PHL 104 Note Compilations
PHL 104 Note Compilations
By
HON. EXPONENT
*** Click on any part of the “automated” TABLE OF CONTENTS to take you directly
to the page you want to go.
PHL 104: Introduction to Philosophy II: Critical Thinking, Argument and Evidence
General Introduction
By
Dr. J.O. Famakinwa
This general introduction was unintentionally omitted in the course outline earlier sent to the
class. However, it is important to do a brief introduction of the course in order to appreciate
the current academic terrain. It is equally necessary to inform the class that PHL 104 is a
continuation of PHL 101. The class will recall that the latter focused on Ethics, Metaphysics
and Epistemology. However, the current class focuses on Logic. What then is logic?
Logic, as a branch of Philosophy, could be defined thus:
i. Logic is one of the core branches of Philosophy. It sets standards and rules for
correct reasoning.
ii. Irving M. Copi and Carl Cohen define logic as “the study of the methods and
principles used to distinguish good (correct) from bad (incorrect) reasoning.”1
According to Chakraborti, logic is a branch of Philosophy that is “dedicated to the
study of reasoning.2
iii. Logic, through its methods and principles, provides structures that enable correct
thinking or reasoning.
iv. Logic is a special branch of philosophy because it provides the solid foundation
upon which all other branches of philosophy rest. Arguments and debates in Ethics,
Metaphysics, Epistemology and even all disciplines outside Philosophy, are
expected to be logical. Engaging in correct reasoning is almost a duty not only in
Philosophy but in all human endeavours.
v. The methods and principles of logic are good tools for analysis across various
disciplines. This explains the constant and eternal relevance of logic in all human
endeavours. As a matter of fact, when the physical structures of the whole world
collapse, in case they collapse, it is only the logical structures or forms that would
remain because logical structures are everlasting and indestructible. The methods
and principles of logic will outlive the current physical world.
vi. The methods and principles of logic are universal. Such methods and principles are
universal in the sense that no human society denies them. A denial would lead to an
obvious contradiction. The class will learn about contradiction before the end of the
current semester.
1
Copi I. M. & Cohen C. 2000. Introduction to Logic New Delhi: Prentice-Hall of India. p.2
2
Chakraborti C. 2007. LOGIC: Informal, Symbolic and Inductive New Delhi: Prentice-Hall of India. p.1
viii. Finally, the flexibility of logic is allowed in order to create room for creativity,
which could lead to new material and non-material inventions. New inventions
could lead to different species of development; political, economic, social,
scientific, technological, cultural and even intellectual. 3 The next section briefly
explains the two kinds of logic.
2. Kinds of Logic
Logic is not only a branch of Philosophy but also a branch of Mathematics. Today, the
applications of logic “are well known in the area of artificial intelligence” especially in
computer science and technology.4 Traditionally, there are two kinds of logic:
i. FORMAL Logic: This is also known as classical logic or classical first order logic.
Formal logic rests on the discovery that “statements in natural language have
underlying logical forms.” 5Experts in Formal logic are of the view that behind
observable statements in natural language, there are un-observables. The study of
formal logic reveals such un-observables. You will learn more about Formal Logic
from Dr. (Mrs) O.O. Badejo in PHL 201/204 in Part Two.
ii. INFORMAL Logic: This kind of logic focuses on the quality of reasoning that
occurs in every day conversations or “exchange of words in media reports, in
advertisement, in legal briefs, political debates…”6
In the current semester, the class will focus on INFORMAL Logic. All issues listed in the
course outline earlier sent come under informal logic. The next class will start to look at
Theories of Meaning. You are all welcome on board. Please enjoy your flight to the world of
Critical or Reflective Thinking.
3
Famakinwa J.O. 2012. “Is the Unexamined Life Worth Living or Not” in Think: Philosophy for Everyone (A
Journal of The Royal Institute of Philosophy), Number 31, pp.97-103.
4
Chakraborti C. 2007. LOGIC: Informal, Symbolic and Inductive New Delhi: Prentice-Hall of India. p.8
5
Ibid. p.8
6
Ibid. p.8
(b). Pragmatic Use of Language: Language is used pragmatically when it serves the
directive function or it is used to cause or prevent an overt action. The clearest examples are
commands and requests. When a parent tells a child to wash up for dinner, the intention is not
to communicate any information or to express or evoke any particular emotion. The language
is intended to get results, to cause action of the indicated kind. When a theatregoer says to the
ticket seller, “Two please”, the language is being used directively to produce action. Between
commands and requests, the differences may be subtle. Almost any command can be
converted into a request with suitable changes in the tone of voice, or merely by the addition
of the word ‘please’. A question may also be classified as directive discourse when, as
ordinarily, it is posed in order to request an answer.
1. Introduction
The aim and objective of this module is to introduce students to different ways in which they
can use inverted commas to achieve clarity in the presentation of their thoughts. Apart from
the usual use of inverted commas to indicate that you are quoting the ideas under inverted
commas verbatim from another source, this module will teach you how you can use inverted
commas to distinguish between when you are using a word and when you are simply
mentioning it. It will also teach you to know when inverted comma is used as scare quotes to
warn you that a particular word or phrase is being used in a particular way to convey some
special meaning.
2. Use and Mention
In Use and Mention, inverted commas are used to distinguish a word from what it names.
It is often convenient to have a way to make it certain when we are using a word and when
we are talking about the word itself. We use words to talk about, refer to, or mention some
things in the world. We use the word “dog” to talk about, refer to, or mention some canine
creature that walks on four legs, sometimes kept as pets or for security. The word “sin” refers
to, or mentions some sort of religious or moral failing. “Love” refers to or mentions the
emotional state of attraction to other being. According to this convention, the name of a word
is formed by putting inverted commas or what you call quotation marks around the word
itself. A word in quotation marks or inverted commas is the name of a word that is mentioned
or talked about.
