E. Dean Kolbas - Critical Theory and The Literary Canon (2001)
E. Dean Kolbas - Critical Theory and The Literary Canon (2001)
E. Dean Kolbas - Critical Theory and The Literary Canon (2001)
E. Dean Kolbas
^JXfestview
• JMItl
- T -^ y\ Member of the Perseus Books Group
All rights reserved. Printed in the United States of America. No part of this publication may
be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, in-
cluding photocopy, recording, or any information storage and retrieval system, without
permission in writing from the publisher.
Published in 2001 in the United States of America by Westview Press, 5500 Central Avenue,
Boulder, Colorado 80301-2877, and in the United Kingdom bv Westview Press, 12 Hid's
Copse Road, Cumnor Hill, Oxford OX2 9JJ
The paper used in this publication meets the requirements of the American National
Standard for Permanence of Paper for Printed Library Materials Z39.48-1984.
PERSEUS
POD
ON DEMAND 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1
Contents
Acknowledgments vii
Introduction 1
3 Cultural Reproduction 59
The Familiarity of Canonical Works, 61
Canon Formation and Social Relations, 72
Whither Aesthetics?, 79
v
VI Contents
Notes 145
References 167
Index 179
Acknowledgments
This book is the result of research done at Cambridge University that was
originally submitted as a doctoral thesis. Although it has been substan-
tially modified and rewritten to be more suitable for publication, its es-
sential content remains the product of work that was done there. Even
the most hermetic research is never a purely solitary endeavor, and 1 owe
a great deal of thanks to friends, faculty, and administrators for their ad-
vice, encouragement, and patience. Above all, I am indebted to my su-
pervisor, Simon Jarvis, for his invaluable guidance and critical attention.
I am also grateful to Graham McCann, Silvana Dean, and the Fellows,
porters, and staff of Queens' College for all of their help, as well as
Christopher Norris and Ato Quayson for examining my work so closely. I
would also like to thank my editors at Westview Press, David McBride
and Kay Mariea, and my reviewers, Noah Isenberg, Geoffrey Gait
Harpham, and Douglas Kellner for their suggestions and support. I am
also grateful to Sharon Dejohn for her meticulous copyediting. A number
of friends deserve special thanks for their help and advice over the years:
Mark Fenwick, Richard Jones, Alex Rehding, Paul Stephenson, Despina
Christodoulou, Julian Murphet, David Mikosz, Tiffany Stern, Heather
Wolfe, and Sam Gibson. In ways that are perhaps less direct, but no less
valuable for being so, many wonderful teachers and professors have also
influenced me throughout my education: David McLellan, Chris Taylor,
Sean Sayers, Thomas Cox, Ed McCann, Richard Prizant, Carole Rosen-
Kaplan, and the late Chet Lieb. Finally, I want to thank my wife, Paula,
and my parents, Eugene and Deanna Kolbas, for their love and support.
This book is dedicated to them.
£. Dean Kolbas
vn
This page intentionally left blank
Philosophy that satisfies its own intention . . . has its lifebiood in the resistance
against the common practices of today and what they serve, against the justification of
what happens to be the case.
-Tlieodor Adonio, "Why Still Philosophy" 0962)
This page intentionally left blank
Introduction
A "literary classic" is a work considered first-rate or excellent of its kind, and there-
fore standard, fit to be used as a model or imitated.
—The Oxford Companion to English Literature <1985)
In the past twenty years, the controversy over the literary canon has gen-
erated a wide range of critical commentary, from editorials and polemics
in journals and newspapers to theories and case studies in seminars and
symposia. By some accounts, the Western canon—the corpus of works
comprising the "classics" of art and literature, the very summit of cul-
tural achievement in the West—once thought of as timeless and univer-
sal, is now being undermined by the combined forces of feminism, multi-
culturalism, popular culture, and relativistic literary theories that have
occupied schools and universities since the 1960s. By other accounts, the
canon has been dominated by "dead, white European males," excluding
authors and artists from social groups that have historically been margin-
alized or that do not conform to the interests of the dominant culture. It is
therefore condemned as an elitist, patriarchical, racist, or ethnocentric
construction. In both cases there is agreement that the current impasse
over the literary canon signifies a change in society at large because the
monuments of the old order are thought to be giving wray to new canons,
greater cultural diversity, and changing political values.
One of the main objectives of this book is to explain how and why
these two lines of argument have been both historically and politically
suspect, largely for neglecting the material processes of canon formation.
A critique of the current debate will demonstrate that their apparently
antagonistic positions actually have a number of ideological assumptions
in common. In particular, there is a widespread belief that literary canons
are maintained by the authority of educational institutions and can there-
fore be changed, or preserved, by engineering the classroom syllabus ac-
cordingly. It is also believed that canons and works of art in general rep-
resent specific cultures or social groups, such as women, African
1
2 Introduction
For Polyclelus taught us all the symmetries of the body in his treatise, and confirmed
his testimony when IK sculpted a statue according to his own rules, and named the
statue, as he had his treatise, the canon.
—Galen, De placitis Hippocrates et Platonis (second century A.o.)
Poetry in general was a gift to the world and to nations, and not the private inheri-
tance of a few refined, cultivated men.
—The Autobiography of Johann Wolfgang von Goethe
(1832), vol. II, book x
It
12 Canons Ancient and Modern
Now in The Canon Epicurus affirms that our sensations and preconceptions
and our feelings are the standards of truth; the Epicureans generally make
perceptions of mental presentations to be also standards. . . . By preconcep-
tion they mean a sort of apprehension or a right opinion or notion, or uni-
versal idea stored in the mind (Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers in
Ten Books, book x, 11.30-34).
ancient classics, as Latin literature had done before with Greek litera-
ture: The poets of antiquity were emulated as authorities to legitimize
contemporary literature and the values it was thought to embody. Thus,
even canonical change, it seems, was dependent in some degree on
canonical precedent.
dermining the authority of the old order and its long-established canon
of antiquity. 16
The material changes and revolutionary consequences brought about
by publishing, beginning with the invention of the printing press in the
1440s, is known well enough not to require repetition here. 17 Although its
most profound effects were not immediate, in time it would transform
both the mode and content of literary production, as well as the social
significance of printed material as such, Alvin Kernan claims that only af-
ter the print revolution did the definition of literature, which had for-
merly embraced any and all written material, narrow to mean works of a
particular quality, as generally distinct from historical, scientific, and
other texts concerned more with facts than eloquence of expression. 18 By
the eighteenth century, he argues, the "most radical tendency of print
and its logic of multiplicity was to destroy the canon of courtly letters
centered on the classics and in a revolutionary, democratic manner to
level all books in a continuous surge of new, ever-accumulating print
products." 1 9 How "revolutionary" (or even effective) the leveling of
books really was, however, is open to debate. The assumption is that the
mere fact of numerical proliferation is necessarily "democratic," without
regard to who is controlling the press and in what interests. Nonetheless,
the boom of literary production in this era is beyond dispute. Among its
social consequences was an apparent anxiety of the learned class, ex-
pressed in England, for example, by Alexander Pope's Dunciad Variorum
(1728) and much of the work of Samuel Johnson, whose essays, and espe-
cially prefaces, eventually collected as The Lives of the English Poets
(1779-1781)—written originally at the behest of publishers—self-con-
sciously confirmed a canon of English literature by investing it with criti-
cal authority at a time when it was believed to be threatened by the grow-
ing deluge of printed material. If the literary canon were entirely at the
mercy of print alone, however, this tendency might have succeeded in
engulfing it long ago, but its preservation also depended on other factors.
Stimulated by the burgeoning publishing industry, the occupations of
professional writer and critic first developed in Europe in the eighteenth
century.20 The enormous growth of literary criticism and the activity of
formally editing literary texts, often with the scholarly apparatus of de-
tailed annotation, further helped to bring modern, secular, vernacular lit-
erature into the canon. The market for new books and newly edited edi-
tions of classics bound writing directly to commercial interests as never
before. In England, the expiration of the 1695 Licensing Act made way for
the creation, under pressure from publishers, of the Copyright Act in
1709. Comparable laws were passed in France and Germany in 1777 and
1794, respectively. Written works were officially deemed to be the prop-
erty of their authors, legally protected as commodities for exchange little
Canons Ancient and Modern 19
markets in which the hierarchy of values that the canon represents has,
supposedly, no place at all. To Harold Bloom, in Tlie Western Canon: The
Books and School of the Ages (1994), the whole notion of a crisis in literary-
study is as much a "journalistic event" as a real institutional problem.
To cite a single reason for the current controversy, however, would be
to oversimplify a complex cultural and historical process. It is rather
more convincing to recognize that several probable causes—including
broad institutional changes and material developments, general ideolog-
ical shifts, and specific socioeconomic tendencies—have all converged to
undermine whatever confidence there once was in a singular and vener-
ated literary heritage. Although the increasing political recognition of so-
cial diversity and the consequent revisions of the classroom syllabus are
certainly involved, I argue in the following chapters that they are insuffi-
cient by themselves to have altered the literary canon or broken it up into
a plurality of separate ones. Rather, such academic strategies may be bet-
ter understood as symptoms of other, broader changes affecting modern
capitalist societies. A materialist critique of the specific terms of the con-
temporary debate, including the implicit assumptions and explicit justifi-
cations of recent arguments both for and against "opening" the canon,
will help to disclose what those changes are as well as their ideological
manifestations. Such a critique is developed in Chapter 2.
2
The Contemporary Canon Debate
Although speculation about the origins and causes of the current canon
debate has been wide ranging, the arguments within the debate itself
have been more limited. In the last twenty years of the twentieth century,
one aspect of these arguments has been remarkably consistent: The
rhetoric within them has tended to be quite clearly divided between mu-
tually antagonistic positions. On the one hand are conservative critics
who attempt to justify the continuing importance of the Western canon
on the grounds of its permanent greatness and the edification that its
study will yield, either to individuals or to society at large. They perceive
the argument that alternative texts have been undeservedly neglected as
symptomatic of the loss of academic standards and the collapse of aes-
thetic judgment in the face of extrinsic political pressures. On the other
hand, liberal critics argue that the canon should be more representative
of the true diversity of society and the wide span of its cultural heritage,
that the canon should include writers previously excluded from literary
history and the educational institutions of the dominant culture. They
find the reverence accorded the Western canon indicative of elitism, pa-
triarchy, and ethnocentrism, each of which is antithetical to the egalitar-
ian ideals of democratic societies. They have also discredited the asser-
tion that aesthetic judgments or works of literature can ever be totally
aloof from political interests. Although the stalemate between these two
25
26 The Contemporary Canon Debate
tural studies courses, and the retreat of senior faculty members from
teaching general education to professional specialization. In Bennett's
view, what is wanting is adequate "educational leadership," one that in-
stills the virtues and "common culture" of Western civilization, its "last-
ing vision, its highest shared ideals and aspirations, and its heritage." As
a corrective, he advocates a reverential regard for canonical authors—
from Homer and Plato to Twain and Faulkner—because "the highest
purpose of reading is to be in the company of great souls." Bennett also
deplores "the tendency of some humanities professors to present their
subjects in a tendentious, ideological manner," apparently unaware that
the idolatry of canonical works is itself an ideological position. 1
Bennett's understanding of the "great tradition" of "the Western
mind" is such that the value of the canon resides in little more than cul-
tural appreciation. Consequently, it works at the expense of any critical
engagement with canonical works, whose specific content might not sim-
ply affirm the idea of a singular tradition and may even have critical
functions itself, rather than being mystified as spiritually edifying. To the
extent that Bennett's argument takes the works' cultural transmission as
unproblematic and their worth as simply given, it is also unhistorical. As
one of his critics remarks, "in Bennett's view, liberal arts study lost its in-
stitutional legitimacy, intellectual credibility, and pedagogical integrity.
. . . [But] Bennett never examines either the historical development of the
'liberal arts' or the social functions of such forms of study in the past or in
the present; he simply asserts their value." 2 Moreover, Bennett targets
teachers and professional academics as solely responsible for the decline,
without regard to the changing socioeconomic conditions that may have
compelled the very increase in specialization he laments. As will be seen
again and again, the exaggeration of the role of formal education in the
formation of canons is a chronic symptom of the current debate.
Nonetheless, Bennett's observations clearly demonstrate that the ideologi-
cal status of the literary canon—that is, the degree to which it legitimizes
the status quo—has been a central preoccupation in the contemporary
debate, whether denied by its apologists or emphasized by its detractors.
Equally enamored of the purity and virtues of Western civilization is
Lynne Cheney, Bennett's successor as chair of the National Endowment
for the Humanities. In 1988, she published a report entitled Humanities in
America, followed in 1989 by 50 Hours: A Core Curriculum for College Stu-
dents, both of which reiterate Bennett's arguments about the purpose of
the literary canon. Cheney likewise criticizes esoteric scholars who, she
believes, "reduce the study of the humanities to the study of politics, ar-
guing that truth—and beauty and excellence—are not timeless matters,
but transitory notions, devices used by some groups to perpetuate 'he-
gemony' over others." As an alternative, she advocates a sort of populist
28 The Contemporary Canon Debate
other contributor to The New Criterion, denies this as "a point of view that
only an activist political ideologue of some stripe could hold," while in
the same breath commending the supposedly apolitical innocence of
canonical figures such as Shakespeare, Milton, T. S. Eliot, and Ralph Elli-
son—as if Henry V, Paradise Lost, The Waste Land, or Invisible Man were
without political content! 7
To keep politics out of the study of the arts and humanities, to preserve
the canon untarnished by the corrupting influence of latter-day theoreti-
cal fashions, Kramer and Kimball advocate treating the arts "on their
own terms, according to aesthetic rather than political criteria." Kramer
in particular argues that "art must be defended and pursued and relished
for what it is rather than as a political instrument in the service of some
other cause." However, in defining what art is, he offers only vague plat-
itudes: "a source of spiritual and intellectual enlightenment... a special
form of pleasure and moral elevation . . . a spur to the highest reaches of
human aspiration." 8 The inadequacy of these criteria is thrown into relief
when they are applied to some of the most canonical literature of the
modern age. For example, it would be difficult to reconcile Crime and
Punishment, A Season in Hell, or In the Penal Colony with Kramer's "inspi-
rational" values. Indeed, to do so would be antithetical to their specific
content, in which humanistic beliefs are themselves seriously questioned,
if not undermined. Even so, it must be appreciated that arguments for
preserving the autonomy of art from explicit politics are not exclusive to
humanists alone. The critical theory of the Frankfurt School also main-
tains the importance of aesthetic autonomy, albeit on totally different
grounds and for completely different purposes (see Part 2). Yet the appar-
ent likeness in this regard of both left- and right-wing critics, particularly
regarding the Literary canon, reveals the specific historical and material
conditions that have coincided with the current debate, such that both
may be reacting to the same socioeconomic tendencies. What distin-
guishes their arguments, however, is whether those tendencies are de-
scribed simply in terms of declining academic standards or as sympto-
matic of wider historical, institutional, and materialistic conditions of
modern capitalist society.
Apart from denying the political aspects of works of literature and lit-
erary evaluation, the arguments exemplified by Bennett, Cheney, and the
contributors to The Neiv Criterion view the Western canon to be histori-
cally transcendent. But other arguments in defense of that canon have
developed into fully formed theories that allow for a degree of historical
contingency. Superficially, Harold Bloom's elegiac account of the fate of
the canon may appear to share the dubious assumptions of conservative
humanism. His best-selling book, The Western Canon (1994), is an explicit
reaction to left-wing literary critics, whom he collectively brands "the
30 The Contemporary Canon Debate
I am not concerned . .. with the current debate between the right-wing de-
fenders of the Canon, who wish to preserve it for its supposed (and nonexis-
tent) moral values, and the academic-journalistic network . . . who wish to
overthrow the Canon in order to advance their supposed (and nonexistent)
programs for social change."
positions. The belief that the aesthetic is "an individual rather than a soci-
etal concern" simultaneously negates its social import and obscures the
institutional and material means by which the literary canon is repro-
duced. (Both ideas are taken up in the following chapters of this book.)
The relentless use of expressions such as the "competition" and "con-
flict" between writers, the "struggle" and "survival" of texts, or the "in-
dividual enterprise" and "self-reliance" of authors perhaps best discloses
Bloom's ideological assumptions.
Whereas Bloom resigns himself to an isolated individualism, another
prominent literary critic considers the functions of literature much more
broadly. Indeed, fewr critics have reflected so thoroughly upon canons
and canon formation as Frank Kermode. In several books and articles,
he has examined a variety of means by which certain works of art and
literature become socially sanctioned as canonical, including the histori-
cal and institutional ones that the critics discussed so far invariably
omit. More nuanced than Bloom and more open-minded than Bennett or
Kramer, Kermode admits of an element of contingency and even fortu-
itousness in the formation of canons (his use of the plural alone dis-
tances him from their narrow singularity). In his most detailed account
of canon formation, Forms of Attention (1985), Kermode maintains that
the reputation of artists and books is initially made according to a con-
fluence of judgments of "mere opinion," but only when their esteem be-
comes institutionally validated as knowledge by academic professionals
do they become canonical. Although he ackiiow ledges the difficulty of
sharply distinguishing knowledge from opinion, the important insight
here is the recognition that works of art are subject to social and institu-
tional confirmation:
In thinking about canonicity in the history of the arts and literature, we have
at once to reflect that our canons have never been impermeable; that our de-
fenses of them are always . .. provisional. .. . Canons . . . are of course de-
constructible; if people think there should not be such things, they may very
well find the means to destroy them. . . . [T]he idea of tradition has never
been so weak as it now is, the sense of a literary past less strong.'8
writes, "canons are useful in that they enable us to handle otherwise un-
manageable historical deposits. They do this by affirming that some
works are more valuable than others, more worthy of minute atten-
tion." 20 Unlike the humanist critics, Kermode does not naively presup-
pose the ideological innocence of canons or what they represent; he is
merely making the case for their inevitability, whatever their particular
political content.
However, the extent to which the pragmatic utility of canons may itself
be an ideological assumption is not considered by Kermode.
Books held to belong to the canon are granted not only high value, but
"an almost rabbinical minuteness of comment and speculation"—"every
word, every letter, is subject to minute commentary." 22 Kermode argues
that constant textual attention, particularly scholastic attention, is the
most fundamental mode of canonical preservation, and that only inter-
pretation maintains the life of a work of art from one generation to an-
other. Whether or not this adequately explains the means of canonical
longevity, it says little by itself about why certain works more than others
attract such attention or how they are singled out for scrutiny in the first
place. Kermode does propose one reason. He suggests that there will al-
ways be more and new things to say about canonical works. Indeed,
"this is what it means to call a book canonical." From artists to lay read-
ers, professional critics to academic expositors, "all grant to the text
something like omnisignificance, all have canons of interpretation that
are permissive rather than restrictive." 23 This is not simply a matter of an
individual reader's open-mindedness or creativity. Rather, it is assumed
to be a quality inherent to the canonical text itself: "the book is a world,
capable of being exfoliated into a universe." 24 Interpretive possibility is
believed to be endless, if not without constraint, since Kermode does not
believe that anything at all may be said of a work, even a canonical one.
The limitations of interpretation, he argues, are imposed by earlier inter-
pretations: "all our interpretations depend in some measure on historical
interpretations; of these some survive and some do not . .. and commu-
nities maintain, with indefinite but quite powerful criteria, some [inter-
pretations] and not others." 25 Nevertheless, Kermode finds that canonical
34 The Contemporary Canon Debate
works have "an inexhaustible potential of meaning," that they are "full
of senses only partly available to any previous reading"; interpretations
"constantly change though their source remains unchangeable." 26
Taking the example of Hamlet, which he regards as "unshakably
canonical," Kermode demonstrates how Shakespeare's play offers inter-
preters the possibility of saying an incredibly wide range of things about
it. He explains that the general shift in exegetical priorities, from the em-
phasis on dramatic character in nineteenth-century readings of Hamlet,
to an emphasis on "the actual language of the play, its very texture" in
those of the twentieth, is indicative of Hamlet's flexibility, its openness to
interpretive appropriation. To fit the changing needs and interests of dif-
ferent generations, "there must be new appraisals, and they will be pos-
sible only so long as new relations, new adjustments of centre and mar-
gin, are perceived in the play and given licit expression in commentary."
