A History of Philosophy - Modern Philosophy - Bentham To - Frederick Copleston - Volume 8, 1966 - Anna's Archive
A History of Philosophy - Modern Philosophy - Bentham To - Frederick Copleston - Volume 8, 1966 - Anna's Archive
A History of Philosophy - Modern Philosophy - Bentham To - Frederick Copleston - Volume 8, 1966 - Anna's Archive
DA History
a OOF
‘PHILOSOPHY:
Modern Philosophy:
Bentham to Russell
Part I
British Empiricism and
the Idealist Movement
in Great Britain
FREDERICK COPLESTON, S.].
<8
lo
VOLUME 5
“Obviously to be the standardee of philosophy for many
years to come.” Blackfriars
VOLUME 6
“One thing at any rate is beyond doubt. No serious student
of western philosophy can dispense with Fr. Copleston’s
History.” Duckett’s Register
VOLUME 7
“Each volume of Fr. Copleston’s history provokes astonish-
ment and wonder. . . The present volume is just as learned,
fair-minded, lucid and interesting as its predecessors.”
The Month
Volumes of A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY now available
in Image Books:
A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY: Volume 1
Parts I & II—-Greece & Rome—D 134A & D 134B
A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY: Volume 2
Mediaeval Philosophy
Part I— Augustine to Bonaventure—D 135A
Part I1— Albert the Great to Duns Scotus—D 135B
A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY: Volume 3
Late Mediaeval and Renaissance Philosophy
Part I-Ockham to the Speculative Mystics—D 136A
Part II—The Revival of Platonism to Su4rez—D 136B
A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY: Volume 4
Modern Philosophy
Descartes to Leibniz—D 137
A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY: Volume 5
Modern Philosophy — The British Philosophers
Part I— Hobbes to Paley—-D 138A
Part II - Berkeley to Hume—D 138B
A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY: Volume 6
Modern Philosophy
Part I—The French Enlightenment to Kant—D 139A
Part II—-Kant—D 139B
A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY: Volume 7
Modern Philosophy
Part I—Fichte to Hegel—D 140A
Part II]—Schopenhauer to Nietzsche—D 140B
A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY: Volume 8
Modern Philosophy — Bentham to Russell
Part I—British Empiricism and the Idealist Movement in
Great Britain—D 141B
Part I1—Idealism in America, The Pragmatist Movement
The Revolt against Idealism—D 141B
A History of Philosophy
VOLUME VIII
Modern Philosophy
Bentham to Russell
PARE
British Empiricism
and the Idealist Movement
in Great Britain
by Frederick Copleston, S. J.
yy
IMAGE BOOKS
A Division of Doubleday & Company, Inc.
Garden City, New York
Image Books Edition
by special arrangement with The Newman Press
Image Books Edition published September 1967
PREFACE
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
PART I
BRITISH EMPIRICISM
PART II
NOTES 300
a
_
?
vi oy
wcaity doll Re ee otSibaeatee
“sai =F H. bias
¥
ELST RO FE ee
aetalteaky 0 Rares segickn wads:
ay: Sate et ete
See COST atin
iy
BRITISH EMPIRICISM
Chapter One
fore the death of Hume. And some of his works were pub-
lished in the last three decades of the eighteenth century. It
is no matter of surprise, therefore, if we find that there is a
conspicuous element of continuity between the empiricism
of the eighteenth century and that of the nineteenth. For
example, the method of reductive analysis, the reduction,
that istosay, OF the whole toitsparts. ofthe complex to its.
primitive or simple elements, which had been_practised by
ume, was continue entham. I his involved, as can be
seen in the philosophy of James Mill, a phenomenalistic
analysis of the self. And in the reconstruction of mental life
out of its supposed simple elements use was made of the
associationist psychology which had been developed in the
eighteenth century by, for instance, David Hartley,? not to
speak of Hume’s employment of the principles of association
of ideas. Again, in the first chapter of his Fragment on Goy-
ernment Bentham gave explicit expression to his indebted-
ness to Hume for the light which had fallen on his mind
when he saw in the Treatise of Human Nature how Hume
had demolished the fiction of a social contract or compact
and had shown how all virtue is founded on utility. To be
sure, Bentham was also influenced by the thought of the
French Enlightenment, particularly by that of Helvétius.3
But this does not alter the fact that in regard to both method
and theory there was a notable element of continuity be-
tween the empiricist movements of the eighteenth and nine-
teenth centuries in Great Britain.
But once the element of continuity has been noted, atten-
tion must be drawn to the considerable difference in empha-
sis. As traditionally represented at any rate, classical British
empiricism had been predominant] = with th -
their throne.’
fastened_to If, therefore, we assume that
pleasure, happiness and good are synonymous terms and that
pain, unhappiness and evil are also synonymous, the question
immediately arises whether it makes any sense to say that
we ought to pursue what is good and avoid what is evil, if,
as a matter of psychological fact, we always do pursue the
one and endeavour to avoid the other.
To be able to answer this question affirmatively, we have
to make two assumptions. First, when it is said that man
see easure, it is mean “his greater pleasure
aS ase arent ofTeSecanittt tre ioe ot
necessaril =i those actions which will as a matter of
this end.17 If we make these assumptions
fact_conduce_to
and pass over the difficulties inherent in any hedonistic
ethics, we can then say that right actions are those which
tend to increase the sum total of pleasure while wrong ac-
re nt
26 BRITISH EMPIRICISM
_are_those_w
tions diminish it, and that we
tend _tohich
ought to do what is right and not do what is wrong.*8
We thus arrive at the principle of utility, also called the
greatest happiness principle. This ‘states the greatest hap-
piness of all those whose interest is in question, as being the
right and proper, and only right and proper and universally
desirable, end of human action’.1® The parties whose in-
terest is in question may, of course, differ. If we are thinking
of the individual agent as such, it is his greatest happiness
which is referred to. If we are thinking of the community,
it is the greater happiness of the greatest possible number
of the members of the community which is being referred
to. If we are thinking of all sentient beings, then we must
also consider the greater pleasure of animals. Bentham is
chiefly concerned with the greater happiness of the human
community, with the common good or welfare in the sense
of the common good of any given human political society.
But in all cases the principle is the same, namely that the
greatest happiness of the party in question is the only de-
sirable end of human action.
If we mean by proof deduction from some more ultimate
principle or principles, the principle of utility cannot be
proved. For there is no more ultimate ethical principle. At
the same time Bentham ties to-shaw that-any_other theory,
of morals involves in the long run an at least tacit appeal to
diepanitiple
caeagrieees-aa
TarWEE Val ser ee
which people act or think that they act, if we once raise the
question why we ought to perform a certain action, we shall
ultimately have to answer in terms of the principle of utility.
The alternative moral theories which Bentham has in mind
are principally intuitionist theories or theories which appeal
to a moral sense. In his opinion such theories, taken by them-
selves, are incapable of answering the question why we
ought to perform this action and not that. If the upholders
of such theories once try to answer the question, they will
ultimately have to argue that the action which ought to be
performed is one which conduces to the greater happiness or
pleasure of whatever party it is whose interest is in question.
In other words, it is utilitarianism alone which can provide
an objective criterion of right and _wrong.2° And to show
THE UTILITARIAN MOVEMENT (1) 27
that this is the case, is to give the only proof of the principle
of utility which is required.
