Germany with a
foreword by Weismann. See Weindling, Healthy Race and German Politics, 97.
The eugenic conscience 223
people 'are obviously unfit to perpetuate themselves, and in the best
interests of the human species, they should be prevented from so doing'
(109). He also opposed the prohibition, or restriction in the sale, of
alcohol. Though there was no evidence that alcoholism was hereditary,
it often accompanied a 'vicious temperament', which was. Excessive
alcoholic consumption was, accordingly, an excellent selective device,
one 'constantly thinning the ranks of those who are weak enough by
nature to give way to it, and leaving unharmed those with healthy tastes
and sound moral constitutions' (86).
Haycraft pointed out that in addition to the struggle for existence
between nations, making the need for a healthy nation an urgent
imperative, another struggle took place within societies for the posses-
sion of property and wealth, although this was based almost entirely on
brain-power. Success in this conflict encouraged idleness and deca-
dence, so Haycraft suggested that there was a need to equalise
conditions in order to increase competition, leading to the formation of
an aristocracy of talent recruited from all social classes (130). Although
this suggestion was left undeveloped, it was evidently not prompted by
any egalitarian sentiments, which Haycraft dismissed as 'ridiculous'. His
goal was a new class system based upon 'real organic differences',
although he warned his readers that this new elite, through its very
success in the struggle, would be likely to be selfish and devoid of
generosity (131-3). He side-stepped this issue by drawing attention to
an expansion in altruism, although he gave no clue as to the origins of
this trend. He concluded by insisting on the need to educate the masses
into an awareness of mankind's relationship to animals and to the
general laws of evolution, and on the need to prevent the marriage of the
unfit: 'If the community undertakes its own selection we can dispense
with the selective influence of the micro-organism of whooping-cough,
scarlet fever, or tubercle' (170).
Haycraft's text reproduced the four assumptions underpinning eu-
genics identified in Darwin's Descent. In addition, it drew upon the
premise of a struggle for existence between nations as justification for
the elevation of the rights of the nation over those of the individual in the
name of national survival. Another striking example of this type of
argument is afforded by the British idealist philosopher, Francis Herbert
Bradley (1846-1924). An admirer of Hegel, Bradley was opposed to
materialist and empiricist metaphysics. For him, ultimate reality - the
Absolute - was spiritual but, contra Hegel, could not be adequately
comprehended in thought but through feeling. 13 This idealist perspec-
13
See F. H. Bradley, Appearance and Reality, second edn (Oxford: Clarendon Press,
224 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
tive hardly seems compatible with Social Darwinism, and yet in a
pungently argued essay on punishment, Bradley unflinchingly adopted a
Social Darwinist position.14
Bradley declared that while Darwinism was unlikely to lead to any
revolutionary conclusions as far as the ends of morality were concerned,
it could force a radical reassessment of the means of achieving these
ends, taking us beyond Christianity back to Hellenic principles (269-
70). The Chief Good was 'the welfare of the community realised in its
members'. Darwinism demonstrated that the survival and progress of
the race in the past was due to the struggle for existence among its
members and the natural selection of the fittest. Bradley insisted that it
was impossible to reinstate this state of affairs because no community
could tolerate an unchecked struggle in its midst. At the same time, in
terms of the Chief Good, it was equally the case that the principle of
natural selection could not be totally disregarded. 'We do not deny that
progress has been made largely by natural selection, and we must admit
that in this process the extinction of the worse varieties is essential. It is
clear again that with this struggle and this extinction the community
now interferes' (271). The unchecked competition of the past was
replaced by a 'competition of fertilities' in which the 'higher types' were
being outbred by the 'weaker and lower'.
In response to this development, Bradley argued that there was an
urgent need to divorce punishment from considerations of guilt and
justice. The latter was 'but a subordinate and inferior principle. It can
hear no appeal from the tribunal of the common welfare' (276). He
stipulated the right of a community to perform 'moral surgery' on its
membership if this was required for the good of the whole. 'Once admit
that life in this world is an end in itself, and the pure Christian doctrine
is at once uprooted. For, measured by that end and standard, individuals
have unequal worth, and the value of each individual is but relative, and
in no case infinite' (277). It was meaningless to appeal to the rights of
the individual, for 'over its members the right of the moral organism is
absolute' (278).
Bradley's aim in adumbrating these arguments was to highlight the
need for eugenics - one of the cardinal lessons of Darwinism. 'It
teaches, in a word, the necessity of constant selection. It insists that the
way to improve - the way even not to degenerate - is on the whole
unchanging. That way consists in the destruction of worse categories, or
1897). For a brief but accessible introduction to Bradley's metaphysics, see J. Passmore,
A Hundred Years of Philosophy, second edn. (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1968), 60-71.
14
F. H. Bradley, 'Some Remarks on Punishment', International Journal of Ethics, 4(1894),
269-84.
The eugenic conscience 225
at least in the hindrance of such varieties from reproduction' (280). To
do otherwise was to sustain the unfit at the expense of the fit. What was
required was 'social amputation' because wholesale confinement, even
mutilation, of the worse specimens was inadequate, burdening the
community with the maintenance of 'useless lives' and condemning the
members of this latter group to a cruel existence: capital punishment
was far kinder. Bradley left his readers in no doubt as to his feelings on
this matter:
15
Second edn (London: Adam and Charles Black, 1905). The lecture was originally
delivered in Newcastle in 1900.
The eugenic conscience 227
of its 'better elements' or else it would destroy itself 'far more effectively
than its foes could ever hope to destroy it in the battlefield' (ix).
The data on army recruits demonstrated that Britain could no longer
rely upon the blind workings of natural selection to guarantee the
dominant fertility of its superior members. This was because a number
of social forces were removing or weakening the checks which 'the
unrestrained struggle for existence places on the fertility of the unfit',
while simultaneously contributing to the diminishing fecundity of the fit.
In the latter category, he hinted vaguely at 'love of ease, a mistaken sense
of duty, insidious new social habits' (viii). In the former he targeted
charitable endeavours and state welfare programmes which encouraged
the multiplication of the 'feckless and improvident', in addition to
criminals, lunatics and the chronically sick (29-30, 31). Elsewhere,
Pearson criticised minimum wage legislation, proposals for an eight-
hour working day, and the public provision of free medical advice for the
same reasons.16
Having described the world as an arena of struggle Pearson then
converted moral issues into questions of group survival. 'By moral
conduct... we mean that which tends to the welfare and progress of the
group of which we are members, and by immoral conduct the reverse'
(96-7). In this light, parenthood acquired new significance as a matter of
national importance, yet people persisted in falsely regarding it as a
realm of individual preference and choice. 'From the point of view of the
nation', insisted Pearson, 'we want to inculcate a feeling of shame in the
parents of a weakling, whether it be mentally or physically unfit' (28).
Equally at fault was the public's indulgent attitude to criminals. Crime
and 'health, sanity, conscientiousness and ability are inherited charac-
ters', but this was ignored by people who wanted to suspend the
principle of natural selection. 'A hundred years ago you hung a rogue if
you caught him. Nowadays you provide him with soup-kitchens and
night-shelters up and down the country, and leave him to propagate his
kind at will'(101).
The result of the failure to perceive these issues within the context of
national - as opposed to individual - welfare was a situation whereby the
less worthy elements in society multiplied while the stocks from which
the nation's leaders should be recruited, which Pearson estimated to be
about one half of one per cent of the population, married late and had
small families. Pearson drew a stark conclusion and, by implication,
16
Kevles, In the Name of Eugenics, 34. At the same time, Pearson was supportive of many
feminist goals, and did not subscribe to the view that women were innately inferior to
men; see Kevles, In the Name of Eugenics, 34; Soloway, Demography and Degeneration,
111-21.
228 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
offered his audience an equally stark choice: 'The problem is simple in
the extreme. We have two groups in the community - one parasitic on
the other. The latter thinks of tomorrow and is childless, the former
takes no thought and multiplies. It can only end as the case so often ends
- the parasite will kill its host, and so end the tale for both alike' (106).
Pearson hastened to add that recognition of these facts did not require
the hanging of rogues or the refusal of medical assistance to the
physically and mentally sick, only the prevention of the unfit from
reproducing themselves. His use of the expression 'parasite', however,
suggests a contemptuous and punitive attitude that is reflected in his
actual recommendations, which included sending criminals to a 'sub-
tropical climate', and the institutionalisation and strict surveillance of
paupers and the insane (105).
Pearson also attacked the dysgenic consequences of a social system
which allowed aristocrats to be recruited into important posts on the
basis of wealth rather than ability. Nevertheless, Pearson did not
propose any radical restructuring of the class system because he thought
that existing inequalities had a biological basis:
If we look upon society as an organic whole, we must assume that class
distinctions are not entirely illusory; that certain families pursue definite
occupations because they have a more or less specialised aptitude for them. In a
rough sort of way we may safely assume that the industrial classes are not on the
average as intelligent as the professional classes and that the distinction is not
entirely one of education.17
Pearson's position was that inequalities of health and education should
not be allowed to compromise the sense of national solidarity. Class
conflict was disruptive and impaired national efficiency: 'The true
statesman has to limit the internal struggle of the community in order to
make it stronger for the external struggle' (54). This struggle, involving
warfare and commercial competition with other nations and races, made
it imperative that the nation should achieve a strong sense of unity and
identity. Insisting that 'national spirit is not a thing to be ashamed of,
Pearson admonished his countrymen for their lack of patriotism. A
nation containing a large number of people imbued with fraternal regard
for the entire human species and devoid of the patriotic spirit would
experience serious difficulties in the struggle for survival (52-3).
Pearson's refusal to countenance a social explanation for the existence
and alleged proliferation of the 'unfit' was bound up with his attitudes to
class and racial inequalities, which he attributed to biological causes that
were refractory to modification through ameliorative social action. Thus
17
Pearson, The Groundwork of Eugenics (1912), 33. Cited in Jones, Social Darwinism, 114.
The eugenic conscience 229
for him the black races were inherently and therefore permanently
inferior to whites, a situation which had been brought about by selective
forces and was hence unalterable by education. Racial inter-mixing was
deleterious for the 'good stock', and even the physical proximity of
differently endowed races was demoralising. Pearson recognised that to
many people this might appear a bleak representation of the human
condition, but struggle was a law of evolution, and 'intense suffering'
was the price of progress: 'This dependence of progress on the survival
of the fitter race, terribly black as it may seem to some of you, gives the
struggle for existence its redeeming features; it is the fiery crucible out of
which comes the finer metal' (26).
Since national survival was at stake in the struggle for existence it was
vital to reverse the counter-selective policies and actions that were
swelling the numbers of the unfit. Urgent action was needed if the
'parasites' were not to overwhelm the host and destroy it. These
included the indigent, criminals, the feebleminded and insane, vagrants,
prostitutes and 'weaklings'. Their various conditions were caused by
hereditary defects, and they had to be prevented from reproducing their
kind, given the obvious dysgenic consequences this would entail.
It has been suggested that among British eugenicists, Pearson, with
his strident nationalism and his endorsement of war, was something of a
maverick.18 Yet the reasoning, as well as the tone, of Pearson's text does
not differ in essentials from those of Bradley or Haycraft. Furthermore,
an examination of seemingly more moderate proposals reveals the same
features: the subordination of the individual to the nation-state in the
interests of national survival, and a call for the reduction of the unfit as a
substitute for the seemingly defunct culling action of natural selection.
These features are fully apparent in the publications of Darwin's son,
Major Leonard Darwin (1850-1943), who was president of the British
Eugenics Education Society from 1911 to 1928. Towards the end of his
period in office, Darwin produced a lengthy tome on eugenics, followed
by a scaled-down version for more popular consumption.19 In both he
presented a Darwinian view of man as an animal that had evolved
through natural selection and about whom much could be learned by
observing the breeding practices of farmers. As with livestock, superior
humans should be encouraged to reproduce as much as possible, the
18
For comparisons between Pearson's ideas and those of other British eugenicists, see
Searle, Eugenics and Politics in Britain, 1900-1914 (Leyden: Noordhoff International
Publishing, 1976), 36-9; Soloway, Demography and Degeneration, chap. 7. Pearson only
approved of war between civilised and inferior races. Struggle between the former took
the form of competition for markets, trade-routes and raw materials.
19
L. Darwin, The Need For Eugenic Reform (London: Murray, 1926), and What is
Eugenics? (London: Watts, 1928).
230 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
inferior encouraged to reproduce less. Eugenics demonstrated that good
breeding practices were crucial to the future welfare of the country:
'Eugenics calls upon us to include all future generations amongst our
neighbours . . . for whom we ought to be prepared to sacrifice our own
immediate interests.'20
Darwin surmised that it was folly to allow 'parents with bad natural
qualities' to reproduce at a faster rate than the better endowed. 21 In the
former category he included not only the mentally and physically
handicapped, but a large 'inferior class' living on low wages, comprising
'the stupid, the careless, the inefficient, the intractable, the idle, the
habitual drunkard, as well as those too feeble in body or in health to do a
good day's work'.22 Finally, for good measure he added manual
labourers, for whom parenthood had been made less onerous than it
should be by both public and private philanthropy.23
Similar anxieties are discernible in the eugenics writings of Julian
Huxley (1887-1975), a distinguished biologist and a grandson of T. H.
Huxley. In a series of essays entitled What Dare I Think?,24 Huxley
depicted heredity as a lottery, a throw of the genetic dice determining an
individual's biological constitution and physical and mental capabilities
(74). But he went on to draw attention to the doubling of the number of
morons and defectives in Britain during the previous quarter of a
century, which he attributed to improvements in public health, infant
welfare and preventive medicine. Huxley then evoked Social Darwinism
to highlight the counter-selective impact of these measures: 'By reducing
the rigour of natural selection, we are allowing an undue proportion of
unfit types to survive.' The only 'civilised' course of action was to
prevent mental defectives from having children, though whether this was
best achieved by prohibiting marriage, by segregation or by sterilisation,
he described as not 'our present concern'. What Huxley sought was 'a
general agreement that it is not in the interests of the present
community, the race of the future, or the children who might be born to
defectives, that defectives should beget offspring' (97, 98).
Huxley constructed a gloomy scenario. He was convinced that the
genetic changes taking place in the population were for the worse, and
believed alteration of the socio-economic system, though perhaps an
ultimate goal, could only be achieved slowly, during which time
degeneration would advance unchecked. These problems all stemmed
from the fact that society had deflected the workings of natural selection
and 'without attempting to put anything in its place, has allowed harm-
ful mutations to accumulate instead of weeding them out or prevented
20 21 22
L. Darwin, What is Eugenics?, 5-12, 24. Ibid., 19. Ibid., 57, 58.
23 24
Ibid., 63-4, 70-1. London: Chatto and Windus, 1932.
The eugenic conscience 231
them from appearing, and in fine has neglected eugenic measures'
(115-16).
Huxley propounded a form of 'scientific humanism' in which
humanistic values and science could be harmonised. He did not want to
see science enthroned as a dictator to which every human value had to
be referred for approval. But he was equally opposed to the current
tendency to push certain values - for example, those pertaining to the
sanctity of life - to absolute limits. In such circumstances: 'The value of
human life becomes so absolute that it is murder to put away a deformed
monster at birth, and criminal to suggest euthanasia; and we push on
with our reduction of infant mortality until we save an excess of cripples
and defectives to breed from' (165). It was essential to realise that
humanity was implicated in a 'gigantic evolutionary experiment'.
Science could furnish 'impersonal guidance and efficient control' over
the workings of this process, and this was the responsibility and the
promise of eugenics. 'On its negative side it becomes racial preventive
medicine: on its positive side, racial hope' (119).
Although there are considerable differences in tone in the proposals of
Darwin and Huxley (who subsequently abandoned eugenics) on the one
hand, and Haycraft, Bradley and Pearson on the other, there are also a
number of striking continuities. In all of these thinkers there can be
discerned an elitism which attributed social hierarchies to differences in
biological worth; which subordinated the welfare of individuals to that of
the race or nation; and which, in the name of evolutionary science,
consigned large portions of their co-nationals to the realm of the
biologically worthless. In all of these examples, the need to improve the
race or nation - these concepts tended to be employed interchangeably -
against the pernicious actions of counter-selective practices was pro-
pounded as an evolutionary imperative. This need was invested with
added urgency by invoking the spectre of the struggle for existence in
which only the fittest, healthiest and socially efficient nations/races
would survive. Thus Huxley, during the 1920s, foresaw a time when
eugenics would become 'practical politics' and raise the quality of the
population 'by altering the proportion of good and bad stock, and if
possible eliminating the lowest strata in a genetically mixed popula-
tion'. 25 Genetics became an analytical tool for diagnosing the racial
health of the population, and Social Darwinism furnished the rationale
for eugenic intervention, while science legitimated the claim to expertise
in these matters.
26
Weindling, Race, Health and Politics, 3 9 3 - 4 .
27
K. Binding and A. E. H o c h e , Die Freigabe der Vernichtung Lebensunwerten Lebens: Ihr
Mass und Ihre Form (Leipzig: 1920). Extract in J. Noakes and G. Pridham, eds.,
Nazism, 1919-1945: A Documentary Reader, 3 vols. (University of Exeter, 1983-8), III,
1000-1.
The eugenic conscience 233
Huxley. What the shock of defeat in Germany did was produce
circumstances in which these ideas could attain widespread currency,
something which never happened in Britain or France. 28 The concept of
racial hygiene enunciated by German theorists during the early years of
the century could thus acquire added plausibility and their proposals
could achieve the urgency of racial survival. An indication of what this
would entail is contained in an internal Nazi Party memorandum
circulated by a party official, Franz von Pfeiffer, in 1925. 'No pity is to
be shown to those who occupy the lower categories of the inferior
groups: cripples, epileptics, the blind, the insane, deaf and dumb,
children born in sanatoria for alcoholics or in care, orphans (= children
born out of wedlock), criminals, whores, the sexually disturbed, etc'
Such people constituted an immense waste of resources. Hence: 'This
bottom category means destruction and death. Weighted and found
wanting. Trees which do not bear fruit should be cut down and thrown
into the fire.'29 The Third Reich provided the opportunities for the
realisation of these proposals.
Chapter 11 will examine Nazi eugenic ideology in some detail. Here I
want to explore the academic rationalisation of eugenics which linked
genetics, eugenics and race prior to the Third Reich. A good example of
this is an influential textbook on heredity.30 Written by established
experts in their fields and often highly technical and mathematical, this
text cited Ammon's work in its bibliography of 'important and
comprehensive books'. Continuity with earlier race theories was
signalled even more clearly by its approval of de Gobineau's Essay, of
which the authors observed: 'Notwithstanding manifold errors, this is an
inspired book whose fundamental ideas remain incontrovertible. It
stands unrivalled as a pioneer book on the racial problem' (706).
In a section entitled 'Racial Differences in Mankind', Eugen Fischer
(1874-1967) rejected the cranial index as a measure of race while
remaining convinced of the reality of race (117). 'Technically speaking',
28
Although both countries had supporters of radical eugenic measures. In Britain,
Winston Churchill, when H o m e Secretary, tried in 1910 to convince the Prime
Minister, Asquith, and the Cabinet, of the need for forcible sterilisation and
incarceration of the feebleminded and insane. See C. Ponting, 'Churchill's Plan for
Racial Purity', The Guardian, 20 June 1992. In France, the defeat of 1940 paved the
way for a racially inspired eugenics under the Vichy regime. See Schneider, Quality and
Quantity, chap. 10.