It is this that makes it possible to say “Love” has four letters. Love which “Love”
mentions is an emotional state in human beings in the world, it cannot have four letters. What
has for letters is the word “Love” which mentions Love which is an emotional state. The
same thing goes for “Dog” has three letters. Dog is an animal in the world which is
mentioned or referred to by the three letters “Dog”.
Consider these statements and the use of inverted commas:
(a) The word “” Ibadan”” is the word we shall use to refer to the word “Ibadan” which refers
to Ibadan, the capital of Oyo state in Nigeria.
Here, you can see that the first Ibadan has two sets of inverted commas because it refers to
the second Ibadan which is also a word that refers to or mention Ibadan a city in Nigeria.
That is why the second Ibadan has only one set of inverted commas, and the third Ibadan has
no inverted comma because it is a city which actually exists in the world.
(b) The word “””Ibadan””” refers to “”Ibadan”” which refers to “Ibadan” which is a name
that refers to Ibadan a city in Nigeria.
The difference between (a) and (b) is in the number of the words Ibadan and that determines
the number of sets of inverted commas. In (a) Ibadan appears three times and only one
appearance refers to the city, while in (b), Ibadan appears four times and only one out of four
PHL 104: Introduction to Philosophy II: Critical Thinking, Argument and Evidence
Module 3: Theories of Meaning (Part 1)
By
Dr. J.O. Famakinwa
In the last class, we briefly talked about the primary concerns of logic as a branch of Philosophy
and Mathematics. The current class will focus on Theories of Meaning. The first information
the class is needed to be provided with is that language is the primary weapon in the hand of a
good philosopher. Philosophy requires a good command of language. In view of this initial
observation, Philosophy of language is the root of Philosophy and, as a matter of fact, the root
of analytic Philosophy. The qualifier ‘Analytic’ is from the word ‘Analysis/Analyses’.
Philosophy analyzes and interprets words, concepts, statements, sentences and thoughts etc,
with a view to knowing their meanings. To analyze is to break words, statements, sentences
and specific thoughts into their various parts, just the way a roadside mechanic could break or
dismantle a car into its various parts. The need to know the meaning of certain words and
expressions became a central issue in the analytic and Continental Philosophy of the 20th
Century. Without the knowledge of the meaning of a word or expression, it is difficult, if not
totally impossible, to know how they are used or should be used in human communication.
In his book Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus Ludwig Wittgenstein emphasizes the centrality of
language to philosophy. According to Wittgenstein, major problems in Philosophy arise due
the misuse and mismanagement of language. Wittgenstein says that endless disagreements,
debates, and arguments among Philosophers persist because “the logic of our language is
misunderstood.”7 In his view, all controversial problems in Philosophy would end once the
language in which such controversies are carried out is analyzed just the way a watch-repairer
dismantles a faulty wrist-watch in order to restore the wrist-watch back to its functional state.
Now, it is time the class addressed specific questions in order to make relevant issues about the
centrality of language to Philosophy clearer. However, before the questions, check the
following group of words and expressions below:
Group 1: Table, Lion, Fire, Cup,
Group 2: Good, Bad, Right, Wrong
Group 3: 2+2=4,
Group 4: God, Angel, Spirit (either holy or unholy)
Group 5: There is a table in the room, There are two cars in from of the house
Group 6: Killing is bad, It is good
Group 7: Spirit is spiritual, God exists, God does not exist
Group 8: Abuja is the capital of Oyo State
7
Wittgenstein L. T 1969. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul) p. 3
ii. How did you arrive at their meaningfulness or meaninglessness of those you
consider meaningful or meaningless? Briefly explain
Your response to the question is being expected.
Anyway, in order to know the meaning of words, statements and expressions such as in groups
1-9 above, Analytic Philosophers have formulated different Theories of Meaning. For instance,
under the influence of Bertrand Russell and Ludwig Wittgenstein, the Logical Positivist School
emerged around 1924 under the leadership of Moritz Schlick and Mathematician Hans Han.
The Logical Positivist School is also known as Logical Empiricist School or Scientific
Empiricist School or simply the Vienna Circle.8 The primary aims of the Vienna Circle are:
1. To protect science and its methodology. Members of the Vienna Circle are of the view
that the method of science is the best method for understanding the physical world you
and I currently occupy.
2. To develop theories of meaning that will promote science and eliminate all
metaphysical, ethical and religious claims through the analysis of language.
The current class will end at this point. The second part of the current class will look at major
theories of meaning. Among theories of meaning to be considered are:
1. The Picture Theory of Meaning/
2. Referential Theory of Meaning
3. The Use Theory Meaning
4. The Emotive Theory of Meaning
5. The Prescriptivist Theory of Meaning
Thank you.
8
Blackburn S. Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005) p. 214
P PHL 104: Introduction to Philosophy II: Critical Thinking, Argument and Evidence
Module 3: Theories of Meaning (Part II)
By
Dr. J.O. Famakinwa
The Part I of the current class addressed the centrality of language to Philosophy. The focus
was the analytic orientation in Philosophy, especially that of Ludwig Wittgenstein and some
of his disciples in the Vienna Circle. On page 37 of Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus
Wittgenstein declares:
‘All Philosophy is a Critique of Language…’9
Meaning that in any disagreement between two philosophers, each philosopher is only
responding to the way other philosopher uses language. The current class will briefly address
specific theories of meaning. Among such theories are: the Picture Theory of Meaning, the
Use Theory of Meaning and the Referential Theory of Meaning. Let us start with the
Picture Theory of Meaning.