In passing we can note that though hedonism represented
only one element in Locke’s ethical theory, he explicitly
stated that ‘things then are good or evil only in reference
to pleasure or pain. That we call good which is apt to cause
or increase pleasure or diminish pain in us. . . . And on the
contrary we name that evil which is apt to increase any pain
or diminish any pleasure in us. . . .’22 The property which
is here called ‘good’ by Locke is described by Bentham as
‘utility’. For ‘utility is any property in any object, whereby
it tends to produce benefit, advantage, pleasure, good or
happiness, or . . . to prevent the happening of mischief, pain,
evil or unhappiness to the party whose interest is con-
sidered.’28
Now, if actions are right in so far as they tend to increase
the sum total of pleasure or diminish the sum total of pain
of the party whose interest is in question, as Bentham puts
iEEhe moral agenE WHEN ISCAS“ WHCMICE ENE CHIOn
Is right or wrong, will have to estimate the amount of pleas-
UTEANEUEaU oFpa TOWichTheationseen Hely
the other
entham provides a hedonistic or ‘felicific’ calculus for this
purpose.?4 Let us suppose that I wish to estimate the value
of a pleasure (or pain) for myself. I have to take into ac-
count four factors or dimensions of value: intensi ura-
tion, certainty or uncertainty, propinquit . For
ject that this is precisely what the utilitarians try to do. That
is to say, they first assert that as a matter of empirical fact
man seeks happiness, and they then conclude that he ought
to perform those actions which are required to increase happi-
ness and that he ought not to perform those actions which
diminish happiness or increase pain or unhappiness.
One possible way of dealing with this objection is, of
course, to challenge its validity. But if it is once admitted
that an ought-statement cannot be derived from a purely
factual statement, then, to defend utilitarianism, we have
to deny the applicability of the objection in this case. Ob-
viously, we cannot deny that the utilitarians start with a
factual statement, namely that all men seek happiness. But
it might be argued that this factual statement is not the only
statement which functions as a premiss. For example, it might
be maintained that a judgment of value about the end,
namely happiness, is tacitly understood. That is to say, the
utilitarians are not simply stating that as a matter of empirti-
cal fact all men pursue happiness as the ultimate end of
action. They are also stating implicitly that happiness is the
only end worthy of being an ultimate end. Or it might be
maintained that together with the factual statement that all
men seek for happiness as the ultimate end of action, the
utilitarians tacitly include the premisses that to act in the
way which effectively increases happiness is the only rational
way of acting (given the fact that all seek this end), and
that to act in a rational manner is worthy of commendation.
Indeed, it is fairly clear that Bentham does assume that, as
all seek pleasure, to act in the way which will effectively in-
crease pleasure is to act rationally, and that to act rationally
is commendable. And it is also clear that Mill assumes that
to act in such a way as to develop a harmonious integration
of the powers of human nature or of the human person is
commendable.
It is not the purpose of these remarks to suggest that in
the opinion of the present writer utilitarianism either in its
original Benthamite form or in the somewhat incoherent
shape that it assumes with J. S. Mill, is the correct moral
THE UTILITARIAN MOVEMENT (2) 53
3
resuppose other premi i e-
ments. Hence, even if it is admitted that an ought-statement
cannot be derived from a purely factual statement, the ad-
mission is not by itself necessarily fatal to utilitarian moral
theory.
As for the general merits and demerits of utilitarian moral
theory, this is too broad a question for discussion here. But
we can make two points. when we are asked why we
think that one action is right and another action wrong, we
frequently refer to consequences, An is suggests that a
teleological ethics finds support in the way in y wines ordi-
narily think and speak about moral questions. Secondly? the
fact_that_a_man of the calibre of J. S. Mill found himself
driven to transcend the narrow hedonism of Bentham and
to_interpret happiness in the light of the idea of the develop-
ent_of the human personality suggests that we cannot un-
derstand man’s moral life except in terms of a philosophical
anthropology. Hedonism certainly tends to recur in the his-
tory of ethical theory. But reflection on it prompts the mind
to seek for a more adequate theory of human nature than
that which is immediately suggested by the statement that
all men pursue pleasure. This fact is well illustrated by Mill’s
development of Benthamism.
3. Mill’s idea of the self-development of the individual
plays a central role in his reflections on civil or social liberty.
As he follows Hume and Bentham in rejecting the theory of
‘abstract right, as a thing independent of utility’,31 he can-
not indeed appeal to a natural right on the part of the in-
dividual to develop himself freely. But he insists that the
principle of utility demands that every man should be free
to develop his powers according to his own will and judg-
ment, provided that he does not do so in a way which inter-
feres with the exercise of a similar freedom by others. It is
not in the common interest that all should be moulded or
expected to conform to the same pattern. On the contrary,
society is enriched in proportion as individuals develop them-
selves freely. “The free development of individuality is one
of the principal ingredients of human happiness, and quite
54 BRITISH EMPIRICISM
the chief ingredient indivi ocial progress.’32
Hence the need for liberty.
When he is thinking of the value of free self-development
on the part of the individual, Mill not unnaturally pushes
the idea of liberty to the fullest extent which is consistent
with the existence and maintenance of social harmony. “The
liberty of the individual must be thus far limited; he must
not make himself a nuisance to other people.’8? Provided
that he refrains from interfering with other people’s liberty
and from actively inciting others to crime, the individual’s
freedom should be unrestricted. “The only part of the con-
duct of anyone, for which he is amenable to society, is that
which concerns others. In the part which merely concerns
himself, his independence is, of right, absolute. Over him-
self, over his own body and mind, the individual is sov-
ereign.’34
In the passage just cited the phrase ‘of right’ suggests, at
first sight at least, that Mill has forgotten for the moment
that the theory of natural rights does not form part of his
intellectual baggage. It would not indeed be matter for as-
tonishment if after inheriting the rejection of this theory
from Bentham and his father Mill then tended to reintro-
duce the theory. But presumably he would comment that
what he rejects is the theory of ‘abstract’ rights which are
not based on the principle of utility and which are supposed
to be valid. irrespective of the historical and social context.
‘Liberty, as a principle, has no application to any. state of
things anterior to the time when mankind have become ca-
pable of being improved by free and equal discussion.’$5 In
a society of barbarians despotism would be legitimate, ‘pro-
vided that the end be their improvement, and the means
justified by actually effecting that end’.36 But when civiliza-
tion has developed up to a certain point, the principle of
utility demands that the individual should enjoy full liberty,
except the liberty to do harm to others. And if we presup-
pose a society of this sort, we can reasonably talk about a
‘tight’ to liberty, a right grounded on the principle of utility.
Mill’s general thesis is, therefore, Peace es
munity the only legitimate ground for the exercise of coer-
cion in regard to the individual is ‘to prevent harm to others.
THE UTILITARIAN MOVEMENT (2) 55
His own good, eith i r_moral, is not_a_ sufficient
warrant.’8?But where does the boundary lie between what
does harm to others and what does not, between purely self-
regarding conduct and conduct which concerns others? We
have noted that Mill quotes with approval Wilhelm von
Humboldt’s statement that the end of man is ‘the highest
and most harmonious development of his powers to a com-
plete and consistent whole’.88 And Mill is, of course, con-
vinced that the common happiness is increased if individuals
do develop themselves in this way. Might it not be argued,
therefore, that harm is done to others, to the community, if
the individual acts in such a way as to prevent the harmoni-
ous integration of his powers and becomes a warped per-
sonality?
This difficulty is, of course, seen and discussed by Mill
himself. And he suggests various ways of dealing with it. In
general, however, his answer is on these lines. The common
good demands that as much liberty as possible should be
conceded to the individual. Hence injury to others should
be interpreted as narrowly as possible. The majority is by no
means infallible in its judgments about what would be bene-
ficial to an individual. Hence it should not attempt to impose
its own ideas about what is good and bad on all. The com-
munity should not interfere with private liberty except when
‘there is a definite damage, or a definite risk of damage,
either to an individual or to the public’.39
Obviously, this does not tonstitute a complete answer to
the objection from the purely theoretical point of view. For
questions can still be asked about what constitutes ‘definite
damage’ or ‘a definite risk of damage’.4° At the same time
Mill’s general principle is, by and large, that which tends to
be followed in our Western democracies. And most of us
would doubtless agree that restrictions on private liberty
should be kept to the minimum demanded by respect for
the rights of others and for the common interest. But it is
idle to suppose that any philosopher can provide us with a
formula which will settle all disputes about the limits of this
minimum.