In short, "the canonical work, so endlessly discussed, must be assumed
to have permanent value and, which is really the same thing, perpetual
modernity." 27
Unlike Bloom and others, therefore, Kermode recognizes that interpre-
tation does not occur in a social vacuum as a solitary, individualistic en-
terprise. As he writes in "The Institutional Control of Interpretation,"
valid interpretations depend on the sanction of certain social institutions,
a professional community with the authority, though not undisputed, to
define a subject, impose valuations, and validate interpretations. Indeed,
the very definition of what it is to be canonical itself involves interpreta-
tion. Kermode locates such authority and relative consensus specifically
within the academic community, in universities, colleges, and other asso-
ciations of higher learning. So the question of which works are accredited
as canonical is determined largely by the "tacit knowledge" of academic
professionals and, less directly, by the control of appointments and the
awarding of degrees. 28
Just as he admits of historical changes in what constitutes the canon,
Kermode links them to corresponding changes in the institution of criti-
cism: "The intrusion of new work into the canon usually involves some
change in the common wisdom of the institution as to permissible
hermeneutic procedures." But in terms of radical innovations within the
academy-—even those that aim to unsettle or discredit institutional au-
thority (Kermode cites as examples the influence of Barthes, Lacan, Der-
rida, and Foucault)—the institution is expected "to contain or control"
them. To Kermode, this is easily done because such radical forms of criti-
cism are "not, in the end, subversive at all" and because there is an "un-
derlying continuity," he believes, between such criticism and the "tradi-
tional modes" of interpretation from which they try to distinguish
themselves. Thus, even anti-canonical criticism ends up merely lending
The Contemporary Canon Debate 35
canonical texts "another span of life," adding another chapter to the his-
tory of their interpretation. 29 If this were all that radical literary criticism
amounts to, it would be a troubling thought indeed to more than a few of
its practitioners.
In the process of attempting to explain the relation between canonical
and institutional "change," therefore, Kermode actually minimizes the
possibility of any substantial change at all. He does this by discounting
the radical critiques of social institutions that post-structuralist or Marx-
ist theories have offered. He is not troubled by the "necessary conser-
vatism" of learned institutions because, he believes, "it is by recognizing
the tacit authority of the institution that we achieve the measure of lib-
erty we have in interpreting. It is a price to pay, but it purchases an incal-
culable boon." 30 Elsewhere, he declares that "there must be institutional
control of interpretation," and that all institutions "are bound to be reac-
tionary in some sense." While remaining open to the possibility of new
canons to suit, for example, feminists, African Americans, or Derrideans,
Kermode believes that truly "revolutionary revisions would require
transfers of powers" and "a reign of literary terror." He concludes that
"absolute justice arid perfection of conscience are unlikely to be more
available under that new dispensation than they are now." 31 Ultimately,
therefore, Kermode betrays himself as an apologist for the status quo,
keeping the institutions that he believes are responsible for sustaining the
canon intact, so as to avoid what he believes would only be worse—and
apparently destructive—alternatives.
Before leaving Kermode's account of canon formation, a few of the
methodological assumptions and political implications underlying it
need to be examined. First, in direct contrast to Bloom, he takes for
granted that the responsibility for shaping and perpetuating canons falls
squarely on the academic establishment. However, such academicism
disregards the wider social, institutional, and historical factors that also
affect canonization, factors that are explored in Chapter 3. Although
Kermode recognizes and describes changing interpretative values—as
read out of, or projected upon, canonical works—his partiality for the
academic severely limits an explanation of the social, historical, or eco-
nomic rationale that helps to determine such changes, that is, one that
might explain why critical emphasis fell upon the characters of Hamlet in
the nineteenth century but moved to the actual language of the play in
the twentieth.
Second, the idea of inexhaustible interpretive potential, "omnisignifi-
cance," or timeless modernity is also vulnerable to criticism. If a close read-
ing of canonical works is thought to yield greater depth or ambiguity,
metaphorical complexity, or varied allusions than a reading of other texts,
Kermode does not make it clear on what grounds, methodologically, the
36 The Contemporary Canon Debate
Or, as Jan Gorak has summarized in The Making of the Modern Canon:
It is asserted that the modern canon exists only in order to conserve existing
institutional practices and definitions; that it requires teachers of the human-
ities to transmit time-honoured platitudes; that it favours a privileged set of
writings that alone constitute "literature," while conspiring to conceal the
way those writings become the basis for the curriculum; and that it com-
pounds these sins of omission and commission by employing methods of
reading that remove favoured authors and texts from processes of struggle
and conflict.33
Periodicals like the Neu> York Times Book Review, for instance, inadver-
tently reinforce the values that certain books are thought to represent by
encouraging their success with favorable reviews. 38 More than simply ex-
plaining the process that leads to mass readership for relatively few
books each year, Ohmann argues that publishers and periodicals affect
the canon of "serious" literature as well. By reaching the majority of
America's elite intellectuals, he writes,
a major Times review could help put a novel on the cultural agenda and in-
sure that other journals would have to take it seriously. . . . If a novel was
certified in the court of the prestigious journals, it was likely to draw the at-
tention of critics in more specialized and academic journals . . . and by this
route make its way into college curricula, where the very context.. . gave it
de facto recognition as literature.3'*
The implications for the literary canon are obvious: If active intervention
in contemporary politics were the primary grounds of literary evalua-
tion, perhaps very little of the Western canon would remain intact.
Underlying this type of argument is an assumption that the content of
bourgeois European literature is not, or cannot be, as political or radically
significant as the explicitly political content of post-colonial works like
testimonies. It is not even considered whether testimonies might have cer-
tain ideological tendencies themselves, including the disguise of their
own mediations by affecting immediacy. (Beverley's passing admission
of Latin American literature being mediated is more subterfuge than crit-
ical analysis.) Ultimately, arguments like his construct a false dichotomy
between politically effective, committed literature and that which is de-
tached, "humanistic," and therefore supposedly inert, even though the
boundaries of the two can be much more porous, as discussed in Chapter
4. Moreover, transforming the canon on the grounds of political recogni-
tion, representation, or effect also has other ideological consequences.
no women or people of color were ever able to discover the reflection or rep-
resentation of their images, or hear the resonances of their cultural voices.
The return of "the" canon, the high canon of Western masterpieces, repre-
sents the return of an order in which my people [i.e., African-Americans]
were the subjugated, the voiceless, the invisible, the unrepresented, and the
unrepresentable.53
Rather than limit his argument to the idea of communal autonomy alone,
Gates makes the further suggestion that the reflection of racial and gen-
der identity is a condition for political agency and social change.
Just how effective or comprehensive such change has been or can be
when superimposed on literary history, however, remains to be seen. It is
claimed that marginalized groups especially benefit from symbolic repre-
sentation by giving them voice where they had none before, but it may
also have inadvertent consequences as far as it leaves untouched the re-
production of social relations, the economy in which it operates, and the
pragmatic rationale by which it functions. The gesture toward a more
representative and accurate literary canon, in which the greatest variety
of social groups can find their own traditions reflected, also presupposes
that a primary function of the canon is to mirror society's diverse, multi-
cultural character. Although they are made in the name of political jus-
tice, equality, or emancipation, it is far from certain that claims for literary
representation necessarily amount to substantial political praxis.
Granted, in certain circumstances recognition may indeed be politically
significant, but only an impoverished conception of politics would
equate literary representation per se with political praxis. The reflection
of social diversity, however "accurate," may well even impede political
potential by reducing it to an empirical confirmation of the status quo in-
stead of enabling its transformation.
Even if the canon had historically formed according to prejudice, it
would be simplistic to suppose that a more representative literary canon in
the schools will now begin to redress social injustice in society at large.
Indeed, it is sometimes argued that the canon has already become notice-
ably multicultural, but how much social equality has been achieved as a
result? Without a critique of the whole socioeconomic order—including
its structural dependence on the division of labor, the dominance of prag-
matic, means-over-ends rationality, and the global commodification of
46 The Contemporary Canon Debate
admire books which are prima facie antithetical [to each other] by perform-
ing some sort of synthesis. We would like to admire both Blake and Arnold,
both Nietzsche and Mill, both Marx and Baudelaire, both Trotsky and Eliot,
both Nabokov and Orwell. So we hope some critic will show how these
men's books can be put together to form a beautiful mosaic. We hope that
critics can redescribe these people in ways which will enlarge the canon, and
will give us a set of classical texts as rich and diverse as possible.69
the aim of a just and free society as letting its citizens be as privatistic [sic],
"irrationalist," and aestheticist [i.e., subjectivistj as they please so long as
they do it on their own time—causing no harm to others and using no re-
sources needed by those less advantaged. There are practical measures to be
taken to accomplish this practical goal.70
nificance of canonical art in capitalist societies are neglected arid the po-
litical implications of art are diminished. This is perhaps the most salient
indication that pragmatism has become the dominant political paradigm
in the current debate over literature and the arts as well as in other areas
where it is inappropriate.
In conclusion, despite their apparent antinomy, the liberal-pluralistic
and conservative-humanistic arguments for preserving or revising the
literary canon betray several striking affinities. Essentially, they either
conceive of the canon in idealistically aesthetic terms, with little or no ref-
erence to objective historical and material conditions, or they appropriate
the canon for the purposes of political or pedagogical pragmatism, with-
out regard to the functionless or mediated aspects of art in modernity.
What tends to be neglected in eager claims to open the canon are the
material constraints of canon formation. Because canonical works have
historically been the source of imitation and reproduction over pro-
tracted periods of time, a necessary feature of any such work will be its
historical persistence and broad cultural familiarity. But arguments that
do admit as much are no better if they merely celebrate the monuments of
culture and take their historical reproduction as unambiguous evidence
of aesthetic superiority. What the latter arguments neglect is the potential
of canonical works to become culturally inert or aesthetically sterile ob-
jects, such that they end up serving the most trivial purposes. By con-
trast, a materialistic, sociological, and critical account of canon formation
will show on what specific social, economic, and institutional conditions
it depends. These matters are the subject of Chapter 3.
3
Cultural Reproduction
"But Slutkespeare one gets acquainted with without knowing how. It is a part of an
Englishman's constitution. His thoughts and beauties are so spread abroad that one
touches them every where, one is intimate with him by instinct.—No man of any
brain can open at a good part of one of his plays, without falling into the flow of his
meaning immediately."
"No doubt, one is familiar with Shakespeare in a degree," said Edmund, "from
one's earliest years. His celebrated passages are quoted by every body; they are in half
the books we open, and we all talk Shakespeare, use his similies, and describe with his
descriptions."
—lane Austen, Mansfield Park (1814), vol. Ill, ch. iii
The terms in which the debate over the canon has been articulated, evi-
dent in nearly every example in Chapter 2, indicate a widespread as-
sumption that canons are created and preserved primarily by the author-
ity of formal educational institutions such as schools and universities.
The prevalence of this belief may well be due to the social situation of
those who hold it, the majority of whom are themselves professional aca-
demics; but that need not confine an examination of the debate to a cri-
tique of its participants or the conventions of their discourse, as if they
existed independently of other institutions or apart from wider economic
and historical contexts. No single judgment creates a canon, so the assort-
59
w Cultural Reproduction
authors and artists. It includes sites and actors as varied as places of exhi-
bition such as galleries and museums; institutions of consecration like
academies and salons; institutions for "the reproduction of producers"
themselves such as schools and universities; and other, specialized
agents, including dealers, critics and art historians. The vast array of offi-
cial forms of recognition includes government arts councils, literary
prizes, academic exegeses, and authorized biographies, not to mention
translations and publication in multiple editions. Less directly, there are
more subtle, but no less important, modes of evaluation such as staff ap-
pointments in relevant agencies and word of mouth among the literati.
Of course, even forms of repudiation, such as negative reviews and cen-
sorship, also play a role in the success or failure of works of art and liter-
ature. Political revolutions and changes of regime; the symbolic minutiae
of popular culture, including commemorative stamps, memorial statues,
and the attribution of street names; mention in film and popular song; ci-
tations or allusions in the works of other artists, whether or not in the
medium of literature: All combine in the logic of the cultural field to val-
orize or stigmatize certain writers and works, hi short, a whole "market
of symbolic goods" operates to canonize. 2 Taking into account so many
variables alone should deflate the academic conceit that the canon is pri-
marily determined by formal institutions of education.
Given the wide range of institutions and agents, types of discourse,
and symbolic signification that informs the process of canonization,
Bourdieu affirms that cultural familiarization is constitutive of any work
that becomes canonical:
In more than 300 years Paradise Lost has never been out of print, and Mil-
ton's poems, it has been remarked, were once so familiar that "they
formed part of what one might call the national consciousness. Genera-
tions of literate Englishmen found resonant phrases from Milton on their
lips." 13 Similarly, the reproduction of the Faust legend in Goethe's play,
Gounod's opera, Berlioz's oratorio, Liszt's symphony, Thomas Mann's
novel, and Murnau's and Svankmajer's films—to name only the most ex-
plicit adaptations—has only strengthened its reputation as a literary clas-
sic. Indeed, one scholar describes Faust, along with Don Quixote, Don
Juan, and Robinson Crusoe, as one of the dominant myths of modern soci-
ety.14 Today, the making and remaking of the novels of Scott, Austen,
Dickens, and the Brontes for film and television continually ensure their
familiarity, while the multiple editions of Ulysses, To the Lighthouse, and
other "modern classics" contribute to their distinction over other pub-
lished literature. The collected works of canonical authors in elegant edi-
tions also confer on them a certain prestige: "the uniform bindings con-
firm us in our belief that we are reading a classic, and they make the
authors appear in some timeless space in which they all coexist to-
gether." 15 Of course, no single adaptation or edition of a work is enough
to canonize it, because the means by which it is disseminated and be-
comes familiar—in whatever form—are many and diffuse. Moreover, the
consecration of a work in one medium will often excite or rekindle inter-
est in its antecedents, thereby furthering the potential for canonization by
association with the already canonical.
None of this, however, appeals to the sheer scale of numerical prolifer-
ation or the extent of cultural dispersion alone. Contrary to those who be-
66 Cultural Reproduction
lieve that "it is in mass and not high or official culture that the value of
literary canon formation is preserved," 16 the process of canonization de-
pends no less on the relative authority of those groups with institutional
influence on the evaluation and reproduction of selected works of litera-
ture. Populist optimism can be faulted for ignoring the hierarchical struc-
ture of institutions, including those in the service of "mass" culture.
Bourdieu documents at length the conflicts of social and economic power
involved in acquiring and maintaining such authority, and he shows how
the institutional process of familiarization also relies on access to the es-
tablished codes—including technical vocabulary and symbolic c a p i t a l -
necessary to participate in the appreciation (in both senses) of any work.
Indeed, the struggle to establish a "monopoly of literary legitimacy" is it-
self a function of the logic of the field: "cultural heritage, which exists in a
materialized and in an incorporated state . . . , only exists and effectively
persists (meaning actively) in and through the struggles located in fields
of cultural production; that is, cultural heritage exists by and for the
agents disposed and able to assure its continued reactivation." 17 Cultural
familiarity may not be transparently universal-—in the sense of being
equally recognized across the spectrum of class, gender, and racial differ-
ences—but neither does it result from individual assertiveness, popular
acclaim, or discursive contestation alone. Rather, the processes of famil-
iarization are objectively bound to the structure of the field of cultural
production, including the internal hierarchies and materiality (i.e., the
modes and relations of production) of institutions within it, which are
themselves situated within the wider economy. Liberal-pluralists who
pronounce obscure works to be suddenly canonical or who suggest that
aesthetic criteria hitherto used for literary evaluation can now be simply
cast aside fail to perceive the intransigence of social relations and institu-
tional structures or the dependence of canonization on broad cultural
and historical reproduction. New or historically underappreciated works
are unlikely to be canonized without corresponding social, institutional,
and material changes sufficient to promote their reproduction, dissemi-
nation, and familiarization. The gesture of liberally claiming recent or
"recovered" texts to be deservedly or spontaneously canonical—whether
for exciting sudden critical interest or for representing culturally disen-
franchised groups—is therefore misleading to the extent that it underesti-
mates the control of institutions upon which canonization depends.
Canonicity requires an historical quality that is not so quickly ob-
tained. What newly acclaimed works lack—no less than those that have
belatedly become, or had once been, popular—is a cumulative history, a
continuum of judgments and rewritings over extended periods of time.
Some of the feminist calls for a novel and distinct canon of female writ-
ers, for example, betray a misunderstanding of the historical depth con-
Cultural Reproduction 67
exist in complete isolation from the dominant culture and its institutions,
if they were devoid of social hierarchy themselves or could somehow
maintain a canon independent of the means of cultural reproduction—all
of which seems unlikely in a world where different societies are increas-
ingly interdependent and even the most remote cultures are mediated by
common economic principles and modes of production.
Given the means of material reproduction and cultural transmission,
the discrepancies of symbolic capital necessary for legitimization, and
the social logic of canonical change, an adequate sociology of literature
must historically consider which specific institutions most effectively deter-
mine these variables and therefore do most to canonize individual works
at any given time. Unlike others, Bourdieu is ambivalent about how fun-
damental formal education remains today. His own diagnosis of the in-
creasing "autonomization" of the field of cultural production, especially
in Europe since the nineteenth century, precludes any clear certainty that
the literary canon relies wholly on educational institutions. 21 In spite of
advising that "it would be foolish to search for an ultimate guarantor or
guarantee" of the power of consecration, however, Bourdieu does make
some appeal to the authority of education, albeit in a very loose sense.
The recognition of works of art as "art" begins, he alleges, with teachers
and parents because they are in charge of "the initial inculcation of artis-
tic dispositions." 22 But this assumption uncritically presupposes that ed-
ucation precedes culture or the processes of acculturation. It does not
even consider whether the reverse may be true, or whether both may ac-
tually coincide. In fact, Bourdieu ultimately does attribute the highest
power of consecration to educational institutions, writing that "it is im-
possible to understand the peculiar characteristics of restricted culture
without appreciating its profound dependence on the educational sys-
tem, the indispensable means of its reproduction and grow r th," and that
"the educational system plays a decisive role in the generalized imposi-
tion of the legitimate mode of consumption." 2 3 In even more explicit
terms, the process of canonization has led to "the constitution of a corpus
of canonic works whose value the education system tends continually to
reproduce by producing aware consumers (which means converted
ones) as well as sacralizing commentaries." Thus, "the infallible sign of
consecration" in the field of cultural production "is constituted by the
canonization of works as classics by inscribing them in curricula/' even if
belatedly.24
However, in Bourdieu's own account, the educational monopoly on
consecration and canonization historically ended in the nineteenth cen-
tury. In France, for example, the "monopoly holder of the legitimate def-
inition of art and the artist" had been the Academic Frangaise; but its
power was broken, Bourdieu suggests, with the "institutionalization of
Cultural Reproduction 69
For all these reasons, Bourdieu regards the power of the literary field by
itself to be relatively "weak."