The Picture Theory of Meaning is formulated by Ludwig Wittgenstein. It says that a word or
proposition or statement is meaningful if it pictures reality. In Wittgenstein view, ‘to picture
reality’ is to state fact(s) about the only physical world you and I currently occupy because ‘the
world is the totality of facts and not of things.’10 Any word or proposition or statement that
does not fulfill this condition is meaningless. For examples:
1. All human beings are biped (beings with two feet)
2. Birds fly
3. Any Unsupported object in space falls
Propositions 1, 2 and 3 are meaningful because they state facts about human beings, birds and
direction of any unsupported object in space. Besides, Wittgenstein formulates three kinds of
propositions:
i. Propositions with Sense: these are propositions that fulfill the conditions of
meaningfulness stated in the Picture Theory of Meaning above. They are
propositions with sense because they are verifiable through any of the human five
senses. Now, try and identify propositions with sense among Group 1 to 9 in the
previous class. Write down other examples of propositions that will qualify as
propositions with sense.
iii. Non-Sensical Propositions: these are propositions that neither state facts about the
physical world nor measure reality accurately. Non-sensical propositions are also
senseless because they are neither part of the physical structures of the Universe nor
derived from any of the five senses or verifiable through any of such senses. For
example, propositions such:
2. In view of 1 above, it is argued that the Picture Theory of Meaning is too narrow a
theory of meaning.11
Major criticisms of the picture theory of meaning are so strong and convincing to the point that
Ludwig Wittgenstein himself drops the theory and replaced it with what is known as The Use
Theory of Meaning in another book of his, Philosophical Investigation published in 1953.
According to Wittgenstein, Language is like a game and there is no game that does not have
its own rules. Do you agree with the last point or not? If you do not agree then provide an
example of a game without any rule or set of rules.
Just like a game, every language has its own rules that must be followed by speakers of the
language. Communication would breakdown if rules of a language are not followed by
language speakers. In view of this observation, The Use Theory of Meaning states:
11
For more criticisms of the Picture Theory of Meaning see Honderich T. The Oxford Companion to Philosophy
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005). P. 719
12
Wittgenstein L. Philosophical Investigation 3rd edition G.E. Anscombe (Trans) (New York: The Macmillan
Company, 1959) p.220
P PHL 104: Introduction to Philosophy II: Critical Thinking, Argument and Evidence
Module 4: Definitions (Part I)
By
Dr. J.O. Famakinwa
The last class addressed the concluding part of Theories of Meaning. The current Module
provides a detailed explanation of Definitions. Three key issues will be addressed:
1. Definitions/ what are they?
2. Kind of Definitions
ii. Definiens: it refers to what defines the word that is being defined14
Try and identify definiendum and definiens in the following examples:
1. A triangle is a three-sided figure (True)
5. 4 is 3+5 (False)
13
Copi I. M. & Cohen C. 2000. Introduction to Logic New Delhi: Prentice-Hall of India. p.169
14
Ibid. p.169
The following points could be made from definitions listed in 1-8 above:
i. True and false definitions are definitions
ii. True and false definitions are meaningful. You need to note that the very fact that
someone offers a false definition does not make the definition meaningless. A false
definition is as meaningful as a true definition. A factually false statement or
proposition is a meaningful statement or proposition.
iii. Is it possible to have a definition that is neither true nor false? Although there could
be such definitions, I cannot think of one because definitions are usually in form
of a statement. In logic, any statement is either true or false.
3. Enumerative definition
4. Synonyms
PHL 104: Introduction to Philosophy II: Critical Thinking, Argument and Evidence
Module 4: Definitions (Part II)
By
Dr. J.O. Famakinwa
In Part I of Module 4, the class defined a definition, definiendum, definien and the difference
between a statement and a sentence. The current class will provide a detailed explanation of
different kinds of definitions, and how definitions go bad. Among the kinds of definitions to
be considered are Stipulative, Reportive (Lexical, Technical and Historical), Enumerative,
Synonyms and Definition by Mentioning Examples (Ostensive and Mentioning an Example).
Let us start with the Stipulative Definition.
1. Stipulative Definition: the primary goal of a stipulative definition is creativity and the
expansion of knowledge. A stipulative definition is a definition that announces a
deliberate decision to use a word or an expression in a particular way. For example, an
author of a book or a writer of an article or essay can make a pronuncement at the
beginning of his or her book or essay thus:
‘In this book, by ‘blue’ I mean ‘love’/or/ In this essay, by ‘OA’ I shall mean ‘objective
assessment’ /or/ In this article, by ‘Christmus’ I shall mean someone who is neither a
Christian nor a Muslim.
Basically, a stipulative definition clearly states a special sense in which a word is going to be
used or actually used in a piece of work, in order to notify and guide readers about its special
meaning.
2. Reportive Definition: Unlike stipulative definition, Reportive definition clearly states
how a word is generally used among language speakers. There are three types of
Reportive Definition; Lexical, Technical and Historical Definitions. Let us consider a
brief explanation of each.
(a). Lexical Definition: It is a definition that states or describes the ordinary or general
meaning of a word as used by language speakers. A good example of lexical definition
is the dictionary meaning, e.g. Table (a piece of furniture), Father (A male parent) etc
(c). Historical Definition: refers to the meaning of a word in the past. For example, the
word ‘Bougeoisie’ used to mean ‘a gentleman’. Today, the same word means ‘a man
or a woman with a lot of economic power or wealth that enables him or her to own and
control the basic means of production and the labour power of others’.
Note: Not all words can be defined by enumeration. There are some words that are not
definable by enumeration e.g. Water, Salt, Sand etc
i. Ostensive Definition: The word ‘Ostensive’ is derived from the word ‘Ósten’
which means “display’ or ‘to display’. A word is defined ostensively by pointing
at or exhibiting the concrete object the word refers to among language speakers.