Mill’s insistence on the value of private liberty and on the
principle of individuality or originality, the principle, that is
56 BRITISH EMPIRICISM
logicians for passing over words such as ‘or’ and ‘if’, which
can certainly not be described as parts of names.
Turning to propositions, we find, as already indicated, that
Mill’s over-emphasis on names and naming leads him to re-
gard all propositions as affirming or denying one name or
another. The words which are commonly, though not neces-
sarily, used to signify affirmative or negative predication are
‘is’ or ‘is not’, ‘are’ or ‘are not’. Thus Mill takes the subject-
copula-predicate form of proposition as the standard, though
not invariable, form. And he warns his readers about the
ambiguity of the term ‘is’. For example, if we fail to dis-
tinguish between the existential use of the verb ‘to be’ and
its use as a copula, we may be led into such absurdities as
supposing that unicorns must possess some form of existence
because we can say that the unicom is an animal with
one horn, or even because we can say that it is an imaginary
beast.
In the course of his discussion of the import or meaning
of propositions Mill distinguishes between real and verbal
propositions. In a real proposition we affirm or deny of a
subject an attribute which is not already connoted by its
name, or a fact which is not already comprised in the sig-
nification of the name of the subject. In other words, a real
proposition conveys new factual information, true or false
as the case may be, information which is new in the sense
that it cannot be obtained simply by analysis of the meaning
of the subject term. As proper names are not connotative
terms and, strictly speaking, possess no ‘meaning’, every prop-
osition, such as ‘John is married’, which has as its subject
a proper name, must necessarily belong to this class. Verbal
propositions, however, are concerned simply with the mean-
ings of names: the predicate can be obtained by analysis of
the connotation or meaning of the subject term. For ex-
ample, in ‘man is a corporeal being’ the predicate already
forms part of the connotation or meaning of the term ‘man’.
For we would not call anything a man unless it were a
corporeal being. Hence the proposition says something about
the meaning of a name, about its usage: it does not convey
factual information in the sense that ‘John is married’ or ‘the
74 BRITISH EMPIRICISM
mean distance of the moon from the earth is 238,860 miles’
conveys factual information.
The most important class of verbal propositions are defini-
tions, a definition being ‘a proposition declaratory of the
meaning of a word: namely, either the meaning which it
bears in common acceptance or that which the speaker or
writer, for the particular purposes of his discourse, intends
to annex to it’.16 Mill thus does not exclude the use of
words in new ways for specific purposes. But he insists on the
need for examining ordinary usage very carefully before we
undertake to reform language. For an examination of the
different shades of meaning which a word has in common
usage, or changes in its use, may bring to light distinc-
tions and other relevant factors which it is important that the
would-be reformer of language should bear in mind.
Obviously, when Mill says that definitions are verbal prop-
ositions, he does not intend to imply that they are by na-
ture purely arbitrary or that inquiries into matters of fact
are never relevant to the framing of definitions. It would be
absurd, for example, to define man with complete disre-
gard for the attributes which those beings whom we call men
possess in common. Mill’s point is that though the connota-
tion of the term ‘man’ is grounded in experience of men,
and though inquiries into matters of fact can render this
connotation less vague and more distinct, what the definition
as such does is simply to make this connotation or meaning
explicit, either wholly or in part, that is, by means of.selected
differentiating attributes. True, we may be inclined to sup-
pose that the definition is not purely verbal. But the inclina-
tion can be easily explained if we bear in mind the ambiguity
of the copula. A general connotative term such as ‘man’ de-
notes an indefinite number of things and connotes certain
attributes which they have in common. When, therefore, it is
said that ‘man is . . .’, we may be inclined to suppose that
the definition asserts that there are men. In this case, how-
ever, we tacitly presuppose the presence of two propositions,
corresponding to two possible uses of the verb ‘to be’; on the
one hand the definition, which simply makes explicit the
meaning of the term ‘man’, and on the other hand an ex-
istential proposition which asserts that there are beings which
J. S. MILL: LOGIC AND EMPIRICISM 75
possess the attributes mentioned in the definition. If we omit
the existential proposition which we have surreptitiously in-
troduced, we can see that the definition is purely verbal,
concerned simply with the meaning of a name.
Let us return for a moment to real propositions and con-
sider a general proposition such as ‘All men are mortal.’!7
Looked at from one point of view, as a portion of speculative
truth, as Mill puts it, this means that the attributes of man
are always accompanied by the attribute of being mortal.
And under analysis this means that certain phenomena are
regularly associated with other phenomena. But we can also
look at the proposition under the aspect of a memorandum
for practical use. And it then means that ‘the attributes of
man are evidence of, are a mark of, mortality’.18 In other
words, it tells us what to expect. According to Mill these
different meanings are ultimately equivalent. But in scientific
inference it is the practical aspect of meaning, its predictive
aspect, which is of special importance.
We have, therefore, a distinction between verbal proposi-
tions in which the predicate is either identical with or a
part of the meaning of the subject term, and real proposi-
tions, in which the predicate is not contained in the conno-
tation of the subject. And Mill remarks that ‘this distinction
corresponds to that which is drawn by Kant and other meta-
physicians between what they term analytic and synthetic
judgments; the former being those which can be evolved
from the meaning of the terms used’.19 We may add that
Mill’s distinction also corresponds more or less to Hume’s
distinction between propositions which state relations be-
tween ideas and propositions which state matters of fact.
If we mean by truth correspondence between a proposi-
tion and the extra-linguistic fact to which it refers,?° it ob-
viously follows that no purely verbal proposition can be
properly described as true. A definition can be adequate or
inadequate; it can correspond or not correspond with linguis-
tic usage. But by itself it makes no statement about mat-
ters of extra-linguistic fact. The question arises, however,
whether for Mill there are real propositions which are
necessarily true. Does he agree with Hume that no real prop-
osition can be necessarily true? Or, to use Kantian termi-
76 BRITISH EMPIRICISM
nology, does he recognize the existence of synthetic a priori
propositions?
It is a notorious fact that Mill tends to speak in different
ways, his way of speaking being influenced by his reaction to
the type of theory which he happens to be discussing. Hence
it is difficult to say what the view of Mill is. However, he is
undoubtedly opposed to the view that there is any a priori
knowledge of reality. And this opposition naturally inclines
him to reject synthetic a priori propositions. Mill is not in-
deed prepared to say that when the negation of a given
proposition appears to us as unbelievable, the proposition
must be merely verbal. For there are doubtless some real
propositions which reflect a uniformity or regularity of ex-
perience such that the negations of these propositions seem
to us unbelievable. And for all practical purposes we are
justified in treating them as though they were necessarily
true. Indeed, we can hardly do otherwise, because ex
hypothesi we have had no experience which has led us to
question their universal applicability. But a real proposition
can be necessarily true in the psychological sense that we
find its opposite unbelievable, without being necessarily true
in the logical sense that it must be true of all possible ex-
perience, of all unobserved or unexperienced phenomena.
This seems to be more or less Mill’s characteristic posi-
tion. But to appreciate the complexity of the situation it is
advisable to consider what he has to say about mathematical
propositions, the great stronghold of intuitionists and up-
holders of a priori knowledge.
3. It is scarcely necessary to say that Mill recognizes that
mathematics possesses some peculiar characteristics. He re-
marks, for example, that ‘the propositions of geometry are
independent of the succession of events’.21 Again, the truths
of mathematics ‘have no connection with laws of causation.
. . . That when two straight lines intersect each other the
opposite angles are equal, is true of all such lines and angles,
by whatever cause produced.’22 Again, mathematical reason-
ing ‘does not suffer us to let in, at any of the joints in the
reasoning, an assumption which we have not faced in the
shape of an axiom, postulate or definition. This is a merit
which it has in common with formal Logic.’23
J. S. MILL: LOGIC AND EMPIRICISM WF
EMPIRICISTS, AGNOSTICS,
POSITIVISTS
not only the relevant parts of the scientific field but also a
considerable part of the field of empiricist philosophy.