29
Reading no. 62 in R. Griffin, ed., Fascism (Oxford University Press, 1995), 119.
30
Bauer, Fischer and Lenz, Human Heredity. Weindling describes this book as
'authoritative in linking genetics and medicine with racial hygiene', which 'established
the scientific status of the concept of a Nordic race'. First published in 1921, it went to
a revised fifth edition in 1940. See Weindling, Health, Race and German Politics, 4 7 3 ,
306.
234 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
he wrote, 'there is no such generalised being as "man"; there are only
men and women belonging to particular races or particular racial
crossings.' This was because 'in human heredity the innumerable
characters which differentiate individuals and groups (races) are tena-
ciously and inalterably transmitted from generation to generation . . . '
(209). This held true for psychology as for physiology: 'The various
races of men differ from one another to an extraordinary degree in
mental respects no less than in bodily' (181). Mental aptitudes were
inheritable, established 'once and for all', which meant that races varied
considerably in their capabilities (130, 181).
Fischer argued that humans were descended from an anthropoid
ancestry and their evolution had been, and still was, governed by natural
selection, although the rigour of this tended to diminish with the
advance of civilisation. The extinction of races could not be accounted
for by applying the metaphors of senescence: 'The races of man no more
grow old and die than do the races of lower animals or of plants. They
can only be eliminated by selection, thus dying an unnatural death'
(183). Nor was racial inter-crossing necessarily the cause of a race's
elimination. Such crossings could be deleterious, but they also gave rise
to new varieties and were a source of regeneration and development
(182). The answer he gave was one of a 'reverse selection' which altered
the racial composition of a people and deprived it of effective leadership,
thus making it a less functional biological unit. The author hinted darkly
that the present fate of Germany had precisely such an 'anthropological
cause' (183). 'We are coming to recognise more and more clearly', he
wrote, 'that racial factors, and especially hereditary mental endowments
. . . are among the most influential in determining the course of a
nation's history' (182).
These themes were extended in the contributions by Lenz, professor
of racial hygiene at the University of Munich. Like many of his
countrymen, Lenz was affected by an acute sense of crisis brought about
by Germany's defeat in the Great War. Faced with the contingency and
transience of human values and achievements he looked to race for
permanence and certainty.31
Lenz contended that the distinction between health and sickness
turned upon the adaptational capacity of an organism. However, he
made it clear that the significance of this distinction lay in its bearing
upon 'racial rather than individual survival' (216). 'Thus every adapta-
tion upon which we make the concepts of health and disease turn, is in
the last analysis directed towards the preservation not of the individual
31
Weindling, Health, Race and German Politics, 302-3.
The eugenic conscience 235
but of the race. Individual-survival is only a means to the end of race-
survival' (216).
What did Lenz mean by race? In constructing a racial classification, he
disclaimed any intention of ranking races in a hierarchy because this
implied a standard of value other than race itself (696-7). But the entire
thrust of his analysis of racial differences was aimed at precisely the
creation of such a hierarchy, and then to draw out the implications of
this for the future of Germany. The criteria he adopted for this task were
psychological, on the grounds that the mental differences between races
were even more pronounced than bodily differences and equally rooted
in heredity to the extent that environmental influences, including
education, 'can do no more than help or hinder the flowering of
hereditary potentialities5. Lenz completely rejected the inheritance of
acquired characters and insisted on the need to abandon Lamarckian
prejudices in order to arrive at an accurate understanding of the genetic
determinants of race (565, 604, 607). Notwithstanding the scholarly
apparatus deployed by Lenz, his classification reproduced all the
standard racial prejudices and stereotypes found in the writings of de
Gobineau, Lapouge and Chamberlain.
At the bottom of his scale Lenz located 'primitive races', such as the
Veddahs and Australian Blackfellows, whom he described as feeble-
minded and 'closely akin to our simian forefathers' (628). The negro
races he considered more advanced than primitives, but lacking in
foresight and initiative, influenced by their senses, unintelligent and
displaying many of the mental traits of children (628-34). In his
description of the next level, Lenz succeeded in combining racial
stereotypes with shibboleths on gender. Mongoloids were hard-working
and frugal, but unimaginative. They related to Europeans in the same
way as women to men, 'for Mongols are receptive rather than creative;
and are at the same time frugal, contented, and patient' (634-9).
After describing a series of 'intermediary' races, Lenz reached the
summit of the hierarchy, the Nordic race, which created the Aryan
languages and civilisation (647-61). The Nordic possessed great
intelligence and creativity, enormous energy and a vivid imagination,
but was an individualist, devoid of a sense of community. 'The Nordic
finds it difficult to put himself in another's place. His instincts are
individualistic rather than social, his craving for independence makes
him resist being enrolled in a community.' Above all, the Nordic was
motivated by a will-to-power and proclivity for war, tempered by an
aristocratic capacity for self-restraint (658-9).
The implication that individualism was a vice mirrored the claim that
the individual was only a means to the end of racial survival. But from
236 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
whence did the threats to this survival derive? Lenz was far from explicit
on this point. One such threat obviously came from people afflicted with
hereditary diseases. But the physical and mental descriptions of the
Nordic race, and Lenz's concentration on the racial divisions within
Europe, were redolent with other implications. Some of these appeared
in his discussion of Jews. According to Lenz the Jews were not a unified
race, but their solidarity and closedness made them something of a
'mental' race. They possessed a great talent for economic activities, and
were capable of intellectual greatness, as shown by Einstein. Indeed,
Lenz went so far as to argue: 'Next to the Teutonic, the Jewish spirit is
the chief motive force of modern civilisation' (674). But these positive
assessments were interspersed with familiar negative stereotypes. Thus
Jews lived within other cultures, which they mimicked; they induced
other races to accept Jewish leadership; they were averse to physical
labour and inept at warfare. They were partially composed of the Near
Eastern race, 'which has been selected to excel, not so much in the
control and the exploitation of nature, as in the control and exploitation
of man' (644). Lenz maintained that whereas the Jew could not exist
without the Teuton, the latter would be perfectly capable of getting
along without the Jew (677). While such comments were not so overtly
disparaging as the more virulent anti-Semitic rhetoric of the period, they
relied upon a similar set of contrasts with the psychic disposition of the
Nordic race, against which they acted mainly as a negative counterpoint.
Thus Lenz, who maintained that racial mixing could be advantageous,
insisted that the reverse was true if the races were widely divergent and,
in spite of his acknowledgements of Jewish achievements, condemned
the crossing of Teutons and Jews (692-3).
For Lenz, the realities of racial and other hereditary differences
rendered idealistic dreams of equality biologically untenable: 'The
inequalities among human beings are mainly dependent upon the
hereditary equipment, and this cannot be transformed in any simple way
either by material or by spiritual influences. In the individual it cannot
be changed at all, and in the race it can only be changed by selection'
(698). This did not justify inaction on the part of a nation. To the
contrary, membership of a superior race should not lull one into a false
sense of security, because the 'biological heritage of the mind' is just as
perishable as that of the body. 'If we continue to squander that biological
heritage as we have been squandering it during the last few decades, it
will not be many generations before we cease to be the superiors of the
Mongols. Our ethnological studies must lead us, not to arrogance, but
to action - to eugenics' (698).
Lenz was convinced that the reason for the collapse of classical
The eugenic conscience 237
civilisation was to be sought in the 'extermination of the creative racial
elements' responsible for their achievements (696). His views contain
the same mixture of elitism and biological reductionism that occur in the
writings of the British eugenicists and Lapouge and, as we shall see, the
American Stoddard. Moreover, selection and struggle were implied to
be forces of preservation rather than change. A politics geared towards
guarding the forces of nature against subversive social practices was
offered as the only hope for the future. The consequences of this politics
were to be fully realised under the Third Reich.
The USA
Eugenics took hold in the USA more so than in any European nation
excepting Nazi Germany, which expressed great interest in American
policies and practices.36 The state of Indiana enacted the first sterilisa-
tion law in 1907; by 1933 twenty-nine other states had followed suit,
although three states had by then repealed their acts. 37 At this time,
officially over 16,000 people had been sterilised, many involuntarily.
Furthermore, recent research has shown that these practices did not
disappear with the discrediting of eugenics after revelations of Nazi
excesses, but continued until well after the conclusion of World War II
into the 1970s.38 On this evidence some scholars have surmised that the
real magnitude of enforced sterilisation in the USA between 1907 and
1974 involved hundreds of thousands of victims.39 Despite the consider-
able amount of research devoted to American eugenics, the success of
36
T h e connections between Nazi and U S eugenics are documented in S. Kuhl, The Nazi
Connection ( N e w York/Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994).
37
Kevles, In the Name of Eugenics, 100; Report of the Departmental Committee on
Sterilisation, C m d . 4 4 8 5 (London: H M S O , 1933), 3 5 , 1 0 9 - 1 2 .
38
According to the Channel Four T V documentary of 17 February 1994, 'The
Lynchburg Story', involuntary sterilisations of inmates of an institution in Lynchburg,
Virginia, continued until 1972. In all, some 8,300 people were sterilised, primarily
young, white vagrants, paupers, petty criminals and the 'feebleminded'. T h e rationale
for this policy was the prevention of racial deterioration and the promotion of national
success in the struggle for existence.
39
For an analysis of eugenics in the U S A which estimates sterilisations in hundreds of
thousands, see A. Chase, The Legacy of Malthus ( N e w York: Knopf, 1980). For an
overview of the evidence see A. Cockburn, 'Social Cleansing', New Statesman and
Society, 5 August 1994, 1 6 - 1 8 .
The eugenic conscience 243
these policies in a nation which prides itself on its tradition of
individualism and personal freedom still requires an adequate explana-
tion. As with other eugenics movements discussed in this chapter, my
concern is not with American eugenics per se but with the interaction
between eugenic ideas and Social Darwinism. The treatment is selective
but aims to convey the flavour of this interaction.
One of the earliest supporters of eugenics has already been encoun-
tered in an earlier chapter, the feminist and radical Victoria Woodhull.
By the time she published her eugenicist views Woodhull was residing in
England and had tempered much of her earlier radicalism. But her
writings of the early 1890s anticipated most of the themes propounded
by later eugenicists. Woodhull demanded that artificial laws should be
predicated upon the laws of nature, and called for a new religion based
upon scientific truths.40 Insisting that criminality, feeblemindedness and
pauperism were hereditary and incurable, she argued that the current
growth of these phenomena was contrary to the survival of the fittest.41
It was imperative, therefore, that nations refrain from breeding from the
unfit and instead encourage the breeding of the fit, which she heralded
as the 'first principle of the breeder's art'. There was no reason why
societies could not be organised so as to assign prominence to this
principle. This entailed a new creed that would 'make a religion of the
procreative principle'.42 But it also required governmental policies
aimed at preventing the birth of unfit people. 'A humanitarian govern-
ment', opined Woodhull, 'would stigmatise the marriages of the unfit as
crimes; it would legislate to prevent the birth of the criminal rather than
legislate to punish him after he is born.' 43 False ideas of liberty which
permitted the procreation of the unfit imposed a heavy burden on the
provident who had to support them. 'And it is these false ideas of liberty
which makes the struggle for existence so terrible.' 44 Moreover,
Woodhull did not confine the label of unfit to the urban underclass, but
gave it an additional racial signification. Thus, in contrast to her youthful
support for the enfranchisement of blacks, she asked rhetorically:
'Eventually, if America is owned and governed by negroes, would it be
the survival of the fittest?'45
40
Victoria C. Woodhull, Humanitarian Government (London: no pub., 1890), 25, 29.
41
Ibid., 30; Woodhull, The Rapid Multiplication of the Unfit (London/New York: no pub.,
1891), 18.
42
Woodhull, Rapid Multiplication, 38, 39.
43 44
Woodhull, Humanitarian Government, 49. Ibid., 55.
45
Woodhull, Rapid Multiplication, 18-19. For Woodhull's earlier support of black (and
female) suffrage, see her Origin, Tendencies and Principles of Government, 38-40c. In
1872 Woodhull had nominated herself the presidential candidate of her Equal Rights
Party and asked the black leader Frederick Douglas to stand as her running mate.
Douglas ignored the request - wisely as it happened, since Woodhull spent the election
244 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
Woodhull did not develop her eugenic proposals in any detail and her
writings did not sustain a consistently hereditarian position since she
sometimes attributed indigence, alcoholism, crime and illness to
environmental conditions. But her eugenic publications were a remark-
able anticipation, both in substance and tone, of later eugenicists such as
D. Colin Wells (1858-1911). In a provocative conference paper entitled
'Social Darwinism',46 Wells advocated the application of Darwinian
evolutionary theory 'to the investigation of the manner in which social
institutions and doctrines influence the competition, elimination,
survival of individuals and groups of individuals' (697). He postulated
that natural selection had been superseded by social selection, and that
'society is the sieve by which human beings are sifted ...' (698). This
prompted the question of what kind of persons were favoured by the
selective actions of modern industrial societies. Wells' response was
gloomy but predictable, namely that modern conditions reversed the
action of natural selection and favoured the multiplication of the unfit.
He then linked this claim to an attack on contemporary political and
social developments. Trade unionism, socialism, heavy taxation, urbani-
sation and higher education for women were all implicated in facilitating
the postponement of marriage and small families among the worthier
sections of society coupled with the survival and procreation of the
'incapable and weak' (702). Thus while Wells possessed a more
sophisticated knowledge of Darwinian theory that Woodhull, and was
conversant with current (particularly European) theoretical develop-
ments, his paper displayed essentially the same concerns: the substitu-
tion of social for natural selection and a concomitant multiplication of
the unfit.
The continuity of these themes in eugenic discourses is illustrated by
The Revolt Against Civilisation by Lothrop Stoddard (b. 1883), a text
which was popular in Britain and the USA and which appeared in
German translation.47 Stoddard's theme was the racial impoverishment
that he deemed to be endemic to modern civilisation. Civilisation was
the consequence of 'the creative urge of superior germ-plasm. Civilisa-
tion is thus fundamentally conditioned by race' (2). The progress from
animality through savagery and barbarism to civilisation was an uneven
one, with many races confined to the earlier phases of evolution. Only
superior races reached civilisation, and within them it was the actions of
in jail on an adultery charge. See G. Blodgett, 'Victoria Woodhull', Notable American
Women 1607-1950: A Biographical Dictionary (Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press, 1971),
III, 654.
46
Published in The American Journal of Sociology, 12(1907), 6 9 5 - 7 0 8 .
47
L o n d o n : C h a p m a n and Hall, 1922. T h e G e r m a n edition was published in 1925. See
Weindling, Healthy Race and German Politics, 3 1 1 .
The eugenic conscience 245
an elite which caused advancement. Elite qualities were hereditary -
Stoddard completely rejected the inheritance of acquired characters -
and were developed through natural selection. Unfortunately, with
civilisation natural selection was substituted by social selection allowing
the weak and degenerate to thrive and reproduce. Hence 'instead of
dying at the base and growing at the top, civilised society was dying at
the top and spreading out below' (18).
Stoddard enumerated several types of inferior person. There were
savages and barbarians, people who were arrested at early evolutionary
phases and therefore congenitally incapable of achieving civilisation.
Then there were true 'degenerates' - the insane and neurotic - and
finally the 'border-liners', consisting of those with 'neither the wit nor
the moral fibre to meet the sterner demands of high, complex civilisa-
tions'. Collectively, these inferior specimens constituted the 'Under-
Men', 'the vast army of the unadaptable and incapable' (21). They
represented a reservoir of potential discontent; inimical to the demands
of civilised existence, they were a threat to social order and had to be
controlled (23). Failure to do so would result in revolution.
Invoking an 'iron law of inequality', Stoddard insisted that the IQ
tests performed by the US Army on 1.7 million servicemen during
World War I demonstrated conclusively that intelligence was hereditary
(52). The declining birth-rates in the upper echelons of American
society, accompanied by the high rate of reproduction among the lower,
meant that 'intelligence is today being steadily bred out of the American
population' (64, original emphasis). The Under-Man was on the
increase while the racially valuable elements responsible for civilisation
were declining. Since the Under-Man was unconvertible to the demands
of civilisation Stoddard concluded - in terms reminiscent of those used
by Lombroso - that 'we have among us a rebel army - the vast host of
the unadaptable, the incapable, the envious, the discontented, filled with
instinctive hatred of civilisation and progress, and ready on the instant to
rise in revolt' (80-1). The world was in fact a vast battleground - the war
against chaos (202-3).
Faced with this problem, Stoddard ruled out any possibility of
returning to natural selection. The solution was to be found in eugenics,
which was 'an improved social selection based upon natural law ...' (86,
original emphasis). Social rebels - by which he apparently meant
Bolsheviks - should be 'hunted down and extirpated' (215). As for
degenerates, Stoddard was a firm advocate of negative eugenics on the
grounds that: 'Race cleansing is the obvious starting-point for race
betterment' (226). He proposed that habitual paupers should be
prevented from having children, while the insane and feebleminded
246 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
should be institutionalised or sterilised and birth control encouraged
among other inferior groups. This entailed the emergence of new social
ideals through the development of the 'eugenic conscience', which
would also 'impel the well-endowed to raise larger families, prefer
children to luxuries' and think more of duties than of rights (236).
Stoddard was unquestionably a hardliner on eugenic issues. He met
German eugenicists such as Lenz and Fischer as well as Nazi politicians
like Himmler, and continued to enthuse over Nazi eugenic and racial
measures into the 1940s. 48 It would be wrong, however, to dismiss him
as a marginal figure in American eugenics. The racist and elitist
perspectives which grounded Stoddart's eugenic proposals were
common to all the American and European examples considered in this
chapter. Equally common was the Social Darwinism which was
employed to explain the proliferation of the unfit through the suspension
or obstruction of natural selection. The continuity of these themes in the
overwhelming majority of eugenicist arguments is attested by the
appearance, in 1949, of a biology textbook by Garrett Hardin (b.
1915). 49 In the final chapter of this text, Hardin reported data which
purported to show that the birth-rate was negatively correlated with
educational attainment. Since higher education signified high IQ, and
the latter was partly due to heredity, then Hardin concluded that under
present social arrangements 'there will be a slow but continuous downward
trend in the average intelligence' (612, original emphasis). 50
Hardin's response to this trend was more nuanced than that of
Stoddard. Nevertheless, he argued: 'It is difficult, on rational grounds,
to object to the sterilisation of the feebleminded' (613). Similarly, he
proposed that only full knowledge of their public responsibilities - the
'eugenic conscience'? - would encourage high IQ individuals to have
more children (615). People needed to be aware of the selective
consequences of their actions: 'When one saves a starving man, one may
thereby help him to breed more children' (619). Hardin's conclusion
was that 'the logic of our situation is clear. Either there must be a
relatively painless weeding out before birth or a more painful and
wasteful elimination of individuals after birth' (618). The language may
have been more sophisticated than Stoddard's, but the concerns of both
he and Hardin were similar, as were their diagnoses and recommenda-
48
Kiihl, The Nazi Connection, 53, 59-63.
49
Biology: Its Human Implications (San Francisco: Freeman and Co., 1949).