If you are asked to define a word ostensively, what you need to do is to point at
the object or raise the same object and make a verbal pronouncement. To define
the word ‘cup’ ostensively, you only need to point at a cup and say ‘cup’ or you
raise the cup and make a verbal pronouncement, ‘cup’.
There are things to be avoided when defining a word. When we are asked to define a
word, it is important to pay attention to some possible but avoidable errors in presenting
our definitions. Among things to be avoided are hereby mentioned below:
2. Too Narrow or Too Broad Definitions: A definition should not be too narrow or too
broad. A bad definition either excludes too much or includes too much. A definition that
either excludes too much or includes too much is bad. For example;
Wale’s definition of ‘talent’ is too narrow (it excludes too much) because there are so
many other abilities talented people possess. Again, consider the definition of the word
‘Chair’ as ‘a piece of Furniture’. The definition is bad because it includes too much. A
piece of furniture could refer to so many other items e.g. table, cabinet, cupboard. Again
consider the definition of the word ‘uniform’ as ‘a common attire worn by Policemen
and Policewomen’. Is this too broad or too narrow?
All these are bad definitions because they are metaphorical. For instance, the word ‘Lion’
is better defined as ‘an animal in the family of cat.’
PHL 104: Introduction to Philosophy II: Critical Thinking, Argument and Evidence
ARGUMENTS (I)
By
DR. O.O. BADEJO & DR. A.O. ALADE
WHAT IS AN ARGUMENT?
■ When you hear the word ‘argument’ what comes to mind?
■ Probably a scene where two people or more raise their voices at each other in anger
trying to ‘outshout’ the other.
■ However, this is not what an argument entails.
■ In philosophy, an argument is a set of statements presented to persuade an audience to
accept a position.
■ One of the statements in a simple argument is the position that the arguer wants to
convince the audience of, while the other(s) is/are the reason(s) why the arguer wants
the audience to accept the conclusion. These reasons are called the grounds or the
premises of the argument.
■ The position the arguer wants to convince the audience of is known as the claim or
the conclusion, while the reason(s) why the arguer wants the audience to accept the
claim is the ground(s) or the premise(s).
■ Simply put, a simple argument consists of a claim or conclusion and one or more
ground(s) or premise(s).
■ The conclusion of an argument is the statement stating the position that an arguer is
trying to defend.
■ The premises are facts, data, information, concepts, or definitions which are knowable
to all the parties involved in assessing the argument. Where the premises are not
knowable to some party in the argument, we cannot have a successful argument.
■ Examples:
1. A woman carries her pregnancy alone, she bears all the pain and discomfort of
pregnancy. More so, a foetus is a parasite since it depends on its host for everything.
Hence, the decision on abortion should be left solely to the woman and not to any other
gender, religion or group.
2. All animals are mortals. All humans are animals. Therefore, all humans are mortals
3. Jingo had a pistol with him at the stadium during the games. Jingo fatally shot
Bongo during the games. Therefore, Jingo deserves to be punished.
ANATOMY OF AN ARGUMENT
- The two major parts of an argument are the premises/grounds and the claim/conclusion.
- However, in the process of argumentation, there is usually a need to defend, or challenge,
claims by providing certain backings or exceptions to the arguments.
Thus, the process of argumentation involves certain other elements which are sometimes not
obvious in the body of the arguments.
- These other elements in an argument serve other justificatory functions that helps an
argument to withstand criticisms.
- Stephen Toulmin suggested that a good argument should consist of six
components/elements.
These elements are claim, ground, warrant, backing, qualifier, and rebuttal.
- As explained earlier, the claim is the assertion/position an arguer makes and wants to
defend.
- The ground is the reason, evidence, justification for why the claim ought to be accepted.
- Asides the claim and the ground there are four other elements.
WARRANT
- A warrant is a general statement that justifies an arguers movement from the
ground/premises to the claim/conclusion.
- In other words, a warrant connects the premises of the argument to the conclusion and
answers the question ‘why’ the conclusion ought to be accepted, given the premises.
- The warrants for arguments vary depending on the context of the argument, or the relevant
field of inquiry. The warrants may be legal, sociological, psychological, medical, ethical,
theological, scientific, logical, etc.
- For instance, the warrant for example (3) in the examples given can be “anyone who kills
BACKING
- A backing is a widely held belief, law, custom or truth that justifies the warrant.
- A backing provides the justification for the warrant of an argument.
- A backing is usually a principle, statute, law, decree, etc., which is not obsolete,
controversial or obscure, and it must be relevant to the warrant.
- For instance, the backing for the argument in example (ii) above may be some stated law in
the relevant section of the nation’s criminal code.
- The criminal act code of Nigeria for example stipulates that murder should be punished
under the law.
- Hence, this is a backing, a justification for the warrant.
QUALIFIER
- A qualifier states the level of confidence the arguer has in the claim given the grounds.
- A qualifier states if the claim is absolute or not. Qualifiers indicate the degree of strength of
the argument.
- In other words, a qualifier indicates the degree of confidence that the arguer has towards the
conclusion given the premises of the argument.
- It is usually a word of phrase which expresses how strongly the arguer affirms the
conclusion of the argument.
- When the evidence is not sufficient to guarantee the conclusion, non-absolute qualifiers
such as the following may be adopted; ‘presumably’, ‘very likely’, ‘probably’, ‘tentatively’,
etc. However, when the evidence guarantees the conclusion, absolute qualifiers such as the
following may be adopted; ‘necessarily’, ‘certainly’, ‘logically’, ‘definitely’, etc.
- The non-absolute qualifiers are usually adopted in arguments within the context of history,
law, social sciences, sciences, management, etc. the absolute qualifiers are mostly applicable
in mathematics and logic.
- A qualifier for the example (3) can be ‘very likely’ for example.
