Game Theory Slides Chapter 6x6timeinconsistentpreferences

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 13

Time Inconsistent Preferences

Felix Munoz-Garcia

Advanced Microeconomics II - Washington State University


Time Inconsistent Preferences - Tadelis 8.3.4

Previously, we assumed that players maximize their discounted


sum of payo¤s.
This is typically done using exponential discounting, where
every future period is multiplied by δt .
We can show that using exponential discounting, an
individual’s consumption choices are consistent across time
periods.
Time Inconsistent Preferences

Consider a player with u (x ) = ln(x ) who needs to allocate a


…xed budget K across three periods. Assume that prices all
equal 1. His maximization problem is

max ln(K x2 x3 ) + δ ln(x2 ) + δ2 ln(x3 )


x2 ,x3 | {z }
x1

with …rst-order conditions


1 δ
+ = 0
K x2 x3 x2
1 δ2
+ = 0
K x2 x3 x3
Time Inconsistent Preferences

Solving, we …nd
1
x1 = K
1 + δ + δ2
δ
x2 = K
1 + δ + δ2
δ2
x2 = K
1 + δ + δ2
But what if the player made his choices sequentially? Would
he reach the same equilibrium? Let’s try backward induction.
Time Inconsistent Preferences

In period 2, the player solves

max ln(x2 ) + δ ln(K2 x2 )


x2 | {z }
x3

where

1 δ + δ2
K2 = K x1 = K K = K
1 + δ + δ2 1 + δ + δ2
Solving, we …nd

K2 δ
x2 = =K
1+δ 1 + δ + δ2
Time Inconsistent Preferences

Thus, regardless of his previous actions, the player will choose


the same consumption amounts sequentially as he will
simultaneously. Thus, this player has time consistent
preferences.
This is a useful property of exponential discounting.
What about other types of discounting, namely hyperbolic
discounting.
In this case, a player uses the discount rate δ as seen in
exponential discounting, but he uses an additional discount
factor β 2 (0, 1) to discount all of the future compared to
present consumption. Our previous example would look as
follows under hyperbolic discounting:

max ln(K x2 x3 ) + βδ ln(x2 ) + βδ2 ln(x3 )


x2 ,x3 | {z }
x1
Time Inconsistent Preferences

Intuitively, if the player is looking toward the future, the


discount factor he uses between periods t = 1 and t = 2 is
stronger than the one he uses between periods t = 2 and
t = 3.
Hyperbolic discounting will cause problems with self-control,
in that a player will plan to do one thing but later choose to
revise his plan.
This is studied frequently in behavior economics. In laboratory
setting, it is frequently found that individuals do not consume
"rationally." Robby Rosenman’s module in Applied
Microeconomics touches on this very topic, as well as other
similar ones.
Time Inconsistent Preferences
Let δ = 1 for simplicity. We know that a rational person using
exponential discounting will equalize his consumption across
the three periods, i.e., xi = K3 i = 1, 2, 3. Let’s look at the
case where a player uses hyperbolic discounting, and for
simplicity, we’ll assume that β = 21 .
Our simultaneous problem becomes
1 1
max ln(K x2 x3 ) + ln(x2 ) + ln(x3 )
x2 ,x3 | {z } 2 2
x1
with solution
1
x1 = K
2
1
x2 = K
4
1
x3 = K
4
Time Inconsistent Preferences

Checking to see if the player’s sequential solution is the same,


we use backward induction. Our period 2 problem becomes
1
max ln(x2 ) + ln(K x1 x2 )
x2 2 | {z }
x3

This yields best-response functions of


2
x2 (x1 ) = (K x1 )
3
1
x3 (x1 ) = (K x1 )
3
Time Inconsistent Preferences

We can substitute these best-response functions back into our


period 1 problem to obtain
1 2 1 1
max ln(x1 ) + ln (K x1 ) + ln (K x1 )
x1 2 3 2 3
with solution
1
x1 = K
2
1
x2 = K
3
1
x3 = K
6

Note: This di¤ers from Tadelis’solution. He has an error in his


FOCs. (This is why we check them!)
Time Inconsistent Preferences

This results in a very di¤erent solution than our simultaneous


benchmark, x1 = 21 K , x2 = 14 K , x3 = 14 K .
In this situation, the player consumes the same amount as he
would normally in period 1, but in period 2, he becomes
impatient once again, and overconsumes what he would have
wanted to in period 1. We refer to this as the player having
time inconsistent preferences.
Time Inconsistent Preferences

Comparing time consistent with time inconsistent preferences


in the simultaneous game (δ = 1):

Time Inconsistent Preferences, β = ½


½

Time Consistent Preferences, β = 1



¼

Period 1 Period 2 Period 3


Time Inconsistent Preferences

Comparing time consistent with time inconsistent preferences


in the sequential game (δ = 1):

Time Inconsistent Preferences, β = ½


½

Time Consistent Preferences, β = 1


Period 1 Period 2 Period 3

You might also like