Each of these assumptions—the collapse of the educational monopoly
on consecration, the autonomy and diversification of the field of cultural
production, and the competition for legitimacy—depends on the relative
strength or cohesion of the literary or artistic field, which Bourdieu finds
today to be characterized by "a weak degree of codification"; few fields,
he claims, are as "little institutionalized." 2y Indeed, so incohesive and
vulnerable to competition is the literary field in particular that even char-
acterizing it as an "institution," he believes, is a mistake:
This process does more than simply explain canon formation as an ongo-
ing contest between the familiar and the unfamiliar, the novel and the
conventional. The concept of aging also implies that established works
can become "dated" and aesthetically neutralized when their potential to
offer anything new—to remain compelling or critical—is diminished. The
"wearing out of the effect" of canonical works, Bourdieu believes, "is pri-
marily the result of the routinization of production associated with the im-
pact of epigones and academicism, which even avant-garde movements
do not escape, and arises from the repeated and repetitive application of
proved procedures and the uninventive use of an art of inventing already
invented." 32 In other words, the very process of familiarization that con-
tributes to the canonization of particular works of art and literature also
leads to their neutralization, or "banalization." When they become so fa-
miliar that they are reduced to simple cliches, memorized in disconnected
segments in school, fetishized in lists of "greatest books," or regarded
merely as sources of pleasure and entertainment, literary classics risk los-
ing whatever makes them distinctive and distinguished, including their
aesthetic force or potential for critical knowledge. As far as it dehistori-
cizes selected texts by elevating them into a pantheon of canonical au-
thors, traditional humanistic and forrnalistic academic criticism also con-
tributes to their neutralization. 33 Because canonical works are indeed
often trivialized as filler for textbooks, used as resources for profit, or
pragmatically reduced to being vehicles for preaching "traditional" cul-
tural values (whether of dominant or marginal social groups), the concept
of aging is especially revealing of the contemporary canon debate.
Such aging is not only a matter of consumption and how works of art
are used; it can also affect the production and specific content of the works
themselves. When authors and artists remain attached to modes of pro-
duction that have become dated, Bourdieu writes, "when they lock them-
selves into patterns of perception or appreciation that become converted
into transcendent and eternal norms and so prohibit the acceptance or
even the perception of novelty," both their own work and that on which it
is modeled may become aesthetically sterile. 34 As much as they might
complement or promote the status of canonical literature, the formulaic
72 Cultural Reproduction
imitations of a literary classic can also dim its aesthetic power or distinc-
tiveness. The stories of Edgar Allan Poe, for instance, now seem almost ir-
retrievably old-fashioned and even tame in light of subsequent horror fic-
tion, just as the film adaptations of the novels of Jane Austen, Charlotte
Bronte, and George Eliot have rendered them almost indistinguishable
from soap opera kitsch. In effect, the emulation, proliferation, and increas-
ing commodification into different media that historical canonization re-
quires can also be its undoing. As far as it cripples artistic innovation, sti-
fles original interpretation, or suppresses critical understandings—merely
reproducing the style of canonical works or the values that they are
thought to embody—imitation has serious ideological repercussions. In
the following chapters, I demonstrate that such aesthetic neutralization is,
in part, what the critical aesthetic theory of Theodor Adorno tries to come
to terms with. Before turning to that, however, in the next section I con-
sider the ways in which canonization as a form of cultural reproduction
may also reinforce the status quo by reproducing social relations.
"the relation between the aesthetic and the work of art cannot be defined
as their absolute distinction any more than the experience of the aesthetic
can be identified exclusively with the experience of a work of art," Guil-
lory finds the whole discourse of the canon debate to be founded on the
"illusion" that works of art are uniquely aesthetic:
[S]o far as the object of sociology is concerned, nothing exists besides the
cultural capital embodied on the one hand in the aesthetic disposition, and
on the other in the cultural products judged according to the criteria inter-
nalized as the aesthetic disposition. It is easy enough to recognize here the
largest effect of the discourse of canonicity: the illusion that aesthetic experi-
ence is really restricted to the experience of High Cultural works.52
Whither Aesthetics?
By understanding how artistic reproduction, cultural familiarity, histori-
cal cumulativity, and the social relations of production are all essential to
canon formation, the sociological theories reviewed above reveal the
material constraints of canon formation. If the social mechanisms of that
process are recognized, then the humanistic idealizations of the literary
canon as irreproachable or timeless should be tempered, if not refuted.
Equally, if the extent of historical reproduction and institutionalization
necessary for any work to become canonical is appreciated, then the lib-
eral-pluralist claims to alter the canon or spontaneously create alterna-
tive ones will also be understood to be idealistic insofar as they, too, ne-
glect those constraints.
Because canonization requires cultural dissemination and artistic re-
production, the degree to which the commodification of art and culture
affects canon formation must be factored into any account of the literary
canon. Although some critics have remarked that the commodification of
marginalized cultures has indeed contributed to the recognition and can-
onization of authors and books that would otherwise have remained ne-
glected, they have generally treated it as no more significant than other
factors, such as their establishment within academia. 58 But if the aca-
demic monopoly on literary consecration—if indeed there ever was
one—has actually eroded since the nineteenth century, then factors such
as cultural commodification may now play an even greater role in canon-
ization than academic institutionalization.
For all their insight into the processes by which certain works are made
culturally familiar and canonized, however, sociological accounts of
canon formation take these processes to be the social or political limit of
canonicity. Although they do, at least in principle, push the debate be-
yond purely academic discourse, they also reveal their own limitations
regarding the specific content of individual works. In particular, socio-
logical conceptions of the aesthetic find that to distinguish qualitatively
between canonical and non-canonical works, or between art and aes-
thetic experience in general, is always and necessarily ideological for
mystifying social relations in the name of detached "judgment." Guillory,
for instance, believes that the canon serves primarily to reproduce social
relations and perpetuate class distinctions via standards of literacy, and
Bourdieu barely considers the qualitative content of works of art at all
(see Chapter 5). Such conclusions implicitly or explicitly rule out the pos-
sibility that the aesthetic can also have a distinctive, non-ideological, cog-
nitive content, and that individual canonical works can thereby also have
a unique critical potential, subverting the status quo by pointing beyond
80 Cultural Reproduction
it. In Part 2,1 show how critical theory, and especially Theodor Adorno's
aesthetic theory, goes beyond the limitations of sociology.
Even though sociological theory does much to correct the idealistic as-
sumptions prevalent in the current canon debate, sociological theorists
say nothing about the instrumental or pragmatic justifications of art that
have also been shown to be characteristic of this debate. Chapter 4 shows
how critical theory's unique conception of art establishes a framework
through which a critique can be mounted of such instrumental and prag-
matic justifications. It also sets the stage for a further critique of sociolog-
ical accounts of canon formation that leave out the aesthetic content of
works of art and literature. Without succumbing to the limitations of con-
servative humanism, liberal pluralism, or sociological empiricism, criti-
cal theory provides a reading of art in modern societies that can be ex-
tended to both the nature of canon formation and the prevailing
assumptions about it.
PART TWO
That tlte work of art lives on is due to the very moments that are suppressed when it is
elevated to the Pantheon.
—Theodor Adorno,
"On the Classicism of Goethe's Iphigenie" (1967)
The preceding chapters have illustrated the contours of the current situa-
tion regarding the literary canon and exposed certain key assumptions in
the rhetoric within the contemporary debate. To move beyond the ideal-
ism and narrow academicism of this debate, sociological theories of cul-
tural reproduction were used to highlight the material conditions and
constraints of canon formation. The sociological approach, however, re-
veals its own limitations when the social and institutional aspects of
canon formation are emphasized at the expense of the specific content of
individual works. Whereas liberal-pluralist and conservative-humanist
arguments have tended to neglect the concrete means by which certain
works become canonical, the materialism of sociology tends by contrast
to empty such works of any social purpose beyond the reproduction of
the status quo; the canon is redticed to being little more than a function of
class distinction. What is not sufficiently considered in either approach is
whether the very concept of art under modern socioeconomic conditions
has far more radical implications when not limited to pedagogical func-
tions or immediate political interests.
The purpose of this chapter is to construct an argument for the aes-
thetic content of works of art by appealing to the critical theory of the
Frankfurt School, and particularly the aesthetic theory of Theodor
Adorno. The first section provides an exposition of those aspects of his
theory that are most relevant to the literary canon, with specific attention
to the critical role of art in modern capitalist societies. I then demonstrate
83
84 Critical Theory and Canonical Art
how the explicitly political justifications for revising the canon, as well as
the instrumental applications of works of art in general, can be subject to
a dialectical and materialist critique. Contrary to pluralist arguments for
opening the canon on the grounds of social representation or pragma-
tism, Adorno makes the case that only the historical autonomy of art—free
from social, political, and practical obligations—is truly and substan-
tively critical of current social relations, and that any explicit political
content, or direct political application, of socially "committed" art actu-
ally ends u p serving the social order it ostensibly seeks to overcome.
Although originally articulated in response to the works of Bertolt Brecht
and the theories of Georg Lukacs, among others, this idea remains strik-
ingly pertinent to the canon debate today.
Finally, to show that critical theory does not simply defend the estab-
lished canon of Western literature nor automatically exclude works that
have not historically been regarded as canonical, I examine in detail a no-
tion of canonical change that is implicit to Adorno's and Walter
Benjamin's theories of art. Essentially, the image of configurations, or
"constellations," may be taken as a metaphor for canon formation itself.
The attempt to read the aesthetic content of canonical works against
the grain of critical orthodoxy or empirical sociology, with particular ref-
erence to class, capitalism, and materialism, is hardly unique to critical
theory. However, its distinctive conception of history and modernity—
and how they are inscribed in individual works of art—sets critical the-
ory apart from other schools of interpretation, including those that ap-
pear on the surface to be quite similar, such as traditional Marxist or
socialist literary criticism. It is hoped that this half of the book will also
help to distinguish it further.
any other aspect of culture. In that case, what Marcuse writes of culture
in general could be applied to the literary canon today: "The absorbent
power of society depletes the artistic dimension by assimilating its antag-
onistic contents. In the realm of culture, the new totalitarianism manifests
itself precisely in a harmonizing pluralism, where the most contradictory
works and truths peacefully coexist in indifference." 3 To the extent that
they are autonomous, however, works of art also provide a critique of the
society that would absorb them.
In his posthumous book, Aesthetic Theory, Adorno traces aesthetic au-
tonomy as historically derived from art's partial liberation from its ear-
lier cultic functions, which coincided with the emancipation of rational
thought from the superstitions of the mythical world during the
European Enlightenment. Because the concept of autonomy is a function
of "the bourgeois consciousness of freedom," its social origins are based
on class relations. 4 The historical development of art beyond religious
iconography and the imitation of nature, for example, depended on three
factors: the relative autonomy of the artist from the burden of common
wage-labor, which expanded his or her creative potential; the imagina-
tive, non-conformist perspective on the world that such independence af-
fords; and the peculiar space occupied by the artwork in cultural institu-
tions, which in turn allows the exceptional interpretative latitude that
commentators have traditionally ascribed to art. However, to the extent
that artworks are granted a special status as "Art," autonomy has also
contributed to their fetish character, an irrational devotion that has sup-
plied opponents of the Western canon with no shortage of reasons to
denounce it.
Due to its social quality, its dependence on the division of labor, and
the fetish character of its objects, aesthetic autonomy is never "pure" or
fully realized. Indeed, the autonomy of art in modernity is partly owing
to the commodification of culture in general because cultural artifacts are
treated, exchanged, and consumed as products not unlike those of mod-
ern industry, as Bourdieu's theory of cultural capital suggests. In
Adorno's aesthetic theory, "the absolute artwork converges with the ab-
solute commodity." Therefore, even autonomous works cannot be
wholly free from socioeconomic constraints. Art is not fully autonomous
because "absolute freedom in art" contradicts "the perennial unfreedom
of the social whole." Because art is always socially produced, its distance
from society can only ever be partial. Nevertheless, a degree of autonomy
from immediate social interests remains, albeit residually, in spite of ef-
forts to force individual works into various political roles, whether con-
servative or liberal, reactionary or progressive. And although it is neces-
sarily circumscribed or "shattered" as long as society itself remains
unfree, artistic autonomy "remains irrevocable," an irreversible historical
86 Critical Theory and Canonical Art
fact.5 This point is crucial to the critique of political art and its relevance
to the literary canon.
Apart from its social and historical origins, aesthetic autonomy is the
basis for what is perhaps the most vital aspect of art to critical theory: an
intrinsic opposition to a society dominated by destructive instrumental
rationality and founded on pervasive social injustice. This critical per-
spective furnishes art with its unique cognitive content, its capacity for
being a valid form of knowledge, revealing certain historical truths about
the world that other forms of knowledge, such as scientific or empirical
forms, either inherently cannot provide or would approach in qualita-
tively different ways. Because the work of art criticizes reality, it repre-
sents "negative knowledge of reality."6 As a unique form of critical in-
sight it acquires the capacity for being true, of illuminating both the
material conditions of society and its inherent contradictions. Thus, "the
truth content of artworks is fused with their critical content." 7 In particu-
lar, the truth content of art combines critical knowledge of economic rela-
tions that alienate people and the products of their labor into readily
transferable objects, a critique of society and the existent world at large,
and even a self-reflexive critique—an attack on the work of art itself. The
first is an indictment of social relations that are reduced to the status of
commodity exchange in which the irreducible individtiality of artworks
is violated. "On behalf of what cannot be exchanged," Adorno writes, art
must "bring the exchangeable to critical self-consciousness." In other
words, "artworks are plenipotentiaries of things that are no longer dis-
torted by exchange, profit, and the false needs of a degraded humanity." 8
This theme is largely in keeping with the traditional Marxist opposition
between use-value and exchange-value, wherein the latter comes to pre-
dominate especially under the socioeconomic conditions of bourgeois
capitalism, although it would be inaccurate simply to equate critical the-
ory with Marxist orthodoxy.
Art stands as a critique not only of the exchange principle, but also of
society per se, insofar as the latter is organized on that principle. It is "the
social antithesis of society," of society in its present guise. 9 The work of
art remains effectively critical because it is simultaneously social and au-
tonomous, thoroughly implicated in the society that it criticizes.
According to Adorno, "art exists in reality, has its function in it, and is
also inherently mediated with reality in many ways. But nevertheless, as
art, by its very concept it stands in an antithetical relationship to the sta-
tus quo." Art is social by its "opposition to society," but it occupies this
position only as autonomous art; "it criticizes society by merely exist-
ing." 10 This critique becomes an indictment of what passes for "reality,"
of the status quo mentality that naturalizes given circumstances, how-
ever unjust or inhumane: "Today the socially critical aspects of artworks
Critical Theory and Canonical Art 87
Art that makes social injustice its explicit subject matter risks trivializing
real human suffering for the sake of aesthetic expression. That is why
"the artwork is not only an echo of suffering, it diminishes it," too. 20
If the ideological characteristics of art are recalled, then the inescapable
culpability of art becomes clearer. Owing to the division of labor, artistic
production achieves a measure of autonomy, but it also reinforces that di-
vision. Autonomy enables a critical perspective on the social totality, but
it also relies on a notion of freedom derived from bourgeois individual-
ism. Although art's Utopian content preserves the promise of social trans-
formation, it also jeopardizes consciousness of injustice if it merely sym-
pathizes with the victims, rather than denouncing the source of their
suffering. So thoroughly does critical theory expose any vestige of ideol-
ogy that it even challenges the idea that art can be understood in purely
aesthetic terms, without constant awareness of its social situation and
collusion with injustice. The maxim that "art perceived strictly aestheti-
cally is art aesthetically misperceived" implies much more than a simple
amendment to the "disinterestedness" of Kant's Critique of Judgement, the
nineteenth-century attitude of 1'art pour I'art, or sociology's latter-day cri-
tique of the "pure gaze." The actuality of a purely aesthetic understand-
ing, like that of an ideologically untainted work, is precisely what the so-
cial debt and guilt of art necessarily refutes.21
The aesthetic thus occupies an extraordinarily delicate position: "If art
cedes its autonomy, it delivers itself over to the machinations of the sta-
tus quo; if art remains strictly for-itself, it nonetheless submits to integra-
tion as one harmless domain among others." 2 2 Whether social or au-
tonomous, ideological or pure, celebrated or condemned, artworks are in
constant danger of being politically accommodated and aesthetically
neutralized, thereby losing what may be their greatest critical import.
Both critics of and apologists for the literary canon underestimate the
depth of this predicament. When liberal critics dissolve the autonomy of
art within society so as to expose and denounce the ideological complic-
ity and elitism of the canon, they sacrifice the radically critical perspec-
tive that artworks afford only to the extent that they are autonomous. A
critique of the social totality—the whole stratified social order and its
economic rationale—is abandoned in favor of showing how individual
social groups have been inadequately represented in literary history and
school curricula. Of course, such omissions are taken as symbolic of the
wider lack of representation in society at large, within all its institutions,
but the specific arguments for opening the canon, as reviewed in Chapter
2, have not been made in tandem with a critique of the division of labor
that permeates society on every level and that is a condition for the pro-
duction of art itself, including that of women, homosexuals, and ethnic
minorities. Alternatively, when the Western canon is justified on the tra-
90 Critical Theory and Canonical Art
that contradict that claim, including the social caste of characters within
them or the very language in which they are written. Imposing an artifi-
cial universality on canonical works of art ends up serving only the ideo-
logical interests of the claimants. The opposite extreme, however, is no
better. "Particularity in the bad sense," which emphasizes "the antago-
nistic interests of individuals," is evident today in the assumption that
certain works can only or primarily represent specific social groups, such
as women, African Americans, or European males. If the culturally spe-
cific elements of artworks are emphasized at the expense of their univer-
sal social content, that assumption is equally ideological. 32 As shown in
Chapter 2, the emphasis on interest group politics, although confirming
certain objective social divisions like racial or gender differences, inad-
vertently legitimizes other social divisions, such as class hierarchy and
the division of labor on which it is based.
Although "artworks are, a priori, socially culpable," Adorno suggests
that "each one that deserves its name seeks to expiate this guilt." To do
so, works of art bear witness to human misery and social injustice.
Suffering, not celebration, is the "humane content" of art. 33 Like
Benjamin's "angel of history," art cannot look forward without glancing
back. "The reality of artworks testifies to the possibility of the possible,"
but at the same time, "the object of art's longing, the reality of what is
not, is metamorphosed in art as remembrance." 34 hi distinctive ways that
vary from work to work according to specific content, true art embodies
the "remembrance of accumulated horror," the historical memory of "ac-
cumulated suffering"—not of one or another individual social group, but
of humanity as a fragmented whole. 35 If the promesse du bonheur implies
that "art does its part for existence," then remembrance of injustice is
part of the debt to history which, along with the current productive ca-
pacity, is the basis of Utopian promise. 36 Benjamin implicitly qualifies
Utopian aspirations that are without this sense of debt: "Like every gen-
eration that preceded us, we have been endowed with a weak Messianic
power, a power to which the past has a claim. That claim cannot be set-
tled cheaply." 37 As Habermas writes of Benjamin's conception of history:
The obligation to the past, hope for the future, and critical demands on the
present cannot be forgotten in striving for a truly rational and qualita-
tively just, as opposed to formally equal, society. Ultimately, the debt to all
92 Critical Theory and Canonical Art
those who have suffered can only be paid by a reconciled future, in which
all irrational and arbitrary social antagonisms, not only a select few,
would be overcome and humanity would become truly emancipated.
Adorno suggests that a liberated, reconciled humanity may someday
be able to devote itself to the art of the past without guilt and thus "make
amends to the dead." 39 The intention, of course, is radically Utopian. Like
works of art themselves, the critical theory of art will indict reality, or the
current form of society, until art's promise is fulfilled, for "the idea of
art's implacable efforts has reconciliation as its end." 40 However, al-
though art clings to the promise of reconciliation even "in the midst of
the unreconciled," Adorno maintains that, for the sake of reconciliation,
"authentic works must blot out every trace of reconciliation in mem-
ory."41 Like the promesse du bonheur that is broken by the continuing real-
ity of barbarism and universal injustice, the reconciliation of irrational
social antagonisms is impossible as long as current social relations and
material conditions persist as they are, for "erecting truth directly amid
the general untruth . . . perverts the former into the latter."42 Only when
economic exploitation, the division of labor, and the domination of in-
strumental rationality and its ideology of pragmatism are vanquished
might true social reconciliation transpire. Only then would art cease to be
fetishized as inertly canonical, idealistically revered, appropriated as a
pedagogical tool, or employed as a useful pawn of cultural politics.