REBUTTAL
- As stated earlier, the warrants of various arguments are general statements which provide
the link between the premises and conclusion of the argument.
- However, most of these warrants allow for reasonable exceptions when necessary. Such
exceptions are known as rebuttals.
- A rebuttal tries to show that the link between the premises and conclusion is weaker in the
relevant context.
- Rebuttals are expressed in words or phrases such as ‘provided that’, ‘unless’, etc.
For instance, the rebuttal for example (3) can be ‘unless it was in self defence’.
- The rebuttal anticipates a likely objection to the argument and states such objection.
EXAMPLE (1)
- Let us consider this example:
Dende should be sentenced to death.
Claim: Dende should be sentenced to death (This is what the arguer wants her audience to
accept.
Grounds: He robbed a store at gun point
He held three children hostage
He shot the security man and killed him
He shot the lady in charge of the safe and injured her. (These are the reasons why
the arguer wants her audience to accept the claim).
Warrant: Anyone that robs a store at gun point, hold children hostage, shoot people, kill and
injure in the process should be sentenced to death. (This is the general statement that provides
the justification for moving from the grounds to the claim. Hence, if anyone ask why the
audience should accept the claim given the grounds, the arguer can refer to the warrant).
Backing: The criminal act code of Nigeria. (This is a justification for the warrant. If the
arguer is asked why the warrant is true, the arguer refers to the backing).
Once the audience accepts the warrant and the backing, it is not likely the audience
will reject the claim.
Qualifier: Most likely (This is the level of confidence the arguer has in the claim given the
grounds).
Rebuttal: Except he is a minor or found to be insane. (This shows there is an exception to the
qualifier. As long as the qualifier is not certain, there must be a rebuttal. The rebuttal states
the conditions under which the claim might not follow from the grounds).
PHL 104: Introduction to Philosophy II: Critical Thinking, Argument and Evidence
ARGUMENTS (II)
By
DR. O.O. BADEJO & DR. A.O. ALADE
CANONS OF REASONING
In the previous class, you were introduced to arguments.
An argument is simply a statement or a set of statements presented with the aim of
persuading an audience to accept a position.
Reasoning is the building block of arguments.
There are two canons (rules) of reasoning: Deductive Reasoning and Inductive
Reasoning. This means that there are, basically, two types of arguments.
Deductive reasoning produces deductive arguments while Inductive reasoning
produces inductive arguments.
DEDUCTIVE ARGUMENT
A deductive argument is an argument in which the conclusion seems to or appears to
follow necessarily from the premises. In other words, the premises appears to give
conclusive support to the claim.
Examples: Jingo is either a teacher or a lawyer
Jingo is not a teacher
.: Jingo is a lawyer.
All cows are animals
some animals are mortal
.: some cows are mortal
In the examples, the conclusion seems to follow necessarily from the premises.
In other words, it seems that given that the premises are true, the conclusion is true.
When the claim of a deductive argument actually follows from the premises, the
argument is a valid deductive argument.
PHL 104: Introduction to Philosophy II: Critical Thinking, Argument and Evidence
ARGUMENTS (III)
By
DR. O.O. BADEJO & DR. A.O. ALADE
INDUCTIVE REASONING
➢ In the last class, we were introduced to the two canons of reasoning, deductive and
inductive reasoning, and deductive arguments was examined.
➢ Now we will examine the other canon of reasoning – inductive reasoning.
➢ Inductive reasoning births inductive arguments.
➢ An inductive argument is an argument that given the premises, it is probable that the
conclusion is true.
➢ For example: It rained in July 2014
It rained in July 2015
It rained in July 2016
It rained in July 2017,
.: It will rain in July 2018.
➢ The relationship between the premises and conclusion of an inductive argument is that
of probability.
➢ Thus, an inductive argument cannot be valid or invalid, neither can it be sound or not
sound.
An inductive argument is either weak or strong.
An inductive argument is strong when given the premises, the probability that the
conclusion will follow is high.
For example:
I have had headache 50 times
In the actual human society, people do agree and disagree sometimes. The ability to agree and
disagree are necessary features for human beings to co-exist, interact and function well on daily
basis. There may not be a successful human intercourse without agreements and disagreements.
The next topic in this course is DISAGREEMENTS. There is a need for this topic because as
we interact on daily basis, we are bound to see issues and facts differently sometimes, hence
disagreeing with one another.
What are disagreements? When do we disagree? Why do we disagree? Is it in all cases that we
have genuine disagreement? How do disagreements arise? What are the conditions for the
occurrence of disagreements? What are the types/kinds of disagreements we have? How do we
resolve disagreements when they occur? These are important guiding questions in this topic.
At the end of the topic, each student should be able to answer the above questions competently.
The ability to agree and disagree with one another in human society is essential characteristics
human existence. The ability to agree with one another, when we do, is a demonstration of our
reasonableness. But we should note that it is not in all cases that we agree. We disagree
sometimes; this shows that as human beings, we are not completely or perfectly reasonable.
This implies that as human beings, we are neither completely reasonable nor completely
unreasonable. It follows from this that if we were completely reasonable we would probably
arrive at the same view about the truth of statements when presented with the same evidence.
When this happens, we say that there is agreement. But when we have different opposing views
with one another, we have a disagreement.
As human beings, by virtue of being reasonable, at least sometimes, instead of fighting, boxing,
threatening, forcing each other when we disagree we try to consider each other’s evidence or
reasons available and come to common conclusions or a joint view in order to agree. This
implies that we disagree to agree. It is when two or more people disagree about the truth of one
statement or the other that arguments ensue, as each party tries to convince the other of its own
correctness and the other’s incorrectness as to the truth of the matter in question.