The idea of biological evolution was not, of course, an
invention of the middle of the nineteenth century. As a purely
speculative idea it had appeared even in ancient Greece. In
the eighteenth century the way had been prepared for it by
Georges-Louis de Buffon (1707-88), while Jean-Baptiste
Pierre Lamarck (1744-1829) had proposed his theories
that in response to new needs brought about by changes in
the environment changes take place in the organic structure
of animals, some organs falling into disuse and others being
evolved and developed, and that acquired habits are trans-
mitted by heredity. Moreover, when the idea of evolution
was first publicized in Britain, the publicist was a philosopher,
Spencer, rather than a scientist. At the same time this does
not affect the importance of Darwin’s writings in setting the
theory of evolution on its feet and in giving an enormously
powerful impetus to its propagation.
Charles Robert Darwin (1809-82) was a naturalist, not a
philosopher. During his famous voyage on the ‘Beagle’
(1831-6), observation of variations between differently situ-
ated animals of the same species and reflection on the dif-
ferences between living and fossilized animals led him to
question the theory of the fixity of species. In 1838 study
of Malthus’s Essay on the Principle of Population helped
to lead him to the conclusions that in the struggle for exist-
ence favourable variations tend to be preserved and un-
favourable variations to be destroyed, and that the result of
this process is the formation of new species, acquired char-
acteristics being transmitted by heredity.
Similar conclusions were reached independently by another
naturalist, Alfred Russel Wallace (1823-1913), who, like
Darwin, was influenced by a reading of Malthus in arriving
at the idea of the survival of the fittest in the struggle for
existence. And on July ist, 1858, a joint communication by
Wallace and Darwin was presented at a meeting of the Lin-
nean Society in London. Wallace’s contribution was a paper
On the Tendency of Varieties to Depart Indefinitely from
the Original Type, while Darwin contributed an abridgment
of his own ideas.
EMPIRICISTS, AGNOSTICS, POSITIVISTS 123
in
far
so as it differs from that of Aristotle, is untenable.’
Coleridge’s distinction between the scientific understand-
ing and the higher Teason OT, as € Germans wou
between Verstand and Vernunft_ was one expression of his
revolt against the spirit of the eighteenth-century Enlighten-
sienf. Hedidnot,oFcouse, meantobmplythatthescientific
and critical understanding should be rejected in the name
of a higher and intuitive reason. His point was rather that
the former is not an omnicompetent instrument in the inter-
pretation of reality, but that it needs to be supplemented
and balanced by the latter, namely the intuitive reason. It
can hardly be claimed that Coleridge made his distinction
between understanding and reason crystal clear. But the gen-
eral line of his pitek is sufficiently plain. In Aids to ne:
flection (1825) he describes the understandin
which judges according to sense. Its appropriate sphere is the
“sensible world, and it reflécts and generalizes on the basis of
sense-experience. Reason, however, is the vehicle of ideas
which are presupposed by all experience, and in this sense it
predetermines and governs experience. It also perceives
truths which are incapable of verification in sense-experience,
and it intuitively apprehends spiritual realities. Further,
Coleridge identifies it with the practical reason, which com-
prises the will and the moral aspect of the human personality.
J. S. Mill is thus perfectly justified in saying in his famous
essay on Coleridge that the poet dissents from the ‘Lockian’
view that all knowledge consists of generalizations from ex-
perience, and that he claims for the reason, as distinct from
the understanding, the power to perceive by direct intuition
realities and truths which transcend the reach of the senses.®
178 THE IDEALIST MOVEMENT IN GREAT BRITAIN
a iritual ities.
Characteristic of Carlyle was his vivid sense of the mystery
of the world and of its nature as an appearance of, or veil
before, supersensible reality. In the State of German Litera-
ture he asserted that the ultimate aim of philosophy is ay
In any case Hegel starts with Being, whereas his own system
took knowledge as its point of departure,
Ferrier’s first move is to look for the absolute starting-point
of metaphysics in a proposition which states the one invari-
able and essential feature in all knowledge, and which cannot
be denied without contradiction. is is that ‘along with
whatever any intelligence knows, it must, as the ground or
condition of its knowledge, have some cognizance of itself’.8*
over against the world and the finite spirit. Hence he depicts
é spiritual life of man as a participation in the divine life.
But he also wishes to avoid using the word ‘God’ simply as a
label either for the spiritual life of man considered univer-
sally, as something which develops in the course of the evolu-
tion of human culture, or for the ideal of complete knowl-
196 THE IDEALIST MOVEMENT IN GREAT BRITAIN
edge, an ideal which does not yet exist but towards which
human knowledge progressively approximates. He does in-
deed speak of the human spirit as ‘identical’ with God; but
he adds, ‘in the sense that He is all which the human spirit
oursphitual
piritual lives’*"
liver20This
This does
docs not
not mean,
mean, however,
however, that
that the
th
idea of God is completely indeterminate, so that we are
forced to embrace the agnosticism of Herbert Spencer. For
God manifests Himself in both subject and object; and the
more we understand the spiritual life of humanity on the
one hand and the world of Nature on the other, so much the
more do we learn about God who is ‘the ultimate unity of
our life and of the life of the world’.41
Insofar as Caird goes behind the distinction between sub-
ject and object to an ultimate unity, we can say that he does
not absolutize the subject-object relationship in the way that
Ferrier does. At the same time his epistemological approach,
namely by way of their relationship, seems to create a diffi-
culty. For he explicitly recognizes that ‘strictly speaking, there
is but one object and one subject for each of us’.42 That is
to say, for me the subject-object relationship is, strictly, that
between myself as subject and my world as object. And the
object must include other people. Even if, therefore, it is
granted that I have from the beginning a dim awareness of
an underlying unity, it seems to follow that this unity is the
unity of myself as subject and of my object, other persons
being part of ‘my object’. And it is difficult to see how it
can then be shown that there are other subjects, and that
there is one and only one common underlying unity. Common
sense may suggest that these conclusions are correct. But it
is a question not of common sense but rather of seeing how
the conclusions can be established, once we have adopted
THE DEVELOPMENT OF IDEALISM 209
tn
kc
ABSOLUTE IDEALISM: BRADLEY 221
It scarcely needs saying that the very idea of a moral code
involves the idea of a relation to possible conduct, and that
a code which had no relation at all to a man’s historical and
social situation would be useless to him. But it does not
necessarily follow that I must identify morality with the exist-
ing moral standards and outlook of the society to which I
happen to belong. Indeed if, as Bradley admits, a member of
an existing society can see the defects in the moral code of
a past society, there does not seem to be any adequate reason
why an enlightened member of the past society should not
have seen these defects for himself and have rejected social
conformism in the name of higher moral standards and ideals.
This is, after all, precisely what has happened in history.
In point of fact, however, Bradley does not reduce morality
simply to social morality. For in his view itisa dutyrealize
to
the ideal self; and the content of this ideal self is not ex-
clusively social. Forexample, ‘itisamoral duty fortheartist
or the inquirer to lead the life of one, and a moral offence
when he fails to do so’.22 True, the activities of an artist or
of a scientist can, and generally do, benefit society. But ‘their
social bearing is indirect, and does not lie in their very es-
sence’.?8 This idea is doubtless in tune with Hegel’s attribu-
tion of art to the sphere of absolute spirit, rather than that
of objective spirit, where morality belongs. But the point is
that Bradley’s assertion that ‘man is not man at all unless
social, but man is not much above the beasts unless more
an socia might well have led him to revise such state-
ments as that ‘there is nothing better than my station and its
duties, nor anything higher or more truly beautiful’.25 If
mora ity is self-realization, and if the self cannot be ade-
quately described in purely social categories, morality can
hardly be identified with conformity to the standards of the
society to which one belongs.