To anticipate an objection, it could be argued that the literature of his-
torically marginalized groups, perhaps even more than that traditionally
regarded as canonical, does indeed raise the specter of guilt, indict unjust
social relations, and attempt to record and redeem the historical suffering
of generations past, often even making these its explicit subject matter. In
spite of the best intentions, however, this argument is potentially ideo-
logical itself, as explained below.
the ideological concern to keep culture pure obeys the wish that in the
fetishized culture, and thus actually, everything remains as it was. Such in-
dignation has much in common with the opposing position's indignation
that has been standardized in the phrase about the obsolete ivory tower
from which, in an age zealously proclaimed an age of mass communication,
art must issue. . . . [W]hat the two basic censorial positions of bourgeois
consciousness hold in common—that the artwork must not want to change
the world and that it must be there for all—is a plaidoyer for the status quo;
the former defends the domestic peace of artworks with the world and the
latter remains vigilant that the sanctioned forms of public consciousness be
maintained.65
contradictions of capitalist society, they have the capacity for being true,
for being truly critical and exemplary works of art. The judgment of aes-
thetic content is therefore not simply subjective, arbitrary, or culturally
relative—a matter of "taste," ephemeral social and intellectual fashions,
or the timely strategies of cultural politics. Rather, it is objectively deter-
mined by the cumulative history of society and material developments,
both of which are indirectly inscribed in the works themselves.
Central to critical theory's conception of history and philosophical in-
terpretation is the idea that the truth content of art and literature is dis-
closed in a configuration, or "constellation" of concepts. According to
Benjamin, ideas are related to objects as constellations are to stars. 83 Ideas
bind together otherwise disparate and particular objects to form a newly
coherent and distinctive body of knowledge. In terms of art, the various
components of an individual work—its formal, thematic, material, and
even spiritual elements (or even the absence thereof)—as well as the ten-
sions and contradictions between them, may likewise be interpreted as
existing in changeable configurations. As a constellation of constitutive
elements—some of which are ideological, others true—a work of art
forms and transforms over time. That is why "even in artworks that are
to their very core ideological, truth content can assert itself. Ideology, so-
cially necessary semblance [illusion], is . . . also the distorted image of the
true." 84 Thus, residues of aesthetic truth can be found even in the work of
reactionary artists, such as Stefan George. 85 Aesthetic evaluation, and ul-
timately canonicity, is therefore never simply a matter of determining
which works are ideological or false and which ones are true, which
works are politically progressive and which ones are regressive. Rather,
"what the work demands from its beholder is knowledge"—that is, that
both "its truth and untruth . . . be grasped." 86 Indeed, the very idea of a
canon, as an aesthetic concept that has been multifaceted or contradic-
tory since its inception—combining practical and idealistic elements, aes-
thetic and moral values, universal and nationalistic connotations—can it-
self be thought of as a constellation whose elements are the particular
works that it comprises at any given historical moment. Different config-
urations will be seen at different times, but the component stars remain
objects of illumination even as they recede. Equally, new configurations,
the relationship of whose constitutive parts cannot now be conceived,
will emerge in the future via changing social conditions and developing
artistic forms.
Although wary of the consequences of official, institutional canoniza-
tion, the critical theory of art strives to realize what is worth preserving
of the canon, without being nostalgic about what is not. Neither endors-
ing the Western canon nor banishing it as wholly ideological, neither con-
fining it to immediate political interests nor acclaiming it as timeless and
702 Critical Theory and Canonical Art
Authentic art of the past that for the time being must remain veiled is not
thereby sentenced. Great works wait. While their metaphysical meaning dis-
solves, something of their truth content, however little it can be pinned
down, does not; it is that whereby they remain eloquent. A liberated human-
ity would be able to inherit its historical legacy free of guilt. What was once
true in an artwork and then disclaimed by history is only able to disclose it-
self again when the conditions have changed, on whose account that truth
was invalidated: Aesthetic truth content and history are that deeply meshed.
A reconciled reality and the restituted truth of the past could converge.
What can still be experienced in the art of the past and is still attainable by
interpretation is a directive toward this state.87
Note let us imagine an extreme ease: that a book speaks of nothing but events that He
altogether beyond the possibility of any frequent or even rare experience—tlmt it is the
first language for a new series of experiences. In that case, simply nothing will be
heard, but there will be the acoustic illusion that where nothing is heard, nothing is
there.
—Fricdrich Nietzsche, Ecce Homo 0888), part III, section I
703
W4 Subverting the Canon
this chapter I will show how these sociological approaches dispense with
the most critical attributes of art in modern society.
Sociology of art, according to the meaning of the words, embraces all as-
pects of the relationship between art and society. It is impossible to restrict it
to any single aspect, such as the social effect of works of art. This effect is it-
self only a moment in the totality of that relationship. To extract it and de-
clare it the only worthy object of the sociology of art, which cannot be con-
706 Subverting the Canon
That is because any method by wbich the social impact of a work be-
comes the primary criterion of analysis or evaluation implies that the so-
ciology of art must be guided by the status quo. It succumbs to the imme-
diate circumstances of the empirical world as it stands, yet overlooks the
degree to which the work of art is relatively autonomous of that world, in
terms of its specific form and the historical developments that have made
it so: "[T]he principle that governs autonomous works of art is not effect
but their inherent structure.'"* Through its formal qualities—its abstract,
negative, or enigmatic aspects; its degree of freedom—art, as explained
in Chapter 4, implicitly opposes existent social reality. It is social "not
only because of its mode of production, in which the dialectic of the
forces and relations of production is concentrated, nor simply because of
the social derivation of its thematic material"—nor, it could be added, be-
cause of its social impact or appropriation. "Much more importantly, art
becomes social by its opposition to society, and it occupies this position
only as autonomous art." 10
Although he recognizes that society as an abstract whole is indeed
manifested in the work of art, Adorno adds that true aesthetic contem-
plation must include an immanent critique of the work itself, of its for-
mal attributes and their own historical rationale broadly conceived.
Contrary to purely sociological reflection, immanent critique involves a
relationship to the aesthetic object that is opposed to "a genetic method
that confuse[s] the specification of the conditions under which literary
works were created—the biographical circumstances, the models, the so-
called influences—with knowledge of the works themselves."' 1 The aim
of critical aesthetic theory is the truth content, whereby the formal prop-
erties of autonomous works, not simply their social impact, influence,
and appropriation, disclose the sociohistorical truths that are otherwise
obfuscated by those very effects. What Adorno writes of the psychoana-
lytic theory of art likewise applies to the sociology of art: It "treats art-
works as nothing but facts, yet it neglects their own objectivity, their in-
ner consistency, their level of form, their critical impulse, their relation to
nonphysical reality, and, finally, their idea of truth." 12
Because it presupposes the relativity of artistic value from the start, the
sociology of reception and authorial reputation also jeopardizes critical
judgment. To take for granted the radically contingent nature of reputa-
tion or the existence of an infinite variety of canons for any group that
Subverting the Canon 107
With the continuing organization of all cultural spheres the desire grows to
assign art its place in society theoretically and indeed practically. . . . Once
art has been recognized as a social fact, the sociological definition of its con-
text considers itself superior to it and disposes over it. .. . Such endeavors
Subverting the Canon 109
themselves call for social criticism. They tacitly seek the primacy of adminis-
tration, of the administered world even over what refuses to be grasped by
total socialization or at any rate struggles against it. The sovereignty of the
topographical eye that localizes phenomena in order to scrutinize their func-
tion . .. ignores the dialectic of aesthetic quality and functional society.22
that the literary text will reveal only in veiled terms, that it will say only
in such a manner as to leave it unsaid." 35 In the sociology of the field, the
hidden truth content of literature reveals the social structure and histori-
cal determinations of cultural production, particularly regarding the re-
production of literary value. It is on these terms that Bourdieu declares
Sentimental Education to be "a true example of the absolute masterpiece,"
because it contains "an analysis of the social space in which the author
was himself located," that is, a "sociological content" within the work it-
self.36 In Bourdieu's reading, the actions and motivations of characters in
the novel, as well as the social disposition of Flaubert as an autonomous
bourgeois author (e.g., his "aloofness from the social world"), exhibit as-
pects of the social relations and objective functioning of the literary field
in France in the nineteenth century. 37 However, Bourdieu's interpretation
is so sociological that the quality of a work literally comes down to how
good a sociologist its author is: "Flaubert the sociologist gives us a socio-
logical insight on Flaubert the man." 38 The content of literature is there-
fore reduced to explicit socioeconomic relationships, and its aesthetic
quality is measured only by the light that the work sheds on them.
In contrast, the immediate social context of a work is only one aspect of
a constellation of elements that critical theory perceives in art, and not
necessarily the one most vital in modernity. "Certainly," Adorno writes,
"art, as a form of knowledge, implies knowledge of reality, and there is
no reality that is not social. Thus truth content and social content are me-
diated." Even so, contrary to the sociology of cultural production, "art's
truth content transcends the knowledge of reality as what exists."39 As seen in
Chapter 4, this is because "something in reality, something back of the
veil spun by the interplay of institutions and false needs, objectively de-
mands art"; for works of art are "plenipotentiaries of things that are no
longer distorted by exchange, profit, and the false needs of a degraded
humanity." 40 Yet the sociology of the field of artistic production discounts
anything about literature that does not involve its own social context;
nothing points beyond it. As Bourdieu himself writes, "the transcendent
world of cultural works does not encompass within itself the principle of
its transcendence; neither does it contain the principle of its becoming,
even if it helps to structure the thoughts and acts which are the source of
its transformation." 41 In critical theory, though, it is precisely social real-
ity in its current form—its dependence on economic exchange and
means-over-ends rationality, its recourse to pragmatism, and its domina-
tion by scientistic rationality (of which the totalizing sociology of the
field is itself an example)—that the most successful works of art oppose.
Those elements that escape the purview of the sociology of the field—for
example, aesthetic abstractness or non-representational art; a Utopian vi-
sion of a world beyond current social conditions; the memory of histori-
Subverting the Canon 113
the power struggles that must be waged in order to achieve canonical status
for a particular figure require a redistribution of what often turns out to be
limited resources: just as the manufacturers of consumer products struggle
for consumer shelf space, so those who seek to expand the canon must com-
pete for limited space in anthologies, limited time in college courses, and . ..
the limited capacity of readers to hold a lengthy list of towering authors in
mind at once.68
Like liberal pluralism and the sociology of repute, new historicism takes
aesthetic value to be determined by contending and immediate social in-
terests. Not only are canonical works trivialized as filler for textbooks—
commodities as expendable as any other—but canonicity is anachronisti-
cally reduced to being the product of modem economic rationality. In a
passage reminiscent of Bourdieu, Greenblatt remarks that the work of art
is not "a pure flame," but "the product of a negotiation between a creator
or class of creators, equipped with a complex, communally shared reper-
toire of conventions, and the institutions and practices of society. In order
to achieve the negotiation, artists need to create a currency that is valid
for a meaningful, mutually profitable exchange." 69 By characterizing the
value of texts as dependent on an economy of symbolic negotiations and
social profitability in the manner of cultural capital, however, new his-
toricism imposes on the canon what is perhaps most inimical to aesthetic
autonomy: the principle by which all difference, individuality, and par-
ticularity collapse into identity for the sake of exchange. Like sociology,
new historicism divests artworks of their potential to criticize current
socioeconomic relations and the calculating, pragmatic rationality that
reinforces them. Unhistorically, it universalizes the modern conception of
exchange so that it becomes its own "overarching" historical construct,
elevating the governing principle of the status quo as the final arbiter,
now and always, of aesthetic value. In short, new historicism's pretense
of "remembering" history within a technocratic and commodified society
ends up doing little more than conforming to the very logic of that soci-
ety, willfully subjecting to exchange and commodification the artifacts
that would best embody a critique of them.
Subverting the Canon 119
[T]he literary canon has normally been seen as "authentic" and "inspired"
in ways that other (merely "fictional") texts are not. Such distinctions be-
tween more or less authentic and more or less inspired texts are, of course,
judgements of value rather than statements of fact. But in so far as literary
studies understands itself as the study of great literature, then such value-
judgements enter into the very definition of its subject matter, and thereby
take on the quasi-objectivity of what we might well term a pseudo-fact.76
One of the most damaging charges that the cultural studies movement has
leveled against aesthetics is that it is wedded to a ("high cultural") canon of
works expressing the taste and values of a particular class. . . . [However,]
the aesthetic is not identified with a particular kind of literary object but
with an attitude individuals can adopt in relation to all kinds of objects, lit-
erary or not.78
In either case, the pundits of cultural studies will just as readily analyze
the semiotics of cigarette advertisements as that of canonical literature;
the literary tropes of Ridley Scott's film, Blade Runner, as those of Milton's
Paradise Lost; or the aesthetic value of fine wines and even professional
cricketers as much as that of Titian's work.7y
Such an all-embracing application of aesthetic value or content is per-
haps taken to its farthest extreme with the "aesthetic practice of the self,"
in which aesthetics becomes "a distinctive way of actually conducting
one's own life," in Hunter's words, of "bringing oneself into being as the
subject of an aesthetic experience." 80 Whatever it means for individual
Subverting the Canon 121
Indeed, "a transgression of the frontiers between high and low, esoteric
and demotic, lies in the very nature of capitalism itself."86 Cultural stud-
ies as a discipline seems to be the institutional expression of an overbear-
ing market society that reduces true individuality to equivalence and
conformity for the sake of exchange, the process of which it also acceler-
ates. Whether it focuses on solitary subjects, commercial advertising,
products of the entertainment industry, or officially consecrated works of
art, cultural studies finds identical qualities in everything it fixes upon.
Critical theory, however, is not content with acquiescing to the status
Subverting the Canon 123
quo. To Adorno and Horkheimer, "that art may best serve human eman-
cipation which detaches itself from the controlled and levelling interrela-
tions of a consumption, the democratic nature of which now only serves
as ideology." 87 Without sufficiently critical discrimination—which in-
cludes recognizing the historical and critical legitimacy of canonical dis-
tinction as well as its potential to be neutralized by institutional accom-
modation—cultural studies disregards the fact that true culture, like
canonical art, involves "an irrevocably critical impulse toward the status
quo and all institutions thereof. . . . [It is]a protest against integration
which always violently opposes that which is qualitatively different," an
objection "directed against the idea of levelling unification itself."88
Both products manufactured by the industries of culture and works
historically considered canonical may wrell be "torn halves of an integral
freedom"—as in Adorno's famous phrase—but the pretense of cultural
studies to have overcome the divide fails to realize the force of the pro-
viso that those halves "do not add up."89 The division cannot be glossed
over because it is historically objective, that is, the result of actual social
and material processes. It therefore remains both true and inevitable as
long as society itself is governed by a divisive rationale that endorses ex-
ploitation and inequality. "The dual character of culture . . . is derived
from the unresolved social antagonism which culture would like to cure
but as mere culture caniiot." 90 The idealistic liberal faith in educational
reform shows up again in this context: Without radical social change
founded on qualitative material transformation, aesthetic distinctions
will not simply evaporate, despite declarations to the contrary. Although
its specific content changes over time, the canon of "high art" remains
valid—indeed, indispensable—because it provides qualitative alterna-
tives, not concessions, to both the dominant pragmatic rationality of the
administered world and its quantitative notion of democracy, as well as
to the antagonistic social relations fostered by capitalism and its bour-
geois ideas of freedom. Just as the claims of socialist art (and Lukacs's de-
fense of it) amount to an "extorted reconciliation," and those of a plural-
istic canon to a fraudulent equality, the claim of cultural studies to
collapse the distinction between works high and low, canonical and pop-
ular, is ideological as long as social and material inequality prevails.
Because "the elitist isolation of advanced art is less its doing than soci-
ety's," 91 a critique of the canon cannot draw a line at art, but must take in
the whole socioeconomic order and the variety of ways in which it is le-
gitimized, including the specific methods by which cultural studies itself
ends up serving the status quo. The populist critique of the canon in the
guise of an egalitarian curriculum may well succeed in the classroom, but
the rationality of society as currently constituted—its governing princi-
ples of instrumentality, economism, and exchange—is left thoroughly in-
124 Subverting the Canon
tact, if not reinforced: "[Sjocial injustice continues after it has been offi-
cially declared to have been eliminated." 92
This is also why the "indignation that has been standardized in the
phrase about the obsolete ivory tower from which . . . art must issue" has
something in common with the conservative concern to "keep culture
pure." 9 3 In the name of equality, these demands would abandon that
which perhaps best stands as a measure of how far from true reconcilia-
tion society remains. Where social, economic, and educational privilege
persists—including that of the professional artist and the specialist
critic—so will the distinction of canonical art; to dissolve the latter with-
out a radical critique of the former is false. More than simply negligent, it
is also ideological for preserving those privileges while claiming to have
overcome them. As long as society continues to be governed by prag-
matic, means-over-ends rationality, the "rational irrationality" of art re-
mains valid, if only to contradict it.94 This is certainly not to recommend a
static, lofty canon such as that exalted by cultural conservatism, which
would only reproduce the fetish of art in the service of the status quo, but
to stigmatize art, high culture, or the canon as primarily elitist is not only
unhistorical and politically dubious, it also willfully sacrifices the truth
content of art to the commodification of culture that passes itself off as
democratic.
One remarkable passage from Adorno's Aesthetic Theory draws the
connections between each of the preceding approaches to understanding,
subverting, or abolishing the canon:
Those who have been duped by the culture industry and are eager for its
commodities... perceive art's inadequacy to the present life process of soci-
ety—though not society's own untruth—more unobstructedly than do those
who still remember what an artwork once was. They push for the deaes-
theticization [Entkutistung] of art.... The humiliating difference between art
and the life people lead, and in which they do not want to be bothered be-
cause they could not bear it otherwise, must be made to disappear: This is
the subjective basis for classifying art among the consumer goods under the
control of vested interests.95
The sociology of art, new historicism, and cultural studies might offer bet-
ter alternatives than the appeal to "pure" aesthetics or the institutional
neutralization of the canon, but the price these approaches pay for the
challenge does not amount to what they bargained for. In the end, one set
of ideologies is exchanged for another, each of which leaves the radically
critical, cognitive content of canonical works out of the equation.
6
The Boundaries of
a Critical Theory of
Canon Formation
Philosophy offers no place from which theory as such might be concretely convicted of
the anachronisms it is suspected of, now as before. Perhaps it was an inadequate inter-
pretation which promised that it would be put into practice. Theory cannot prolong
the moment its critique depended on. ... Having broken its pledge to be as one with
reality or at the point of realization, philosophy is obliged ruthlessly to criticize itself.
—Theodor Adorno, Negative Dialectics (1966)
125
726 Boundaries of a Critical Theory of Canon Formation
the critical theory of art in modernity would still apply. Moreover, the
"neglect" of "proletarian" literature is not a case of simple methodologi-
cal oversight or bias but rather a function of the critique of committed art
and skepticism regarding the orthodox Marxist faith in the proletariat. 7
Ultimately, the critique of their specific choice of literary subjects is a cri-
tique of Adorno and Benjamin as subjective individuals, foregrounding
their personal idiosyncrasies rather than engaging objectively with criti-
cal theory as such. When the actual content of Adomo's literary criticism
is engaged, however, other revealing problems arise.