Disagreements lead to arguments among reasonable people while arguments seek to terminate
disagreements. For a disagreement to occur, one person or party must be right and the second
person or party must be wrong. Another way whereby a disagreement occurs is for both persons
and parties to be wrong about the truth-value of some statements, although each of them
believes himself or herself to be right. When both of them are right, there is no disagreement
between them.
In summary, concerning any statement, we have three possible situations: (i) All parties rightly
or wrongly hold the same view. In this case, there is agreement, although they may be in mutual
error, hence no need for arguments; (ii) A situation whereby the parties hold opposing or
contradictory views where one party or person is right and the other wrong. In this case, there
is disagreement and only argument of sufficient strength will bring the wrong party to see the
truth, if he or she is not totally unreasonable; (iii) A situation whereby the parties disagree but
In the last lecture note, the topic of Disagreements was introduced. We were able to define
what disagreements are, the conditions for disagreements to take place, why people do
disagree, how disagreements do arise, and as well as how to resolve disagreements when they
occur. We also started the discussion on the types of disagreements. In this regard, we have
been able to discuss factual disagreement. We have discussed how factual disagreements arise,
the conditions for factual disagreements to occur as well as how they are to be resolved when
they occur. We discussed the possibility of factual disagreements in law, literature, history,
social sciences and the natural sciences.
We are continuing today, by first, looking into some examples of factual disagreement.
Some Examples of Factual Disagreement
Two individuals or discussants are involved in the following discussions or dialogue. It is
important to note that disagreements may involve more than two individuals in a discussion of
any matter or issue. Let us look at the following examples of factual disagreement.
(i) Segun: Chinua Achebe is the author of “Things Fall Apart”
Bimbo: Segun, you’re wrong, Wole Soyinka is the author of “Things Fall Apart”
This dialogue involves two individuals; Segun and Bimbo. The issue at stake is
about the author of the book “Things Fall Apart”. Segun says Chinua Achebe while
Bimbo says Wole Soyinka. In this case, there is a factual disagreement between
Segun and Bimbo on who is the author of Things Fall Apart.
It can be resolved by appealing to facts as recorded in appropriate documents and
places. This includes consulting libraries and bookshops to get the book and confirm
the author of the book. Segun is right while Bimbo is wrong. With this, the factual
disagreement will disappear.
(ii) Sola: Abeokuta is located in Ogun state, in fact, it is the state capital
Funmi: I agree that Abeokuta is in Ogun state but shagamu is the capital, not
Abeokuta. It is important to note that in this dialogue, Sola and Funmi agreed to
something but disagreed on another thing on which one of them is right and the
other wrong. They agreed that Abeokuta is in Ogun state but the point of their
disagreement is whether Abeokuta is the state capital or not. Sola is right while
Funmi is wrong. The disagreement can be resolved by appealing to documents,
asking other people, searching online for evidences or even traveling to Ogun state
to confirm.
(iii) Okafor: There is only one amphi theatre in all Nigeria universities and it is located
in OAU, Ile-Ife.
Okonkwo: No, you’re wrong, the only amphi theatre in Nigeria universities is
located in University of Nigeria, Nsukka.
There is a disagreement between Okafor and Okonkwo about the university where
the only amphitheatre in Nigeria universities is located. Okafor says OAU while
Okonkwo says UNN. It can be resolved by looking for evidences or traveling to the
Verbal Disagreements
The next in our discussion of the types of disagreement is verbal disagreement. What is a verbal
disagreement? Can verbal disagreement be really characterized as a type of disagreement? If
yes, why? If No, why not? A verbal disagreement occurs when, unknown to one of the two
parties engaged in a dialogue that the other person or party is using one or more words or terms
in a different sense. Each person believes that the other is wrong whereas the other is only using
the same word in a sense that is different from that of his opponent. The disagreement here is
not about the description of the world rather it concerns the use of words. In verbal
disagreement, there is no real disagreement. What appears to be a disagreement can be settled
by identifying the ambiguous word and try to have a uniform understanding by specifying the
sense or senses in which it is being used. When this is done, the two disputants could see that
the problem is just about the different senses in which they have used and understood a word
or term. In which case, both of them could be right. This is unlike what we have in real
disagreement whereby if one party is right, the other cannot be right, although both can be
wrong.
Examples of Verbal Disagreements
Speaker A: Bongo is too materialistic; he is always thinking and talking about how to acquire
property, latest dresses, fanciful cars and sophisticated electronic gadgets.
Speaker B: You’re wrong, how dare you describe Bongo, who believes in God, immortality
of the soul and life after death, as materialistic?
In this dialogue between Speakers A and B, the ambiguous word that is at stake and being
given different meanings is ‘materialistic’. Speaker A means by it ‘the love of material things’
while speaker B means by it ‘a philosophical position that holds that everything in the world is
ultimately material’. Each meaning is correct in its own merit but the only problem is that
Speakers A and B thought they meant the same thing by the word ‘materialistic’ whereas they
did not. As soon as they see that they are giving different meaning to the same word, the
In the last lecture note, we continued with the discussion of the types of disagreements. Having
identified factual disagreement earlier, we were able to state some examples of factual
disagreements and how they could be resolved. We also identified verbal disagreement, and
how it is not a description about the world but about identifying the ambiguous word such that
when realized by the parties, the seeming or apparent disagreement disappears. This is why it
is said that verbal disagreement is not really a genuine disagreement.
In today’s class, we have to move to another type of disagreement. The next is Evaluative
Disagreement. What is evaluative disagreement? What the kinds of evaluative disagreement
we have? What does each of the kinds of evaluative disagreement say and how so we identify
them?