50
There is a clear continuity in American concern with what is currently referred to as the
'dumbing down' of the population, exhibited in the writings of Wells, Stoddard and
Hardin and its most recent advocates, Murray and Hernnstein. See C. Murray and
R. J. Hernnstein, The Bell Curve: Intelligence and Class Structure in American Life (New
York: Free Press, 1994).
The eugenic conscience 247
tions. In this they were part of an international tradition of eugenicist
thinking which typically drew upon Darwinian premisses for its
support.51
Conclusion
Soloway's verdict on British eugenics as a biological way of thinking
about socio-economic, political and cultural change, has a wider
relevance.52 The biology in question was invariably Darwinian, with its
stress on inheritance, selection and survival of the fittest. In eugenics
discourses the unit of concern became the race, a term which could still
be used in a number of senses, even by the same theorist, but which
increasingly tended to be conceived as a biological entity whose defining
traits were resistant to cultural forces. The fusion of eugenics, racial
theories and Social Darwinism, therefore, produced a graphic picture in
which racial survival in a world of incessant conflict was predicated upon
the maintenance of a healthy population purged of those elements which
threatened its integrity. Given the increasing tendency of Social
Darwinists to present collectivities rather than individuals as the agents
of adaptation and survival and thus to assign moral priority to the group,
these developments provided a powerful rationale for policies aimed at
the elimination of racially undesirable elements.
The fit between eugenics and Social Darwinism was a coherent one
because most proponents divorced natural selection from cultural
processes. Darwin, it will be recalled, derived altruism - and hence
charitable institutions and policies - from social and moral sentiments
that developed through natural selection, resulting in ambivalence
towards the maintenance of the unfit. Subsequent eugenicists invariably
depicted a rupture between nature and culture: natural selection had
been replaced by selective forces which were social in origin and which
usually acted contrary to the former. Eugenic policies were, in contrast,
social practices modelled upon the workings of nature.
Yet the effect of this device was, as we saw with Lapouge, to break the
continuity between nature and culture which was central to Social
51
The vitality of eugenics is evidenced by its continuing relevance in the modern era.
China embarked upon a eugenics programme in 1995 as part of its policy of birth
control. See Linda Jakobson, 'China Brings in Tough Law to Stamp Out Birth
Defects', Guardian, 6 June 1995. In the West, welfare cutbacks in Britain and the U S A ,
coupled with advances in genetic engineering, have aroused interest in the 'new
eugenics'. See Cockburn, 'Social Cleansing', and D . King, 'The State of Eugenics',
New Statesman and Society, 25 August 1995. Though the context of these policies
differs from pre-World War II, it would be interesting to examine their relationship to
Social Darwinism.
52
Soloway, Demography and Degeneration, xviii.
248 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
Darwinist thought. Cultural practices arose which were not only
inexplicable on Darwinist principles but which overrode the supposedly
ineluctable laws of nature. Thus eugenics was harmonised with Social
Darwinism by depicting nature as a model rather than a threat, with
social practices and values portrayed as the source of pathology. But the
virulence of the latter was such that nature itself seemed threatened
unless bolstered by social intervention.
10 Social Darwinism, nature and sexual
difference
Introduction
Sexual - like racial - characteristics have visible manifestations capable
of being ordered and classified, read as symbols for other differences,
and assigned values. Concern with such characteristics, both physical
and mental, and with their meaning, have a long pedigree in Western
thought. What invested this concern with particular urgency from the
mid-nineteenth century on was the interface of two processes: political
agitation for female emancipation and a reinterpretation of nature.
The growth of movements throughout Europe and the USA dedicated
to the extension of civil and political rights to women created an intense
interest in what became known, both to sympathisers and opponents, as
the 'Woman Question'.1 These movements challenged prevailing
notions of the appropriate division of labour between the sexes and in so
doing raised issues about the respective 'nature' of men and women and
the extent to which these natures were biologically or culturally
determined. Feminism, therefore, posed a comprehensive and dis-
turbing challenge in ways not matched by class or even racial issues. As
Cynthia Eagle Russett has argued, it not only encompassed education,
occupation and legal issues, but intruded into such intimate areas as
personal and matrimonial relationships.2
The debate was complicated by the fact that while nature often acted
as a court of appeal for the protagonists, the understanding of nature
was itself undergoing a transformation. There was a long-standing
tendency - general if not universal - to personify nature as a female, as at
once both a physical and spiritual presence, nurturing, caring and erotic.
But this imagery, as much a conception of femininity as of nature, had
been undergoing revision even prior to the publication of the Origin.
The palaeontological record had disclosed the impermanence of species,
1
For the development of women's emancipation movements, see R. J. Evans, The
Feminists (London: Croom Helm, 1977).
2
C. E. Russett, Sexual Science (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989), 10.
249
250 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
revealing a fossilised chronicle of elimination and extinction.3 This was
accompanied by a shift in the image of woman/nature, evident in
Tennyson's 'In Memoriam' (1850). Here nature was still represented as
a female, but one 'red in tooth and claw', not a nurse but a monstrous
and impersonal agent of death which even destroyed her own depen-
dants. Hence this reassessment of nature was mediated through a
revaluation of femininity in which woman was conceived as a much
more threatening and subversive figure.4
Yet this symbolisation of nature was nuanced, with the angel of death
imagery sometimes juxtaposed with a more nurturing and optimistic
representation, as is evident in Tennyson's great poem, where the red in
tooth and claw portrait of nature in stanzas LIV-LVI contrasts with the
more optimistic imagery of stanza CXVIII.5 This dualism and the
tension it reflects were reproduced within Darwinism itself, as I have
frequently argued. It also resonated an additional set of images
surrounding the notion of womanhood and the revisions to this notion
occasioned by women's fight for emancipation. It is for this reason,
perhaps, that the ambivalent status of nature as both model and threat is
particularly pronounced in Social Darwinist discourses on women.
Modern feminist historiography has tended to depict Social Darwin-
ism (and nineteenth-century science in general) as broadly supportive of
patriarchal values and as reinforcing traditional gender stereotypes.6
Even feminist appropriations of Social Darwinism are perceived as
succumbing to these stereotypes in that their promotion of women's
causes was premissed on notions of distinctive but complementary
sexual difference.7 These interpretations are surely correct; evolutionary
science was enlisted in the cause of patriarchy. But this is not the whole
story and I shall argue that Social Darwinism could be, and was, turned
against patriarchy and conventional Victorian views on gender. More-
over, some of the most innovative and influential efforts in this direction
were made by women themselves. In arguing thus I am developing a
point made some years ago by Rosaleen Love, namely that women
28
Royer, ' L a Natalite', suppressed p a p e r to the Societe d'Anthropologie de Paris, July
1874. F o r details of this paper, a n d an analysis of its c o n t e n t s , see Harvey, 'Strangers to
E a c h O t h e r ' , 1 6 0 - 1 , 3 2 2 , n o t e 2.
29
Harvey, 'Strangers to E a c h O t h e r ' , 160, 165.
30
T h i s merging has already b e e n signalled by Rosaleen Love in her study of G i l m a n a n d
Schreiner, ' D a r w i n i s m a n d F e m i n i s m ' , 120.
31
E. B. Gamble, The Evolution of Woman: An Enquiry into the Dogma of Her Inferiority to
Man (New York/London: Putnam's Sons, 1894). I have been unable to ascertain any
details of Gamble's career and background.
Social Darwinism, nature and sexual difference 261
that Sexual Selection comes into play, then she is the primary cause of the very
characters through which man's superiority over woman has been gained. As a
stream may not rise higher than its source, or as the creature may not surpass its
creator in excellence, it is difficult to understand the process by which man,
through Sexual Selection, has become superior to woman (29).
Gamble's alternative account of sexual difference maintained that
natural selection evolved the maternal instinct in females which then,
through sexual selection, became the foundation of parental bonding
and all the social sentiments among humans (62). This was brought
about through female choice of mates which not only selected for these
qualities, but which also produced the distinctively male attributes of
energy, perseverance and courage - to which Gamble contrasted the
feminine traits of perception, intuition and endurance (65). This choice
was still exercised in primitive tribes where the independence of women
had often been misconstrued as evidence of promiscuity by ethnogra-
phers (91-8).
Gamble insisted that primitive tribal structures were democratic and
solidaristic, with land held in common and descent reckoned through
women, who enjoyed high status and autonomy (109-21). Male
domination occurred with the emergence of wife-capture and the
development of private property in land (140). Marriage then became
based upon 'the power of a man over a woman and her offspring' (166),
and women were reduced to the status of a possession. Since then,
women had been subjected to the vilest slavery in which they had been
systematically denied opportunities to develop their talents and were
exposed to an 'excessive and useless maternity' (52), a position from
which they were beginning to emerge although there was still a great
deal to be done (347-8).
Gamble's treatise made novel use of sexual selection for the purpose
of underlining the injustice of female subordination. For her, nature
provided a model for the organisation of social relations and sexual
selection based upon female mate selection should be once again
allowed full expression. Gamble contended that the 'unnatural' condi-
tion of women illustrated how the survival of the fittest did not
necessarily produce success for the best endowed (73). Indeed, she
suggested that the restoration of sexual selection could even produce the
elimination of the struggle for existence. She contemplated a future
social condition in which 'man will no longer struggle with man for
place or power, and that the bounties of the earth will no longer be
hoarded by the few, while the many are suffering for the necessities of
life; for are we not all members of one family, and dependent for all that
we have on the same beneficent parent - Nature?' (78). In this imagery,
262 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
nature is benevolent and women its true representatives and guardians.
Yet the above passage also suggests a tension already encountered in
other theorists, for natural selection is also one of nature's laws, and
Gamble's comments indicate an ambivalence towards the struggle for
existence and its social consequences. The dark side of nature is still
present in Gamble's reinterpretation of sexual selection, just as it was for
Darwin.
This dark side was also evident in the work of Charlotte Perkins
Gilman (1860-1935), the American novelist, poet and social theorist.
Gilman was a feminist and a socialist, an avid reader of popular science,
and influenced by the sociology of Ward. The interests converged in her
Women and Economics (1898), a biting attack on the subordinate status
of contemporary women which achieved a very wide readership, having
been reprinted seven times by the early 1920s and translated into seven
languages.32 In this text Gilman argued that in primitive times both
women and men were agile, independent and strong, qualities evolved
through natural selection. The male was larger and more ferocious
because he fought with other males for the right to mate; females
selected the victors. At a certain point in time, the male realised that it
was easier to fight a small female than a large male, and so enslaved the
female, depriving her of her independence. From then on women,
confined to narrow domestic functions, were excluded from the direct
action of natural selection. Instead, they developed only the faculties of
sexual attraction required to secure a mate and ensure being fed.
Fortunately, this situation was not irremediable due to the action of
heredity. 'Heredity has no Sallic Law' (58). Each girl inherited some of
her father's abilities: hence 'the daughter of the soldier and the sailor, of
the artist, the inventor, the great merchant, has inherited in body and
brain her share of his development in each generation, and so stayed
somewhat human for all her femininity' (59).
When Gilman wrote: 'There are other purposes before us besides
mere maintenance and reproduction' (55), she did so in painful personal
awareness of the psychic costs to women caused by their imprisonment
in these roles, an awareness used to harrowing effect in her fiction.33
The argument about the relationship between natural and sexual
selection, however, was developed in her The Man-Made World,
published in 1911.34 Here Gilman proposed that there were sexual traits
32
Love, ' D a r w i n i s m a n d F e m i n i s m ' , n o t e 4, 128. T h e text u s e d here is the extract in
Hollinger and Capper, American Intellectual Tradition, II, 5 5 - 6 0 .
33
C . P . G i l m a n , The Yellow Wallpaper [1892] ( L o n d o n : Virago, 1983).
34
C. P. Gilman, The Man-Made World Or Our Androcentric Culture (London: Fisher
Unwin, 1911).
Social Darwinism, nature and sexual difference 263
specific to males and females, but there were also common traits
deriving from a shared humanity: 'Woman's natural work as a female is
that of the mother; man's natural work as a male is that of the father.
Every handicraft, every profession, every science, every art, all govern-
ment, education, religion, the whole living world of human achievement
- all this is human' (27).
Gilman's thesis was that the original relations between the sexes were
matriarchal, due to the principle of female mate selection. This was
subverted by the enslavement of women and their conversion into
possessions, with the concomitant usurpation of their economic activ-
ities and the conversion of the family into a patriarchal institution (36-
40). As a result, in a history both made and recorded by men, specifically
male attributes had become identified with human nature per se (20, 24).
The human species thus represented an aberration in the natural
order for, according to Gilman, it was the only one where the male
selected females and where the female was dependent for her livelihood
on the male (64-5). The outcome was a situation in which females were
excluded from the action of natural selection, while males escaped the
effects of sexual selection. 'Nothing was required of woman by natural
selection save such capacity as should please her master; nothing was
required of the man by sexual selection save power to take by force, or
buy, a woman' (56). The impact on the race could not fail to be
deleterious. 'Nature did not intend him [the male] to select; he is not
good at it. Neither was the female intended to compete - she is not good
at it' (34-5). By 'compete' Gilman was not referring to the struggle for
existence within a certain milieu but to the exercise of what she saw as
peculiarly male impulses to fight and destroy (117). Whereas women
originally organised for gathering and maternal activities, men organised
for hunting and, later, for warfare (186). Hence warfare was not a
human but a male process for eliminating the unfit, whereas by contrast:
'The female process is to select the fit; her elimination is negative and
painless.' Gilman continued: 'Greater than either is the human process,
to developfitness'(190, original emphasis).
This equation of warfare with masculinity points to a contradiction in
Gilman's analysis. She argued that a number of contemporary evils were
the product of the exclusive action of male traits. Thus punishment was
androcentric, based on the principle of if hit, hit back harder; for
Gilman, apart from the odd pervert, criminals were made rather than
born, hence punishment was archaic (205, 210-12). Similarly, laissez-
faire and economic competition reflected the spirit of the predatory
male. Thus economic development was hindered 'by this artificially
maintained "struggle for existence", this constant endeavour to elim-
264 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
inate what, from a masculine standard, is "unfit"' (251). Gilman
insisted that life consisted of growth and combat belonged to lower
levels of existence (228). But this raised the issue of how, if at all, natural
selection operated in ideal modern social circumstances. In Woman and
Economics Gilman extolled the action of natural selection when it acted
upon both sexes 'with inexorable and beneficial effect' to develop the
species (56). In the later text, she tended to equate the forces of natural
selection with maleness, which then obstructed the development of the
'human instinct of mutual service' (246). Industry, on the other hand,
portrayed as a human sphere in the clarification of male, female and
human nature cited earlier, became attributed to women, later to be
perverted by the male spirit of competitiveness (242).
These oscillations suggest that Gilman, like many radicals and
reformers, was unhappy with the idea of natural selection continuing to
hold sway in culturally advanced societies based upon equality and
mutual cooperation. Nonetheless, her ideal did not require a complete
abandoning of evolutionary laws because she believed that sexual
equality would augment the action of sexual selection in species
development. Equality would restore the primacy of female choice and
men who were not selected for fatherhood would not be eliminated but
would still be able to pursue full human lives (256).
Gamble and Gilman were creative in their adaptation of sexual
selection for the feminist cause, and pioneering to the extent that only
fairly recently has sexual selection been assigned prominence in Social
Darwinism. Their strategy consisted in constructing biologically evolved
sexual natures which were then stultified or perverted by social
processes. In both instances, though, the remedies sought were social
and political, and the normative standards, while still set by nature,
reflected a nature seemingly shorn of the pernicious effects of natural
selection. Thus Gilman became an opponent of eugenics - the attempt
to pattern social upon natural selection - which she castigated as a
'primal process of promoting evolution through the paternity of the
conquering male . . . ' (250).35 Her hostility to eugenics may have been
well founded, for it has been suggested that the adoption of eugenics by
the women's movements in Germany gradually led to a weakening
(though not a total renunciation) of their radical emancipatory pro-
grammes.36 Yet my last example, though Swedish rather than German,
shows that some women found it possible to unite Social Darwinism
and eugenics with feminism, socialism and pacifism.
35
See also G i l m a n ' s ' R e s p o n s e to Wells' "Social D a r w i n i s m " ' , The American Journal of
Sociology, 1 2 ( 1 9 0 6 - 7 ) , 7 1 3 - 1 4 .
36
See R. J. E v a n s , Rethinking German History ( L o n d o n : H a r p e r C o l l i n s , 1987), 2 2 6 - 9 .
Social Darwinism, nature and sexual difference 265
Conclusion
The literature scrutinised in this chapter shows that Social Darwinism
was certainly enlisted in the defence of patriarchy, but that this was not
its exclusive function. The world view was also used in the service of
feminism and some of its most notable adaptations were by women
writers. Their theories were not devoid of tensions and aporia, but I
have argued that these were similar to those encountered in much Social
Darwinist thought, particularly if of a radical orientation. The evidence
suggests that at least some women experienced Darwinism as an
enlightening and emancipatory intellectual current containing the
potential for alternative - i.e. gynaecocentric - evolutionary histories.
The radicalism displayed in the attacks by Gamble, Gilman and Key
on monogamy and marriage, and in their gynaecocentrism, is apparent
57
See, for example, E. Faguet, Le Feminisme (Paris: Societe Francaise d'lmprimerie et de
Librairie, 1910). The chapter entitled 'L'Anarchie morale' contains an attack on Key's
views on these topics.
270 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
58
London/New York: Macmillan. This book went tofiveeditions by 1921, and expanded
to three volumes.
Social Darwinism, nature and sexual difference 271
Positing an evolutionary foundation for sexual difference these theorists
then looked to one of the sexes as the seedbed of future change - change
which was sometimes presented as a development, perhaps even
transformation, of the laws governing evolution itself.
This strategy is clearly exemplified in another female writer, the poet
Mathilde Blind (1841-96). Blind's family were Germans exiled to
England after the abortive insurrection of 1848, and her poetry often
reflects a radical political persuasion. She was also influenced by
Darwinism, which is clearly in evidence in her The Ascent of Man
(1889).59 Here she graphically described the struggle for existence as a
relentless slaughter - 'A dreadful war, where might is right, / Where still
the strongest slay and win, / Where weakness is the only sin' (12-13).
Humanity was forged through this process, and the struggle for life was
continued by man against man. However, Blind found the manner in
which this struggle was culturally represented (to the benefit of the rich
and powerful) hypocritical. 'Better far for the plain, carnivorous fashion/
Which is practiced in the lion's den' (104). At times, a powerful feeling
of meaninglessness and despair pervaded the poem, for example, 'Life is
but a momentary blunder / In the cycle of the Universe' (105). Yet Blind
finished on an optimistic note, proclaiming the triumph of God and
Love from man's martyrdom. The explanation for this transcendence of
blind struggle and carnage was vague, but hinted that it would appear
through the agency of women:
O redeem mefrommy tiger rages,
Reptile greed, and foul hyaena lust;
With the hero's deeds, the thoughts of sages,
Sow andfructifythe passive dust;
Drop in dew and healing love of woman
On the bloodstained hands of hungry strife,
Till there breakfrompassion of the Human
Morning - glory of transformed life (109).