Hohendahl devotes an entire chapter to Adorno's essay on Heine. He
tries to construct a case for why Adorno seems to have had "doubts" and
"reservations" about the value of Heine's poems, why "he cannot fully
acknowledge Heine's poetry as part of the German canon." 8 Adorno be-
lieved that Heine's status as an outsider inhibited his use of the German
language: "[H]is lack of resistance to words that are in fashion is the ex-
cessive mimetic zeal of the person who is excluded." 9 Because of Heine's
alienation from the language and because, "for Adorno, the idea of an
authentic poetic language remains crucial—particularly after the
Holocaust," Hohendahl believes that Adorno is initially reluctant to rec-
ognize Heine's modernity, his value as a modern writer; only "grudg-
ingly" does he admit him into the canon. 10 In Hohendahl's view, it is
Heine's German-Jewish identity that leads Adorno to surmise that he is
not "at home" in the German language. However, Hohendahl finds this
reasoning to rely on a problematic notion of linguistic authenticity that
contradicts Adorno's own thesis that anti-semitism is foimded in part on
the false essentialism of an "authentic" Jewish character:
Anti-semitism, Adorno rightly argues, has little to do with Jews; its mecha-
nisms do not depend on but rather exclude real experience with its victims.
At the same time, however, Adorno suggests that there is a link between
Heine's Jewishness and his lack of an authentic language, that there is real
difference after all between a German poet and a Jewish-German writer.
Obviously, these arguments are not quite compatible. The psychological
model of racism as a mechanism in which the victim is replaceable presup-
poses that there can be no essentially Jewish character, that the "Jewish"
character—its otherness—is the invention of the racist. Yet Heine's linguistic
deficit, his not being quite at home in the German language, appears to be
real—a specifically Jewish deficiency."
concrete artifact as the basis for aesthetic theorizing. His emphasis on the
objective status of the artwork, on its structural and material features,...
could be perceived as specifically modernist," and therefore, presumably,
less relevant to cultural and theoretical concerns today. 17
Although there is indeed much in Adorno's theory that lends itself to
this interpretation, the conclusion that it is narrowly modernist for being
bound to a strict concept of the unified work is not entirely accurate. On
the opening page of Aesthetic Theory, the assertion is made that "nothing
concerning art is self-evident any longer, not its inner life, not its relation
to the world, not even its right to exist."18 Amid such radical skepticism,
not even the concept of the artwork itself can be taken for granted; criti-
cal theory implicitly subverts dogmatic definitions, whether of the work
of art or of authentic language and unmediated identity. In the section in
Aesthetic Theory entitled "Toward a Theory of the Artwork," Adorno re-
marks that "the thesis of the monadological character of artworks is as
true as it is problematic." Even though aesthetics "irrevocably . . . pre-
supposes immersion in the particular work," the notion of a determinate
or fully coherent work is as thoroughly mediated by abstract conceptual-
ization as the idea of art is by history and society, because any such con-
cepts are necessarily "introduced externally to the monad" rather than
derived directly from it.19 To that extent, the critical theory of art is not
simply wed to a unequivocal idea of the artwork, and may be more com-
patible with the post-structuralist conception of an open "work" than is
widely believed. The emphasis on artworks as historically becoming,
rather than simply "being," attests to Adorno's and Benjamin's implicitly
open-ended concept of the work.
A similar case has been made against critical theory's assumption of a
totally administered society, or socioeconomic totality, on which the idea
of art as radical critique depends. In opposition to the claim that modem
society is closed and monolithic, many critics have countered that critical
theory overestimates the cohesion of advanced capitalism and exagger-
ates its powers of social control. 20 In historical terms, its characterization
of society is thought at best to be more applicable to the period of mo-
nopoly capitalism in the first half of the twentieth century than to the
socioeconomic conditions of the latter half, when economic "Fordism"
gave way to decentralized, postindustrial capitalism. 21 In sociological
terms, the concept of a totally integrated, administered society may also
be criticized for its ethnocentrism, extrapolating solely from European
bureaucracy or Anglo-American experience at the expense of non-
Western societies that do not obviously fit into its model.
Although these criticisms might provide a more complex or nuanced
account of late capitalism, the degree to which they contradict the claims
of critical theory is less certain. For one thing, in spite of other structural
Boundaries of a Critical Theory of Canon Formation 131
The media do engage in social critique, but only . . . to facilitate the further
rationalization of advanced capitalism by eliminating social anachronisms
or lingering dysfunctional features, such as racism, sexism and any kind of
discrimination that resists the collective homogenization that is already, for
the most part, fairly well accomplished. Far from subverting anything other
than obsolete traditional remnants, this social critique is one of the most
powerful legitimating forces at work, positing advanced capitalism, as it is,
as the best of all possible emancipatory and democratic social systems.23
Because they tend to reflect the immediate interests of society, the various
organs of the mass media are incapable of providing alternatives to the
status quo, and often serve to reproduce and legitimize it instead.
Moreover, the criticism of the concept of totality on the grounds that it
132 Boundaries of a Critical Theory of Canon Formation
conceals the actual diversity of Western society, or the critical nature of its
institutions, is itself subject to criticism. If the idea of a qualitatively dif-
ferent or non-capitalist society is excluded in favor of accurately repre-
senting social diversity, then the concept of "difference" on which the cri-
tique of totality relies is not radically critical, but merely empirical. Like
the liberal-pluralistic arguments for opening the canon, without address-
ing the division of labor and the social relations of production, it leaves
the class basis of society essentially intact.
However problematic the concept of totality may or may not be when
applied to global capitalism and the reproduction of social relations, it is
even less clear whether it can be usefully extended to encompass the cul-
tural diversity of artistic production. In other words, the concept of total-
ity might be better suited to capitalism than to culture, unless one simply
reduces the latter to being a mechanical function of the former. Given
critical theory's own emphasis on mediation and its move away from the
crude base/superstructure model of Marxist orthodoxy, however, the
category of culture cannot be reduced to merely reflecting the socio-
economic "base." 24 If not, then to what extent does the concept of totality
extend to cultural forms such as art and literature? One of art's most dis-
tinguishing characteristics is a cognitive content distinct from positivistic
knowledge and forms of ideology; therefore, it poses, at least abstractly,
alternatives to totalizing thought. By their very existence, artworks sig-
nify something beyond the status quo. And although the current ten-
dency is for diverse cultures and artistic canons to flourish under the
socioeconomic conditions of market capitalism, it can still be argued that
decisive differences persist between canonical works, even in spite of the
inclination of administered society to categorize and homogenize them.
Indeed, the historical marginality of certain literary forms, authors, and
works has been seen as pointing to the fissures and gaps of totalizing sys-
tems and, by extension, of a static or closed literary canon. Yet, paradoxi-
cally, to make the case for their validity, import, or comparable value is
also to risk assimilation by the totality: The marginal remains dependent
on the center, just as the non-canonical is on the canonical. In other
words, non-Western or historically neglected works, cultures, and tradi-
tions might be presented as alternatives to the Western canon, but they
can hardly be said to lie outside the social totality for being so; that is,
even alternative works of literature, in terms of both their composition
and their reception, inevitably rely on the division of labor and the corn-
modification of culture. Nonetheless, given critical theory's own empha-
sis on the autonomy of art, which enables its critical perspective on the
empirical world, a concept of totality that really does embrace every
manifestation of culture and society could at least be refined, so as to ac-
count differentially for forms of art and culture that do not conform
Boundaries of a Critical Theory of Canon Formation 133
wholly to the dominant ones and that are therefore potentially more au-
tonomous than those that do.
In Chapter 4, I explained that the critical theory of art does not auto-
matically or necessarily exclude the truth content of hitherto neglected
works of literature, that immanent critique can be applied to them as
much as to the most canonical works of art. However, the qualitative dis-
tinctions that can be made among popular forms of art, which are notori-
ously lacking in Adomo's aesthetic theory, have not yet been examined.
In the following section I show how this absence, along with Adomo's
ambiguous view of canonization, may ultimately point to the limits of a
critical theory of canonical art.
To claim that autonomy is a precondition for truth in art is to ignore the abil-
ity of heteronomous works and events to challenge the status quo, some-
times in ways that are more effective than those available to autonomous
works. . . . Adomo's aesthetics [is] inadequate with respect to popular art.
134 Boundaries of a Critical Theory of Canon Formation
As is known, when a people vanishes, the first to disappear are the upper classes, and
with them literature; all that remains are books of late, which the people know In/
lieart.
Milorad Pavic,
Dictionary of the Khazars: A Lexicon Novel in 100,000 Words (1989)
139
HO Conclusion
thetic quality can also be the judgment of a work's radically critical po-
tential, one which is as subversive of the status quo as it is of its own in-
stitutional accommodation. In spite of these tensions, contradictions, and
ambiguities, it is possible to make some general concluding remarks
without denying those tensions or forcing them into a premature and ar-
tificial reconciliation.
Superficially, the "either/or" terms of the debate as it has been framed
suggest that its arguments are divided along ideologically opposed lines
that are wholly incompatible and irreconcilable. The Western literary
canon is either pedagogically useful or socially oppressive, a source of
enlightenment or of deception, a fetish disguising political interests or an
instrument of democratic humanism. The individual works it comprises
are either socially committed or aloof, historically autonomous or het-
eronomous, politically populist or elitist, representative of society or re-
moved from it, products of the dominant culture or independent of it. Yet
each of these antinomies has served to obscure the actual ideological
affinities between them. For all the diverse claims that have been made
about the canon, characteristic of each is an idealistic conception of the
role of aesthetic judgment in the appraisal of canonical works or a prag-
matic notion of their political and pedagogical functions, both of which,
it has been shown, are inherent to the concept itself, but neither of which
accounts for the material constraints of canon formation as a social and
historical process. The idealism of those who take the aesthetic quality of
literature to be timeless, subjective, or without social implications is
matched by those who find the Western canon to be the result of an his-
torical prejudice that can be overcome with a substitution of texts in the
classroom. In neither case are objective historical and material determi-
nations seen as constitutive of both the production of all works of art and
the specific content of a canon in any given period.
Literature is not made in a social vacuum, and neither are its critical
reappraisals. To be at all comprehensive, therefore, any critique or analy-
sis of the canon must also include a metacritique of the claims that are
made about it, an assessment of the social and material conditions of
their own possibility, especially those that have done most to influence
the form the debate has taken. To the extent that specific modes of pro-
duction affect not only the form and dissemination of cultural works but
also the discourse about them, the economic principles and ideological
mystifications of capitalist society affect not only the production and re-
production of literary canons but also the rhetoric surrounding them.
That even those works of literature raised to challenge the hegemony and
unjust exclusions of the Western canon owe their authorship in part to
the division of labor mitigates from the start whatever measure of social
justice and equality is actually achieved by their recognition. To promote
Conclusion Ul
When classless society promises the end of art, because it overcomes the ten-
sion between reality and the possible, it promises at the same time also the
beginning of art, the useless, whose intuition tends towards the reconcilia-
Conclusion 143
tion with nature, because it no longer stands in the service of the exploiter's
use. 1
Introduction
1. Andrew Bowie's book, From Romanticism to Critical Theory: The Philosophy of
German Literary Theory (1997), has made a start in suggesting how critical theory
addresses many of the most salient issues in literary theory today. Because his
primary concern is with the philosophical heritage of critical theory, however, he
devotes only a few pages of his introduction and conclusion specifically to the
canon debate (pp. 6-8 and 284-289).
2. Theodor Adorno, "Cultural Criticism and Society," in Prisms (1981), pp.
17-34. See also Simon Jarvis, Adorno: A Critical Introduction (1998), p. 74.
3. For example, "The struggle between curricular multiculturalism and the
conservative redefinition of Western intellectual traditions has little relevance
outside the American academy, where it expresses local anxieties about 'multicul-
turalism,' ethnicity and American cultural identity rather than any more univer-
sal issues.... It is difficult to see how this debate could be of deep interest to any-
one outside the United States." John Gray, "Classic Problems" (review of Terence
Ball's Reappraising Political Theory), Times Literary Supplement, (April 28, 1995),
p. 28.
4. This is one of the points made by John Guillory in Cultural Capital: The
Problem, of Literary Canon Formation (1993). Guillory has written extensively about
the literary canon debate, and his arguments are examined in detail in Chapter 3.
5. Theodor Adorno and Helmut Becker, "Education for Autonomy," Telos,
no.56 (Summer 1983), p. 109. Adorno's skepticism that purely educational re-
forms can resolve a cultural crisis is also found in "Theory of Pseudo-Culture,"
Telos, no.95 (Spring 1993), pp. 15-20 and 25.
6. On the canon of political theory, see Conal Condren, The Status and Appraisal
of Classic Texts (1985) and the title essay of John Dunn, The History of Political
Theory and Other Essays (1996), pp. 11-38. On the canon of sociology, see Peter
Baehr and Mike O'Brien, "Founders, Classics and the Concept of a Canon,"
Current Sociology, vol. 42, no. 1 (Spring 1994). On challenges to the canon of
American history, see Gary Nash, Charlotte Crabtree, and Ross Dunn, History on
Trial: Culture Wars and the Teaching of the Past (1997). On the canon of Western mu-
sic, see Lydia Goehr, The Imaginary Museum of Musical Worts (1992). For a specifi-
cally feminist challenge to the Western canon of music, see Marcia J. Citron,
Gender and the Musical Canon (1993).
145
146 Notes
Chapter O n e
1. One notable exception is Jan Gorak, The Miking of the Modem Canon: Genesis
and Crisis of a Literary Idea (1991), especially pp. 9-88.1 am indebted to his work
for the first part of this chapter.
2. John Boardman, Creek Sculpture: Tire Classical Period (1985), p. 7.
3. Gisela Richter, A Handbook of Greek Art: A Survey of the Visual Arts in Ancient
Greece (1959; eighth edition, 1983), p. 120.
4. Nigel Spivey, Understanding Greek Sculpture: Ancient Meanings, Modern
Readings (1996), pp. 40 and 222.
5. Boardman (1985), p. 21, and Gorak (1991), pp. 10-12. A hypothetical recon-
struction of the details of Polykleitos's rules for sculpture, deduced from the evi-
dence of the Doryphoros and Diadoumenos, may be found in Brunilde Sismondo
Ridgway, Fifth Century Styles in Greek Sculpture (1981), pp. 202-204.
6. Ridgway, p. 202.
7. Citations to Platonic Dialogues are noted parenthetically by line number in
the text and are taken from The Collected Dialogues of Plato, Including the Letters,
edited by Edith Hamilton and Huntington Cairns (1961).
8. Cf. also Republic, book ii, 1.379a; and Laws, books ii, 1.660a, and vii, 1.817d.
9. Edward Alexander Parsons, The Alexandrian Library, Glory of the Hellenic
World: Its Rise, Antiquities, and Destructions (1952), pp. 219-228. See also Adrian
Marino, The Biography of "The Idea of Literature": From Antiquity to the Baroque
(1996), p. 32.
10. Ernst Robert Curtius, European Literature and the Latin Middle Ages (1953),
pp. 249-255.
11. The Church pronounced a dogmatic definition of the biblical canon at the
Council of Trent in 1546, which "required equal reverence for all forty-five books
of the Old Testament and all twenty-seven books of the New Testament on the
grounds that God is their author." Karl Rahner and Herbert Vorgrimler, Concise
Theological Dictionary (1965), p. 65. See also Hans von Campenhausen, The
Formation of the Christian Bible (1972) and the detailed account by Bruce Metzger,
The Canon of the New Testament: Its Origin, Development, and Significance (1987).
12. On the canon's use for the instruction of grammar, see John Guillory,
Cultural Capital: The Problem of Literary Canon Formation (1993), pp. 71-74.
Guillory's own theoiy that the formation of canons depends on socially mediated
conceptions of literacy is examined in Chapter 3.
13. Curtius (1953), pp. 48-52 and 260-264.
14. Ibid., p. 264. Cf. also Marino (1996), p.59: "Throughout the Middle Ages,
national vernacular literature is little appreciated and, therefore, little used. The
enormous prestige of Latin keeps it permanently on the fringe, where it receives
little attention"—that is, before the emergence of the modern nation-state.
15. Joseph Levine, The Battle of the Books: History and Literature in the Augustan
Age (1991), p. 5. "Already under Queen Elizabeth the curriculum is determined
that will govern English education for two or three centuries."
16. Ibid.
17. For a concise account of the cultural impact of print technology, see
Elizabeth Eisenstein, The Printing Revolution in Early Modern Europe (1983).
Notes 147
18. Alvin Kernan, Printing Technology, Letters & Samuel Johnson (1987), p. 7.
Although it is true that litieratura had signified grammar in general and all man-
ner of writing, words and phrases of literary distinction were hardly new to the
era of printing: The phrase ars poetica in the Middle Ages had long served a dis-
criminating purpose for Latin and Greek texts. See Curtius (1953), pp. 42 and
437-439; and Marino (1996), pp. 1-28.
19. Kernan (1987), p. 159.
20. Terry Eagleton, The Function of Criticism: From "The Spectator" to Post-
Structuralism (1984), pp. 29-43.
21. On the dependence of the modern sense of professional "author" on copy-
right law, see Mark Rose, "The Author as Proprietor: Donaldson v. Becket and the
Genealogy of Modern Authorship," Representations, no. 23 (Summer 1988), pp.
51-85; and Martha Woodmansee, "The Genius and the Copyright: Economic and
Legal Conditions of the Emergence of the 'Author'," Eighteenth-Century Studies,
vol. 17, no. 4 (Summer 1984), pp. 425-448.
22. Kernan (1987), pp. 97-100 (quotation from p. 98).
23. On the formation of the modern French literary canon, see Ann Jones and
Nancy Vickers, "Canon, Rule and the Restoration Renaissance," Yale French
Studies, no.75 (1988), pp. 9-25; and Joan Dejean, "Classical Reeducation:
Decanonizing the Feminine," Yale French Studies, no.75 (1988), pp. 26-39.
"Increasingly, the modern writers who continued to be read were only those who
could be promoted as French classics, that is, as part of a national, and nationalis-
tic, literary program." Dejean, p. 36.
24. Peter Uwe Flohendahl, Building a National Literature: The Case of Germany,
1830-1870 (1989), pp. 140-200; and James Sheehan, German History: 1770-1866
(1989), pp. 160-174. On the Schillerfest, see Hohendahl, pp. 179-192; and
Sheehan, pp. 867-868.
25. Andrew Sanders, "Poets' Corner: The Development of a Canon of English
Literature," in The Short Oxford History of English Literature (1994), pp. 1-7.
26. Michael Dobson, The Making of the National Poet: Shakespeare, Adaptation and
Authorship, 1660-1769 (1992), pp. 3,5 and 14.
27. D. J. Palmer, The Rise of English Studies: An Account of the Study of English
Language and Literature from Its Origins to the Making of the Oxford English School
(1965); Chris Baldick, The Social Mission of English Criticism 1848-1932 (1983); and
Robert Crawford, Devolving English Literature (1992).
28. Terry Eagleton, Literary Tiwory: An Introduction—Second Edition (1996), p. 26.
Although the chair of English was founded at Cambridge in 1912, the Final
Honours School, which awards the degree in English, was established only in
1917. Eagleton notes that the war "signalled the final victory of English studies at
Oxford and Cambridge," and the national patriotism it aroused serviced "less
English literature than English literature" (pp. 24-25).
29. Sanders (1994), p. 7; and Terry Eagleton, "The Crisis of Contemporary
Culture: An Inaugural Lecture Delivered before the University of Oxford on 27
November 1992," (1993), p. 3.
30. Gerald Graff, Professing Literature: An Institutional History (1987), pp. 28-51,
130, and 211-214.
148 Notes
Chapter Two
1. William J. Bennett, To Reclaim A Legacy: A Report on the Humanities in Higher
Education (1984), pp. 2-4,11, and 16.
2. Paul Lauter, Canons and Contexts (1991), p. 227.
3. Lynne Cheney, Humanities in America: A Report to the President, the Congress,
and the American People (1988), pp. 7 and 14.