Evaluative Disagreement
As the name implies or suggests, this type of disagreement is a type of disagreement that deals
with the evaluation of something. Before this disagreement can occur, it must be the case that
disputants in a dialogue differ in the way (s) they are evaluating a particular phenomenon. In
general terms, evaluative disagreements occur as a result of how assessment of persons, group
of persons, institutions, events, countries, objects, claims, artistic works (such as novels,
poems, plays, fine art, dance, music, and so on) are carried out. As human beings, we place
different degrees of worth or values on objects of assessments in relation to different desires,
interests, standards, orientations, criteria and commitments. In evaluative disagreement, the
issue in contest is essentially axiological, that is, value-laden. In this regard, three kinds of
evaluative disagreement could be identified as: ethical, aesthetic and pragmatic disagreements.
Evaluative Ethical Disagreement
This disagreement is about ethics and ethics is concerned with the study and evaluation of
human conducts. It is about the evaluation of a moral conduct or standard of behavior. This
extends to social, political and institutional activities. This deals with ethical concepts or terms
which includes ‘good’, ‘bad’, ‘right’, ‘wrong’, ‘ought’, ‘ought not’, ‘just’, ‘unjust’, ‘fair’,
‘unfair’, and so on. When any of such terms or concepts leads to a disagreement, we have an
evaluative ethical or moral disagreement. It is about the evaluation of a moral standard of
behavior or level of persons, groups or institutions.
Examples of Evaluative Ethical Disagreement
Speaker A: Bobby is a bad boy, he does not open up to others, and he is an introvert.
Speaker B: Bobby is a good boy; he is quiet and not obstructive.
In the above dialogue between speakers A and B, there is a disagreement. The disagreement is
evaluative ethical disagreement. This is because the two speakers are disagreeing about the
ethical evaluation of Bobby’s behavior. They employed the concepts of ‘good’ and ‘bad’. Each
In the last lecture note, we discussed evaluative type of disagreement. We were able to discuss
what evaluative disagreements are and how to identify them. The three kinds of evaluative
disagreement: ethical; aesthetic and pragmatic evaluative disagreements and the examples were
discussed as well as how to identify them. We will be taking the last type of disagreement today
which is Interpretative Disagreement. With this, the topic will be concluded.
Interpretative Disagreement
This type of disagreement is over the meaning, significance, purpose, theme, focus, or message
of an event, a person’s conduct, a programme or a project, a literary or art work, a statue, law
or policy, etc. It is a disagreement about how any of such things is to be understood, or the
interpretation, or interpretation to give to them.
Examples
Speaker A: In 1999 presidential election, Nigerians voted in large numbers. It was evidence
that they really want democracy.
Speaker B: It is not so. You misunderstood the issue. The large turnout only means that most
Nigerians never had the opportunity to vote. Hence, they were eager to vote for the fun of doing
so.
There is a disagreement here and it is about how to understand the large turnout of voters in
1999 presidential election. That is, what is the real significance, importance, purpose or
meaning of that particular phenomenon?
Shola: It is interesting to find some respectful young people in this city. Two days ago, I saw
a young boy politely relinquished his seat in a commuter bus to an old woman.
Ashafa: No, you missed the point of his action. It was not respect but prudence. The young
boy gave up his seat in the hope that the old woman would pay his fare, or at least pray for him.
In this disagreement, the two speakers are disagreeing over the intention, or motive of the
young boy in doing what he did. It has to do with the interpretation of human behavior.
Interpretative disagreements frequently occur in most academic disciplines and professions.
For example in history, there may be a disagreement over the significance of an event such as
the battle of the waterloo, the first military coup in Nigeria. In Religious studies, there may be
a disagreement over doctrinal meaning or theological message of a passage, event or action in
the scriptures of a particular religion. In literature, there may be a disagreement over the
interpretation or meaning of a passage in a text, or verse in a poem, or the theme of a novel or
play. In the social sciences, we also have disagreements on how to interpret or give meanings
to human behavior. Similarly, we have disagreements in the natural sciences over the
interpretation of certain occurrences in our in our physical environment. Interpretative
disagreement has a wide scope.
A fallacy is a misleading defect in an argument. A fallacy can arise from the ignorance of the
arguer and in some cases it could be deliberately committed. There are two broad categories of
fallacies. The first is formal fallacies which occurs in deductive arguments and can be detected
in the structure of an argument. The second category is informal fallacies which occurs in the
inductive arguments and has to do with the content of the arguments. In this class, we shall
study the informal fallacies.
The informal fallacies are grouped into three. These are fallacies of irrelevant grounds, fallacies
of presumption and fallacies of ambiguity. Below are illustrations of some of the informal
fallacies.
Explanations
A fallacy of this nature is identified as Fallacy of Irrelevant Grounds, Argument against the
Person (argumentum ad hominem), Circumstantial ad Hominem.
3. Argumentum ad Hominem, Tu Quo Que: “What about you?” occurs when rather than
respond to an argument, a respondent simply rejects the argument because the person
who presented the argument is supposedly guilty of the same issue addressed in the
argument.
Example: Suppose I am a chain smoker and a friend who used to smoke cigarettes tells me to
stop smoking because smokers are susceptible to lung cancer, and in response, I argue thus;
“so I should stop smoking, when you were a chain smoker before, who even knows if you are
still smoking.
This fallacy is identified as Fallacy of Irrelevant Grounds, Argument against the Person
(argumentum ad hominem), what of you? (Tu Quo Que).
This fallacy occurs when an arguer attempts to make another party accept his or her
claim or argument by using threat, either directly or subtly.
Example: Suppose a Director in an office argues that, “It is not necessary that you come to the
office on Saturday, but remember that evaluation for promotion is around the corner and I am
in charge of your evaluation.” The arguer is using subtle force to convince the listener to come
to the office on a weekend. This is not a good argument since force is not an acceptable ground.