Blind's poem reproduces two themes highlighted in the analysis of
female Social Darwinists. First there is the ambivalence over nature -
the model/threat dualism which is so prevalent in Social Darwinist
discourses. Second, though nature as a whole is not accorded a female
persona, those features of nature through which salvation is possible are
invested with features designated as feminine. The nurturing/caring
model of womanhood is still retained as natural, even if no longer typical
of nature in its entirety.
59
M. Blind, The Ascent of Man (London: Chatto and Windus, 1889). The 1899 reissue of
this poem had a foreword by A. R. Wallace. (I am grateful to Christine Pullen for
drawing my attention to this poem.)
11 Nazism, Fascism and Social Darwinism
Introduction
There is an enormous scholarly literature on Nazism and Fascism, one
that is marked by controversy over how the two movements are to be
defined, over their origins, sources of support, ideologies and signifi-
cance. The genocidal policies of the Nazi regime in Germany from
1933 to 1945, culminating in the Holocaust against the Jews, raise
additional issues concerning the causes of such actions and the roots of
anti-Semitic and racial thinking and policies in German, and more
generally, European, culture and history. It has also inclined some
commentators to question the extent to which Fascism and Nazism can
be considered as members of the same ideological and political family,
and to suggest that the latter may be a distinctive and unique
phenomenon.1
One point on which scholars do seem to have reached a consensus
relates to the role of Social Darwinism in both Nazi and Fascist ideology.
Social Darwinist ideas are cited as underpinning Nazi policies on war,
eugenics and race,2 and providing a rationale for the emphasis on
struggle and conflict found in Italian and French Fascism.3 Yet there is
to date no detailed analysis of the nature and function of Social
Darwinism within Nazism and Fascism, or of whether the two ideologies
1
For an overview of the pros and cons of this latter debate, see I. Kershaw, The Nazi
Dictatorships second edn (London: Edward Arnold, 1989), chap. 2.
2
For examples, see Kershaw, The Nazi Dictatorship, 74, 129, 146; J. Noakes and
G. Pridham, eds., Nazism 1919-1945, III, 610-11, 617-8; H. Krausnick and M.
Broszat, Anatomy of the SS State, tr. D. Long and M. Jackson (London: Granada,
1970), 27-35; Burleigh and Wipperman, The Racial State, 28-33; H. Dicks, Licensed
Mass Murder (London: Heinemann, 1972), 112, 267.
3
See A. Lyttleton, Italian Fascisms From Pareto to Gentile (London: Jonathan Cape,
1973), 32; Z. Sternhell, 'Fascist Ideology', in W. Laqueur, ed., Fascism: A Reader's
Guide (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1976), 334-5; Sternhell, M droite ni gauche (Paris:
Editions du Seuil, 1983), 47, 141; P. Milza, Les Fascismes (Paris: Imprimerie Nationale,
1985), 51-2; R. Eatwell, Fascism: A History (London: Chatto and Windus, 1995), 26,
166.
272
Nazism, Fascism and Social Darwinism 273
exhibited any significant differences in these respects. The purpose of
this chapter is to make a start at filling this lacuna by conducting such an
investigation. For the sake of convenience I will deal with German
Nazism and Italian Fascism separately, and then conclude by making
some general comparative observations. Given the sheer volume and
complexity of the material under consideration, I must emphasise the
provisional nature of this enterprise and the tentativeness of the
conclusions, although the latter do indicate some fruitful lines of further
inquiry. I will also be confining the analysis to the period up to 1945,
since an investigation of the development of these ideologies after World
War II is beyond the scope of this study.
Material from Nazi ideologues other than Hitler has been published in B. Lane and
L. Rupp, eds., Nazi Ideology Before 1933: A Documentation (Manchester University
Press, 1978); Griffin, ed., Fascism, Readings 60-89.
274 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
battle against thousands upon thousands of resistances just as life itself is
an eternal struggle against death.'5
According to Hitler, the twin dynamics of life were hunger and love,
the first of which promoted self-preservation, the second the preserva-
tion of the species. However, the space in which these instinctive drives
had to be satisfied was limited - here Hitler was undoubtedly endorsing
a version of the earlier Lebensraum theories - with the result that
organisms were compelled to struggle for space and resources. It is out
of this struggle that evolution occurred through the survival of the fittest.
'From the invisible confusion of the organisms there finally emerged
formations, clans, tribes, peoples, states. The description of their origins
and their passing away is but the representation of an eternal struggle for
existence.'6
Among the lowest organic beings, self-preservation was confined to
survival of the individual. With increasing development the focus was
transferred to spouse and offspring, and among the highest creatures, to
the 'entire species'. Men, therefore, acted in accordance with the instinct
of self-preservation when they sacrificed themselves for their people.7 By
'people' and 'species', Hitler meant 'race'. In Mein Kampf he wrote:
'The racial question gives the key not only to world history, but to all
human culture.'8 Race was not a matter of language or historical
continuity, but of blood. Since nature did not reserve the use of the soil
to particular nations and races, the acquisition of space and resources
could only be decided by conflict. Nature established no political
boundaries, but rather conferred 'the master's right on her favourite
child, the strongest in courage and industry'.9 This was an unalterable
law: 'Providence has endowed living creatures with a limitless fecundity;
but she has not put in their reach, without the need for effort on their
part, all the food they need. All that is very right and proper, for it is the
struggle for existence that produces the selection of the fittest.' 10 It was
through the survival of the fittest that nature contrived the elimination of
the weak and the improvement of the race:
Those whom she permits to survive the inclemency of existence are a thousand-
fold tested, hardened, and well adapted to procreate in turn, in order that the
process of thorough-going selection may begin againfromthe beginning. By thus
brutally proceeding against the individual and immediately calling him back to
5
A. Hitler, Hitler's Secret Book, tr. S. Attanasio (New York: Grove Press, 1961), 5.
6 7
Ibid.,1. Ibid., 5.
8
Hitler, Mein Kampf, tr. R. Manheim (London: Hutchinson, 1974), 308.
9
Ibid., 123.
10
Hitler, Hitler's Table Talk 1941-1944, tr. N. Cameron and R. Stevens (Oxford
University Press, 1988), 134.
Nazism, Fascism and Social Darwinism 275
herself as soon as he shows himself unequal to the storm of life, she keeps the race
and species strong, in fact, raises them to the highest accomplishments.1 x
To abolish this struggle would deprive men of 'the highest driving power
for their development'.12 Struggle determined the worth of both
individuals and races by establishing a hierarchy according to their
capabilities for preservation and development, and for Hitler the task of
National Socialism was to ensure that society mirrored this principle of
nature:
the folkish philosophy finds the importance of mankind in its basic racial
elements. In the state it sees on principle only a means to an end and construes
its end as the preservation of the racial existence of man. Thus, it by no means
believes in the equality of the races, but along with their differences it recognises
their higher or lesser value and feels itself obligated, through this knowledge, to
promote the victory of the better and stronger, and demand the subordination of
the inferior and weaker in accordance with the eternal will that dominates this
universe. Thus, in principle, it preserves the basic aristocratic idea of Nature and
believes in the validity of this law down to the last individual. It sees not only the
different value of the races, but also the different value of individuals.13
One of nature's rules which Hitler thought it vital to observe was the
deleterious effects of race mixing. Nature, he proclaimed, 'has little love
for bastards', as evinced by the punishment in the form of decadence
and defeat inflicted on races which violated this rule. 'Eternal Nature
inexorably avenges the infringement of her commands.' 14 The mixing of
the blood of higher with lower races must therefore be resisted at all
costs, for: 'The stronger must dominate and not blend with the weaker
.. .' 15 Anything which represented a racial danger must be resisted, 'for
in a bastardised and niggerised world all the concepts of the humanly
beautiful and sublime, as well as all ideas of an idealised future of our
humanity, would be lost forever'.16
Needless to say, it was the Aryan, Nordic or Germanic race - Hitler
employed these terms interchangeably - which represented the height of
human development, whereas the Jew was a parasite, a bacillus, a 'world
plague' threatening to poison and destroy the Aryan unless counteracted
with appropriate measures. With these images of the Jew as an alien
'otherness', whose materialism and lack of 'rootedness' in his own native
soil contrasted with the idealistic and racially superior Aryan, Hitler was
drawing upon a long tradition of anti-Semitic and Volkish racial
stereotyping in Germany.17 He argued that the Jewish race possessed a
1 l2
* Hitler, Mein Kampf, 121. Hitler, Secret Book, 16; also Hitler, Mein Kampf, 259.
13 14
Hitler, Mein Kampf, 348. Ibid., 363, 60.
15 16
Ibid., 259; Hitler, Secret Book, 28. Hitler, Mein Kampf, 348.
17
For an analysis of the interplay between Volkish and anti-Semitic currents in German
276 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
great instinct for survival but this only acted at the level of the self-
preservation of the individual; hence Jews lacked sufficient idealism to
form their own state. Instead they sought to corrupt and then subjugate
the states which harboured them. 18 But the Jews were not the only
'racial danger' which the 'culture-creating5 Aryan needed to guard
against, and one of the crucial functions of the state was to maintain and
improve the racial health of its people. In keeping with a long-standing
feature of a certain genre of Social Darwinist thought, Hitler was of the
opinion that modern civilisation tended to substitute social for natural
selection, with highly damaging consequences for racial hygiene. Mod-
ern warfare, for example, tended to eliminate the healthiest specimens in
the population while sparing the weaklings, and modern judicial and
penal practices likewise preserved the lives of criminals. Birth control
had created a situation in which people sought to limit the size of their
families while paying little attention to the racial value of the children
they did beget. It was racial suicide to countenance the continued
propagation of defective and incurably sick infants. Hitler lauded the
eugenic practices of ancient Sparta on the grounds that the destruction
of weak, sickly and deformed children 'was more decent and a thousand
times more humane than the wretched insanity of our day'. 19 In a
speech to the Nuremberg Party Rally on 5 August 1929, Hitler
denounced 'sentimental humanitarianism' and the 'sense of charity'
which he considered responsible for 'maintaining the weak at the
expense of the healthy'. He complained 'that even cretins are able to
procreate while more healthy people refrain from doing so ... Criminals
have the opportunity of procreating, degenerates are raised artificially
and with difficulty. And in this way we are gradually breeding the weak
and killing off the strong.'20
Hitler's writings and speeches portrayed nature in rigidly deterministic
terms. Expressions such as 'eternal', 'inexorable' and 'iron' were used to
refer to nature and its laws. Sometimes 'God' or 'Providence' were
substituted for nature, but it is evident that Hitler was not appealing to
any Christian deity, for he defined God as 'the dominion of natural laws
throughout the whole universe', and referred to Providence as 'the
unknown, or Nature, or whatever name one chooses'.21 These natural
laws were inescapable realities which could not be ignored without
courting disaster: 'Nothing that is made of flesh and blood can escape
39
Hitler, Table Talk, 6 9 .
40
See O . Bartov, The Eastern Front, 1941-45 ( L o n d o n : M a c m i l l a n , 1985), chap. 3 .
41
G o e b b e l s , Diaries, 3 4 3 ; also 4 8 , 5 9 , 8 7 , 4 1 1 , 4 1 4 .
42
Ibid., 214.
43
Hitler's War Directives 1939-1945, ed. H . R. T r e v o r - R o p e r ( L o n d o n : P a n , 1966), 2 8 8 .
282 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
existence of our people compels us, even within the territory of the
Reich, to exploit every means of weakening the fighting strength of our
enemy, and impeding his further advance.'44 The Fuhrer's rationalisa-
tion of this policy to his subordinates showed a consistent adherence to
the premisses of Social Darwinism to the very end, for he asserted that
Germany had shown itself to be weaker than its eastern opponents and
did not therefore deserve to survive.45
Conclusion
If the position adopted in this study is accepted - i.e. that Social
Darwinism comprises the philosophical infrastructure of a social theory
or ideology - then, on the basis of the material reviewed in this chapter,
it is reasonable to conclude that German Nazism and Italian Fascism,
during the period studied here, reposed upon different intellectual
foundations. In the former case, these foundations were Social
Darwinist, in the latter not. The world view underpinning Fascism was
one which regarded historical time as a dimension devoid of any pattern,
and though it accepted the existence of laws of nature, it denied the
ability of these to set limits to human endeavour or to dictate the course
and content of public policies. In this, Fascism can be seen to be
partially inspired by the philosophies deriving from Hegelian doctrines
of conflict and synthesis, Sorelian celebrations of myth and violence, the
Nietzschean advocacy of self-transcendence and Bergson's notion of
evolution as a process of self-creation.
This is not the place to examine the precise ways in which these
various components of Fascism were articulated and elaborated, but it
does seem clear that in this formulation there would be little scope for
biological determinism or, indeed, for any kind of determinism. Fascism
would therefore be inimical to one of the core assumptions of Social
Darwinism, namely, that human beings are, both morally and culturally,
76
See E. Robertson, 'Race as a Factor in Mussolini's Policy in Africa and Europe',
Journal of Contemporary History, 23(1988), 37-58. The release of material from United
Nations archives in early 1988 exposed the viciousness and brutality of the Italian
occupation of Abyssinia and Europe. See William Scobie, 'Revealed: Italy's Savage
War Crimes', Observer, 24 January 1988.
290 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
governed by natural laws. Thus while they placed a high value on
struggle and conflict, Fascists did so for reasons other than those
invoked by Social Darwinists, seeing in adversarial conditions the
opportunities for men (or, rather, some men - those of the elite) to
display the heroic qualities that differentiated the spiritual from the
material realms.
This stress on heroism and spirituality can also be found in Nazism.
But in this instance, heroism consists in expressing values that are
consistent with the dictates of nature, in accordance with the natural
order. To fight against the determinism of the latter is to court disaster.
In this way, the different metaphysical foundations of Nazism and
Fascism have important ideological consequences, not least of which is
the salience of race in the former creed. For Nazism, race was genetically
based and hence hereditary, its features produced by selection and
adaptation and threatened by miscegenation. The exigencies of the
struggle for survival justified the most radical measures in eugenics and
racial hygiene. There is, consequently, a relentless continuity between
the Nazi conception of human nature and history on the one hand, and
the racial and eugenic practices of the Third Reich on the other.
There are a number of caveats which need to be made at this juncture.
First, I have no desire to argue that Nazi praxis was an inevitable con-
sequence of its ideological premisses. Though ideologies make up an
important aspect of reality, they are not the whole of that reality and do
not possess the power of independent causation. The history of the Third
Reich does not flow inexorably from the pages of Mein Kampf, and Nazi
ideology is only one factor in the conditions in which policies of war,
racial purification and genocide occurred. My points are simply that: (a)
there is a great deal of consistency between the Nazis' ideology and the
policies that they implemented; (b) this ideology is one in which race occ-
pies a central role; (c) race is, in turn, predicated upon a Social Darwinist
world view in which the struggle for survival is a prescient fact of life.
My second caveat relates to the role of race in Fascist thought. Racism
was, as we have seen, rampant throughout the West during this period,
and few Europeans or white colonialists harboured any doubts over their
superiority vis-d-vis the indigenous populations of Asia, Africa and the
New World. Italian Fascism contained racist factions, and the initial
success of Nazism would have encouraged imitation of their ideas. Such
could well be the reason for the anti-Semitic legislation of 1938, which
was criticised by some Italian Fascists precisely for this reason.77 This
77
For condemnations of this legislation for imitating Nazism, see Carlo Costamagna
(1881-1965), reproduced in J.-P. Faye, Langages Totalitaires (Paris: Hermann, 1973),
[84-90]; Gioacchino Volpe (1876-1971) in Griffin, ed., Fascism, Reading 39.
Nazism, Fascism and Social Darwinism 291
being said, the texts analysed here show race not to have been an integral
feature of Fascist theorising. Some commentators have responded to
this difference by referring to Nazism as 'Fascism + racism'.78 But
Nazism cannot be adequately conceived in these terms: racism was not a
simple accretion to the world view of Fascism but, on the contrary,
reflected a different, even incompatible, view of nature, time and
humanity. If all references to race were removed the essential structure
of Fascist ideology would remain intact, whereas a similar excision for
Nazism would remove its central core. This has implications for Fascist
practice, for the experience of Fascism in Italy for Jews, brutal and
distressing as it undoubtedly was, did not approach the genocidal horror
of the Third Reich.79
I have argued that whereas Nazi racism was legitimated by a Social
Darwinism of a particularly deterministic ilk, Fascism was anti-determi-
nistic, and its concept of national community therefore was less
exclusive than one based upon race. Or rather, the exclusionary criteria
employed by Fascists in their conception of national identity were less
rigid than those adopted by Nazis. Once again, I am not arguing that
ideas are the sole (or even major) determinants of social processes, only
pointing to a certain degree of congruence between world view, ideology
and praxis.
These conclusions are tentative. The analysis has been confined to
two countries, and I have only examined a small sample of individual
texts rather than surveying the entire corpus of Fascist literature.
Furthermore, there is some evidence of the language of Social Dar-
winism, notably in some of the writings and speeches of Rocco. What
are needed are detailed comparative investigations of the ideology of the
various Fascist movements and ideologues of the period. Though much
progress has been made in recent years in the understanding of Fascist
ideology it is still a neglected area of study. Hopefully the analyses
conducted in this chapter have suggested some interesting lines of
inquiry.
78
Ball and Dagger, Political Ideologies and the Democratic Ideal, 192.
79
Mussolini's position on the Jews tended to fluctuate, but seems to have been governed
by pragmatic rather than by ideological considerations. See M. Michaelis, Mussolini and
the Jews (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978).
Postscript: Social Darwinism old and new: the case
of sociobiology
Introduction
There is a widely held view among historians and social scientists that
Social Darwinism declined in popularity after World War II due to its
association with racism and Nazism. The belief is that in the post-war
democratic consensus that emerged in the Western states there was little
tolerance for theories which apparently gave a biological justification for
racism, war or exploitation. The American historian Degler considers
these circumstances were not just uncongenial for Social Darwinism but
actually fatal to it. 'Social Darwinism', he writes, 'was definitely killed,
not merely scotched .. . j l
The thesis that Social Darwinism is dead is false, as will be shown
below. The weaker claim that it declined in importance during the
immediate post-war period is plausible although the detailed studies
required to substantiate it have yet to be made. In any case, by the mid-
1960s Social Darwinism had re-emerged and was reaching wide
audiences in Britain and the USA. It took the form of popular writings
about the evolutionary heritage of humans that were the forerunners of
sociobiology which itself, I shall argue, is a particularly powerful
example of Social Darwinism. It is possible that Social Darwinism was
manifested in other currents of thought in the post-war era, and that
accounts of its decline have been exaggerated, but an investigation of
this possibility is outside the scope of this study.2 In confining this
chapter to sociobiology the intention is not to engage in a critical
appreciation of this discipline but to examine its relationship to Social
Darwinism. The aims are to test the robustness of the model of the
1
Degler, In Search of Human Nature, ix.
2
Social Darwinism has certainly been appropriated by neo-Fascist and extreme right-
wing groups in Europe. Examples for Britain are cited later in this chapter and there is
evidence to suggest that the Front National in France has also adopted Social Darwinist
rhetoric. See P. A. Taguieff, 'La Metaphysique de Jean-Marie Le Pen', in N. Mayer
and P. Perrineau, eds., Le Front National a decouvert (Paris: Presses de la Fondation
Nationale des Sciences Politiques, 1989), 173-94.