4. Lynne Cheney, 50 Hours: A Curriculum for College Students (1989), p. 22 and
11.
5. Hilton Kramer and Rober Kimball, eds., Against the Grain (1995), p. x.
6. Ibid., pp. 79 and x. For a comparable British version of the same argument,
with particular reference to the literary canon, see Anthony Quinton, "Clash of
Symbols," Times Higher Education Supplement (April 30,1993), pp. 15-16.
7. James Tuttleton, "Back to the Sixties with Spin Doctor Graff," in Kramer and
Kimball (1995), p. 88.
8. Kramer and Kimball (1995), pp. x and 77.
9. Harold Bloom, The Western Canon: The Books and School of the Ages (1994), pp.
18 and 35.
10. Ibid., pp. 29 and 16.
11. Ibid., p. 4.
12. Ibid., p. 522.
13. Ibid., pp. 54 and 8.
14. Ibid., pp. 6 and 8-9.
15. Despite his own admission that "capital is necessary for the cultivation of
aesthetic values," Bloom still ridicules Marxist insights into artistic production
and consumption. Ibid., p.33. The respective contributions of Marxism and new
historicism to understanding canon formation are considered in the following
chapters.
16. Ibid., pp. 30 and 524.
17. Ibid., p. 23.
18. Frank Kermode, Forms of Attention (1985), pp. 78-79.
19. Ibid., p. 89.
Notes 149
20. Frank Kermode, "Canon and Period," in History and Value (1988), p. 115.
21. Ibid., pp. 116-117. "Some workable notion of canon, some examined idea of
history, though like most human arrangements they may be represented as un-
just and self-serving, are necessary to any concept of past value with the least
chance of survival, necessary even to the desired rehabilitation of the unfairly ne-
glected. So the tradition of value, flawed as it is, remains valuable" (p. 127).
22. Kermode (1985), p. 89, and Kermode (1988), p. 115.
23. Kermode (1985), p. 62.
24. Ibid., p. 90: "To be inside the canon is to be protected from wear and tear, to
be credited with indefinitely large numbers of internal relations and secrets, to be
treated as a heterocosm, a miniature Torah."
25. Kermode, Essays on Fiction 1971-82 (1983), p. 29.
26. Kermode (1985), p. 75, and Kermode (1988), pp. 115-116.
27. Kermode (1985), pp. 33-63.
28. "The Institutional Control of Interpretation/' in Kermode (1983), pp.
169-174.
29. Ibid., pp. 180-181.
30. Ibid., pp. 173 and 184. Kermode's optimism about institutional authority is
slightly qualified in a later writing, when he comes to consider other forms of
control and coercion that institutions may also exercise. Nevertheless, he still
manages to legitimize at least the more subtle forms of "institutional power" as
unavoidable, even if sometimes "arbitrary," by naturalizing them as simply "the
old contest between authority and freedom." Kermode, "Freedom and
Interpretation," in Barbara Johnson, ed., Freedom and Interpretation: The Oxford
Amnesty Lectures 1992 (1993), pp. 62 and 67.
31. "Canon and Period," in Kermode (1988), p. 126.
32. See the 1979 selection of papers from the English Institute, subsequently
collected in Leslie Fiedler and Houston Baker, eds., English Literature: Opening Up
the Canon (1981). On the MLA forum, see Paul Lauter, Canons and Contexts (1991),
pp. 7 and 170, note 3.
33. George McFadden, "'Literature': A Many-Sided Process," in Paul Hernadi,
ed., What Is Literature? (1978), p. 52; Paul Lauter (1991), p. 23; and Lillian
Robinson, "Treason Our Text: Feminist Challenges to the Literary Canon," in
Elaine Showalter, ed., The New Feminist Criticism (1986), p. 115.
34. Robert Weimann, "Shakespeare (De)Canonized: Conflicting Uses of
'Authority' and 'Representation'," New Literary History, vol. 20, no. 1 (1988), pp.
69-70.
35. Jan Gorak, Making of the Modern Canon (1991), p. 6.
36. The idea of counterbalancing the canon is made explicit in Anne Haselkorn
and Betty Travitsky, eds., The Renaissance Englishwoman in Print: Counterbalancing
the Canon (1990).
37. H. Bruce Franklin, "English as an Institution: The Role of Class," in Fiedler
and Baker (1981), pp. 98 and 104.
38. Richard Ohmann, "The Shaping of a Canon: U.S. Fiction, 1960-1975/' in
Robert von Hallberg, ed., Canons (1984), pp. 378-397. It is worth noting a flaw in
Ohmann's method: To determine a periodical's presumed complicity with the
publishers' agenda, he attempts to establish a correlation in a given year between
150 Notes
pages of advertising by particular publishers and the pages of reviews those pub-
lishers are granted. However, Ohmann fails to support his claim that the largest
advertisers get "disproportionately large amounts of review space" with any
supporting figures of the total number of books published by each company each
year.
39. Ibid., pp. 382-384.
40. Jane Tompkins, Sensational Designs: The Cultural Work of American Fiction
1790-1860 (1985), pp. xii, 30, and 32.
41. Ibid., p . 4
42. John Guillory, "The Ideology of Canon-Formation: T. S. Eliot and Cleanth
Brooks," in Robert von Hallberg, ed., Canons (1984), p. 339.
43. Charlotte Pierce-Baker, "A Quilting of Voices: Diversifying the
Curriculum/Canon in the Traditional Humanities," College Literature: The Politics
of Teaching Literature, no. 17.2/3 (June/October 1990), pp. 152-161 (quotation
from p. 154).
44. Paul Lauter, "Canon Theory and Emergent Practice," and "Reconstructing
American Literature: Curricular Issues," in Lauter (1991), p p . 161-162 and
110-111.
45. Toni Morrison, Playing in the Dark: Whiteness and the Literary Imagination
(1992), pp. 3 and 53.
46. Marilyn Butler, "Literature as a Heritage, or Reading Other Ways" (1987),
pp. 7-8.
47. Morris Dickstein, "Popular Fiction and Critical Values: The Novel as a
Challenge to Literary History," in Sacvan Bercovitch, ed., Reconstructing American
Literary History (1986), pp. 29-66.
48. Nina Baym, "Melodramas of Beset Manhood: How Theories of American
Fiction Exclude Women Authors," in Elaine Showalter, ed., The New Feminist
Criticism (1986), pp. 63ff. Cf. also Carey Kaplan and Ellen Cronan Rose, The Canon
and the Common Reader (1990), pp. 66-96, in which Doris Lessing and Alice Walker
are claimed to have been made canonical by a combination of popularity and aca-
demic endorsement.
49. Tompkins (1985), pp. 84-85, her emphasis.
50. Lauter (1991), pp. 36-40. For an almost identical proposal, see also Gregory
S. Jay, American Literature and the Culture Wars (1997), pp. 205-206.
51. John Guillory, "Canonical and Non-canonical: A Critique of the Current
Debate," English Literary History (Fall 1987), pp. 491 ff.
52. John Beverley, Against Literature (1993), pp. 97-98, his emphasis.
53. Henry Louis Gates, Jr., "The Master's Pieces: On Canon Formation and the
African-American Tradition," in Loose Canons: Notes on the Culture Wars (1992), p.
35.
54. See John Searle, "The Storm Over the University," in Paul Herman, ed.,
Debating P.C.: Tlw Controversy over Political Correctness on College Campuses (1992),
pp. 106-108; and W. B. Carnochan, The Battleground of the Curriculum: Liberal
Education and American Experience (1993), pp. 100-103.
55. Martin Luther King, Jr., Where Do We Go from Here: Chaos or Community?
(1968), p. 20. King encouraged "programs that impinge upon the basic system of
Notes 151
social and economic control"; those that "go beyond race," for example, "and
deal with economic inequality, wherever it exists" (p. 17).
56. Mas'ud Zavarzadeh and Donald Morton, "(Post)modern Critical Theory
and the Articulations of Critical Pedagogies," College Literature: The Politics of
Teaching Literature, no. 17.2/3 (June/October 1990), pp. 54-55.
57. See, for example, Eric Hobsbawm and Terence Ranger, The Invention of
Tradition (1983).
58. For example, Dale Spender, "Women and Literary History," in Catherine
Belsey and Jane Moore, eds., The Feminist Reader: Essays in Gender and the Politics of
Literary Criticism (1989); Margaret J. M. Ezell, Writing Women's Literary History
(1993); Germaine Greer, Slip-Shod Sibyls: Recognition, Rejection, and the Woman Poet
(1995); and Henry Louis Gates, Jr., and Nellie Y. McKay, eds., The Norton
Anthology of African American Literature (1997).
59. Hilde Heirs, "Refining Feminist Theory: Lessons from Aesthetics," in Hilde
Hein and Carolyn Korsmeyer, eds., Aesthetics in Feminist Perspective (1993), p. 14,
note 1.
60. Diana Coole, "Is Class a Difference That Makes a Difference?" Radical
Philosophy, no. 77 (May/June 1996), pp. 20-22.
61. Ellen Meiksins Wood, Democracy Against Capitalism: Renewing Historical
Materialism (1995), pp. 238-263 (quotation from p. 246). Like Diana Coole, Woods
writes that "the 'difference' that constitutes class as an 'identity' is, by definition,
a relationship of inequality and power, in a way that sexual or cultural 'differ-
ence' need not be. A truly democratic society can celebrate diversities of life
styles, culture, or sexual preference; but in what sense would it be 'democratic' to
celebrate class differences?" (p. 258).
62. James Davidson, "To the Crows!" (review of Bernard Knox, The Oldest Dead
White European Males, and Other Reflections on the Classics, 1993), Loudon Review of
Books, (January 27,1994), p. 20.
63. Jonathan Culler, "Excerpts from the Symposium on 'Humanities and the
Public Interest,'" Yale Journal of Criticism, vol. 1, no. 1 (Fall 1987), p. 187.
64. Lauter (1991), p. xii. Despite paying lip service to class, the fact that Lauter
ends up challenging the conventional canon almost entirely with literature writ-
ten by women and minorities is perhaps indicative of the liberal inability to sus-
tain the rhetoric of difference with respect to class.
65. Marjorie Perloff, "An Intellectual Impasse," Salmagundi, no. 72 (Fall 1986),
p. 128.
66. Eric Hobsbawm, "Identity Politics and the Left," New Left Review, no. 217
(May/June 1996), p. 40. Cf, also Eric Hobsbawm, The Age of Extremes: TIK Short
Twentieth Century, 1914-1991 (1994), pp. 428-430.
67. Charles Altieri, "An Idea and Ideal of a Literary Canon," in Robert von
Hallberg, ed., Canons (1984), p. 43.
68. Ibid., p. 44.
69. Richard Rorty, Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity (1989), pp. 80-81.
70. Ibid., p. xiv.
71. Charles Altieri, Canons and Consequences: Reflections on the Ethical Force of
Imaginative Ideals (1990), pp. 109-188. Cf. also "If Richard Rorty's critique of foun-
752 Notes
dationalist thought did not exist, literary theory would do well to invent it" (p.
163).
72. Ibid., pp. 109-111.
73. Ibid., pp. 36-37 (quotation from p. 36).
74.1bid.,p.34.
75. Gerald Graff, Professing Literature: An Institutional History (1987), p. 131.
76. Ibid., pp. 260-261.
77. Gregory S. Jay, American Literature and the Culture Wars (1997), pp. 56 and
176.
78. Martha C. Nussbaum, Cultivating Humanity: A Classical Defense of Reform in
Liberal Education (1997), pp. 6 and 295.
79. Jay (1997), pp. 199 and 190-191.
80. Ibid., p. 14. Cf. pp. 56,171, and 199.
81. Ibid., p. 138.
82. Terry Eagleton, Literary Theory: An Introduction—Second Edition (1996), p.
173.
83. Lauter (1991), p. x.
Chapter Three
1. Pierre Bourdieu, The Rides of Art: Genesis and Structure of the Literary Field
(1996), pp. 225-230, his emphases'.
2. Ibid., pp. 225, 253, and 292. See also Pierre Bourdieu, The Field of Cultural
Production: Essays on Art and Literature (1993), Part I, pp. 29-141.
3. Bourdieu (1996), p. 159.
4. Bourdieu (1993), p. 108, and Bourdieu (1996), pp. 253 and 225.
5. E. H. Gombrich, Ideals and Idols: Essays on Values in History and in Art (1979),
p. 12.
6. Bourdieu (1993), p. 110, my emphasis, and Bourdieu (1996), p. 171.
7. Andre Lefevere, Translation, Reuniting and the Manipulation of Literary Fame
(1992), p. 112.
8. E.g., Thomas Dabbs, Reforming Marlowe: The Nineteenth-century Canonization
of a Renaissance Dramatist (1991); Michael Berube, Marginal Forces/Cultural Centers:
Tolson, Pynchon, and the Politics of the Canon (1992); John Timberman Newcomb,
Wallace Stevens and Literary Canons (1992); Michael Millgate, Testamentary Acts:
Browning, Tennyson, James, Hardy (1992); Gary Scharnhorst, Henry David Thareau:
A Case Study in Canonization (1993); John Xiros Cooper, T. S. Eliot and the Ideology of
Four Quartets (1995), especially chapter 4; and Joan Acocelta, "Gather and the
Academy," The New Yorker (November 27,1995), pp. 56-71.
9. John Rodden, The Politics of Literary Reputation: The Making and Claiming of
"St. George" Orwell (1989).
10. Lawrence Schwartz, Creating Faulkner's Reputation: The Politics of Modern
Literary Criticism (1988), p. 47.
11. Gary Taylor, Reinventing Shakespeare: A Cultural History from the Restoration
to the Present (1990), p. 371. See also Michael Dobson, The Making of the National
Poet: Shakespeare, Adaptation and Authorship, 1660-1769 (1992).
Notes 153
12. Stephen Orgel and Jonathan Goldberg, eds., "Introduction," in John Milton
(The Oxford Authors edition) (1991), p. ix.
13. Dustin Griffin, "Milton's Literary Influence," in Dennis Danielson, ed., Tlte
Cambridge Companion to Milton (1989), pp. 243-244.
14. Ian Watt, Myths of Modern Individualism: Faust, Don Quixote, Don Juan,
Robinson Crusoe (1996). See especially the appendix, pp. 277-283, on the "world-
wide diffusion" of the myths.
15. Charles Rosen, "The Scandal of the Classics," New York Review of Books
(May 9,1996).
16. Jonathan Freedman, "Autocanonization: Tropes of Self-Legitimation in
'Popular Culture'," Yale journal of Criticism, vol. 1, no. 1 (Fall 1987), p. 208.
17. Bourdieu (1996), pp. 224 and 271.
18. For claims about the canonical status of Aphra Behn, see, for example, W. R.
Owens and Lizbeth Goodman, eds., Shakespeare, Aphra Behn and the Canon (1996).
A similar claim for Alice Walker is made by Carey Kaplan and Ellen Cronan Rose,
The Canon and the Common Reader (1990), pp. 89-93.
19. Bourdieu (1996), pp. 242-243, his emphases.
20. Ibid., pp. 300-301.
21. "Artistic development towards autonomy progressed at different rates, ac-
cording to the society and field of artistic life in question. It began in quattrocento
Florence,... was interrupted for two centuries under the influence of absolute
monarchy and of the Church . . . [and] accelerated abruptly with the Industrial
Revolution and the Romantic reaction." Bourdieu (1993), p. 113. Bourdieu re-
gards the nineteenth century in particular as the "critical" or "heroic phase of the
conquest of autonomy." Bourdieu (1996), pp. 60-61.
22. Ibid., pp. 230 and 229.
23. Bourdieu (1993), pp. 123 and 37. Cf. also: "The educational system con-
tributes very substantially to the unification of the market in symbolic goods, and
to the generalized imposition of the legitimacy of the dominant culture, not only
by legitimizing the goods consumed by the dominant class, but by devaluing
those transmitted by the dominated classes . . . and by tending, in consequence,
to prohibit the constitution of cultural counter-legitimacies" (p. 292, note 26).
24. Bourdieu (1996), pp. 304 and 147. The process is belated, Bourdieu explains,
because "the education system .. . does not grant, except post mortem, and after a
long process," such curricular consecration.
25. Ibid., p. 230.
26. Ibid., p. 250.
27. Rather than being fully independent of the economy, however, the field of
cultural production bears an inverse relation to it—such that the value of works
of art becomes greater, the less they have obvious economic value—which is why
Bourdieu speaks of the field of cultural production as operating within "an in-
verted economic world." Bourdieu (1993), pp. 29 and 75-76; and Bourdieu (1996),
pp. 83 and 216.
28. Bourdieu (1993), p. 112. On the potential role of non-academic publishers in
canon formation, see, for example, Alan Golding, "Little Magazines and
Alternative Canons: The Example of Origin," American Literary History, vol. 2, no.
4 (Winter 1990), pp. 691-725.
154 Notes
58. E.g., Henry Louis Gates, Jr., "Preface," in The Norton Anthology of African
American Literature (1997), pp. xxxiii-xxxvi; and Gregory S. Jay, American Literature
and the Culture Wars (1997), pp. 36-37.
Chapter 4
1. Cf. Max Horkheimer, "Traditional and Critical Theory," in Critical Theory:
Selected Essays (1992), pp. 188-243; Theodor Adorno, "Society," in Stephen
Bronner and Douglas Kellner, eds., Critical Theory and Society: A Reader (1989), pp.
267-275; and Herbert Marcuse, One-Dimensional Man: Studies in the Ideology of
Advanced Industrial Society (1964).
2. Theodor Adorno, "The Schema of Mass Culture," "Culture Industry
Reconsidered," and "Culture and Administration," in Jay Bernstein, ed., The
Culture Industry: Selected Essays on Mass Culture (1991), pp. 53-113. Cf. also
Theodor Adorno and Max Horkheimer, Dialectic of Enlightenment (1979), pp.
120-167.
3. Marcuse (1964), p. 61.
4. Theodor Adorno, Aesthetic Theory (1997), p. 225.
5. Ibid., pp. 21 and 1.
6. Theodor Adorno, "Extorted Reconciliation," in Notes to Literature: Volume
One (1991), p. 225.
7. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory (1997), p. 35.
8. Ibid., pp. 83 and 227.
9. Ibid., p. 8.
10. Adorno, "Extorted reconciliation," in Notes to Literature: Volume One (1991),
p. 224; and Aesthetic Theory (1997), pp. 225-226.
11. Ibid., p. 255.
12. Ibid., p. 233. "[UJtopia is essentially in the determined negation . . . of that
which merely is, and by concretizing itself as something false, it always points at
the same time to what should be." Theodor Adorno, "Something's Missing: A
Discussion between Ernst Bloch and Theodor W. Adorno on the Contradictions
of Utopian Longing," in Ernst Bloch, The Utopian Function of Art and Literature:
Selected Essays (1988), p. 12.
13. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory (1997), p. 132.
14. Ibid., p. 18.
15. Ibid., p. 311.
16. Adorno and Horkheimer (1979), p. 140. "There is no art that is entirely de-
void of affirmation, since by its very existence every work rises above the plight
of degradation and daily existence. . . . This apriority of the affirmative is art's
ideological dark side." Adorno, Aesthetic Theory (1997), p. 160.
17. Walter Benjamin, "Theses on the Philosophy of History," thesis vii, in
Illuminations (1969), p. 256.
18. On misogyny in Paradise Lost, see, for example, Christine Froula, "When
Eve Reads Milton: Undoing the Canonical Economy," Critical Inquiry, vol. 10, no.
2 (December 1983), p. 325; on T. S. Eliot's and D. H. Lawrence's elitism, see John
756 Notes
Carey, The Intellectuals and the Masses: Pride and Prejudice among the Literary
Intelligentsia, 1880-1939 (1992).