Yet in a sense all this is simply grist to Bradley’s mill. For,
as has already been mentioned, he wishes to show that moral-
ity gives rise to antinomies or contradictions which cannot
be overcome on the purely ethical level. For example, and
this is the princi icti th 1 Jaw dem
the perfect identification of the individual will with the
ideally “good and universal will, though at the same time
222 THE IDEALIST MOVEMENT IN GREAT BRITAIN
prove it,’$®
What precisely is the content of this assumption or pre-
supposition or initial act of faith? In the appendix which
he added to the second edition of Appearance and Reality
Bradley tells us that ‘the actual starting-point and basis of
this work is an assumption about truth and reality. I have
assumed that the object of metaphysics is to find a general
view which will satisfy the intellect, and I have assumed that
whatever succeeds in doing this is real and true, and that
whatever fails is neither. This is a doctrine which, so far as
I can see, can neither be proved nor questioned.’46
The natural way of interpreting this passage, if it is taken
simply by itself, seems to be this. The scientist assumes that
there are uniformities to be discovered
within his field of
investigation. Otherwise he would never look for them. And
he has to assume that the generalizations which satisfy his
intellect are true. Further investigations may lead him to
modify or change his conclusions. But he cannot proceed at
all without making some presupposition. Similarly, we are
free to pursue metaphysics or to leave it alone; but if we
pursue it at all, we inevitably assume thata‘general view’ of
reality is possible, and therefore that reality as a whole is
intelligible in ‘principle. We further inevitably assume_that
we can |fTecognize the truth whenyhenwe find it. We assume,
that is say,
to that the generalwhich
view satisfies the in-
tellect is true and valid. For our only way of discriminating
between rival general views is by choosing the one which
most adequately satisfies the demands of the intellect.
Considered in itself this point of view is reasonable
enough. But difficulties arise when we bear in mind Brad-
ley’s doctrine about the shortcomings of discursive thought.
And it is perhaps not surprising to find expression being
given to a somewhat different view. Thus in a supplementary
note to the sixth chapter of his Essays on Truth and Reality
ABSOLUTE IDEALISM: BRADLEY 229
Bradley maintains that the One which is sought in
_meta-
Physics 1s not reached simply by a process of inference but
1s given in a basic feeling-experience. ‘The subject, the object,
and their relation, are experienced as elements or aspects in a
One which is there from the start.’47 That is to say, on the
pre-reflective level there is an experience ‘in which there is
no distinction between my awareness and that of which it is
aware. There is an immediate feeling, a knowing and being
in one, with which knowledge begins.’48 Indeed, ‘at no stage
of mental development is the mere correlation of subject
and object actually given’.4® Even when distinctions and re-
lations emerge in consciousness, there is always the back-
ground of ‘a felt totality’ .5°
This point of view is possibly compatible with that previ-
ously mentioned, though one would not normally describe a
as an ‘assumption
basic_immediate experien ce ’. In any case
Bradley’s thesis that there is such an experience enables him
|Absolute.
6. By the nature of the case there is not much that can
be said by way of positive description either about the alleged
pre-reflective experience of a felt totality or about the infinite
act of experience which constitutes the Absolute. And it is
hardly surprising if Bradley concentrates his attention on
showing that our ordinary ways of conceiving reality give
rise to contradictions and cannot yield a ‘general view’ capa-
ble of satisfying the intellect. But it is not possible to enter
here into all the details of his dialectic. We must confine
ourselves to indicating some of the phases of his line of
thought.
(i) We are accustomed to group the world’s contents into
things and their qualities, in Scholastic language into_sub-
stances and accidents, or, as Bradley puts it, into the substan-
tive and adjectival. But though this way of regarding reality
is embedded in language and undoubtedly has a practical
utility, it gives rise, Bradley maintains, to insoluble puzzles.
Consider, for example, a lump of sugar which is said to
have the qualities of whiteness, hardness and sweetness. If
we say that the sugar is white, we obviously do not mean that
it is identical with the quality of whiteness. For if this were
what we meant, we could not then say that the lump of
sugar is hard, unless indeed we were prepared to identify
whiteness and hardness. It is natural, therefore, to conceive
the sugar as a centre of unity, a substance which possesses
different qualities. ;
ABSOLUTE IDEALISM: BRADLEY 231
If, however, we try to explain what this centre of unity is
in itself, we are entirely at a loss. And in our perplexity we
are driven to say that the sugar is not an entity which pos-
sesses qualities, a substance in which accidents inhere, but
simply the qualities themselves as related to one another.
Yet what does it mean to say, for example, that the quality
of whiteness is related to the quality of sweetness? If, on the
one hand, being related to sweetness is identical with being
white, to say that whiteness is related to sweetness is to say
no more than that whiteness is whiteness. If, on the other
hand, being related to sweetness is something different from
being white, to say that whiteness is related to sweetness is
to predicate of it something different from itself, that is,
something which it is not.
Obviously, Bradley is not suggesting that we should cease
to speak about things and their qualities. His contention is
that once we try to explain the theory implied by this ad-
mittedly useful language, we find the thing dissolving into its
qualities, while at the same time we are unable to give an
satisfactory explanation of the way in which the qualities
Se utbiingg these
thesetwo
ee points of view which leads
ee Bradley
to_conclude_that relational thought is concerned with the
sphere of appearance, and that ultimate reality, the Absolute,
‘must be supra-relational.
(iii) Bradley remarks that anyone who has understood the
chapter in Appearance and Reality on relation and quality
‘will have seen that our experience, where relational, is not
true; and he will have condemned, almost without a hearing,
the great mass of phenomena’.®¢ We need not, therefore,
say much about his critique of space, time, motion and cau-
sality. It is sufficient to illustrate his line of thought by
reference to his critique of space and time.
On the one hand space cannot be simply a relation. For
any space must consist of parts which are themselves spaces.
And if space were merely a relation, we should thus be com-
pelled to make the absurd statement that space is nothing
but the relation which connects spaces. On the other hand,
however, space inevitably dissolves into relations and cannot
be anything else. For space is infinitely differentiated in-
ternally, consisting of parts which themselves consist of parts,
and so on indefinitely. And these differentiations are clearly
relations. Yet when we look for the terms, we cannot find
them. Hence the concept of space, as giving rise to a con-
tradiction, must be relegated to the sphere of appearance.
A similar critique is applied to the concept of time. On
the one hand time must be a relation, namely tha
‘before’ and arter
before and ‘after’. . On the other
Un the hand it cannot ul be arelation.
other ne
234 THE IDEALIST MOVEMENT IN GREAT BRITAIN
level than they would occupy if they were the result of reason
and free choice. Hence the employment of force and com-
pulsion should be restricted as far as possible, not because it
is thought to represent an interference by society with self-
enclosed individuals (for this is a false antithesis), but be-
cause it interferes with the attainment of the end for which
the State exists.
In other words, Bosanquet shares the view of T. H. Green
that the primary function of legislation is to remove hin-
drances to the development of the good life. How far, for
example, social legislation should extend is not a question
which can be answered a priori. As far as general principles
go, we can only say that to justify compulsion we ought to
be able to show that ‘a definite tendency to growth, or a
definite reserve of capacity, . . . is frustrated by a known
impediment, the removal of which is a small matter com-
pared to the capacities to be set free’.26 On this principle
we can justify, for instance, compulsory education as the re-
moval of a hindrance to the fuller and wider development
of human capacities. Obviously, the legislation itself is posi-
tive. But the object of the law is primarily that of removy-
ing hindrances to the attainment of the end for which politi-
cal society exists, an end which is ‘really’ willed by every
member as a rational being.
If we assume that the moral end is the fullest possible
development of man’s capacities, and that it is attained or at
any rate approached only in the context of society, it seems
only natural to look beyond the national State to the ideal of
a universal society, humanity in general. And Bosanquet does
at least admit that the idea of humanity must have a place
‘in any tolerably complete philosophical thinking’.27 At the
same time he claims that the ethical idea of humanity does
not form an adequate basis for an effective community. For
we cannot presuppose in mankind at large a sufficient unity
of experience, such as exists in a national State, for the ex-
ercise of a General Will. Further, Bosanquet condemns pro-
posals for a World-State with plans for substituting a uni-
versal language for national languages, a substitution which,
in his opinion, would destroy literature and poetry and te-
duce intellectual life to a level of mediocrity. Like Hegel,
ABSOLUTE IDEALISM: BOSANQUET 259
therefore, Bosanquet is unable to transcend the
idea of the
national State, animated by a common spirit which
expresses
itself in objective institutions and submits these institu
tions
to a critical evaluation in the light of experience
and present
needs.