292
Social Darwinism old and new 293
world view constructed in chapter 1 for a different historical epoch and
to explore the continuing relevance of Social Darwinism to Western
culture.
Before embarking on this exercise it is useful to take cognisance of
developments in biology since the Modern Synthesis. The discovery of
the structure of DNA in 1953 paved the way for advances in molecular
biology which have greatly enhanced knowledge about the processes of
genetic mutation and transmission. Developments in population ge-
netics and evidence from ecology and detailed ethological studies have
deepened our understanding of selection and evolution. 'Fitness' is
denned as the differential success of organisms in survival and the
leaving of offspring. Since the 1960s a consensus has emerged over the
unit of selection, with group selection rejected by the majority of
biologists in favour of individual selection, although some persist in
retaining a notion of species selection.3 Others maintain that since it is
genes which are actually replicated, selected and transmitted then the
gene is the appropriate level of analysis. Gene and individual-level
models are broadly compatible and are both opposed to group selection.
The trend towards individual or gene-based models of evolution has
developed out of attempts to solve the hoary problem of altruism.
Actions apparently favouring the group at the expense of the individuals
performing them, as in the case of the warning cries emitted by certain
species of birds in the presence of predators, are explained as examples
of 'kin selection'. Altruistic actions can increase the likelihood of an
organism preserving copies of its own genes in its relatives. On average
an organism's offspring or siblings will possess half of its own genes;
hence even a self-sacrificing action which leaves two or more siblings
alive promotes 'inclusive fitness'. The inclusive fitness of a gene is
therefore defined as 'the reproductive rate of its bearer plus that of the
copies of the gene carried by relatives to whom the bearer may extend
help'.4
Another important concept is that of 'reciprocal altruism'. Animals
that extend help to other (unrelated) animals in their group improve the
chances of receiving aid themselves in times of need. In these cases (as
was suggested by Darwin), seemingly altruistic actions in fact derive
from individual self-interest. Here, then, as with inclusive fitness,
behaviour which potentially benefits the group at the expense of the
3
For discussions of these different positions, see Smith, Did Darwin Get it Right?, chap.
16; Wilson, Diversity of Life, 81-5.
4
D. J. Futuyma, Evolutionary Biology (Sunderland, MA: Sinauer Associates, 1979), 305.
For a brief overview of the development of the notion of inclusive fitness, see Smith,
Did Darwin Get it Right?, chap. 13; Gould, Ever Since Darwin, chap. 33.
294 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
individual is explained by reference to the selective advantages accruing
to the individual.
Modern evolutionary theory is therefore Darwinian in its explanatory
structure. It combines genetics, ecology, ethology and mathematics in
its models of evolutionary dynamics. Palaeontology continues to be
closely relevant to Darwinian theory, particularly the spectacular
discoveries of early hominid fossils in Africa. The outcome is a theory of
evolution which is more powerful but more abstruse than the original
version. Whereas Darwin's technical writings could be readily assimi-
lated by non-specialist audiences, modern Darwinism is much less
accessible. Despite this, Darwinism continues to excite public contro-
versy and debate and scientists have been remarkably successful in
producing popular accounts of the latest developments in evolutionary
theory. This is the intellectual context in which sociobiology made its
appearance.
Sociobiology
Sociobiology as a discipline is usually traced to the publication, in 1975,
of the bestselling Sociobiology: The New Synthesis by the Harvard
biologist, Edward Osborne Wilson. Wilson defined sociobiology as 'the
systematic study of the biological basis of all social behaviour'.
According to his own testimony he had concluded his Insect Societies
(1971) with the hypothesis that the principles of population biology and
comparative zoology that had worked so well for the analysis of the
social insects could be extended to the study of vertebrate animals. This
goal was realised in Sociobiology, the final chapter of which contains
Wilson's controversial assertion that these principles could be applied to
the study of human social behaviour, thereby closing the gap between
the natural and the social sciences. His On Human Nature (1978) was a
first step in the achievement of this synthesis.5 Since then there has been
a veritable efflorescence of literature devoted to this project. This has in
turn inspired an enormous level of criticism and a great deal of debate -
much of it acrimonious - over the methods, conclusions and alleged
political implications of sociobiology. The existence of this body of
criticism coincident with the continued thriving of sociobiology -
especially in the USA - provides an important lesson for an under-
standing of the history of Social Darwinism: hostility towards a body of
ideas in certain social circles provides no warrant for assuming its overall
unpopularity.
5
This account of Wilson's ideas is taken from his On Human Nature, ix-x.
Social Darwinism old and new 295
A recurrent theme in this criticism has been the accusation that
sociobiology is a renascent Social Darwinism. The claim was made at
the birth of the discipline and has remained a basis of condemnation
ever since. 6 Sociobiologists are accused of espousing a rigid biological
determinism in their efforts to explain phenomena such as incest
prohibitions, rape, adultery, warfare, homicide and homosexuality -
among many others - as the consequences of a genetic heritage shaped
by natural selection. Such efforts are deemed by some critics to provide
a justification, at least implicitly, for capitalism, class inequalities,
racism, patriarchy and armed conflict. For them, there is nothing novel
about the proposed 'New Synthesis', which reprises the basic themes of
the Social Darwinism of the 1870s. 7
Sociobiologists and their supporters have been vociferous in their
rejection of these allegations. While without exception they claim to be
Darwinists, the majority seem to agree with the political scientist
Lopreato that the link between Darwinism and Social Darwinism was
'theoretically disastrous' as the latter was bad science and bad
Darwinism. This was because Social Darwinism 'was to a large extent
an ideology and an apologia for the worst form of capitalism,
ethnocentrism, and racism'.8 Degler likewise insists on the ideological
discontinuity between the politically liberal sociobiologists and conserva-
tive defence of the capitalist status quo which he sees as typical of Social
Darwinism.9 The psychologist Crawford bemoans the 'heavy burden'
placed on evolutionary theory by Social Darwinist defences of predatory
business practices, racism, inequality and imperialism, while the
philosopher Ruse, in denying the connection, stresses the scientific
authenticity of sociobiology. 10
Both accusers and accused share one point in common: they agree in
describes this literature as 'totally and utterly wrong', primarily for its insistence on
group as opposed to individual selection. Dawkins, Selfish Gene, 2. For Wilson's
reaction, see Rose et al, Not in Our Genes, 240. J. Diamond is dismissive of Ardrey in
his The Rise and Fall of the Third Chimpanzee (London: Vintage, 1992), 33.
13
London: Collins, 1967.
298 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
than a biological morality' (79). Hence there was 'no qualitative break
between the moral nature of the animal and the moral nature of man'
(78). This morality, however, was confined to the ingroup. Resurrecting
the arguments of Arthur Keith on the 'dual code', Ardrey insisted that
aggression and warfare - the 'code of enmity' - were equally deeply
ingrained in human nature as the result of selective forces (286-8).
Ardrey's books were bestsellers and so these ideas reached a large
public. Of significance to this study are a number of features which these
writings shared with the other pop ethologists. First, there was a clear
endorsement of Darwinian evolutionary theory, with particular emphasis
on the importance of natural selection and competition. Second, there
was an unhesitating application of this theory to human psychology and
culture in order to grasp the fundamental attributes of human nature.
Thus the pop ethologists reproduced both the discursive substance and
the ambitions of earlier Social Darwinists.
There was one point, though, on which these modern Social Darwin-
ists differed from their earliest counterparts like Bagehot, Spencer,
Royer and Haeckel. The latter had posited a socio-psychological
development from primitive to modern - usually from military to
industrial types of social organisation and mentality. True, all believed
in the possibility of arrested development and atavism at both the
individual and the social levels: the primitive legacy could still assert its
presence in modern civilisation. But as I have sought to show, the
primary function of the primitive in these theories was to define the
starting point of evolution by marking the threshold of animality/
humanity. In pop ethology this threshold was erased and evolutionary
time no longer acted to distance the modern from the primitive but
served to underscore the continuity of the primitive in the modern. The
Social Darwinism of Ardrey et al collapsed the distance not only
between the primitive and the modern but between the animal and the
human. In this, they continued a form of Social Darwinism already
developed by, for example, Lapouge, in which human nature appears as
an unchanging essence. As we shall see, this tendency is maintained in
sociobiology.
14 15
Wilson, On Human Nature, 32-3. Dawkins, Selfish Gene, 67, 83.
16
M. Ridley, The Red Queen (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1994), 208, 226.
17
Diamond, Rise and Fall, chaps. 8 and 9.
18
Lopreato, Human Nature, chap. 3; C. J. Lumsden and E. O. Wilson, Genes, Mind and
Culture: The Coevolutionary Process (Harvard University Press, 1981).
300 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
be constrained in accordance with their effects on the human gene
pool.'19
One of the most provocative examples of sociobiology challenging
conventional approaches to a topic is the theory of rape advanced by the
Thornhills. After studying 'rape' - i.e. forced copulation of a female by a
male - among scorpion flies, the authors turn their attention to human
rape. Rejecting alternative explanations, the Thornhills argue that, as
with scorpion flies, human rape is 'an evolved mating tactic'. It occurs
when low-status males are denied mating opportunities, allowing these
males some opportunity to spread their genes and increase their
inclusive fitness. Although the reproductive benefits of rape are very low,
in evolutionary terms they could prove to be important. According to
the Thornhills: 6A small difference in fitness between men who raped
when other avenues of reproduction were closed compared to men who
did not rape in this context during evolutionary history would be
expected to lead to major evolutionary change.'20
Another controversial focus has been on sexual differences. Wilson
claims that men and women have evolved different physical and mental
traits through evolutionary history. Among our early forebears, men
hunted and competed with other males for women, hence men, as with
males in most species, tend to be aggressive, women much less so.21
Males can in principle impregnate many females, while females have to
invest much time and effort in childbearing. These different reproduc-
tive strategies have produced different traits in males and females, with
the latter, according to Ridley, favouring monogamous relationships and
the former more promiscuous, prone to opportunistic mating 'and to
use wealth, power and violence as means to sexual ends in the
competition with other men .. .'22 Ridley goes on to argue that while, in
contrast to chimpanzees and gorillas, humans tend to form monoga-
mous pairs in which the males invest time and effort in childcare,
adultery nevertheless can be advantageous to both sexes, which is why it
is a 'chronic problem throughout human society .. .' 23 Ridley believes
that these evolved sex differences explain much social behaviour. Thus
for men he maintains that 'deep in the mind of modern man is a simple
male hunter-gatherer rule: strive to acquire power and use it to lure
women who will bear heirs; strive to acquire wealth and use it to buy
affairs with other men's wives who will bear bastards.'24
19
Wilson, On Human Nature, 167.
20
R. Thornhill and N . W. Thornhill, 'Human Rape: The Strengths of the Evolutionary
Perspective', in Crawford et al, Sociobiology and Psychology, 283.
21 22
Wilson, On Human Nature, 125-8. Ridley, Red Queen, 198.
23 24
Ibid., 220. Ibid., 236.
Social Darwinism old and new 301
c
Ridley insists that: Men and women have different minds. The
differences are the direct result of evolution.'25 Equally adamant that
difference does not entail inequality he nonetheless insists that the
differences are real and cannot be attributed to social conventions.26 A
similar position is upheld by Wilson, who proposes that: 'Even with
identical education for men and women and equal access to all
professions, men are likely to maintain disproportionate representation
in political life, business and science. Many would fail to participate fully
in the equally important, formative aspects of child rearing.' 27
These examples suffice to demonstrate the Social Darwinist creden-
tials of sociobiology, the entire rationale for which is predicated on the
fifth assumption of the world view, namely that Darwinian theory can
explain important aspects of human society, culture and psychology.
Moreover, despite their protestations to the contrary, sociobiologists are
in this respect closely allied to the pop ethologists of the 1960s. Whatever
the sophistication of the former, in both instances the project of
synthesising evolutionary theory with ethology and ecology and applying
this synthesis to problems erstwhile deemed to be the province of
psychology, anthropology and sociology is clearly articulated. In this, the
pop ethologists may actually have facilitated the wide acceptance of
sociobiology by introducing some of its central ideas to the general
public.
There are two other areas in which sociobiology evinces close links
with pop ethology, and before that with early Social Darwinist texts.
First, sociobiologists concede nothing to previous generations of Social
Darwinists when it comes to speculative audacity. Wilson has proposed
genetic explanations for crime, murder, ethnocentrism and aggression
and homosexuality and speculated as to how these traits might improve
genetic fitness.28 Others have advanced evolutionary explanations for
suicide, fasting, drug taking, and why modern (as opposed to pre-
modern) men prefer slim women.29 Sociobiology excels in the construc-
tion of evolutionary narratives that relate current institutions, fashions
and social practices to the selection of genes in the evolutionary past.
Second, like their predecessors, sociobiologists have been conspicuous
25 26 27
Ibid., 240. Ibid., 253. Wilson, On Human Nature, 133.
28
Ibid., 44, 83-100, 143-7.
29
O n suicide see D . de Catanzaro, 'Evolutionary Pressures and Limitations to Self-
Preservation', in Crawford et ah, Sociobiology and Psychology, 3 1 1 - 3 3 ; for dieting,
Lopreato, Human Nature, 214; for drug addiction, Diamond, Rise and Fall, chap. 11;
for slim women, Ridley, Red Queen, 279-84. There is a resounding critique of these
attempts to explain current social practices through the selection of genes for which n o
evidence actually exists in R. C. Lewontin, The Doctrine of DNA (Harmondsworth:
Penguin, 1993), 100-4.
302 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
for both proclaiming the ethical neutrality of the science of sociobiology
and advertising its relevance to moral debates. Thus Lopreato writes:
'Free competition - that is at once the game and the fundamental
principle of the ethics implicit in biocultural science.' 30 Wilson adopts a
similar position, believing that human biology 'will fashion a biology of
ethics, which will make possible the selection of a more deeply
understood and enduring code of moral values'. 31 In fact Wilson betrays
his affinities with older (and allegedly discredited) modes of discourse in
a disturbing passage where he contends that in the light of our current
knowledge 'we are justified in considering the preservation of the entire
gene pool as a contingent primary value until such time as an almost
unimaginably greater knowledge of human heredity provides us with the
option of a democratically contrived eugenics*'.32 Even Dawkins, who is
sensitive to the charge of biological reductionism, draws ethical conclu-
sions from his thesis of the selfish gene. Organisms, he argues, are
vehicles made by genes in order that the latter can replicate themselves.
Nevertheless, human mental capacities mean that we 'have the power to
defy the selfish genes of our birth .. .' 33 But Dawkins, in language close
to that of Wilson and other sociobiologists, makes plain the fact that this
power renders humans unique in nature:
Be warned that if you wish, as I do, to build a society in which individuals
cooperate generously and unselfishly towards a common good, you can expect
little help from biological nature. Let us try to teach generosity and altruism,
because we are born selfish. Let us understand what our own selfish genes are up
to, because we may then at least have the chance to upset their designs,
something that no other species has ever aspired to.34
In the light of this discursive continuity I am sympathetic to Crook's
verdict that sociobiologists are inflicted with 'collective amnesia about
their forebears'. Reading them induces a feeling of deja vu, because:
'The same old issues keep cropping up, although the language is now
more sophisticated .. .' 35 The remainder of this chapter examines in
more detail the relationship between the Social Darwinism of the
sociobiologists and that espoused by their intellectual ancestors.
30
Lopreato, Human Nature, 3 4 0 , original emphasis.
31 32
Wilson, On Human Nature, 198. Ibid., m y emphasis.
33
Dawkins, Selfish Gene, 2 0 0 .
34
Ibid., 3 , original emphasis. A similar conclusion occurs in M . Konner, ' H u m a n Nature
and Culture: Biology and the Residue of Uniqueness', in J. J. Sheehan and M . Sosna,
eds., The Boundaries of Humanity: Humans, Animals, Machines (Oxford: University of
California Press, 1991), 120.
35
Crook, Darwinism, War and History, 196, 198. Greta Jones also arrived at this
conclusion in 1980; Social Darwinism, 187.
Social Darwinism old and new 303
38 39
Dawkins, Selfish Gene, 2. Konner, 'Human Nature and Culture', 109, 111.
40 41
Ibid., I l l , original emphasis. Ibid., 119.
42 43
Wilson, On Human Nature, 111. Ibid., 119.
Social Darwinism old and new 305
Sexual selection
Few of Darwin's followers assigned much significance to sexual selection
as an evolutionary mechanism, although there were exceptions, and I
have underlined the efforts of feminists like Gamble and Gilman to
enlist sexual selection in the cause of female equality. Modern biologists
recognise the role of sexual selection in evolution. Although it is
ultimately subsumed under natural selection, sexual selection is assigned
importance because traits which foster reproductive success could
conflict with survival, as in the case of the peacock's tail.
Sociobiologists have made sexual selection an important part of their
explanation of sexual dimorphism and have not shrunk from extending
the analysis to human sexual differences. The differences they accent-
uate are almost identical to those emphasised by earlier Social
Darwinists although, unlike some of the latter, sociobiologists are quick
to repudiate any implication of female inferiority. As with the earlier
period, such theorising is not exclusively male: several prominent
sociobiologists are female and some feminists have insisted on the need
to recognise the importance of sex differences.44 Other feminists, while
recognising the relevance of biology to the formation of sexual
identities, reject sociobiological accounts of these identities as exces-
sively reductionist.45
Sociobiologists dismiss these accusations while at the same time
insisting on the reality of differences established through evolution and
the constraints these differences place upon socio-political action. In
Wilson's words: 'The consequences of genetic history cannot be chosen
by legislatures.'46 As with early forms of Social Darwinism, then,
sociobiologists tend to use sexual and natural selection to represent
certain aspects of the sexual division of labour as reposing upon 'natural'
distinctions, although in ways which would have been most uncongenial
to Gamble and Gilman.
Heredity
Modern Darwinism is unremittingly hereditarian and the action of the
environment through the inheritance of acquired characters is rejected
by sociobiologists. Here one of the original indeterminacies is definitely
closed off in that a Social Darwinist would find it very difficult nowadays
to endorse Lamarckism. The debate about nurture versus nature is as
fierce as ever, although it now takes place between Social Darwinists and
their opponents rather than, additionally, within Social Darwinism itself
as was once the case.
Most sociobiologists acknowledge the importance of culture as a
determinant of human behaviour and even concede a dialectical
interplay between genes and culture, with the latter having a selective
impact on the former. In practice, as I have already indicated, when it
comes to accounting for certain key institutions and practices, socio-
biologists assign causal primacy to inherited biological traits. Thus
Lopreato, in challenging Weber's thesis on the importance of Calvinist
ideas of predestination in the development of early capitalism,
comments: 'ideas may indeed have been powerful forces in the
maturation of modern capitalism, but only because they were "public
images" of a biological substratum. Without the latter, they would have
fallen on deaf ears.'54
An important arena for the contest between sociobiological and
52
I. Silverman, 'Race, Race Differences and Race Relations: Perspectives from Psychol-
ogy and Sociobiology', in Crawford et ah, Sociobiology and Psychology, 2 1 7 - 1 8 .