19. Benjamin, "Theses on the Philosophy of History," in Illuminations (1969), p.
260.
20. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory (1997), pp. 48-49 and 39.
21. Ibid., p. 6. The critique of aesthetic "purity" is assessed in detail in Chapter 5.
22. Ibid., p. 237.
23. Ibid., pp. 207 and 202.
24. Adorno, "Extorted Reconciliation," in Notes to Literature: Volume One (1991),
p. 232.
25. Theodor Adorno, "The Artist as Deputy," in Notes to Literature: Volume One
(1991), p. 100.
26. Theodor Adorno, "On Lyric Poetry and Society," in Notes to Literature:
Volume One (1991), p. 38, my emphasis.
27. Adorno, "Extorted Reconciliation," in Notes to Literature: Volume One (1991),
pp. 223-229 (quotation from p. 223).
28. Adorno, "On Lyric Poetry and Society," in Notes to Literature: Volume One
(1991), pp. 38-39.
29. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory (1997), p. 200.
30. Theodor Adorno, "On the Final Scene of Faust," in Notes to Literature:
Volume One (1991), p . 117.
31. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory (1997), p. 220. Cf. also: "In its relation with collec-
tivism and individualism art today faces a deadlock.. . . This deadlock is a faith-
ful expression of the crisis of our present society itself." Theordor Adorno,
"Theses upon Art and Religion Today," in Notes to Literature: Volume Two (1992),
p. 295.
32. Theodor Adorno, "Trying to Understand Endgame," in Notes to Literature:
Volume One (1991), p. 257. "Subjective differences . . . have degenerated into the
conspicuous consumption of those who can afford individuation.
. . . Differentiatedness cannot absolutely and without reflection be entered on the
positive side of the ledger. . . . Differentiatedness, once the precondition of hu-
manness [Humanitat], is gradually becoming ideology" (p. 248).
33. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory (1997), pp. 234 and 260.
34. Ibid., p. 132. On the "angel of history," see Benjamin, "Theses on the
Philosophy of History," in Illuminations (1969), p. 257.
35. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory (1997), pp. 324 and 261.
36. Ibid., p. 311. Uncharacteristically, Adorno insinuates that, "given the level
of productive forces the earth could here and now be paradise," an assumption
that is certainly debatable (p. 33).
37. Benjamin/Theses on the Philosophy of History," in Illuminations (1969), p.
254, his emphasis.
38. Jiirgen Habermas, The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity: Twelve Lectures
(1987), p. 14.
39. Adorno, Aestlwtic Theory (1997), p. 194.
40. Adorno, "Valery's Deviations," in Notes to Literature: Volume One (1991), p.
173.
41. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory (1997), pp. 33 and 234.
Notes 157
42. Theodor Adorno, Minima Moralia: Reflections from Damaged Life (1974), p.
172.
43. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory (1997), pp. 120-124.
44. Ibid., p. 39.
45. Ibid., p. 21.
46. Adorno, Minima Moralia (1974), p. 218.
47. Karl Marx, "Grundrisse," in David McLellan, ed., Karl Marx: Selected
Writings (1977), p. 359.
48. Simon Jarvis, Adorno: A Critical Introduction (1998), p. 22.
49. Theodor Adorno, "Parataxis: On Holderlin's Late Poetry," in Notes to
Literature: Volume Two (1992), especially pp. 123-137.
50. Peter Burger, Theory of the Avant-Garde (1984), p. 59.
51. Theodor Adorno, "How to Look at Television," in The Culture Industry
(1991), p. 141. On the "crisis of meaning" in art, see Adorno, Aesthetic Theory
(1997), pp. 152-157.
52. Adorno, Aesthetic Tlieory (1997), p. 234.
53. Ibid., pp. 139 and 320.
54. Theodor Adorno, "Commitment," in Notes to Literature: Volume Two (1992),
pp.76 and 89. To the end of his life, Adorno maintained that willful inactivity can
itself be a meaningful political gesture, especially in times when resistance is re-
duced to the crudest forms of political expression, such as mass "demonstra-
tions," flag waving, and finger pointing. See "Resignation," in Theodor Adorno,
Critical Models: Interventions and Catchwords (1998), pp. 289-293.
55. Theodor Adorno, "The Essay as Form," in Notes to Literature: Volume One
(1991), p. 20.
56. Adorno, Aestlietic Theory (1997), p. 241.
57. Adorno, "Commitment,"in Notes to Literature: Volume Two (1992), p. 83. On
the comparatively autonomous aspects, in formal terms, of Beckett's plays, see
pp. 90-91.
58. Ibid., p. 84.
59. Adorno, "The Artist as Deputy," in Notes to Literature: Volume One (1991),
p. 103.
60. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory (1997), p. 61.
61. Adorno, "Commitment," in Notes to Literature: Volume Two (1992), p. 83.
62. Adorno, "The Artist as Deputy," in Notes to Literature: Volume One (1991),
p. 99.
63. Ibid.
64. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory (1997), p. 39.
65. Ibid., pp. 247-248.
66. Theodor Adorno, "On Tradition," Telos, no. 94 (Winter 1992-1993), p. 77.
67. Theodor Adorno, "Theory of Pseudo-Culture," Telos, no. 95 (Spring 1993),
pp. 28-30. "Under prevailing conditions, the blithe dissemination of culture is ex-
actly the same as its destruction. .. . [W]hat aids the dissemination sabotages
what is disseminated" (pp. 29-32).
68. Theodor Adorno, "On the Fetish Character of Music and the Regression of
Listening," in The Culture Industry (1991), pp. 31-32.
69. Theodor Adorno, "Cultural Criticism and Society," in Prisms (1981), p. 34.
158 Notes
70. Adomo, "On Tradition," Telos, no. 94 (Winter 1992-1993), p. 79, my em-
phasis.
71. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory (1997), pp. 129 and 133.
72. Ibid., p. 3; and Adorno, "Theory of Pseudo-Culture," Telos, no. 95 (Spring
1993), p. 28.
73. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory (1997), p. 219. Cf. Adorno, "Valery's Deviations,"
in Notes to Literature: Volume One (1991), pp. 156-157.
74. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory (1997), p. 4.
75. Theodor Adorno, "Nachtmusik," quoted in Susan Buck-Morss, The Origin
of Negative Dialectics (1977), p. 45.
76. Theodor Adorno, "Heine the Wound," in Notes to Literature: Volume One
(1991), pp. 80-85; Adorno, "Extorted Reconciliation," in Notes to Literature: Volume
One (1991), p. 228; Theodor Adorno, "On an Imaginary Feuilleton," in Notes to
Literature: Volume Tivo (1992), p. 36; and Theodor Adorno, "On Dickens's Tlie Old
Curiosity Shop: A Lecture," in Notes to Literature: Volume Two (1992), pp. 171-177.
77. Theodor Adorno, Kierkegaard: Construction of the Aesthetic (1989), p. 85.
78. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory (1997), p. 41, his emphasis.
79. Walter Benjamin, Selected Writings Volume 1,1913-1926, Marcus Bullock and
Michael Jennings, eds. (1996), p. 235.
80. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory (1997), p. 299.
81. Adorno, "Parataxis: On Holderlin's Late Poetry," in Notes to Literature:
Volume Two (1992), pp. 110 and 137.
82. Ibid., pp. 121-136.
83. Walter Benjamin, The Origin of German Tragic Drama (1977), p. 34.
84. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory (1997), p. 233. "Great artworks are unable to lie.
Even when their content is semblance, insofar as this content is necessary sem-
blance the content has truth, to which the artworks testify" (p. 130).
85. Theodor Adorno, "Stefan George," in Notes to Literature: Volume Tim (1992),
pp. 178-192.
86. Adorno, Aesthetic Tlieory (1997), p. 15.
87. Ibid., pp. 40-41
Chapter Five
l.Jane Tompkins, Sensational Designs: The Cultural Work of American Fiction
1790-1860 (1985), p. 5. Recall her thesis that Nathaniel Hawthorne's interests
served those of a New England "dynastic cultural elite which came to identify it-
self with him" (p. 30). Compare also the argument that the class-based individu-
alism of Plath, Salinger, Bellow, and Updike helped to canonize them. Richard
Ohmann, "The Shaping of a Canon: U.S. Fiction, 1960-1975," in Robert von
Hallberg, ed., Canons, (1984), pp. 388-397.
2. Theodor Adorno, "Commitment," in Notes to Literature: Volume Two (1992),
pp. 80-81.
3. Theodor Adorno, "Cultural Criticism and Society," in Prisms (1981), p. 30.
4. Theodor Adorno, "Parataxis: On Holderlin's Late Poetry," in Notes to
Literature: Volume Two (1992), p. 110. Cf. also: "[T]he substance of a work begins
precisely where the author's intention stops; the intention is extinguished in the
Notes 159
71. Simon During, "Introduction," in The Cultural Studies Reader (1993), p. 22.
72. Martin Ryle, (1994), p. 21. Ryle prophesies that, with the rise of cultural
studies, "there mil be a reduction . . . in the size and scope of the canon," and that
"'literature' will tend to shrink insofar as it becomes a branch of cultural studies"
(p. 23, his emphasis).
73. Easthope (1991), pp. 5-6.
74. E.g., Terry Eagleton, Literary Theory: An Introduction—Second Edition (1996),
pp. 206-208.
75. Ian Hunter, "Aesthetics and Cultural Studies," in Lawrence Grossberg,
Cary Nelson, and Paula Treichler, eds., Cultural Studies (1992), p. 356.
76. Andrew Milner, Literature, Culture and Society (1996), p. 5.
77. Ibid., pp. 10-11.
78. Hunter (1992), p. 356.
79. Easthope (1991), pp. 152-156; Milner (1996), pp. 131-187; and Fred Inglis,
Cultural Studies (1993), pp. 190-191.
80. Hunter (1992), pp. 354 and 348.
81. Adorno, "Valery's Deviations," in Notes to Literature: Volume One (1991), p.
143; and Adorno, "Theory of Pseudo-Culture," Telos, no.95 (Spring 1993), p. 26.
82. Adorno, Minima Moralia (1974), p. 77.
83. Milner (1996), p. 178.
84. Ibid., pp. 11,17, and 25. For Bloom on "primal aesthetic value," see Bloom,
The Western Canon (1994), p. 65.
85. Terry Eagleton, Tlie Ideology of the Aesthetic (1990), p. 374.
86. Ibid., p. 375.
87. Adorno and Horkheimer, "Sociology of Art and Music," in Aspects of
Sociology (1973), p. 107.
88. Adorno, "Culture and Administration," in The Culture Industry: Selected
Essays on Mass Culture (1991), p. 100.
89. Adorno, letter to Walter Benjamin, 18 March 1936, in Theodor Adorno and
Walter Benjamin, The Complete Correspondence 1928-1940 (1999), p. 130, my em-
phasis.
90. Adorno, "Theory of Pseudo-Culture," Telos, no.95 (Spring 1993), p. 18.
91. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory (1997), p. 254.
92. Adorno, "Extorted Reconciliation," in Notes to Literature: Volume One (1991),
p. 221.
93. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory (1997), p. 247.
94. On the "rational irrationality" of art, see ibid., pp. 19 and 228.
95. Ibid., pp. 16-17.
Chapter Six
1. The volume of commentary on critical theory and Adorno's aesthetics in
particular is growing each year. See, for example, Albrecht Wellmer, The
Persistence of Modernity (1991), pp. 1-35; Jay Bernstein, The Fate of Art (1992), pp.
188-274; Andrew Bowie, From Romanticism to Critical Theory (1997), pp. 238-280;
Tom Huhn and Lambert Zuidervaart, eds., The Semblance of Subjectivity (1997);
Shierry Weber Nicholsen, Exact Imagination, Lite Work (1997); and Simon Jarvis,
Adorno: A Critical Introduction (1998), pp. 90-147.
Notes 163
24. For a concise account of the problems associated with the base-superstruc-
ture model, as well as of the Frankfurt School's use of mediation as an alternative
to it, see Raymond Williams, Marxism and Literature (1977), pp. 75-82 and 95-100.
25. Theodor Adorno and Max Horkheimer, Dialectic of Enlightenment (1944;
English edition 1979), pp. 120-167. Cf. also Adorno, "On the Fetish Character in
Music and the Regression of Listening," "The Schema of Mass Culture," and
"Culture Industry Reconsidered," in The Culture Industry (1991), pp.26-92.
26. E.g., Adorno, "On Popular Music," in Antony Easthope and Kate
McGowan, eds., A Critical and Cultural Theory Reader (1992), pp. 211-223; and
Adorno, "Perennial Fashion—jazz," in Prisms (1981), pp. 121-132. However, cf.
Adorno, "Is Art Lighthearted?" in Notes to Literature: Volume Two (1992), pp.
247-253.
27. David Held, Introduction to Critical Theory (1980), p. 369. For Adorno's dis-
missive remarks explicitly about The Beatles' relation to the culture industry, see
his interview with Peter von Haselberg, "On the Historical Adequacy of
Consciousness," Telos, no. 56 (Summer 1983), pp. 100-101.
28. Zuidervaart (1991), pp. 232 and 234.
29. Ibid., p. 235.
30. Ironically, with this last remark Zuidervaart seems to have forgotten his
own (erroneous) criticism of Adorno just a few pages earlier: "The contrast be-
tween autonomous and heteronomous art is fluid, however, and it certainly is no
longer so firm as to support Adorno's strong preference for autonomous art."
Ibid., p. 231. Whether or not Adorno simply "prefers" autonomous art, he cer-
tainly realized that heteronomy and autonomy were intertwined in both serious
and "light" art, a fact that is itself largely an effect of the culture industry. See
Adorno and Horkheimer (1979), pp. 135-136. Cf. also Adorno, "Is Art
Lighthearted?", in Notes to Literature: Volume Two (1992), pp. 247-253; and
Aesthetic Theory (1997), pp. 225-227.
31. Zuidervaart (1991), p, 235, my emphasis.
32. Adorno, "Transparencies on Film," in Tlie Culture Industry (1991), p. 160.
33. Ibid., pp. 154-161. For assessments of this essay's positive content, see
Hohendahl (1995), pp. 131-133; and Martin Jay, Adorno (1984), pp. 127-128.
34. Fredric Jameson, Signatures of the Visible (1992).
35. Cf. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory (1997), pp. 34 and 36; Adorno, "On Tradition,"
Telos, no.94 (Winter 1992-1993), p.77; and Adorno, "Theory of Pseudo-Culture,"
Telos, no.95 (Spring 1993), pp. 15-38.
36. Adorno, "Stefan George," in Notes to Literature: Volume Two (1992), p. 178;
and Adorno, "On the Classicism of Goethe's Iphigenie," in Notes to Literature:
Volume Two (1992), p. 155.
37. E.g., Peter Burger, Theory of the Avant-Garde (1984), pp. lii-liii; Hohendahl
(1995), pp. 171,194, and 199; and Zuidervaart (1991), pp. 220,223-224, and 229.
38. Adorno, "Notes on Kafka," in Prisms (1981), pp. 262-263, note 1.
39. Adorno, "Heine the Wound," in Notes to Literature: Volume One (1991), p. 83.
40. Adorno, "In Memory of Eichendorff," in Notes to Literature: Volume One
(1991), pp. 73-79 (quotation from p. 73).
41. Adorno, Minima Moralia (1974), p. 147. On Dumas and Sue, see Adorno,
"How to Look at Television," in The Culture Industry (1991), p. 138. In the same
Notes 165
piece, Adorno also finds the novels of Samuel Richardson and Daniel Defoe to be
prototypes of the culture industry (pp. 137-139).
42. See Adorno, Aesthetic Theory (1997), pp. 225 and 247-248.
43. Aesthetic Theory (1997), pp. 21 and 236.
44. Adorno, "Theory of Pseudo-Culture," Telos, no.95 (Spring 1993), p. 24.
45. Adorno, Minima Moralia (1974), p. 44.
Conclusion
1. Theodor Adorno, "Theses on Need," quoted in Martin Jay, Adorno (1984), p.
100
This page intentionally left blank
References
167
168 References
Birkerts, Sven, The Gutenberg Elegies: The Fate of Reading in an Electronic Age, Faber
&Faber, Boston, 1994.
Bloch, Ernst, The Utopian Function of Art and Literature: Selected Essays, trans. Jack
Zipes and Frank Mecklenburg, The MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts,
1988.
Bloom, Allan, The Closing of the American Mind, How Higher Education Has Failed
Democracy and Impoverished the Souls of Today's Students, Simon & Schuster Inc.,
New York, 1987.
Bloom, Harold, The Western Canon: The Books and School of the Ages, Harcourt
Brace & Company, New York, 1994.
Boardman, John, Greek Sculpture: The Classical Period, Thames & Hudson Ltd.,
London, 1985.
Boaz, David, Libertarianism: A Primer, The Free Press, New York, 1997.
Boaz, David, and Edward Crane, eds., Market Liberalism: A Paradigm for the 21st
Century, CATO Institutie, Washington, D.C., 1993.
Bourdieu, Pierre, Outline of A Theory of Practice, Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge, 1977.
, Distinction: A Social Critique of the judgement of Taste, Routledge, London,
1984.
, The Field of Cultural Production: Essays on Art and Literature, Polity Press,
Cambridge, 1993.
, The Rules of Art: Genesis and Structure of the Literary Field, Stanford
University Press, Stanford, California, 1996.
Bourdieu, Pierre, and Alain Darbel, The Love of Art: European Art Museums and
Their Public, Polity Press, Cambridge, 1991.
Bowie, Andrew, From Romanticism to Critical Theory: The Philosophy of German
Literary Theory, Routledge, London, 1997.
Bronner, Stephen, and Douglas Kellner, eds., Critical Theory and Society: A Reader,
Routledge, London, 1989.
Buck-Morss, Susan, Tlie Origin of Negative Dialectics: Theodor W. Adorno, Walter
Benjamin, and the Frankfurt Institute, The Free Press, New York, 1977.
Burger, Peter, Theory of the Avant-Garde, University of Minnesota Press,
Minneapolis, 1984.
Butler, Marilyn, "Literature as a Heritage, or Reading Other Ways," Inaugural
Lecture delivered 10 November 1987, Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge, 1987.
Byron, Lord, Don Juan, Leslie Marchand, ed., Houghton Mifflin, Boston, 1958.
Canby, Henry, "An American Canon," Saturday Review of Literature, October 15,
1927.
Carby, Hazel, "The Canon: Civil War and Reconstruction," Michigan Quarterly
Review, vol. XXVIII, no. 1, Winter 1989.
Carey, John, The Intellectuals and the Masses: Pride and Prejudice among the Literary
Intelligentsia 1880-1939, Faber & Faber, London, 1992.
Carnochan, W. B.,The Battleground of the Curriculum: Liberal Education and
American Experience, Stanford University Press, Stanford, California, 1993.
Chaucer, Geoffrey, The tlouse of Fame, trans. Brian Stone, Penguin Classics,
Penguin Books, Harmondsworth, 1983.
770 References
Cheney, Lynne V., Humanities in America: A Report to the President, the Congress, and
the American People, National Endowment for the Humanities, Washington,
D.C., September 1988.
Cheney, Lynne V., 50 Hours: A Core Curriculum for College Students, National
Endowment for the Humanities, Washington, D.C., October 1989.
Citron, Marcia ]., Gender and the Musical Canon, Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge, 1993.
Collini, Stefan, "Escape from DWEMsville—Is Culture Too Important to Be Left
to Cultural Studies?" The Times Literary Supplement, 27 May 1994.
, Matthew Arnold: A Critical Portrait, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1994.
Condren, Conal, The Status and Appraisal of Classic Texts: An Essay on Political
Theory, Its Inheritance, and the History of Ideas, Princeton University Press,
Princeton, New Jersey, 1985.