This occurs when an arguer appeals to popular prejudice in order to convince the
audience to accept his or her argument. Argumentum ad populum usually arises from a
deliberate or ignorant belief that what most people subscribe to or agree with is right. However,
an argument is not accepted because many people assent to it. There are variants of this fallacy,
they are bandwagon and appeal to popular belief
This is also known as missing the point. The fallacy occurs when an arguer provides
grounds that are relevant to a particular claim, but provides another claim directly or
indirectly related to that claim as the conclusion to an argument.
Example: “Corruption in the petroleum sector is at its peak, the only alternative is to remove
fuel subsidy completely.” In this example, though the claim is vaguely related to the ground,
the claim to that ground should be related to the corruption mentioned in the ground and not
another issue; fuel subsidy.
FALLACIES OF PRESUMPTION
The second category of informal fallacies to be examined is Fallacies of Presumption. Fallacies
of presumption occur when an arguer deliberately or in error presumes that the ground provided
in support of a claim gives adequate support to the claim, when, in actual fact, it does not.
Fallacies of presumption include following subtypes:
a. accidents,
b. hasty generalisation,
c. false cause,
d. appeal to ignorance (argumentum ad ignorantiam),
e. appeal to inexpert authority (argumentum ad verecundiam),
f. straw man, begging the question (petition principii),
g. loaded question,
h. slippery slope
i. gamblers fallacy (Monte Carlo).
Explanation
A. Fallacy of presumption, Accident
This fallacy occurs when an arguer deliberately or ignorantly ignores an exception to a
general rule while stating an argument and concludes based on it.
Example: “Every organisation has a right to protest; Boko Haram is an organisation
protesting, so the government should let them be”. The arguer deliberately or ignorantly
ignores the fact that in this case the rule of the right to protest does not apply.
This occurs when an arguer wants a claim to be accepted or rejected because it has not
been proven to be or not to be the case.
1. One is because there is no evidence that something is not the case, then it is the
case.
Example of the first variant: Suppose a person argues that “Rev. Musa is definitely
guilty of collecting that bribe, after all no one has been able to present any evidence
that he did not.”
2. The other variant occurs when an arguer wants a claim to be rejected because it has
not been proven true.
Example of the second variant: “I am yet to see anyone that has proven the second
coming of Christ; yet many of you believe it, can you not see that it is false?”
Example: Professor Wole Soyinka says that the Nigerian economy is still in recession.
[Professor Soyinka is professor of Literature.]
The fallacy occurs when rather than address the issue on ground, the arguer presents a
caricature of the argument, criticises it and assumes that a rejection of that caricature
amounts to a rejection of the real argument. The fallacies occur when a person attacks
an exaggerated, distorted, or false version of an opponent's argument because it is
easier than dealing with the real points that the opponent makes. It would be a lot
easier to defeat a person made of straw in a fight then a real person—especially a
strong one.
This fallacy occurs when an arguer uses a ground that obviously needs to be justified
as a justification for a claim or conclusion.
Example: Suppose a person argues that God definitely exists because the Bible says so.
The claim in this argument begs the question; “How do we justify the assertions made
in the Bible?”
It is a fallacy that occurs when an arguer asks more than one question in guise of just
one question. This is a fallacy that is very common in a courtroom; it is used to trick a
respondent into admitting that he or she is guilty of a crime earlier denied.
Example: Suppose a lawyer asks an accused person, “After beating your wife the third
time, did you take her to the hospital?” There are at least three questions hidden in that
one question: “Do you beat your wife?” “If yes, how many times have you beaten her?”
“Did you take her to the hospital on the third occasion?” If the accused should reply
that he took his wife to the hospital, he has admitted that he beats her and he has done
so at least thrice.
The fallacy occurs when an arguer presents a claim based on an assumed chain reaction.
Example: “If we do not remove the subsidy on petroleum products, Nigeria will keep
borrowing at an alarming rate. If Nigeria keeps borrowing at that rate, she will keep
paying to service debts, the money currently being spent on education, health,
infrastructures and welfare will soon go into debt servicing. When this happen schools
will close down one after the other, hospitals will be forced to fold up, people will start
dying at an alarming rate and gradually Nigeria will cease to exist, so I insist that the
subsidy on petroleum products should be removed immediately.” The argument
attempts to persuade people, using a chain of exaggerated reactions, to support the
claim that subsidy on petroleum products should be removed.
The fallacy occurs when an arguer assumes that because something has happened
frequently in the past it will happen again or because something has not happened in a
long time it will not happen.
Examples: “I cannot have lung cancer, I have been smoking since 1976 and I have not
been hospitalised even once on account of my smoking.” or “We have experienced
flooding in this area for ten years consecutively, no matter what we do now there will
still be flooding in this area this year.”
Example: Either we win the war in Vietnam, or all of Asia will fall to communism.
FALLACIES OF AMBIGUITY
The third variety of informal fallacies to be examined is fallacies of ambiguity. Fallacies
of ambiguity occur when a claim is susceptible to another interpretation given the grounds.
Fallacies of ambiguity include; equivocation, amphiboly, composition and division.
Example: If it is argued that, “Every law must have a law giver; natural laws are laws, so
natural laws must have a law giver.” In the example, ‘laws’ in the legislated sense and natural
sense have different meanings, but the arguer used the two senses to mean the same thing. This
is an equivocation on the word “law”.
Example “You can serve the water when completely filled up.” In this example, we are not sure
if it is the person to serve the water that should be completely filled before serving the water
or it is a jug or glass of water that should be completely filled before serving.” or “Serve the
cake when done.” Is it the person to serve that should finish other chores before serving the
cake or it is the cake that should be served immediately the cake is ready?”
Example: “The bottle of syrup contains 10% of vitamin C, each dose of the syrup contains 10%
of vitamin C.” or “That team is strong, so every member of the team must be strong.” Just as
it is with the fallacy of composition, the transfer of the attribute of the whole to the parts is
unjustifiable and not legitimate.