53
See R. Verral, 'Sociobiology: T h e Instinct in Our Genes', Spearhead, 127(March,
1979), 1 0 - 1 1 . T h e same journal later carried an article on Darwin in its 'Great British
Racists' series. See Spearhead, 130(August 1979), 11. I am grateful to Steve W o o d -
bridge for these references.
54
Lopreato, Human Nature, 92.
308 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
cultural explanations has been the topic of incest prohibitions. Since
these can be found in animal societies as well, they are deemed to have
an instinctual basis. In humans, individuals who had a genetic aversion
to mating with close kin would have left more descendants than those
without this trait, and hence incest aversion would have been implanted
through natural selection.
This kind of explanation is not new and a version of it was advanced
over a century ago by Westermarck - as sociobiologists acknowledge.55
Westermarck surmised that if selection favoured those who avoided
injurious sexual unions, then an instinct for incest avoidance would
develop. 'Of course', he continued, 'it would display itself simply as an
aversion on the part of individuals to union with others with whom they
lived; but these, as a matter of fact, would be blood-relations, so that the
result would be survival of the fittest.'56 Sociobiologists claim that
Westermarck's conjectures have been confirmed by modern ethnology:
unrelated children that are brought up together are unlikely to marry
and when they do they tend to produce fewer offspring than couples
who were brought up separately.57 Some sociobiologists have inferred
from this that incest rarely occurs and so-called incest taboos actually
prohibit adultery and inbreeding (i.e. cross-cousin unions) 'and are
made to enhance the fitness of powerful men, the rule-makers'. 58 An
anthropologist has gone so far as to proclaim that 'purely cultural
explanations' of incest avoidance are simply untenable. 59
These views are contentious and tend to receive a hostile reception
from cultural anthropologists.60 I lack the time and competence to
engage in these debates, but fortunately there is no need. All that
requires emphasis is the 'hard' hereditarianism of modern sociobiology
linking it with pop ethology and, before that, with the Weismann-
inspired versions of Social Darwinism which emerged towards the end
of the nineteenth century. The effect is that within Social Darwinism an
indeterminacy has been closed off.
55
F o r example, Ridley, Red Queen, 2 7 4 - 7 .
56 57
Westermarck, The History of Human Marriage, 352. Ridley, Red Queen, 275.
58
N . Thornhill and R. Thornhill, 'Evolutionary Theory and Rules of Mating on Marriage
Pertaining to Relatives', in Crawford et al, Sociobiology and Psychology, 397.
59
P. L. van den Berghe, 'Incest Taboos and Avoidance: Some African Applications', in
Crawford et al., Sociobiology and Psychology, 353.
60
For a balanced assessment of cultural and instinctive explanations of incest taboos, see
A. Kuper, The Chosen Primate (London/ Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,
1994), 156-66. This study is an excellent critical review of sociobiological accounts of
aggression, pair-bonding, kinship and gender differences in the light of the ethno-
graphic record.
Social Darwinism old and new 309
Human nature
Darwinism represented a challenge to the idea of species essentialism
which in turn undermined the notion of a fixed human essence. Very
quickly, however, evolutionary theory itself was used to underwrite the
view that human nature changed so slowly that within the compass of
the historical record and the foreseeable future it could be taken as fixed.
Versions of Social Darwinism appeared and gained wide credence in
which human institutions and behavioural attributes - particularly those
associated with race - were presented as virtually timeless.61 This
assumption was also an important component of pop ethology, as we
saw above.
It is also a premiss of sociobiology whose practitioners, almost without
exception, maintain that the nature of modern humans was, in
essentials, established thousands of years ago. Modern people possess
the emotional and behavioural repertoire of the hunter-gatherers who
were their remote ancestors, much of which is in turn shared with
primates and even other animals. In the words of Wilson: 'Human
nature is ... a hodgepodge of special genetic adaptations to an
environment largely vanished, the world of the ice-age hunter-gatherer.
Modern life, as rich and rapidly changing as it appears to those caught in
it, is nevertheless only a mosaic of cultural hypertrophies of the archaic
behavioural adaptations.'62 We have already encountered a similar
explanation by Ridley, namely the 'hunter-gatherer rule' to acquire
wealth and power for the purpose of acquiring women. In a recent
publication Wilson bases his hope for conservationist policies aimed at
protecting biological and ecological diversity partly on the existence of
innate features of human nature. These he refers to as biophilia: 'the
connections that human beings subconsciously seek with the rest of life'.
The human heritage, he argues, is at least two million years old,
stretching back to the appearance of the genus homo. In intimate contact
with nature, our ancestors struggled to understand it. 'The imprint of
that effort cannot have been erased in a few generations of urban
existence.'63
The effect of arguments such as these is to reinstate human nature as
the foundation of ethical and social thought and practice, as noted
above; a human nature which, to all intents and purposes, we can take as
fixed. Its main parameters were determined perhaps two million years
ago and despite the vast cultural changes that have occurred since then,
these parameters still provide the key to an understanding of much
61
See m y ' T h e Struggle for Existence in Nineteenth Century Social Thought'.
62 63
Wilson, On Human Nature, 196. Wilson, Diversity of Life, 334, 332-3.
310 Social Darwinism in European and American thought
social action and many institutions. I am not concerned here with the
veracity of these arguments, for it seems perfectly consistent with
Darwinism to maintain that some species undergo little change over
long periods. My point is that evolutionary theory - a theory of change -
has been used to reinsert what is in practice a human essence into the
fundamental premisses of socio-political thought. In this, sociobiologists
are continuing a long-standing tendency in Social Darwinism.
Sociobiologists are not therefore interested in social change.64 Unlike
the early Social Darwinists, they do not seek to construct stages of
social and/or mental evolution. Like the pop ethologists, they do not
ask how modern people were differentiated from primitives and
primates: on the contrary, they seek to demonstrate that modern traits
and institutions can be found in primitives and primates because they
have been selected for by evolution. The chronological distance
between modern humans, primitives, hominids and apes is condensed.
Time's arrow becomes Zeno's arrow.65 Whereas this distances socio-
biologists sharply from someone like Spencer, it does show continuity
with certain developments in early Social Darwinism, for example the
theories of Gumplowicz and Lapouge, and the writings of Graham
Wallas.
It is their insistence on the presence of timeless and universal features
of human nature deriving from a genetic basis selected by evolution
which has earned sociobiologists their reputation as conservatives.
However much sociobiologists insist on their ethical neutrality or liberal
credentials, their critics charge them with furnishing justifications for the
status quo. Thus the American geneticist Lewontin sees sociobiology as
'the latest and most mystified attempt to convince people that human
life is pretty much what it has to be and perhaps even ought to be'. 66
There is substance to these charges, as the examples cited here testify.
But this political orientation should not be confused with the Social
Darwinism of sociobiology and nor should it preclude the possibility
that there exist modern examples of Social Darwinism employed in the
service of more radical programmes, just as in the past (compare
Lapouge and Wallas).
64
It is instructive to recall Greta Jones's verdict on Wilson: 'Wilson is searching less for a
scientific theory of human social evolution than for an ontology of human nature in
which there is a strong biological component': Social Darwinism, 192.
65
Zeno was a fifth-century B C Eleatic philosopher who endeavoured to prove that an
object in motion was apparently at rest.
66
Lewontin, Doctrine of DNA, 89. Lewontin continues: 'After all, if 3 billion years of
evolution have made us what we are, do we really think that a hundred days of
revolution will change us?' (90).
Social Darwinism old and new 311
Conclusion
The Social Darwinist world view described in chapter 1 is clearly recog-
nisable in the writings of modern sociobiologists. All of the original five
elements have been retained; what has altered are some of the indeter-
minacies within the world view due to developments in biology and
related sciences. Not only the original world view but many of the
substantive theoretical concerns and tactics of early Social Darwinism -
even many of the same ideas - are reproduced in sociobiology. Social
Darwinism, consequently, is thriving nearly a century and a half after the
appearance of the Origin. Through the publicity accorded their ideas,
the sales of their books, and the dissemination of their theories via
academia, the sociobiologists have reached a very wide audience. Hence
Social Darwinism has likewise been widely popularised and one could
expect it to be manifest in many other areas, though this point cannot be
pursued here.69
It is pointless and misleading to present this popularisation as a
vulgarisation of Darwinism. The application of Darwinian theory to
human society and psychology was an explicit goal of Darwin and the
early Darwinians. There is, therefore, no such thing as 'vulgar' or
'crude' Social Darwinism. What varies between theories is the under-
69
Casual evidence for the penetration of popular culture by Social Darwinism is readily
available. For example, a recent editorial in a utilities magazine on competition within
the industry following privatisation was headed 'Natural Selection'. It began: 'Competi-
tion is a basic instinct. The survival of the fittest determines which species survive and
which ones don't': Utilities Week, 13 October 1995.
Social Darwinism old and new 313
standing of Darwinism and the rigour with which it is applied to social
phenomena. Many sociobiologists are rigorous in both respects but then
so were Spencer, Haeckel and Royer given the state of knowledge of
their time, as were Lapouge, Wallas and Lenz later. Sociobiologists are,
then, quite wrong to insist on their differentiation from Social
Darwinism, an insistence which is based upon an ignorance both of the
nature and the history of Social Darwinism.
In the light of this history it is also apparent that sociobiologists are
naive to disclaim any responsibility for the socio-political implications of
their theories, especially as their own writings are usually redolent with
such implications. It is certainly true that Darwinism does not under-
write any specific ideological position or political programme, but as a
contemporary cultural anthropologist, Kuper, has observed, 'it is well to
bear in mind that any persuasive theory about human nature is bound to
become the basis for policies - about child-rearing, social mobility,
educational selection, immigration, even war and peace .. .' 70 Social
Darwinism can underpin more than one theory of human nature, but
this study has demonstrated that such theories are persuasive and have
precisely the consequences enumerated by Kuper. Since the explicit goal
of sociobiology has been the construction of a scientifically based theory
of human nature, and since sociobiologists themselves have been
prominent in the popularisation of this theory, they should not be
surprised at the consequences. Theirs is a long-standing ambition, and
although conversance with its history can hardly be expected to daunt it,
such awareness would at least make innocence as to its implications
impossible.
70
Kuper, Chosen Primate, 17.
Bibliography
This bibliography includes all items referred to in the chapters except for
newspaper and magazine articles, full references to which are given in
the footnotes.
314
Bibliography 315
The Dangerous Classes of New York and Twenty Years of Work Among Them
(New York: Wynkoop and Hallenback, 1872)
Brace, Emma, ed. The Life of Charles Loring Brace Chiefly Told in His Own Letters
(London: Sampson, Low, Marston and Co., 1894)
Bradley, F. H. Appearance and Reality, second edn (Oxford: Clarendon Press,
1897) [1893]
'Some Remarks on Punishment', International Journal of Ethics, 4(1894), 269-
84
Brinton, Crane. English Political Thought in the Nineteenth Century (London:
Benn, 1933)
Biichner, Ludwig. Man in the Past, Present and Future: A Popular Account of
Recent Scientific Research as Regards the Origins, Position and Prospects of the
Human Race, tr. W. S. Dallas (London: Asher and Co., 1872)
Carrel, Alexis. Man the Unknown (New York/London: Harper, 1935)
Closson, Carlos. 'Social Selection', Journal of Political Economy, 4(1896), 449-
66
Cobbe, Frances Power. Darwinism in Morals and Other Essays (London: Williams
andNorgate, 1872)
Comte, Auguste. Plan des travaux scientifiques necessaires pour reorganiser la societe
(Paris: Aubier-Montaigne, 1970) [1822]
Cours de philosophie positive, 6 vols. (Paris: Bachelier, 1830-42)
Systeme de politique positive, 4 vols. (Paris: Mathias, Carilian-Goury et
Delmont, 1851-4)
Condorcet, Marquis de. Esquisse d'un tableau historique des progres de Vesprit
humaine (Paris: Editions Sociales, 1966) [1795]
Cope, Edward Drinker. On the Hypothesis of Evolution: Physical and Metaphysical
(New Haven, CT: Chatfield and Co., 1870)
The Origin of the Fittest: Essays on Evolution (London/New York: Macmillan,
1887)
'The Energy of Evolution', The American Naturalist, 18(1894), 205-19
Darwin, Charles. Journal of Researches into the Natural History and Geology of the
Countries Visited During the Voyage Round the World of HMS 'Beagle' Under
Command of Captain Fitz Roy, RN (London: Murray, 1909) [1839]
On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, or the Preservation of
Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life, ed. J. W. Burrow (Harmondsworth:
Penguin, 1968) [1859]
The Descent of Man and Selection in Relation to Sex, second revised and
augmented edn (London: Murray, 1896) [1871]
Darwin, Charles and T. H. Huxley. Autobiographies, ed. Gavin de Beer (Oxford
University Press, 1983)
Darwin, Francis, ed. Charles Darwin: His Life Told in an Autobiographical Chapter,
and in a Selected Series of His Published Letters, rev. edn (London: Murray,
1902)
Darwin, Leonard. The Need for Eugenic Reform (London: Murray, 1926)
What is Eugenics? (London: Watts, 1928)
Dewey, John. Human Nature and Conduct: An Introduction to Social Psychology
(London: Allen and Unwin, 1922)
316 Bibliography
Experience and Nature (La Salle, IL: Open Court, 1971) [1925]
John Dewey: The Essential Writings, ed. David Sidorsky (New York: Harper
Torchbooks, 1977)
Durkheim, Emile. The Division of Labour in Society, tr. W. D. Halls (London:
Macmillan, 1984) [1893]
Edmonds, Thomas Rowe. Practical, Moral and Political Economy, or the Govern-
ment, Religion and Institutions Most Conducive to Individual Happiness and to
National Power (London: Effingham Wilson, 1828)
Ellis, Havelock. Man and Woman: A Study of Secondary and Tertiary Sexual
Characters, eighth revised edn (London: Heinemann, 1934)
Morals, Manners and Men (London: Watts, 1939)
Evrie, John H. van. White Supremacy and Negro Subordination; or Negroes a
Subordinate Race and (So-Called) Slavery its Normal Condition, second edn
(New York: van Evrie, Horton and Co., 1868)
Fages, C. 'L'Evolution du darwinisme sociologique', L'Humanite nouvelle,
3(1899), 28-42
Faguet, Emile. Le Feminisme (Paris: Societe Francaise d'Imprimerie et de
Iibrairie, 1910)
Ferguson, Adam. An Essay on the History of Civil Society, ed. D. Forbes
(Edinburgh University Press), 1966 [1767]
Ferri, Enrico. Socialism and Positive Science. (Darwin - Spencer - Marx), tr. from
the French edn E. C. Harvey (London: Independent Labour Party, 1905)
[1894]
Fischer, Eugen. 'Racial Differences in Mankind', in Bauer, Fischer and Lenz,
Human Heredity
Fiske, John. Outlines of Cosmic Philosophy Based on the Doctrine of Evolution with
Criticisms of the Positive Philosophy, 2 vols. (London: Macmillan, 1874)
Darwinism and Other Essays (London/New York: Macmillan, 1879)
The Life and Letters of Edward Livingstone Youmans (London: Chapman and
Hall, 1894)
The Meaning of Infancy (Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1909)
Galton, Francis. 'Hereditary Talent and Character', Macmillanys Magazine,
12(1865), 157-66,318-27
Hereditary Genius (London: Macmillan, 1869)
'Eugenics: Its Definition, Scope and Aims', American Journal of Sociology,
10(1904), 1-25
Gamble, Eliza Burt. The Evolution of Woman: An Inquiry into the Dogma of her
Inferiority to Man (New York/London: Putnam's Sons, 1894)
Gilman, Charlotte Perkins. The Yellow Wallpaper (London: Virago, 1983)
[1892]
Women and Economics, extracts in Hollinger and Capper, eds., The American
Intellectual Tradition, II, 55-60 [1898]
'Response to Wells' "Social Darwinism'", The American Journal of Sociology
12(1906-7), 713-14
The Man-Made World or Our Androcentric Culture (London: T. Fisher Unwin,
1911)
Goebbels, Paul Josef. The Goebbels Diaries, 1939-1941, ed. and tr. F. Taylor
(London: Sphere, 1983)
Bibliography 317
Weber, Max. From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology, tr. H. Gerth and C. Wright
Mills (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1948)
The Methodology of the Social Sciences, tr. E. A. Shils and H. A. Finch (New
York: The Free Press, 1949)
The Agrarian Sociology of Ancient Civilizations, tr. R. I. Frank (London: NLB,
1976)
'The Nation State and Economic Policy', in P. Lassman and R. Spiers, eds.,
Weber: Political Writings (Cambridge University Press, 1994)
Wells, D. Colin. 'Social Darwinism', The American Journal of Sociology,
12(1907), 695-708
Westermarck, Edward. The History of Human Marriage (London/New York:
Macmillan, 1891)
Woltmann, Ludwig. Die Darwinische Theorie und der Sozialismus: Ein Beitrag zur
Naturgesichte der Menschlichen Gesellschaft (Diisseldorf: Michels, 1899)
Woodhull, Victoria C. The Origin, Tendencies and Principles of Government or a
Review of the Rise and Fall of Nations (New York: Woodhull, Claflin, 1871)
Humanitarian Government (London: no publisher, 1890)
The Rapid Multiplication of the Unfit (London/New York: no publisher, 1891)
Wyatt, H. F. 'God's Test By War', The Nineteenth Century and After, 69(1911),
591-606
S O U R C E S P U B L I S H E D A F T E R 1945
Adams, James Eli. 'Woman Red in Tooth and Claw: Nature and the Feminine
in Tennyson and Darwin', Victorian Studies, 33(1989), 7-27
Adams, Mark, ed. The Wellborn Science: Eugenics in Germany, France, Brazil and
Russia (New York: Oxford University Press, 1990)
Alaya, F. J. 'Victorian Science and the "Genius" of Woman, Journal of the
History of Ideas, 38(1977), 261-80
Alaya, F. J. and T. Dobzhansky, eds. Studies in the Philosophy of Biology (London:
Macmillan, 1974)
Anderson, Stuart. Race and Rapprochement: Anglo-Saxonism and Anglo-American
Relations, 1895-1904 (London: Associated University Press, 1981)
Annan, Noel. Leslie Stephen: The Godless Victorian, revised edn (London:
Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1984)
Ardrey, Robert. The Territorial Imperative (London: Collins, 1967)
Arendt, Hannah. On Revolution (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1973)
The Origins of Totalitarianism (London: Andre Deutsch, 1986)
Aschheim, Steven E. 'Max Nordau, Friedrich Nietzsche and Degeneration",
Journal of Contemporary History, 28(1993), 643-57
Badcock, Christopher. Psycho-Darwinism (London: HarperCollins, 1994)
Ball, Terence and Richard Dagger. Political Ideologies and the Democratic Ideal
(New York: HarperCollins, 1991)
Bannister, Richard C. 'The Survival of the Fittest is our Doctrine: History or
Histrionics?5', Journal of the History of Ideas, 31(1970), 377-98
'William Graham Sumner's Social Darwinism: A Reconsideration', History of
Political Economy, 4(1973), 89-109
Bibliography 323
The Idea of Poverty: England in the Early Industrial Age (London: Faber and
Faber, 1984)
Hirst, Paul Q. Social Evolution and Sociological Categories (London: Allen and
Unwin, 1976)
Hofstadter, Richard. Social Darwinism in American Thought 1860-1915, revised
edn (Boston: Beacon Press, 1955) [1944]
Hollinger, D. and C. Capper, eds. The American Intellectual Tradition, vol. II:
1865 to the Present, second edn (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993)
Hughes, H. Stuart. Consciousness and Society: The Reorientation of European Social
Thought, 1890-1930 (St Albans: Paladin, 1974)
Hull, David. Darwin and His Critics: The Reception of Darwin's Theory of Evolution
in the Scientific Community (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,
1973)
'Darwinism as a Historical Entity: A Historiographic Proposal', in Kohn, ed.,
The Darwinian Heritage, 773-812
Jacob, Francois. The Logic of Living Systems: A History of Heredity, tr. B. E.