Coole, Diana, "Is Class a Difference That Makes a Difference?" Radical Philosophy,
no. 77, May/June, 1996.
Cooper, John Xiros, T. S. Eliot and the Ideology of Four Quartets, Cambridge
University Press, Cambridge, 1995.
Coser, Lewis A., Charles Kadushin, and Walter W. Powell, Books: The Culture and
Commerce of Publishing, The University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1985.
Crawford, Robert, Devolving English Literature, Oxford University Press, Oxford,
1992.
Culler, Jonathan, "Excerpts from the Symposium on 'Humanities and the Public
Interest'," The Yale Journal of Criticism, vol. 1, no. 1, Fall 1987.
Curtius, Ernst Robert, European Literature and the Latin Middle Ages, Princeton
University Press, Princeton, New jersey, 1953.
Dabbs, Thomas, Reforming Marlowe: The Nineteenth-century Canonization of a
Renaissance Dramatist, Associated University Press, London, 1991.
Dante Alighieri, The Divine Comedy, Volume I: Inferno, trans. Mark Musa, Penguin
Classics, Penguin Books, Harmondsworth, 1984.
Dante Alighieri, The Divine Comedy, Volume II: Purgatory, trans. Mark Musa,
Penguin Classics, Penguin Books, Harmondsworth, 1984.
Davidson, James, "To the Crows!" (review of Bernard Knox, The Oldest Dead
White European Males, and Other Reflections on the Classics, 1993), London Review
of Books, 27 January 1994.
Dejean, Joan, "Classical Reeducation: Decanonizing the Feminine," Yale French
Studies, no. 75,1988.
Dickstein, Morris, "Popular Fiction and Critical Values: The Novel as a Challenge
to Literary History," Sacvan Bercovitch, ed., Reconstructing American Literary
History, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1986.
Diogenes Laertius, Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers in Ten Books, trans. R.
D. Hicks, The Loeb Classical Library, Harvard University Press, Cambridge,
Massachusetts, 1925.
Dobson, Michael, The Making of the National Poet: Shakespeare, Adaptation and
Authorship, 1660-1769, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1992.
Dolle, Raymond, "The New Canaan, the Old Canon, and the New World in
American Literature Anthologies," College Literature: The Politics of Teaching
Literature, no. 17.2/3, June/October 1990.
References 171
Drabble, Margaret, ed,, The Oxford Companion to English Literature, fifth edition,
Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1985.
Dunn, John, The History of Political Theory and Other Essays, Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge, 1996,
During, Simon, ed., Tlie Cultural Studies Reader, Routledge, London, 1993.
Eagleton, Terry, Criticism and Ideology: A Study in Marxist Literary Theory, Verso,
London, 1978.
, The Function of Criticism: From The Spectator to Post-Structuralism, Verso,
London, 1984.
, The Ideology of the Aesthetic, Basil Blackwell Ltd., Oxford, 1990.
, "The Crisis of Contemporary Culture," Inaugural Lecture delivered before
the University of Oxford on 27 November 1992, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1993.
, Literary Theory: An Introduction—Second Edition, Blackwell Publishers,
Oxford, 1996.
Eagleton, Terry, and Drew Milne, eds., Marxist Literary Theory, Blackwell
Publishers, Oxford, 1996.
Easthope, Antony, Literary into Cultural Studies, Routledge, London, 1991.
Easthope, Antony, and Kate McGowan, eds., A Critical and Cultural Theory Reader,
Open University Press, Buckingham, 1992.
Eisenstein, Elizabeth, The Printing Revolution in Early Modern Europe, Cambridge
University Press, Cambridge, 1983.
Eliot, T. S., To Criticize the Critic and Otlier Writings, Faber & Faber, London, 1965.
, The Selected Prose of T.S. Eliot, Frank Kermode, ed., Faber & Faber,
London, 1975.
Ellis, John M , Literature Lost: Social Agendas and the Corruption of the Humanities,
Yale University Press, New Haven, 1997.
Emerson, Ralph Waldo, The Selected Writings of Ralph Waldo Emerson, Brooks
Atkinson, ed., The Modern Library, New York, 1992.
Euripides, Hecuba, trans. David Kovacs, The Loeb Classical Library, Volume 484,
Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1995.
Ezell, Margaret J. M., Writing Women's Literary History, Johns Hopkins University
Press, Baltimore, 1993.
Felperin, Howard, The Uses of the Canon: Elizabethan Literature and Contemporary
Theory, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1990.
Fender, Stephen, "Textual America: Pioneers of the Critical Revolution?" The
Times Literary Supplement, March 3,1995.
Ferguson, Robert, "'We Hold These Truths': Strategies of Control in the Literature
of the Founders," in Sacvan Bercovitch, ed., Reconstructing American Literary
History, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1986.
Fiedler, Leslie, and Houston Baker, eds., English Literature: Opening up the Canon,
Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore, 1981.
Foley, Barbara, "Subversion and Oppositionality in the Academy," College
Literature: The Politics of Teaching Literature, no. 17.2/3, June/October 1990.
Foucault, Michel, "What Is an Author?" in Paul Rabinow, ed., The Foucault Reader,
Penguin Books, London, 199].
Fowler, Alastair, Kinds of Literature: An Introduction to the Theory of Genres and
Modes, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1982.
772 References
Jameson, Fredric, The Ideologies of Theory, Essays 1971-1986, Volume 2: The Syntax of
History, University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, 1988.
_, Late Marxism: Adorno, or, The Persistence of the Dialectic, Verso, London,
1990.
, Postmodernism, or, The Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism, Verso, London,
1991.
, Signatures of the Visible, Routledge, London, 1992.
Jarvis, Simon, Adorno: A Critical Introduction, Polity Press, Cambridge, 1998.
Jay, Gregory S., American Literature and the Culture Wars, Cornell University Press,
Ithaca, New York, 1997.
Jay, Martin, Adorno, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1984.
Jones, Ann, and Nancy Vickers, "Canon, Rule and the Restoration Renaissance,"
Yak French Studies, no. 75,1988.
Kant, Immanuel, The Critique of judgement, trans. James Creed Meredith,
Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1952.
Kaplan, Carey, and Ellen Cronan Rose, The Canon and the Common Reader, The
University of Tennessee Press, Knoxville, 1990.
Kellner, Douglas, "Critical Theory and the Culture Industries: A Reassessment,"
Telos, no. 62, Winter 1984-1985.'
Kermode, Frank, The Classic: Literary Images of Permanence and Change, second edi-
tion, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1983.
, Essays on Fiction: 1971-82, Routledge & Kegan Paul, London, 1983.
, Forms of Attention, The University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1985.
, History and Value, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1988.
. "Freedom and Interpretation," in Barbara Johnson, ed., Freedom and
Interpretation: The Oxford Amnesty Lectures 1992, Basic Books, New York, 1993.
Kernan, Alvin, Printing Technology, Letters & Samuel Johnson, Princeton University
Press, Princeton, New Jersey, 1987.
, The Death of Literature, Yale University Press, New Haven, 1990.
King, Martin Luther, Jr., Where Do We Go From Here: Chaos or Community? Beacon
Press, Boston, 1968.
Knox, Bernard, "Introduction," in The Iliad, trans. Robert Fagles, Viking Penguin,
New York, 1990.
Kolodny, Annette, "A Map for Rereading: Gender and the Interpretation of
Literary Texts," in Elaine Showalter, ed., The New Feminist Criticism, Virago
Press Ltd., London, 1986.
Kramer, Hilton, and Roger Kimball, eds., Against the Grain: The New Criterion on
Art and Intellect at the End of the Twentieth Century, Ivan R. Dee, Chicago, 1995.
Lauter, Paul, Canons and Contexts, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1991.
Leavis, F. R., The Great Tradition: George Eliot, Henry James, Joseph Conrad, Chatto &
Windus Ltd., London, 1948.
Lefevere, Andre, Translation, Rewriting and the Manipulation of Literary Fame,
Routledge, London, 1992.
Levin, Harry, "Core, Canon, Curriculum," College English, no. 43, April 1981.
Levine, George, ed., Aesthetics and Ideology, Rutgers University Press, New
Brunswick, New Jersey, 1994.
References 175
Levine, Joseph, The Battle of the Books: History and Literature in the Augustan Age,
Cornell University Press, Ithaca, New York, 1991.
Liddell, Henry George, and Robert Scott, A Greek-English Lexicon, Oxford
University Press, Oxford, 1968.
Lindenberger, Herbert, The History in Literature: On Value, Genre, Institutions,
Columbia University Press, New York, 1990.
Lowenthal, Leo, Literature, Popular Culture, and Society, Prentice-Hall, Inc., New
York, 1961.
Lukacs, Georg, History and Class Consciousness: Studies in Marxist Dialectics, trans.
Rodney Livingstone, The MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1971.
Marcuse, Herbert, One-Dimensional Man: Studies in the Ideology of Advanced
Industrial Society, Beacon Press, Boston, 1964.
, The Aesthetic Dimension: Toward a Critique of Marxist Aesthetics, Beacon
Press, Boston, 1978.
Marino, Adrian, The Biography of "The Idea of Literature": from Antiquity to the
Baroque, State University of New York Press, Albany, 1996.
Marsh, Daniel L,, The American Canon, Abingdon-Cokesbury Press, New York,
1939.
McFadden, George, "'Literature': A Many-Sided Process," in Paul Hernadi, ed.,
What Is Literature? Indiana University Press, Bloomington, 1978.
McLellan, David, ed., Karl Marx: Selected Writings, Oxford University Press,
Oxford, 1977.
Meja, Volker, Dieter Misgeld, and Nico Stehr, eds., Modern German Sociology,
Columbia University Press, New York, 1987.
Metzger, Bruce, The Canon of the New Testament: Its Origin, Development, and
Significance, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1987.
Millgate, Michael, Testamentary Acts: Browning, Tennyson, James, Hardy, Clarendon
Press, Oxford, 1992.
Milner, Andrew, Literature, Culture and Society, UCL Press, London, 1996.
Montrose, Louis, "Professing the Renaissance: The Poetics and Politics of
Culture," in H. Aram Veeser, ed., The New Historicism, Routledge, New York,
1989.
Morrison, Toni, Playing in the Dark: Whiteness and the Literary Imagination, Picador,
London, 1992.
Mulhern, Francis, The Moment of "Scrutiny," Verso, London, 1981.
Nash, Gary B., Charlotte Crabtree, and Ross E. Dunn, History On Trial: Culture
Wars and the Teaching of the Past, Alfred A. Knopf, New York, 1997.
Newcomb, John Timberman, Wallace Stevens and Literary Canons, University Press
of Mississippi, Jackson, 1992.
Nicholsen, Shierry Weber, Exact Imagination, Late Work: On Adorno's Aesthetic
Theory, MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1997.
Nietzsche, Friedrich, On the Genealogy of Morals and Ecce Homo, trans. Walter
Kaufmann and R. J. Hollingdale, Vintage Books, New York, 1969.
Nussbaum, Martha Craven, Cultivating Humanity: A Classical Defense of Reform in
Liberal Education, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1997.
Ohmann, Richard, "The Shaping of a Canon: U.S. Fiction, 1960-1975," in Robert
von Hallberg, ed., Canons, The University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1984.
776 References
Orgel, Stephen, and Jonathan Goldberg, eds., John Milton, The Oxford Authors,
Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1991.
Owens, W. R., and Lizbeth Goodman, eds., Shakespeare, Aphm Behn and the Canon,
Routledge, London, 1996.
Palmer, D. J., The Rise of English Studies: An Account of the Study of English Language
and Literature from its Origins to the Making of the Oxford English School, Oxford
University Press, Oxford, 1965.
Parsons, Edward Alexander, The Alexandrian Library, Glory of the Hellenic World: Its
Rise, Antiquities, and Destructions, Cleaver-Hume Press, London, 1952.
Pavic, Milorad, Dictionary of the Khazars: A Lexicon Novel in 100,000 Words, trans.
Christina Pribicevic-Zoric, Vintage Books, New York, 1989.
Perloff, Marjorie, "An Intellectual Impasse," Salmagundi, no. 72, Fall 1986.
Pierce-Baker, Charlotte, "A Quilting of Voices: Diversifying the Curriculum/
Canon in the Traditional Humanities," College Literature: The Politics of Teaching
Literature, no. 17.2/3, June/October 1990.
Plato, The Collected Dialogues of Plato, Including the Letters, Edith Hamilton and
Huntington Cairns, eds., Princeton University Press, Princeton, New Jersey,
1961.
Pliny the Elder, Natural History: A Selection, trans. John Healy, Penguin Classics,
Penguin Books, London, 1991.
Quinton, Anthony, "Clash of Symbols," The Times Higher Education Supplement,
April 30,1993.
Radway, Janice, Reading the Romance: Women, Patriarchy, ami Popular Literature,
Verso, London, 1984.
Rahner, Karl, and Herbert Vorgrimler, Concise Theological Dictionary, Burns &
Oats, London, 1965.
Rajagopalan, Kanavillil, "Aesthetics vs. Ideology: The Case of Canon Formation,"
British journal of Aesthetics, vol. 37, no. 1, January 1997.
Renza, Louis, "A White Heron" and the Question of Minor Literature, University of
Wisconsin Press, Madison, 1985.
Richter, Gisela, A Handbook of Greek Art: A Survey of the Visual Arts in Ancient
Greece, eighth edition, Phaidon, London, 1983
Ridgway, Brunilde Sismondo, Fifth Century Styles in Greek Sculpture, Princeton
University Press, Princeton, New Jersey, 1981.
Robbins, Bruce, "Low Anxiety," Radical Philosophy, no. 79, September/October
1996.
Robinson, Lillian, "Treason Our Text: Feminist Challenges to the Literary
Canon," in Elaine Showalter, ed., 77K New Feminist Criticism, Virago Press Ltd.,
London, 1986.
Rodcien, John, The Politics of Literary Reputation: The Making and Claiming of "St.
George" Orwell, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1989.
Rorty, Richard, Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity, Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge, 1989.
Rose, Mark, "The Author as Proprietor: Donaldson v. Becket and the Genealogy of
Modern Authorship," Representations, no. 23, Summer 1988.
Rosen, Charles, "The Scandal of the Classics," The New York Review of Books, May
9,1996.
References 177
Todd, Janet, Feminist Literary History: A Defence, Polity Press, Cambridge, 1988.
Tompkins, Jane, Sensational Designs: The Cultural Work of American Fiction
1790-1860, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1985.
, "Sentimental Power: Uncle Tom's Cabin and the Politics of Literary
History," Elaine Showalter, ed., The Neiv Feminist Criticism, Virago Press Ltd.,
London, 1986.
Tunstall, Jeremy, and Michael Palmer, Media Moguls, Routledge, London, 1991.
Unsworth, John, "The Book Marketplace II," in Emory Elliott, ed., The Columbia
History of the American Novel, Columbia University Press, New York, 1991,
Veeser, H. Aram, ed., The Neiv Historicism, Routledge, New York, 1989.
von Campenhausen, Hans, The Formation of the Christian Bible, Adam & Charles
Black, London, 1972.
von Fritz, K., review of Herbert Oppel, Kanon (1937), American Journal of Philology,
vol. LX, no. 1,1939.
von Hallberg, Robert, ed., Canons, The University of Chicago Press, Chicago,
1984.
Watson, Ben, Frank Zappa's Negative Dialectics of Poodle Play, St. Martin's Press,
New York, 1995.
Watt, Ian, Myths of Modern Individualism: Faust, Don Quixote, Don Juan, Robinson
Crusoe, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1996.
Weimann, Robert, "Shakespeare (De)Canonized: Conflicting Uses of 'Authority'
and 'Representation'," New Literary History, vol. 20, no. 1,1988.
Wellmer, Albrecht, The Persistence of Modernity: Essays on Aesthetics, Ethics and
Postmodernism, Polity Press, Cambridge, 1991.
West, Cornel, "Minority Discourse and the Pitfalls of Canon Formation," The Yale
Journal of Criticism, vol. 1, no. 1, Fall 1987.
West, Cornel, "Diverse New World," in Paul Berman, ed., Debating P.C., Dell
Publishing, New York, 1992.
Whiteside, Thomas, "The Blockbuster Complex—II," The New Yorker, October 6,
1980.
, "The Blockbuster Complex—III," The New Yorker, October 13,1980.
Wilde, Oscar, Lady Windermere's Fan: A Play About a Good Woman, sixth edition,
Methuen and Co., London, 1911.
Williams, Raymond, Culture and Society, 1780-1950, Penguin Books,
Harmondsworth, 1958.
, The Long Revolution, Chatto & Windus Ltd., London, 1961.
, Marxism and Literature, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1977.
, Culture, Fontana, London, 1981.
Wood, Ellen Meiksins, Democracy Against Capitalism: Renewing Historical
Materialism, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1995.
Woodmansee, Martha, "The Genius and the Copyright: Economic and Legal
Conditions of the Emergence of the 'Author'," Eighteenth-Century Studies, vol.
17, no. 4, Summer 1984.
Zavarzadeh, Mas'ud, and Donald Morton, "(Post)Modern Critical Theory and
the Articulations of Critical Pedagogies/'Co/Jege Literature: The Politics of
Teaching Literature, no. 17.2/3, June/October 1990.
Zuidervaart, Lambert, Adomo's Aesthetic Theory: The Redemption of Illusion, The
MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1991.
Index
Adorno, Theodor, 2, 5, 26, 83, 93,107, Utopian content of, 87, 91,112,
163(n6) 115
aesthetic theory of, 72, 80, 84-88, Austen, jane, 59, 65, 72
90-92, 94-100,102-106,108-112,
114,117,123-124 Bacon, Francis, 22
criticisms of, 126-130,133-138 Balzac, Honore de, 99
See also Critical theory Baudelaire, Charles, 135
Altieri, Charles, 51-53 Baym, Nina, 41
Arac, Jonathan, 116 Beatles, 133-134,135,164(n27)
Arnold, Matthew, 22 Becker, Helmut, 5
Art Beckett, Samuel, 95,127
aging of, 70-72, 98 See also Art, Behn, Aphra, 67
Neutralization of Benjamin, Walter, 5, 26, 84, 88, 91,
autonomy of, 5, 6, 29, 84-86, 89, 100,101,103,127,128,130,
94-97,106,109-110,116-117, 163(n6)
133-134,164(n30) Bennett, William, 26-27, 28,29, 32,
content of, 5, 6, 52, 76, 86-87, 36
90-91, 92-102,109,111-115,120, Beverley, John, 43-44
124,132,133,137 Birkerts, Sven, 23
fetish character of, 61, 85, 92,108, Bloom, Allan, 23
110,137 Bloom, Harold, 24, 29-32, 35, 36, 53,
and modernity, 93-94, 96,100, 137, 121,148(nl5)
142 Boccaccio, 16,19
neutralization of, 71-72, 89, 98, Bourdieu, Pierre, 4, 60, 61-63, 66,
110-111,135 67-71, 75, 78, 79, 85,108-113,
politically committed, 2, 5, 43-44, 118,129
45,54,94-98,104,128 Bowie, Andrew, 145(n1)
popular, 41-42,119,126,133-135 Brecht, Bertolt, 84, 95
See also Canon formation, Bronte, Charlotte, 65, 72
popularity of works and Burger, Peter, 93,117, 161(n66)
pure, 89, 97,109-110 Burroughs, Edgar Rice, 119
as radical critique, 86-89, 91-92, Butler, Marilyn, 40
95
and reconciliation, 92,102,115, Callimachus, 14
124, 142-143 Canhy, Henry, 21
and social guilt, 86, 88-89, 90, 91, Canon formation
102 academia and, 4,16, 20, 46, 59-60,
utility of, 7,42, 43-44, 54, 57, 84, 73-75
94-96 See also Canons, academic monopoly of, 4, 60,
instrumental justifications of 68-69, 78, 79,141'
179
180