Again, like Hegel, Bosanquet is prepared to admit that
no actual State is immune from criticism. It is possible
in
principle for the State to act ‘in contravention of its main
duty to sustain the conditions of as much good life as pos-
sible’.28 But though this admission would appear to most
people to be obviously justified, it creates a special difficulty
for anyone who holds with Bosanquet that the State is in
some sense identical with the General Will. For by defini-
tion the General Will wills only what is right. Hence Bosan-
quet tends to make a distinction between the State as such
and its agents. The latter may act immorally, but the former,
the State as such, cannot be saddled with responsibility for
the misdeeds of its agents ‘except under circumstances which
are barely conceivable’.2®
It can hardly be claimed that this is a logically satisfactory
position. If the State as such means the General Will, and if
the General Will always wills what is right, it seems to follow
that there are no conceivable circumstances in which the
State as such could be said to act immorally. And in the
long run we are left with a tautology, namely that a will
which always wills what is right, always wills what is right.
Indeed, Bosanquet himself seems to feel this, for he suggests
that on a strict definition of State action we ought to say
that the State does not really will an immoral action which
we would ordinarily attribute to ‘the State’. At the same
time he understandably feels bound to admit that there may
be circumstances in which we can legitimately speak of the
State acting immorally. But by speaking of ‘barely conceiva-
ble’ circumstances he inevitably gives the impression that for
practical purposes the State is immune from criticism. For
those who maintain that statements about action by the State
are always reducible in principle to statements about indi-
viduals, there is obviously no difficulty in speaking about the
State as acting immorally. But if we assume that we can make
meaningful statements about ‘the State as such’ which are
260 THE IDEALIST MOVEMENT IN GREAT BRITAIN
Thus selves are spiritual, and so are parts of selves and groups
of selves, though in deference to common usage the term
‘a spirit’ can be reserved for a self.3%
If spirit, therefore, is the only form of substance, the uni-
verse or Absolute will be the all-inclusive society or system
of selves, selves being its primary parts. The secondary parts,
of all grades, are perceptions, which form the contents of
selves. In this case there must be relations of determining
correspondence between these parts. True, this demands the
fulfilment of certain conditions; that ‘a self can perceive an-
other self, and a part of another self’,34 that a perception is
part of a percipient self, and that a perception of a part of
a whole can be part of a perception of this whole. But the
fulfilment of these conditions cannot be shown to be impos-
sible; and there are reasons for thinking that they are in fact
fulfilled. So we can take it that the Absolute is the system
or society of selves.
Are selves immortal? The answer to this question depends
on the point of view which we adopt. On the one hand Mc-
Taggart denies the reality of time, on the ground that an as-
sertion of the reality of the temporal series of past, present
and future compels us to attribute to any given event mutu-
ally incompatible determinations.25 Hence if we adopt this
point of view, we should describe selves as timeless or eternal
rather than as immortal, a term which implies unending tem-
poral duration. On the other hand time certainly belongs to
the sphere of appearance. And the self will appear-to persist
through all future time. ‘In consequence of this, I think we
may properly say that the self is immortal’,3¢ though immor-
tality must then be understood as including pre-existence,
before, that is, its union with the body.
Professor C. D. Broad has remarked37 that he does not
suppose that McTaggart made a single disciple, though he
exercised a considerable influence on his pupils by his logical
subtlety, his intellectual honesty and his striving after clarity.
It is not indeed surprising if McTaggart failed to make dis-
ciples. For, apart from the fact that he does not explain, any
more than Bradley did, how the sphere of appearance arises
in the first place, his system provides a much clearer example
than the philosophies of either Bradley or Bosanquet of the
THE TURN TOWARDS PERSONAL IDEALISM 277
account of metaphysics which has sometimes
been given by
anti-metaphysicians, namely as an alleged science which
pro-
fesses to deduce the nature of reality in a purely a
priori
manner. For having worked out in the first part of his
system
what characteristics the existent must possess, McTag
gart
blithely proceeds in the second part to reject the reality of
matter and time on the ground that they do not fulfil the
requirements established in the first part. And though his
conclusions certainly make his philosophy more interesting
and exciting, their strangeness is apt to make most readers
conclude without more ado that there must be something
wrong with his arguments. Most people at any rate find it
difficult to believe that reality consists of a system of selves,
the contents of which are perceptions. ‘Ingenious but uncon-
vincing’, is likely to be their verdict about McTaggart’s ar-
guments.
It may be objected that this is a very philistinian point of
view. If McTaggart’s arguments are good ones, the strange-
ness of his conclusions does not alter the fact. And this is
true enough. But it is also a fact that few philosophers have
been convinced by the arguments adduced to show that re-
ality must be what McTaggart says it is.
3. McTaggart combined the doctrine that existing reality
consists of spiritual selves with atheism.38 But the personal
idealists generally adopted some form of theism. We can take
as an example James Ward (1843-1925), naturalist, psy-
chologist and philosopher, who studied for a while in Ger-
many, where he came under the influence of Lotze, and even-
tually occupied the chair of logic and mental philosophy at
Cambridge (1897-1925).
In 1886 Ward contributed to the Encyclopaedia Britan-
nica a famous article on psychology, which later provided the
basis for his Psychological Principles (1918), a work which
clearly shows the influence of German philosophers such as
Lotze, Wundt and Brentano. Ward was strongly opposed to
the associationist psychology. In his view the content of con-
sciousness consists of ‘presentations’; but these form a con-
tinuum. They are not discrete isolated events or impressions,
into which the presentational continuum can be broken up.
Obviously, a new presentation introduces fresh material; but
278 THE IDEALIST MOVEMENT IN GREAT BRITAIN
A SHORT BIBLIOGRAPHY
General Works
2. BENTHAM
Texts
The Works of Jeremy Bentham, edited by John Bowring.
11 vols. Edinburgh, 1838-43.
Benthamiana, Select Extracts from the Works of Jeremy
Bentham, edited by J. H. Burton. Edinburgh, 1843.
Oeuvres de Jérémie Bentham, translated by E. Dumont. 3
vols. Brussels, 1829-30.
Coleccién de obras del célebre Jeremias Bentham, compiled
by E. Dumont with commentaries by B. Anduaga y
Espinosa. 14 vols. Madrid, 1841-3.
An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation,
edited by L. Lafleur. New York, 1948. (The 1876 Ox-
ford edition is a reprint of the 1823 edition.)
Theory of Legislation, translated from the French of E. Du-
mont by R. Hildreth. London, 1896.
Bentham’s Theory of Legislation, edited by C. K. Ogden.
London, 1950.
A Fragment on Government, edited by F. C. Montague. Lon-
don, 1801.
Bentham’s Theory of Fictions, edited by C. K. Ogden. Lon-
don, 1932.
Bentham’s Handbook of Political Fallacies, edited by H. A.
Larrabee. Baltimore, 1952.
Deontology, or the Science of Morality, edited by J. Bowring.
2 vols. London, 1834.
The Limits of Jurisprudence Defined, edited by C. W. Ever-
ett. New York, 1945.
Jeremy Bentham’s Economie Writings, Critical Edition based
on his Printed Works and Unprinted Manuscripts,
edited by W. Stark. 3 vols. London, 1952-4. (Each vol-
A SHORT BIBLIOGRAPHY 287
ume contains an introductory essay. The second appen-
dix, contained in the third volume, is a systematic survey
of the surviving Bentham manuscripts. )
Catalogue of the Manuscripts of Jeremy Bentham in the
Library of University College, London, edited by Ag Le
Milne. London, 1937.
Studies
Atkinson, C. M. Jeremy Bentham, His Life and Work. Lon-
don, 1905.