Spillman (London: Allen Lane, 1974)
Jann, R. 'Darwin and the Anthropologists: Sexual Selection and Its Discontents',
Victorian Studies, 37(1994), 287-306
Joll, James. Europe After 1870 (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1983)
Jones, Greta. 'The Social History of Darwin's The Descent of Mart, Economy and
Society, 7(1978), 1-23
Social Darwinism and English Thought: The Interaction Between Biological and
Social Theory (Brighton: Harvester Press, 1980)
Social Hygiene in Twentieth Century Britain (London: Croom Helm, 1986)
Jordanova, L. J. Lamarck (Oxford University Press, 1984)
Keller, Evelyn Fox. 'Language and Ideology in Evolutionary Theory: Reading
Cultural Norms into Natural Law', in James J. Sheehan and Martin Sosna,
eds., The Boundaries of Humanity: Humans, Animals, Machines (Oxford:
University of California Press, 1991), 85-102
Kelly, Alfred. The Descent of Darwin: The Popularization of Darwin in Germany,
1860-1914 (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1981)
Kershaw, Ian. The Nazi Dictatorship: Problems and Perspectives of Interpretation,
second edn (London: Edward Arnold, 1989)
Kevles, Daniel J. In the Name of Eugenics: Genetics and the Uses of Human Heredity
(Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1986)
Kiernan, V. G. 'Conscription and Society in Europe before the War of 1914—
18', in Foot, ed., War and Society, 141-58
Koch, H. W. 'Social Darwinism as a Factor in the "New Imperialism"' in
Koch, ed., The Origins of the First World War, second edn (London:
Macmillan, 1984), 319-42
Kohn, David, ed. TTie Darwinian Heritage (Princeton University Press, 1985)
Konner, Melvin. 'Human Nature and Culture: Biology and the Residue of
Uniqueness', in Sheehan and Sosna, eds., The Boundaries of Humanity, 103-
24
Korey, Kenneth, ed. The Essential Darwin (Boston: Little, Brown, 1984)
Krausnick, Helmut and Martin Broszat. Anatomy of the SS State, tr. D. Long and
M.Jackson (London: Granada, 1970)
Bibliography 329
adaptation, 11, 12, 45, 68, 126, 136-7, 145 Bannister, R., 4, 10
population growth as stimulus to, 48, 54 Barnes, John Strachey, 287-8
Spencer on, 84, 87-8 Bebel, August, 154-6, 158, 159, 257-8
Wilson on 'adaptiveness', 298-9 Bergson, Henri, 289
adultery, 300, 304 Bernhardi, Friedrich von, 208-9, 213,
Africa, colonisation of, 204-6 215
alcoholism, 78, 223, 244, 279 Bernstein, Eduard, 157, 158
altruism, 54, 86, 92, 93, 107, 270 Billig, Michael, 17
condemnation of, 189, 238 Binding, K., 232
female, 251, 252, 253-4, 255, 268 biology
modern sociobiological thought on, linkage of sociology and, 52, 54, 99, 103,
293-4,306 109, 137
and strict selectionism, problems of modern developments in, 293-4
reconciling, 29, 103, 108, 171, 173-4 see also determinism; reductionism
see also charity; Darwin, Charles birth control, 160-1, 276
American Civil War, 104, 201, 203 for the 'unfit', 96, 167, 223, 228, 230,
American Indians, 62, 201, 203 243, 245-6, 266
Ammon, Otto, 117, 198-9, 233, 289 see also castration; sterilisation
anarchism, 8, 151, 240-1 Bismarck, Otto von, 123, 144-5
* Anglo-Saxon' nations, 36, 172, 204, 210 Blind, Mathilde, 271
animals, continuities between humans and, Boer War, 226
28, 31, 136, 178, 296-7, 298, 299, Bourgeois, Leon, 179-80
300 Bowler, P., 16
animal breeding as model for human Brace, Charles Loring, 37, 99, 103, 146,
reproduction, 55, 216, 217, 229-30, 151
238 on compatibility of Darwinism and
anti-clericalism, 97, 124, 128, 130, 133, religion, 63, 64-5, 81, 121, 148
142-3, 148, 260 racial theory, 62-4, 104, 120, 200
anti-egalitarianism, 129, 138-40, 223, 240 Bradley, Francis Herbert, 223-6, 229, 231,
anti-Semitism, 133, 197, 236, 272, 275-6, 232
290 brain, 86, 93-4
see also Jews see also cranial measurement; intelligence
apes, descent from, see simian ancestry breeding, selective, 55, 216-17, 229-30,
Ardrey, Robert, The Territorial Imperative, 238,243
296, 297-8 Britain
Aryans, Nordic race, 107, 108-9, 127, 133, eugenics in, 216-18, 220-1, 222-31,
158,235 247
Nazi doctrine, 275-6, 281 Fascism, 287-8
theories of decline, 185, 193-7, 200 pioneering examples of Social
Australian Aborigines, 140, 235 Darwinism, 37, 67-74, 82-103
pre-Darwinian theories of social change,
Bagehot, Walter, 37, 67-73, 81, 99, 186, 45-6,48-51,54-8
298 reform Darwinism, 159-75
335
336 Index
Britain {com.) attitude to women, 36, 251-2
views on women and sexual difference, conception of heredity, 25, 26-7, 31, 44
251-2,253,255-7 Descent of Man (1871), 26, 27, 28, 36,
writings on racial and national conflict, 37, 147,223,251,260
184-5, 204-6, 209-10, 213-15 Expression of the Emotions in Man and
Buchner, Ludwig, 65-7, 73, 81, 103, 148, Animals (1872),36
151 influence in France, 124, 125, 127, 128
Burrow, J. W., 23 influence in Germany, 132, 134
influence in USA, 62, 104-5, 106
capitalism, 8, 67, 112, 152, 153, 295, 296 on inheritance of acquired characters, 4,
Carrel, Alexis, 241-2, 253 26,27
castration, 240, 241 and Lamarck, 17, 27, 39, 41-4
catchphrases, Darwinism as set of, 3-4, 10 and Malthus, 15-16, 50
Chamberlain, Houston Stewart, 185, 235 and mutability of species, 30, 41
Chambers, Robert, 37 and natural selection, 4, 26, 27-8, 29,
charity, 65, 86, 140-1, 189 30, 101-2, 147
condemned, 111, 129, 130, 195, 227, On the Origin of Species (1859), 25-7, 28,
242, 276 30, 36, 37, 62, 124, 125, 128, 132
see also welfare relationship to Social Darwinism, 3, 4, 6,
children 14-16, 17,35-8
perceptions of, 77, 81, 91, 98, 99 on sexual selection, 26, 27, 260
rearing of, 265, 270, 300, 301 and Spencer, 4, 14, 15, 37, 84, 87, 88
see also motherhood on struggle, 4, 15-16, 25-6, 29-30, 33,
Christianity, 214, 283 35, 42, 43, 304
denunciation of, 128, 142-4, 195 theory of evolution, 6, 25-30, 34, 36, 41,
see also Roman Catholic Church 119
class structure, 116-17, 185, 228 treatment of human evolution, 27-30,
primitive mentality reproduced in 41
modern lower classes, 70-1, 72 Darwin, Erasmus, 57-8
Cobbe, Frances Power, 259 Darwin, Major Leonard, 229-30, 231, 253
competition, see struggle Dawkins, Richard, 16, 296, 299, 302, 304,
Comte, Auguste, 52-4, 123, 255 306,311
Condorcet, Marquis de, 15 degeneration, 34, 64, 74, 216-17, 219-21,
conflict, see struggle 230
cooperation, social solidarity, 66, 90-1, Degler, C , 8, 295
102, 157, 177-82, 183,213 democracy, 67, 151, 162, 164
Cope, Edward Drinker, 104-5 denunciation of, 194, 198, 242
cranial measurement, 75, 76, 79, 193, 199, Desmond, A., 43
233,256 determinism, 31, 118, 122, 146, 174, 177
Crawford, C , 295 biological, 78-9, 158, 179, 191, 258,
creationism, 23, 55, 63, 105, 125-6, 186 279, 295
criminals, 141, 145, 227, 238, 301 Deweyjohn, 118, 146, 175-7, 183
concept of born criminal, 74-80, 158, Diamond, Jared, 299
263 disease
eugenic solutions, 167, 195-6, 222, beneficial effects in racial improvement,
239-40, 241, 243, 279, 280 222
Crook, D. P., 302 hereditary, elimination of, 225, 240,
cultural and biological transmission, 241-2,279
relationship between, 31, 52, 53, 160, see also sick, the
299-300, 307 division of labour, 49, 66, 136, 153
inequality as foundation for, 108, 125,
Daly, Martin, 306 138, 194
Darwin, Charles Robert, 31, 32, 68, 283 sexual, 249, 253, 256, 267-8, 305
on altruism, 28-9, 189, 247, 251, 293 DNA, 19,293
and assumptions underlying eugenics, Dobzhansky, T., 24
216-17,223,247 Durkheim, Emile, 12-13, 182
Index 337
economic competition, 160, 169, 172, 212, Fabian Society, 159, 160, 162
226, 263-4, 267, 282 Fabianism, 157, 159-68
Spencer's theory, 86, 93 family, condemnation of, 254-5
economic evolution, Molinari's theory, Fascism, 18, 156,272-3
131-2 Italian, 272, 273, 284-9, 290-1
economic selection, 196 feminism, 8, 129-30, 249, 255, 259-64,
Edinburgh University, 43 269
Edmonds, Thomas Rowe, 54-6 Ferguson, Adam, 48-50
education, 169,268 Ferrero, William, 77-8
and evolution, 226, 238, 267, 269, 277 Ferri, Enrico, 156-8, 252
of women, 238, 251, 253, 254 fertility, 102, 155
egalitarianism, 129, 138, 151, 182 concern over differential rates in
see also anti-egalitarianism; inequality; advanced societies, 218, 222, 226-7
women see also population growth
Einstein, Albert, 236 Fischer, Eugen, 233-4, 246
elitism, aristocracy, 116, 139, 223, 231, Fiske, John, 68, 106-8, 109, 114, 118,
237, 245, 246 120-1, 145, 148
Ellis, Henry Henry Havelock, 255-7 fitness, 84, 157,293
embryology, 134, 136 'inclusive', 293, 299, 301, 304, 306
Engels, Frederick, 152-3 Fondation pour l'Etude des Problemes
Enlightenment, 47-51, 54, 128, 198 Humaines, 241
environment, action of, 25, 26-7, 33, 40, Fox, Robin, 296
53, 155 France, 37, 123,272
and heredity, repective roles of, 44, feminist appropriation of Social
134-5, 162-3, 165, 218-19, 222, 241, Darwinism, 129-30, 259-60
307-8 racial theory, 186-9, 191-200, 211-13,
Spencer's theory, 84-8 239-40
see also adaptation; inheritance of solidarity movement, 179-80
acquired characters; struggle see also Darwin, Charles; eugenics;
essentialism, species, 30, 309 French Revolution; progress; struggle
see also human nature; Lapouge, G. free will, see determinism; will
Vacher de; race(s) freedom, see liberty
ethics, see morality French Eugenics Society, 218, 237
ethnocentrism, 295, 301, 304, 306 French Revolution, 67, 123, 194, 198, 199
eugenics, racial hygiene, 55, 96, 215, 264, Freud, Sigmund, 11
265-6, 267, 302
in Britain, 216-18, 220-1, 222-31, Galton, Sir Francis, 37, 117, 217-18
247 Gamble, Eliza Burt, 260-2, 264, 269-70,
and Fabians, 159, 164, 165, 166, 167 305
in France, 196-7, 218, 237-42 Gautier, Emile, 177
in Germany, 79-80, 133, 140-1, 145, Geddes, Patrick, 252
218, 232-7, 246, 276, 279-82 gender
relationship of Social Darwinism to, 6-7, relations, 254-5, 256-7, 258, 260, 261,
216-48,272 263
in the USA, 105, 218, 242-7 stereotypes, 250-1, 252, 255
Eugenics Congress, First International see also sexual differences
(1912), 218 genetics, 24, 231, 252, 293, 303
Eugenics Education Society, 218 genius, evolutionary significance of,
European races, 140 119-20, 121
Lapouge's theory of, 193-200 genocide, 272, 291
euthanasia, 232, 241, 279-80 Gentile, Giovanni, 286-7
evolutionary continuum, primitive Geoffroy Saint-Hilaire, Etienne, 42
mentality in modern humans, 36, germ-plasm theory, 33, 134, 171, 241
70-2,74-8,80,81,298 German Race Hygiene Society, 218
Spencer on, 91,98-9 German Social Democratic Party, 154,
Evrie, J. H. van, 63, 64 158
338 Index
Germany, 37, 65-7, 123-4, 132-45, 146, in Nazi ideology, 277, 278, 282
158-9,206-7 permanence of hereditary traits, 188,
imperialism, 204 189,190, 191,192-3,201-2
science of racial hygiene {see also and sociobiology, 307-8
eugenics), 232-7, 240, 241 Spencer on, 85, 87, 99
Third Reich, 215, 233, 290, 291 see also Darwin, Charles; environment;
uses of Social Darwinism, 8, 61-2, inheritance of acquired characters
207-8,272-3 heroism, 286, 290
women's movement, 264 Himmler, Heinrich, 246
see also Nazism; struggle Hirst, P. Q., 15
Gilman, Charlotte Perkins, 262-4, history
269-70, 305 Fascist conceptions of, 285-8
Gobineau, Arthur de, 185, 192, 198,233, Social Darwinism in revisionist
235 historiography, 9-10
Godwin, William, 15 Hitler, Adolf, 185, 215, 273-7, 279, 281-4
Goebbels, Paul Josef, 279, 280, 281, 283-4 Hitler's Secret Book, 273-4
Gould, S. J., 80 MeinKampf, 274, 290
green issues, 311 Hobbes, Thomas, 45-6, 51
Greene, J. C.,. 27 Hoche, A. E., 232
group, 186 Hofstadter, Richard, 3 - 4 , 8, 9
intra-group competition/conflict, 26, 42, Homo Alpinus (brachycephals), Lapouge's
85, 127, 178, 190, 208, 304 theory, 193-4, 196, 198, 199, 200
role in early stages of evolution, 69, 92, Homo Europaeus (dolichocephals),
213-14 Lapouge's theory, 193-4, 195, 196,
solidarity, 177-81,213 197,200
see also individual homosexuality, 279, 301
Gumplowicz, Ludwig, 117, 189-91,215, human nature, 45-6, 90, 97, 101, 188-9
310 belief in universal, 2 2 - 3 , 5 2 - 3 , 159,
gypsies, Nazi persecution of, 280-1 162-3, 164-5,284,298
challenges to notion of fixed human
habits, inheritance of, 121 essence, 22-3, 30, 46, 51, 128, 176,
Haeckel, Ernst, 10, 37, 106, 132-45, 147, 267, 309
151,298 continuity with animal behaviour, 28, 31,
anti-clericalism of, 133, 142-4, 148 136, 178, 296-7, 298, 299, 300
on dangers of charity and altruism, duality of, 213-14, 298
140-1, 189 Enlightenment theories, 48, 49, 54
on incompatibility of socialism and sociobiologists' thought on, 309-10
Darwinism, 138, 156 humanitarianism, condemned, 240, 242,
on inheritance of acquired characters, 276
27, 134 see also charity; welfare
monism of, 134, 143, 144, 195 humanity
racial theory, 139-40, 145 subject to same laws as rest of nature, 28,
on simian ancestry of humans, 136, 283 3 1 , 3 5 , 4 0 - 1 , 5 2 , 135-6, 178
on struggle for existence, 132, 135, unity of nature and, 45, 46, 47, 48, 191,
136-7, 138-9, 141, 146, 186 296-7, 298
Haller, M. H., 203 see also animals
Hardin, Garrett, 246 'hunter-gatherer rule', 300, 309
Haycraft, John Berry, 222-3, 229, 231, Huxley, Julian, 230-1, 233
232 Huxley, T. H., 43, 94, 142, 148, 168-70,
Hegel, G. W. R, Hegelianism, 51, 223, 171,251
286, 289 evolutionary theory, 34, 106, 174
Helvetius, Claude-Arien, 47-8
heredity, 33, 53, 68, 145, 147, 160, 171 ideologues, 39-40
and criminality, 74-80, 158, 167 ideology
and eugenics, 217, 219, 222, 226-7, ideological functions of Social
233-7,238,241,245,246 Darwinism, 7-8, 17-18, 295-6, 313
Index 339
relationship between world view and, Jones, Greta, 9
21-3,94 Jordanova, L. J., 42
imitation, 69
imperialism, 7, 8, 97, 148, 166, 203-6, 296 Keith, Sir Arthur, 213-15, 298
improvement, ideas of, 99 Kelly, A., 8
see also progress; self-improvement Key, Ellen Karolina Sofia, 265-9, 270
incest, 196, 270, 308 Kidd, Benjamin, 5, 6-7, 171-4, 175
Indiana, USA, sterilisation law, 242 Knox, Robert, 184-5
individual, 107, 119, 190, 211-12 Konner, Melvin, 304
or group as unit of selection? 28-9, 33, Kropotkin, Peter, 157, 177-9, 180-1
165, 189, 293-4, 297-8, 305-6 Kuper, Adam, 313
in Fascist and Nazi ideology, 274-5,
282, 286, 287-8 laissez-faire, 7, 9, 10, 13, 160
priority of collective over, 165-6, 207, critique of, 176,263
209, 213, 223-6, 229, 231, 240 Sumner's defence of, 110-11, 112, 113,
see also individualism; liberty; self- 115
improvement; self-interest; welfare see also individualism; liberalism
individualism, 9, 10, 110-15, 125, 176, Lamarck, Jean Baptiste, 9, 39-44, 53
215,235-6 Lamarckism, 42-4, 104, 134, 167, 235
see also laissez-faire; socialism; Spencer and Darwinism, 17, 27, 39, 41-4, 307
industrial society, 131, 218, 219 of Spencer, 87-8
Spencer on, 90, 92-4, 101 Lanessan, J.-L., de, 181-2
Sumneron, 110, 113, 116 Lankester, E. R., 220-1
see also economic competition Lapouge, G. Vacher de, 5, 117, 311
inequality, 125, 147, 156, 160 essentialism of, 192-3, 200, 284, 298,
biological foundations of, 127, 129, 130, 310
182,228-9,236 eugenics of, 196-7
see also division of labour; egalitarianism racial theory, 191-200, 289
infanticide, 240, 241, 276 theory of social selection, 193, 194-6,
'inferiority' and 'superiority', notions of, 200
217,245 Laveleye, Emile, 8
see also elitism; miscegenation; women Le Bon, Gustave, 186-9
inheritance of acquired characters, 32-3, Le Conte, Joseph, 201-2
44, 146-7 leadership, authority, 69, 91-2, 211, 212
Darwin's stance on, 4, 26-7 Lebensraum theory, 209, 274
