POLITICAL JUSTICE: THE USE or LEGAL PROCEDURE FOR POLITICAL ENDS
POLITICAL JUSTICE: THE USE or LEGAL PROCEDURE FOR POLITICAL ENDS
POLITICAL JUSTICE: THE USE or LEGAL PROCEDURE FOR POLITICAL ENDS
71 :1351
2. P. 172.
3. P. 266.
1366 THE YALE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 71 :1351
disclaims at the outset, may well be the fairest description of the work. It is
of course no criticism to say that the panorama does not survey all the
phenomena of political justice. The very selectivity of materials, however, may
carry with it the obligation of a somewhat sharper focus than Professor
Kirchheimer achieves. To change the metaphor, the proverbial Procrustean bed
was surely not the only alternative. For example, the author might have
worked more explicitly within the configuration of history, as he did in his
earlier co-authored book, Punishment and Social Structure. Despite his greater
concern in the present work with the contemporary period, he does draw
frequently on historical materials and is clearly preoccupied with the nation-
state's retreat, since World War I, from its earlier "magnanimity" toward
political dissent. More pointed emphasis on this historical theme throughout
the book would perhaps have tightened up the analysis.
Since the concept of "judicial space" is also an important concern of the
book, another approach might have been to place the phenomena of political
justice on a continuum ranging from maximum to minimum judicial space.
Although there is more than a hint of such a continuum in the work as it
stands, this approach also is never developed in any explicit fashion. Had it
been, a number of important problems might have been faced squarely rather
than obliquely. In a book which is scarcely "value free," it is more than a
little disconcerting that the analysis is not really grounded in any clear theory
of law. True, Professor Kirchheimer does lay out something of a model of
"judicial action," emphasizing the procedural norm of immunity from govern-
mental pressure, the "interstitial" character of a court's individualizing of
general rules to particular cases, and the reciprocity which ought to exist be-
tween adjudication and community values. Yet, this model comes at an odd
point almost half-way through the book and its relation to the over-all analysis
is disappointingly unfulfilled. For example, the author never quite comes to
terms with the classic question, "What is a legal system ?" Grant his dismay
with the erosion of impartiality, the capricious fluctuation of norms, and re-
course to retroactive, unpromulgated "legality," where along the continuum of
decreasing judicial space does a legal system cease to exist, if it does? In light
of much of the material with which the book deals, this is obviously more than
a moot question.
Aside from the emphasis on impartial, coherent, regularized procedure,
one is also puzzled by the degree or sense in which Professor Kirchheimer is
concerned with the substantive content of norms. At one point he observes that
courts succumb to political partiality most frequently in fragmentized political
contexts, as did Weimar Germany, or during a totalitarian regime's attempt
to impose from overhead a new ideology on society. Then, somewhat later in
his discussion of East Germany, he concludes, "When the regime's major
goals have been fulfilled and its spiritual and social dominion safely anchored,
the eternal guard against individual slackening may be relaxed-and a referee
allowed to mark points for both sides." 4 This may indeed prove to be an ac-
4. P. 299.
1962] REV71EWS 1367
curate prophecy, but one wonders exactly what it means in terms of political
justice. Once the totalitarian regime has triumphed, and judicial space is
restored, does the phenomenon of political justice end? Probably not. First,
there will probably still be occasional extraordinary instances of interference
with the referee. Second, in a more profound sense, tolerance of the referee re-
flects not only the regime's secure establishment in society at large, but also
the fact that the politicizing of the judiciary itself has been carried through
successfully. Norms may now be coherent and regular, but their content and
the courts implementing them are still "political." It is this second point that
Professor Kirchheimer, in his seemingly positivistic emphasis on regularity
and coherence, does not make sufficiently explicit. It would certainly be unfair
to imply that he is oblivious to the substance of norms, or unaware that,
procedure aside, the substance of a norm can itself be outrageous. On a number
of occasions he even seems to use the language of natural law in condemning
"atrocious offenses against the human condition" and postulating "fundamental
minimum requirements of human decency." 5 Indeed, it is ultimately in these
terms that he judges Nazi Germany and justifies that unusual instance of
political justice, the Nuremberg trials. One may agree with his normative con-
clusion, however, and still be disconcerted at the failure to establish a bridge
between his preoccupation with regularized coherence on the one hand and
these apparently substantive natural law standards on the other. Professor
Kirchheimer may well agree with Professor Lon Fuller that "coherence and
goodness have more affinity than coherence and evil." But if he does, this
assumption receives no clear recognition or elaboration. The result is ambiguity
not only in the author's own view of law, but also in the objective relationship
that political justice may have to the problem of positivism versus natural law.
Finally, the notion that political justice appears most frequently in frag-
mentized political contexts raises a question about the institution of judicial
review as practiced in America. Although Professor Kirchheimer discusses
various specific instances of judicial review, he does not identify the institution
in general as an illustration of political justice. Assuming the wide range of
purposes and devices which the author surveys, however, perhaps it is quite
possible to consider American reference of high policy issues to judicial
tribunals as an interesting example of the very subject of the book. This sug-
gestion is offered with some hesitancy and full awareness of the difficulties in-
volved. At the same time, surely judicial review does involve courts in the
arena of strife over political goals. It is also significant that while Professor
Kirchheimer sees a regime's desire to "legitimize" its actions as a perennial
motive for the resort to political justice, Professor Charles Black in his recent
book on the Supreme Court 6 uses this same phrase repeatedly in describing
the function of judicial review over legislative and executive acts. Professor
Black of course views this legitimizing function as instrumental in the engi-
5. Pp. 341 and 429. See also pp. 322 and 328.
6. BLAcK, THE PEOPLE AND THE COURT (1960).
1368 THE YALE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 71 :1351
7. P. 233.
19621 REVIEWS 1369
part of the 19th century reflected the relatively secure establishment of the
bourgeois nation-state. Equally clearly, the social and political order which
that state embodied has been under continuing, fundamental challenge since
World War I-under a challenge which has inexorably "politicized" an ever-
widening range of human endeavor, including not only science and literature,
but also the judicial processes through which men seek justice. Professor
K'irchheimer dedicates his book to "the past, present and future victims of
political justice." Victims there are. But in a deeper sense, they are victims not
simply of subversion control laws and drum courts, but of an as yet undeter-
mined sea-change transformation in the structure of nations and societies.
VINCENT E. STARZINGERjt