Baumgardt, D. Bentham and the Ethics of Today. Princeton
(U.S.A.) and London, 1952.
Busch, J. Die moralische und soziale Ethik Benthams. Neisse,
1938.
Everett, C. W. The Education of Jeremy Bentham. New
York, 1931.
Jones, W. T. Masters of Political Thought: From Machiavelli
to Bentham. London, 1947.
Keeton, G. W. and Schwarzenberger, G. (editors). Jeremy
Bentham and the Law. London, 1948.
Laski, H. J. Political Thought in England: Locke to Bentham.
London, 1950.
Mack, M. P. Jeremy Bentham: An Odyssey of Ideas, 1748-
1792. London, 1962.
Mill, J. S. Mill on Bentham and Coleridge, edited by F. R.
Leavis. London, 1950.
Quintodamo, N. La morale ‘utilitaristica del Bentham e sua
evoluzione nel diritto penale. Naples, 1936.
Stephen, L. The English Utilitarians: Vol. I, Jeremy Ben-
tham. London, 1900.
3. JAMES MILL
Texts
History of India. 3 vols. London, 1817. (4th edition, 9 vols.,
1848; sth edition, with continuation by M. H. Wilson,
10 vols., 1858.)
Elements of Political Economy. London, 1821 (31d and re-
vised edition, 1826). ;
Analysis of the Phenomena of the Human Mind, edited by
288 APPENDIX
5. HERBERT SPENCER
Texts
A System of Synthetic Philosophy. 10 vols. London, 1862-93
.
(For some detailed information about the various edi-
tions of the books comprising the System see Pp. 240-1.)
Epitome of the Synthetic Philosophy, by F. H. Collins. Lon-
don, 1889 (sth edition, 1901).
Essays, Scientific, Political and Speculative. 3 vols. London,
1891. (Two volumes of Essays, Scientific, Political and
Speculative appeared at London in 1857 and 1863 re-
spectively and one volume of Essays, Moral, Political
and Aesthetic at New York in 1865.)
Education, Intellectual, Moral, Physical. London, 1861.
The Man versus The State. London, 1884.
The Nature and Reality of Religion. London, 1885.
Various Fragments. London, 1897.
Facts and Comments. London, 1902.
Autobiography. 2 vols. New York, 1904.
Studies
Allievo, G. La psicologia di Herbert Spencer. Turin, 1914
(2nd edition).
Ardigd, R. L’Inconoscibile di Spencer e il noumeno di Kant.
Padua, 1901.
Asirvatham, E. Spencer’s Theory of Social Justice. New York,
1936.
Carus, P. Kant and Spencer. Chicago, 1889.
Diaconide, E. Etude critique sur la sociologie de Herbert
Spencer. Paris, 1938.
Duncan, D. The Life and Letters of Herbert Spencer. Lon-
don, 1912.
Elliott, H. Herbert Spencer. London, 1917.
Ensor, R. C. Some Reflections on Spencer's Doctrine that
Progress is Differentiation. Oxford, 1947.
Fiske, J. Outlines of Cosmic Philosophy. 2 vols. London,
1874. (These lectures are critical as well as expository
of Spencer’s thought.)
Gaupp, O. Herbert Spencer. Stuttgart, 1897.
292 APPENDIX
2. COLERIDGE
Texts
Works, edited by W. G. T. Shedd. 7 vols. New York, 1884.
The Friend. 3 vols. London, 1812. (2 vols, 1837).
Biographia Literaria. London, 1817. (Everyman Library,
1906 and reprints.)
Aids to Reflection. 2 vols. London, 1824-5 (with addition
of the Essay on Faith, 1890).
On the Constitution of Church and State, edited by H. N.
Coleridge. London, 1839.
Confessions of an Inquiring Spirit, edited by H. N. Cole-
ridge. London, 1840.
Treatise on Method. London, 1849 (31d edition).
Essays on His Own Times. 3 vols. London, 1850.
Anima Poetae, edited by E. H. Coleridge. London, 1895.
Letters, edited by E. H. Coleridge. London, 1895.
Unpublished Letters. London, 1932.
The Political Thought of Coleridge, selected by R. J. White.
London, 1938.
The Philosophical Lectures of S. T. Coleridge, Hitherto Un-
published, edited by K. Cobum. London, 1949.
The Notebooks of S. T. Coleridge, edited by K. Coburn. 2
vols. London, 1957-62.
Studies
Blunden, E. and Griggs, E. L. (editors). Coleridge Studies.
London, 1934.
Campbell J. D. Life of S. T. Coleridge. London, 1894.
Chambers, E. K. S. T. Coleridge: A Biographical Study. Ox-
ford, 1938.
204 APPENDIX
Chinol, E. Il pensiero di S. T. Coleridge. Venice, 1953.
Coburn, K. Inquiring Spirit. A New Presentation of Cole-
ridge (from published and unpublished writings). Lon-
don, 1931.
Ferrando, G. Coleridge. Florence, 1925.
Green, J. H. Spiritual Philosophy, Founded on the Teaching
of the late S. T. Coleridge. 2 vols. London, 1865.
Hanson, L. Life of S. T. Coleridge: Early Years. London,
1938.
Kagey, R. Coleridge: Studies in the History of Ideas. New
York, 1935.
Lowes, J. L. The Road to Xanadu: A Study in Ways of the
Imagination. London, 1927 (revised edition 1930).
Muirhead, J. H. Coleridge as Philosopher. London, 1930.
Richards, I. A. Coleridge on Imagination. London, 1934.
Snyder, A. D. Coleridge on Logic and Learning. New Haven,
1929.
Wellek, R. Immanuel Kant in England. Princeton, 1931.
(Only partly on Coleridge.)
Winkelmann, E. Coleridge und die kantische Philosophie.
Leipzig, 1933.
Wunsche, W. Die Staatsauffassung S. T. Coleridge’s. Leipzig,
1934.
3. CARLYLE
Texts
Works, edited by H. D. Traill. 31 vols. London, 1897-1901.
Sartor Resartus. London, 1841, and subsequent editions.
On Heroes, Hero-Worship and the Heroic in History. London,
1841.
Correspondence of Carlyle and R. W. Emerson. 2 vols. Lon-
don, 1883.
Letters of Carlyle to J. S. Mill, J. Stirling and R. Browning,
edited by A. Carlyle. London, 1923.
Studies
Baumgarten, O. Carlyle und Goethe. Tiibingen, 1906.
Fermi, L. Carlyle. Messina, 19309.
Garnett, R. Life of Carlyle. London, 1887.
A SHORT BIBLIOGRAPHY 295
Harrold, C. F. Carlyle and German T hought, 1819-34.
New
Haven, 1934.
Hensel, P. Thomas Carlyle. Stuttgart, 1901.
Lammond, D. Carlyle. London, 1934.
Lea, F. Carlyle, Prophet of Today. London, 1944.
Lehman, B. H. Carlyle’s Theory of the Hero. Duke, 1939.
Neff, E. Carlyle and Mill: Mystic and Utilitarian. New York,
1924.
Carlyle. New York, 1932.
Seilliére, E. L’actualité de Carlyle. Paris, 1929.
Storrs, M. The Relation of Carlyle to Kant and Fichte. Bryn
Mawr, 1929.
Taylor, A. C. Carlyle et la pensée latine. Paris, 1937.
Wilson, D. A. Carlyle. 6 vols. London, 1923-34.
4. T. H. GREEN
Texts
Works, edited by R. L. Nettleship, 3 vols. London, 1885-8.
(Contains Green’s Introductions to Hume’s Treatise,
lectures on Kant, on Logic and on The Principles of
Political Obligation, together with a memoir of the phi-
losopher by Nettleship. )
Introductions to Hume’s Treatise in vols. 1 and 2 of the
Philosophical Works of David Hume edited by T. H.
Green and T. M. Grose. London, 1874.
Prolegomena to Ethics, edited by A. C. Bradley. London,
1883.
