Logic and Proofs - 5
Logic and Proofs - 5
Logic and Proofs - 5
Induction
SECTION 5.1
Section Summary
Mathematical Induction
Examples of Proof by Mathematical Induction
Mistaken Proofs by Mathematical Induction
Guidelines for Proofs by Mathematical Induction
Climbing an
Infinite Ladder
Suppose we have an infinite ladder:
1. We can reach the first rung of the ladder.
2. If we can reach a particular rung of the
ladder, then we can reach the next rung.
We can conjecture that the sum of the first n positive odd integers is n2,
Assume the inductive hypothesis holds and then show that P(k + 1) holds has well.
Hence, we have shown that P(k + 1) follows from P(k). Therefore the sum of the first n positive odd integers is n2.
Proving Inequalities
Example: Use mathematical induction to prove that n < 2n for all positive
integers n.
Solution: Let P(n) be the proposition that n < 2n.
BASIS STEP: P(1) is true since 1 < 21 = 2.
INDUCTIVE STEP: Assume P(k) holds, i.e., k < 2k, for an arbitrary positive integer k.
Must show that P(k + 1) holds. Since by the inductive hypothesis, k < 2k, it follows
that:
k + 1 < 2k + 1 ≤ 2k + 2k = 2 ∙ 2k = 2k+1
Therefore n < 2n holds for all positive integers n.
Proving Inequalities
Example: Use mathematical induction to prove that 2n < n!, for every
integer n ≥ 4.
Solution: Let P(n) be the proposition that 2n < n!.
BASIS STEP: P(4) is true since 24 = 16 < 4! = 24.
INDUCTIVE STEP: Assume P(k) holds, i.e., 2k < k! for an arbitrary integer k ≥
4. To show that P(k + 1) holds:
2k+1 = 2∙2k
< 2∙ k! (by the inductive hypothesis)
< (k + 1)k!
= (k + 1)!
Therefore, 2n < n! holds, for every integer n ≥ 4.
Note that here the basis step is P(4), since P(0), P(1), P(2), and P(3) are
all false.
Proving Divisibility Results
continued
→
An Incorrect “Proof” by
Mathematical Induction
Inductive Hypothesis: Every set of k lines in the plane,
where k ≥ 2, no two of which are parallel, meet in a
common point.
Consider a set of k + 1 distinct lines in the plane, no two parallel. By the inductive
hypothesis, the first k of these lines must meet in a common point p1. By the inductive
hypothesis, the last k of these lines meet in a common point p2.
If p1 and p2 are different points, all lines containing both of them must be the same
line since two points determine a line. This contradicts the assumption that the lines are
distinct. Hence, p1 = p2 lies on all k + 1 distinct lines, and therefore P(k + 1) holds.
Assuming that k ≥2, distinct lines meet in a common point, then every k + 1 lines meet in a
common point.
There must be an error in this proof since the conclusion is absurd. But where is the error?
Answer: P(k)→ P(k + 1) only holds for k ≥3. It is not the case that P(2) implies P(3). The first
two lines must meet in a common point p1 and the second two must meet in a common
point p2. They do not have to be the same point since only the second line is common to
both sets of lines.
Guidelines:
Mathematical Induction Proofs
Kenneth H. Rosen (2012)
Discrete Mathematics and its Applications, 7th ed.