endorsement of, 27, 68, 126, 134-5, Leeds, A., 10
139,238 Lenz, Fritz, 79-80, 81, 234-7, 246,
in Lamarckism, 39, 40, 42 252-3,313
rejection of, 191, 235, 241, 245, 307 Lewontin,R. C , 310
in Spencer's theory, 85, 87 liberalism, 147-8
see also heredity German, 132-3, 144, 145
insanity, 141, 167, 225, 227, 238, 245-6, Spencer's defence of, 89, 93, 94, 103
306 see also laissez-faire
instinct, 114, 121-2, 162-3 liberty, individual, 112, 113, 121, 128, 180,
intelligence, 176, 199 243
hereditary, 141, 163, 238, 245, 246 Lombroso, Cesare, 74-80, 99, 147, 151,
in racial theory, 239 245, 252, 253
Italy, 281 on primitive heritage in modern humans,
criminology, 74-80 75,76,77-8,80,81
Fascism, 272, 273, 284-9, 290-1 use of cranial measurement, 75, 76, 79,
199
James, William, 11, 68, 118-20, 121-2, Lombroso, Gina, 253-4, 255
146, 148 Lopreato, J., 295, 302, 307
Jews, 185,197,236 Lorenz, Konrad, On Aggression, 296
Nazi policy, 272, 275-6, 280-1, 291 Love, Rosaleen, 250-1
see also anti-Semitism love, evolution of, 265-6, 269
340 Index
Lyell, Sir Charles, 37 Mussolini, Benito, 156, 285, 286-7, 288,
289
Machtpolitik, 206, 209 mutualism, see cooperation
Malthus, Thomas Robert, Malthusianism,
15-16,50-1,53-4, 153,155 National Front Party, 307
marriage, 217, 255, 270, 282 National Socialism, see Nazism
inter-racial, see miscegenation nationalism, 186, 207, 214, 215, 228
Key's ideas on, 265, 266, 267, 269 nations, conflict between, 170, 184, 186,
monogamous, 265, 269-70, 300 199, 212-15, 223, 228, 285
no longer in accord with natural law, natural selection, 24, 56-7, 106-8, 120,
157,238,244 136-7, 224
o f unfit', prevention of, 223, 230, 241 biological principle extended to human
Marx, Karl, 152-3, 182 evolution, 28, 29-30, 37, 106-7
Marxism, 151, 152, 153-9 distinction between creative and
'masses, the', concept of, 67, 71-2, winnowing aspects, 84, 87-8, 96,
116-17, 171, 172 101-2, 104
Matabele Wars, 204-5 equated with maleness, 263, 264
Matthew, Patrick, 56-8 group versus individual as unit of
Mayhew, Henry, 74 selection, 28-9, 33, 165, 189, 293-4,
medical profession, and eugenics, 218 305-6
Mendelian genetics, 24, 252 minimised or denied, 11-12, 178-9,
mental defectives, elimination of, 216, 230, 180-1, 185
239, 243, 279-80 modern thinking on, 293, 305-7
militant society, militancy, 90-2, 97, 100, problems of application to advanced
110,113, 114 societies, 72, 87, 107-8, 264
militarism, 8, 66, 92, 207, 281 see also Darwin, Charles; sexual selection;
see also war social selection; Spencer; struggle
MillJ. S.,95, 161,254-5 nature, 23, 42-3, 125, 146, 188
miscegenation, 63-4, 80, 127, 200, 234, Darwinian picture of, 30, 33, 44, 45
236,239,241 dual aspect of, 18, 35, 183, 250, 261-2,
beneficial effects, 62-3 271,311-12
deleterious consequences, 185, 187, 192, as female, 183, 249-50, 262, 270, 271
196,202,229,239,275 as model for social practices and
Modern Synthesis, 19, 24, 293, 303 institutions, 114, 121, 137, 155, 159,
Molinari, Gustave de, 131-2 248, 269
monism, 134, 143, 144, 195 modern thinking on, 303-4, 311-12
'moral surgery', 224-6 monism, 134, 143, 144, 195
morality, ethics, 123, 129, 130, 174-5, Nazi representations of, 276-7, 282-3,
176, 195-6 284,311
development of moral faculty, 28-9, 92, pre-Darwinian conceptions of, 42, 45,
98, 102-3, 177 46, 47, 48
inheritance of moral disposition, 74-80 as threat, 67, 155, 161, 269
moral and natural law, relationship see also humanity
between, 287-8 Naturphilosophie, 144
notion of moral progress, 108, 169, 171, Nazism, 272-84, 292, 311
189-90,254-5 eugenic ideology, 233, 246, 276,
relationship to struggle for existence, 279-81
135, 168-71 Haeckel as forerunner of, 133, 134, 141,
sociobiological stance on, 298, 302 145
Morris, Desmond, The Naked Ape, 296 and Social Darwinism, 213, 272, 277-8,
Mosca, Gaetano, 11 279,280,282-4,289-91
motherhood, 282 see also nature; race(s); struggle
evolutionary basis to, 257, 267-8, 269 negro races, 62-3, 235, 243, 259
sterilisation of unmarried mothers, 279 neo-Darwinism, 33
see also children 'neo-Lamarckism, 104, 105
murder, 301,304 'New Liberalism', 89, 151, 171
Index 341
Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm, 213, 287, predation, 41, 42, 85, 299
289 primitives, savages, 235, 261
Nordau, Max Simon (originally Siidfeld), conceptualisations of, 68-70, 91, 100-2,
219-20 115-16, 126, 139-40, 171
Nordic race, see Aryans continuity of primitive in the modern,
Novicow, Jacques, 7, 8 298,310
primitive defined as starting point of
ontogenesis, 134, 136 evolution, 48-9, 98, 298
organs, use and disuse of, 25, 26, 27, 32, see also evolutionary continuum
39,40 progress, 5, 4 2 - 3 , 44, 146, 163-4, 198,
220
pacifism, 8, 33, 183, 198, 240, 266-7 American ideas on, 64, 107-8, 109, 114,
Pan German League, 145 121
parenthood, 227, 265, 270, 300, 301 Bagehot's definition, 68-70
see also motherhood Darwin's belief in, 34, 36
Pareto, Vilfredo, 11, 13 Enlightenment doctrines, 48-50
patriarchy, 8, 161, 250, 259, 260, 263, 269 French ideas on, 125, 126-7, 128
paupers, 55, 131-2, 169 German ideas on, 135, 136
condemnation of, 95, 99, 111, 145 Spencer on, 85-6, 92, 99, 146
proposed treatment of, 222, 228, 243, psychiatry, 11
245 psychology, 107, 234, 235
peaceful coexistence as evolutionary role of Darwinism in development of, 11,
outcome, 65-6, 86, 102, 107, 108, 162-3
114, 151
denial of, 114, 131,135 Quinton, Rene, 211
see also cooperation
Pearson, Karl, 226-9, 231, 232, 240, 241 race(s), 184-6, 247
Peirce, Charles Sanders, 118, 146, 175 American thought on, 62-4, 104, 105,
Peters, Carl, 204 120, 126,200-3
Pfeiffer, Franz von, 233 conflict between, 61-2, 85, 127, 140,
phrenology, 74 146, 158-9, 184-215
see also cranial measurement and crime, 79-80
physical anthropology, 74, 76, 79 in Fascist thought, 288-9, 290-1
physical defectives, 216-17, 230 formation of new, 63-4, 190, 191
condemnation of, 145, 225, 228 hierarchy of, 105, 139-40, 158, 184-5,
elimination of, 240, 279 203, 235, 239
Pick, D., 80 in Nazi ideology, 272, 274, 280-2, 290,
Poles, as Untermenschen, 281 291
political exploitation of evolutionary theory, as separate species, racial essentialism,
7-8, 43, 68, 169, 295-6, 313 63, 158, 187, 190, 191, 192-3, 200,
political science, political economy, 11, 202
124, 131 and sociobiology, 306-7
political selection, 194-5 see also France; miscegenation; racism
Politische-Anthropologische Revue, 158 racial hygiene, see eugenics
poor, see paupers racism, 12-13, 202, 203, 246, 281, 288
Poor Laws, 57, 83, 95 association of Social Darwinism with, 7,
pop ethology, 296-8, 301, 308, 309, 310 292, 295-6
population growth, 153, 160 rape theory, 300, 304
as cause of struggle for existence, 31, 32, Ratzel, Friedrich, 117, 209
85, 109, 110, 126,208,209 Reade, Winwood, 74
cause of struggle theory rejected, 73, reason, rationality, 128
240 growth of, 4, 51, 54, 86, 170, 172-3
decline in, 102,218 recapitulation theory of human
pre-Darwinian theories, 45, 47, 48, 50, development, 77, 91, 98
53-4, 56 reductionism, 177, 188
pragmatism, 118 biological, 136, 146-7, 199, 237, 238
342 Index
reform Darwinism, 6, 17, 151-83 sexual selection, 13, 32, 78, 265, 266, 270,
religion, 97, 173-4, 195 305
attempts to reconcile Darwinism with, Darwin's theory, 26, 27, 260
105, 107 female choice of mate, 258, 260-2, 264
belief in compatibility of Darwinism and, perversion of, 182, 238
63, 64-5, 81, 121, 148 Shaler, Nathaniel Southgate, 203
and science, 118-19, 142 Shaw, George Bernard, 7, 166-8
see also anti-clericalism; Christianity sick, the, 147, 238
revolution, 157, 158 elimination of, 140, 141, 145, 225, 230,
Richet, Charles, 237-41 240,241,279
Ridley, Matt, 299, 300-1, 309, 311 see also disease
rights, individual, 198, 238, 242 simian ancestry of humans, 28, 65, 105,
Ritchie, David G., 160-2, 168, 255 126,136, 142-3,283-4
Rocco, Alfredo, 285, 289, 291 slavery, 36, 63, 104
Rolle, Friedrich, 61-2, 146, 186 American attitudes, 62, 63, 116, 200,
Roman Catholic Church, 133, 142, 143, 201, 203
195,260 enslavement of women, 257, 261, 262,
Romanes, George, 11 263
Rosenberg, Alfred, 278 Slavs, Nazi policy on, 280
Rousseau, Jean Jacques, 126, 180 Smiles, Samuel, 88
Royer, Clemence-Auguste, 80, 124-31, social reforms, 110, 151, 161-2, 169, 176,
147, 151,204,313 182,218-19
anti-clericalism of, 124, 128, 148, 260 see also welfare
critique of charity for the 'unfit', 129, social relations, 153, 181, 304
130, 189 tension between biological and cultural
feminism of, 129-30, 259-60 explanations, 155-6, 169-70
on role of struggle and conflict, 126, see also cooperation; struggle
127-8, 146, 186 social sciences, and Social Darwinism,
study of human evolution, 37, 125-8, 8-14
298 social selection, 147, 244, 245, 276
on virtues of individualism and Lapouge's theory, 193, 194-6, 200
liberalism, 125, 128-9, 190 socialism, 8, 67, 110, 151, 172, 240
Ruse, M., 295 and individualism, 173, 174, 179
Russett, Cynthia Eagle, 249 relationship to Darwinism, 138, 152-70,
Russia, Russians, 196, 245, 281 182-3
sociobiology, 16, 19
savages, see primitives relationship to Social Darwinism, 292,
Schmidt, Oskar, 64, 132 294-313
Schneider, W. H., 237 socio-political theory, 15, 19, 21-4
science, 118-19, 134, 142 solidarity, social, see cooperation
and eugenics, 221, 231 Soloway, R. A., 247
see also biology Sorel, Georges, 289
self-improvement, self-help, 43, 64-5, 83, specialisation, 45, 49, 54, 92, 135, 136
88 Marxist view of, 153-4
self-interest, 46, 101, 293-4, 306 see also division of labour
Selous, Frederick Courtney, 204-6 species essentialism, 30, 309
sexual differences, 78, 161, 249-71 see also race(s)
cultural explanations, 254-5, 257, Spencer, Herbert, 82-103, 118, 151, 156,
258-9, 260 163,313
evolution of, 251-64 anti-clericalism of, 97, 148
sociobiological thinking on, 300-1, belief in progress, 85-6, 92, 99, 146
305 and Darwinism, 4, 6, 14, 15, 37, 43, 80,
see also division of labour; gender; sexual 82-3, 84, 87, 88
selection on female suffrage, 252, 255
sexual equality, see women general evolutionary theory ('cosmic
sexual love, 265-9 evolution'), 82, 83-8, 92, 96
Index 343
on human nature, 90, 97, 101 suffrage, universal, 112, 151
individualism, 83, 89, 92-3, 94, 96, 98, female, 66, 164, 252, 255
169, 190 Sumner, William Graham, 109-18, 146,
influence in USA, 105-6, 107, 109 147, 202, 204
and Lamarckism, 87-8 Folkways, 115-17
on natural selection, 84, 87-8, 96, opposition to democratisation and
101-2, 102-3 welfare schemes, 110, 112-13, 148,
opposition to imperialism, 97, 148, 204 168
political thought, 82, 89, 93-8 Social Darwinism of, 10, 109-11, 117,
Social Darwinism of, 81, 95, 98-103, 120-1
121 views on warfare, 110, 114, 121, 145
theory of socio-political evolution, superiority, see 'inferiority' and 'superiority'
89-93, 98, 100-1, 113-14, 147, 298, survival of the fittest, 4, 8-9, 26, 102, 115,
310 126, 182, 187
on warfare, 7, 85-6, 92-3 Hitler on, 274-5
stage theory of development, 48-50 Spencer on, 82, 84, 87, 88
state, 66, 67, 131, 142, 214, 285-6 see also natural selection
critique of interventionist, 89, 93-4, 96, Sweden, 264
110,112-13, 115,117
endorsement of strong, 133, 151, 190 Tennyson, Alfred, 1st Baron, 'In
Stephen, Leslie, 170-1, 174, 175 Memoriam', 250
sterilisation, enforced, 241, 242, 246, 279 territoriality, 297
Sternhell, Z., 9 Teutons, 236
Stoddard, Lothrop, 237, 244-6 thermodynamics, 5
'strongest, law of the', 55-6, 69 Thomas, William Isaac, 258-9
struggle, competition, 8-9, 33-4, 145-6, Thomson, J. Arthur, 252
177-9,271 Thornhill, R. and N. W., 300
in American thought, 109-10, 111, 114, Tiger, Lionel, 296
115-16, 117 totalitarianism, 8, 177
in English thought, 69-70, 72-3, 84-6, Treitschke, Heinrich von, 206-7, 209
92-3, 102-3, 168-72 tribalism, 69, 92, 98, 100, 101, 213-14,
Fascist views of, 285, 287, 288, 290 215,261
in French thought, 12-13, 41-4, 126,
127-8, 181-2, 187,240 underclass, 95, 98, 115, 147, 243
in German thought, 11-12, 65-7, 132, Under-Men, Untermenschen, concept of,
135, 136-7, 138-9, 141, 146 245,281
between individual and environment, 26, 'unfit', category of, 95-6, 113, 115, 145,
64-5, 110,181 147, 171,264
inter-species (see also nations; races), 26, control of reproduction, 96, 167, 223,
127 228, 230, 243, 245-6, 266
intra-species, 26, 42, 85, 127, 178, 190, elimination of, 44, 229, 240, 241,
208 279-80
modern thinking on, 299, 303-4, and obstruction of natural selection, 188,
311-12 216,222,227,244,246
in Nazi ideology, 273-5, 276, 278-9, United States, 145, 175, 196, 258
282, 284 eugenics movement, 105, 218, 242-7
pre-Darwinian theories, 45, 46, 47-8, Social Darwinism in, 13, 37, 62-5,
49,51,54-6 104-22, 148
replaced by social solidarity, 177-82, see also progress; race(s)
183 urbanisation, 218, 219
socialist perspectives on, 152, 154-7, utilitarianism, 170, 173
158-9, 160, 161, 163-4
transformation into peaceful process, Valois, George, 211-13
29-30, 65-7, 102, 127-8, 156, 161 variation, 4, 65, 84, 126, 127, 171, 188
see also Darwin, Charles; economic causes of, 32-3, 68, 104, 116, 119, 120,
competition; population growth; war 186
344 Index
Darwinian theory, 24, 25, 29 opposition to collective schemes, 95, 96,
see also environment; inheritance of 111, 113, 148, 170-1,227
acquired characters see also charity
Veddahs, 140, 235 Wells, D. Colin, 244
Virchow, Rudolf, 138 Westermarck, Edward Alexander, 117,
Volkisch philosophy, 275, 277, 278 270,308
Vorzimmer, P., 15-16 Wilberforce, Samuel, 142
will, volition, 167, 204, 287
Wallace, Alfred Russel, 28, 37, 50, 151, denial of free, 137, 192
161, 169, 186 see also determinism
Wallas, Graham, 162-5, 168, 174, 219, Williams, Raymond, 8-9
310,313 Wilson, Edward Osborne, 294, 296,
war, 46, 121-2, 145-6, 178, 263 298-302 passim, 304, 305, 306, 309
beneficial effects of, 7, 42, 212, 215, 279, Wilson, Margo, 306
286 Woltmann, Ludwig, 158-9, 204
condemned between advanced nations, women
54, 75, 127-8 biological explanations of 'inferiority',
contribution to progress, 13, 49, 55, 81, 91, 98, 122, 188, 235, 252-3
85-6,92,210-11 cultural explanations for subordinate
dysgenic consequences of modern, 93, position, 129-30, 147, 254-5, 257,
163, 195, 214-15, 266-7, 276 260-3
endemic in social relations, 49, 110, 114, education of, 238, 251, 253, 254
187,304 emancipation of, 66, 151, 161, 164, 249,
eradication of, 107, 108 252, 253, 255
rationalisations of, 51, 206-15 equality of, 143, 161, 255, 256-7, 258,
replaced by industrial competition, 86, 259-64, 268
92-3, 131-2, 145-6, 171-2, 182-3, offenders, 77-8
267 thesis of original superiority, 258, 259
role in early stages of evolution, 33, 54, see also Darwin, Charles; motherhood;
6 9 , 7 2 - 3 , 7 5 , 126, 131 sexual differences; sexual selection
see also struggle Woodhull, Victoria C , 105, 243-4
Ward, Lester Frank, 13, 258, 262 World Federation, Fiske's concept of, 107,
Webb, Sidney and Beatrice, 162, 165-6, 108
167, 168 world view
Weber, Max, 11-12, 13, 307 distinction between ideology and, 21-4
Weindling, P. J., 232 Social Darwinism as, 17, 18, 30-5
Weismann, August, 33, 44, 88, 134, 171, World War I, 206, 233, 234, 245
191,222,308 World War II, 213
welfare, personal, 151, 173 Wyatt, Harold F., 210, 213, 215
individual or collective responsibility? 67,
96,113,168, 170 Youmans, Edward Livingstone, 105-6
Young, R. M., 15