Principles of Political Obligation. London, 1895.
Studies
Giinther, O. Das Verhdltnis der Ethik Greens zu der Kants.
Leipzig, 1915.
Fairbrother, W. H. The Philosophy of T. H. Green. London,
1896.
Fusai, M. Il pensiero morale di T. H. Green. Florence, 1943.
Lamont, W. D. Introduction to Green’s Moral Philosophy.
New York, 1934.
Muirhead, J. H. The Service of the State: Four lectures on
the Political Teaching of Green. London, 1908.
296 APPENDIX
Pucelle, J. La nature et l'esprit dans la philosophie de T. H.
Green. I, Métaphysique—Morale. Louvain, 1961. (A
thorough and sympathetic study.)
5. E. CAIRD
Texts
A Critical Account of the Philosophy of Kant. Glasgow, 1877.
(Revised edition in 2 vols. with the title The Critical
Philosophy of Kant, Glasgow, 1889.)
Hegel. Edinburgh, 1883.
The Social Philosophy and Religion of Comte. Glasgow,
1885.
Essays on Literature and Philosophy. 2 vols. Glasgow, 1892.
The Evolution of Religion. 2 vols. Glasgow, 1893.
The Evolution of Theology in the Greek Philosophers, 2
vols. Glasgow, 1904.
Studies
Jones, H. and Muirhead, J. H. The Life and Philosophy of
Edward Caird. London, 1921.
6. BRADLEY
Texts
The Presuppositions of Critical History. London, 1874.
Ethical Studies. London, 1876 (2nd edition, 1927).
Mr. Sidgwick’s Hedonism. London, 1877.
The Principles of Logic. London, 1883 (2nd edition with
Terminal Essays in 2 vols, 1922.)
Appearance and Reality. London, 1893 (2nd edition with
Appendix, 1897).
Essays on Truth and Reality. London, 1914.
Aphorisms. Oxford, 1930.
Collected Essays. 2 vols. Oxford, 1935. (This work includes
The Presuppositions of Critical History.)
Studies
Antonelli, M. A. La metafisica di F. H. Bradley. Milan, 1952.
Campbell, C. A. Scepticism and Construction. Bradley’s Scep-
A SHORT BIBLIOGRAPHY 297
tical Principle as the Basis of Constructive Philos
ophy.
London, 1931.
Chappuis, A. Der theoretische Weg Bradleys. Paris,
1934.
Church, R. W. Bradley’s Dialectic. London, 1942.
De Mameffe, J. La preuve de l’Absolu chez Bradley. Analyse
et critique de la méthode. Paris, 1961.
Kagey, R. The Growth of Bradley’s Logic. London, 1931.
Keeling, S. V. La nature de Texpérience chez Kant et chez
Bradley. Montpellier, 1925.
Lomba, R. M. Bradley and Bergson. Lucknow, 1937.
Lofthouse, W. F. F. H. Bradley. London, 1949.
Mack, R. D. The Appeal to Immediate Experience. Philo-
sophie Method in Bradley, Whitehead and Dewey. New
York, 1945.
Ross, G. R. Scepticism and Dogma: A Study in the Philoso-
phy of F. H. Bradley. New York, 1940.
Schiiring, H.-J. Studie zur Philosophie yon F. H. Bradley.
Meisenheim am Glan, 1963.
Segerstedt, T. T. Value and Reality in Bradley’s Philosophy.
Lund, 1934.
Taylor, A. E. F. H. Bradley. London, 1924. (British Academy
lecture. )
Wollheim, R. F. H. Bradley. Penguin Books, 1959.
In Mind for 1925 there are articles on Bradley by G. D.
Hicks, J. H. Muirhead, G. F. Stout, F. C. S. Schiller,
A. E. Taylor and J. Ward.
7. BOSANQUET
Texts
Knowledge and Reality. London, 188s.
Logic, or the Morphology of Knowledge. 2 vols. London,
1888.
Essays and Addresses. London, 1889.
A History of Aesthetic. London, 1892.
The Civilization of Christendom and Other Studies. London,
1893.
Aspects of the Social Problem. London, 1895.
The Essentials of Logic. London, 1895.
Companion to Plato’s Republic. London, 1895.
298 APPENDIX
Rousseau’s Social Contract. London, 1895.
Psychology of the Moral Self. London, 1897.
The Philosophical Theory of the State. London, 1899.
The Principle of Individuality and Value. London, 1912.
The Value and Destiny of the Individual. London, 1913.
The Distinction between Mind and Its Objects. London,
1913.
Three Lectures on Aesthetics. London, 1915.
Social and International Ideals. London, 1917.
Some Suggestions in Ethics. London, 1918.
Implication and Linear Inference. London, 1920.
What Religion Is. London, 1920.
The Meeting of Extremes in Contemporary Philosophy. Lon-
don, 1921.
Three Chapters on the Nature of Mind. London, 1923.
Science and Philosophy and Other Essays, edited by J. H.
Muirhead and R. C. Bosanquet. London, 1927.
Studies
Bosanquet, H. Bernard Bosanquet. London, 1924.
Houang, F. La néo-hégelianisme en Angleterre: la philoso-
phie de Bernard Bosanquet. Paris, 1954.
De lhumanisme a l'absolutisme. L’évolution de la pensée
teligieuse du néo-hégelien anglais Bernard Bosanquet.
Paris, 1954.
Muirhead, J. H. (editor). Bosanquet and His Friends: Letters
Illustrating Sources and Development of His Philosophi-
cal Opinions. London, 1935.
Pfannenstil, B. Bernard Bosanquet’s Philosophy of the State.
Lund, 1936.
8. MC TAGGART
Texts
Studies in the Hegelian Dialectic. Cambridge, 1896 (2nd edi-
tion 1922).
Studies in the Hegelian Cosmology. Cambridge, 1901 (2nd
edition, 1918).
Some Dogmas of Religion. London, 1906 (2nd edition, with
biographical introduction by C. D. Broad, 1930).
A SHORT BIBLIOGRAPHY 299
_ A Commentary on Hegel’s Logic, Cambridge, 1910
(new edi-
tion, 1931).
The Nature of Existence. 2 vols. Cambridge, 1921-7.
(The
second vol. is edited by C. D. Broad.)
Philosophical Studies, edited, with an introduction by S. V.
Keeling, London, 1934. (Mainly a collection of pub-
lished articles, including that on the unteality of time.)
Studies
Broad, C. D. Examination of McTaggart’s Philosophy. 2 vols.
Cambridge, 1933-8.
Dickinson, G. Lowes. McTaggart, a Memoir. Cambridge,
1931.
NOTES
302 NOTES
304 NOTES
306 NOTES
A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY
The full story of nineteenth-century philosophy is coy-
ered in Father Copleston’s eighth volume of A History oF
Purtosopuy. The series itself is among the most remarkable
« singlehanded scholarly enterprises in recent times. It has
already been said of this volume that it “may well have the
widest appeal of all.”
Volume 8 opens with an examination of the utilitarian
movements of the nineteenth century, the empiricism of
J. S. Mill, and the philosophy of Herbert Spencer. It then
moves to a thorough consideration of the idealist movement
in Great Britain from its literary pioneers, like Coleridge and
Carlyle, to Bradley, Bosanquet, and McTaggart. The next
part of the book is devoted respectively to idealism in Amer-
ica and to the pragmatist movement from C. S. Pierce to
John Dewey. In the concluding section of the book, Father
Copleston discusses modern realism in Britain and America
and Moore’s practice of analysis. ‘The three final chapters are
given over to an intensive study of the philosophy of Ber-
trand Russell. ‘There is also an Epilogue on more recent
trends in British philosophy and an Appendix on John Henry
Newman.
The Historical Bulletin has said of this series: “There can
be no doubt that this is the best text of the history of phi-
losophy now available in English.”
é aS SS SSOP S
IMAGE BOOK
. . making the world’s finest —
Catholic literature available toa
DI4ATA COVER BY RONALD CLYNE ;