(Routledge Studies in Ethics and Moral Theory) Silvia Caprioglio Panizza - The Ethics of Attention - Engaging The Real With Iris Murdoch and Simone Weil-Routledge (2022)
(Routledge Studies in Ethics and Moral Theory) Silvia Caprioglio Panizza - The Ethics of Attention - Engaging The Real With Iris Murdoch and Simone Weil-Routledge (2022)
(Routledge Studies in Ethics and Moral Theory) Silvia Caprioglio Panizza - The Ethics of Attention - Engaging The Real With Iris Murdoch and Simone Weil-Routledge (2022)
Evil Matters
A Philosophical Inquiry
Zachary J. Goldberg
Desert Collapses
Why No One Deserves Anything
Stephen Kershnar
Neglected Virtues
Edited by Glen Pettigrove and Christine Swanton
Incomparable Values
Analysis, Axiomatics and Applications
John Nolt
Value Incommensurability
Ethics, Risk, and Decision-Making
Edited by Henrik Andersson and Anders Herlitz
Acknowledgements ix
Abbreviations xi
Introduction 1
4 Self-knowledge 110
Coda 173
Index 177
Acknowledgements
AD Against Dryness
AIN Art is the Imitation of Nature
DPR The Darkness of Practical Reason
F&S The Fire and The Sun: Why Plato Banished the Artists
IP The Idea of Perfection
KV Knowing the Void
MGM Metaphysics as a Guide to Morals
NP Nostalgia for the Particular
OGG On ‘God’ and ‘Good’
SBR The Sublime and the Beautiful Revisited
S&G The Sublime and the Good
SGC The Sovereignty of Good over other Concepts
T&L Thinking and Language
TSE T. S. Eliot as a Moralist
VCM Vision and Choice in Morality
When 28-year-old Daisy, who had been sleeping rough for 18 months in
London, met journalist Victoria Derbyshire, she told her something that
one may find surprising. The worst thing about rough sleeping, in her
view, was not the cold nights, or the discomfort of a makeshift bed.
Rather, ‘the worst thing about rough sleeping is not being seen’
(BBC 2020). A sentiment echoed by many. Mark Horvath, founder of the
‘Invisible People’ project, was inspired in his work by a homeless man
living in Los Angeles. He said:
For years, the man assumed he was invisible because no one would
look at him. That is until a boy handed him a pamphlet one day and
the man responded, ‘What! You can see me? How can you see me?
I’m invisible!’.
(Mentock n.d.)1
There can be harm in not seeing. This is, I think, a difficult thought to hold.
We can have an impact on others simply by directing, or failing to direct,
our gaze. The people who are harmed by not being seen are, of course, part
of our visual field for at least a short period of time. Then two sets of pos-
sibilities become available to us: to look away immediately or to look at
them as we would somebody else; and to look at them in an unresponsive
and unengaged way, as objects—or to pay attention to them.2
Being attended to can be transformative, as the man in Los Angeles testi-
fies. Attention is a way, perhaps the first way, of acknowledging another’s
existence. Everything follows from that. And yet, it is something we can fail
to do so much of the time. In fact, attention is not easy at all.
In the case of homeless people, there are many reasons for avoiding
attention. We may feel guilt: at living in a society that enables that pre-
dicament; at our comfortable lives; at the fact that we are not helping. We
may feel uncomfortable, for their lives look very different from ours.
We may be afraid of such difference. And so on. These emotions arise
when those individuals enter our landscape. Then, looking away can be
an active rejection of acknowledgment.
DOI: 10.4324/9781003164852-1
2 Introduction
At times not attending can be less like a refusal, and more like a habit
developed, perhaps to avoid those forms of discomfort in the first place.
When one consumes a meal containing animals and their products, for
instance, very seldom is attention directed at the animals themselves.
They are, as Carol Adams (1990) memorably put it, the great ‘absent
referent’. Lack of attention to the animals does not have the consequence
of making animals feel unreal, as in the case above, because the animals
are no longer there. (But we could still worry about lack of acknowledg-
ment, which can also apply to the dead.) What is clearer is that lack of
attention, here, makes it easier to perform certain actions, buying and
consuming products which, if we attended to the animals and the produc-
tion process, we may feel a moral resistance towards.3
Yet we know what happens to animals. We know the meat on the table,
the jacket in the shop, came from once living, breathing animals. But atten-
tion is not just knowledge. It is participating in what we are seeing or think-
ing about, even if we are not actors on the scene. Knowledge can be abstract,
attention is concrete. Iris Murdoch contrasts attention with ‘looking’
(IP 329). Both knowing and looking may be detached, attention is engaged.
Knowing and looking may be superficial, attention is imaginative. Looking
(but not knowing) may be distorting, attention is truth-directed. Attention is
directed at reality and, specifically, at an individual reality: not ‘people’, not
‘animals’, not ‘nature’, but this person, this animal, this blade of grass.4
We begin to see that attention is far from inconsequential. It can effect
significant changes in others, in our actions, as well as in ourselves. But
attention does not only matter in terms of its consequences. It also mat-
ters in itself. In attention, we join reality, we become more truthful, more
present—and that has far reaching, although sometimes imperceptible,
effects on our consciousness, our character, our priorities … as well as
our present and future actions.
To summarise, the exercise of attention (or its failure) has two main,
interconnected, manifestations: one is that there are things that we may
wish to ignore, but that in order to be morally responsible we ought not
to ignore; the other is that, while some things are within our field of
vision, we may not fully engage with them, we may ‘look’ without ‘see-
ing’, and ignore certain aspects, block our sympathy, avoid exercising the
imagination, and so on. Attention involves not just ‘knowledge’, but also,
with Stanley Cavell (1979), ‘acknowledgment’.
This book
In this book I propose an ‘ethics of attention’: a meta ethical and norma-
tive view that takes attention to be central. My claim in this book is that
attention is fundamental to morality. It returns the experience of a reality
from which distraction, defenses, or projection separate us. That, in itself,
makes us better, more open and less self-concerned. Every time, often
imperceptibly, attention shapes us and our world. It constitutes the
Introduction 3
background upon which deliberation, choice, and action occur. At its
most successful, attention renders deliberation and choice unnecessary,
because the experience of the reality that attention reveals already con-
tains within itself both motivation and direction. Attention can do all of
this, yet it is often overlooked when moral questions are discussed, or
moral situations confronted. The idea, unfortunately, is not mine. It
comes from Irish Murdoch, on whom I will be mainly drawing, who in
turn took it from Simone Weil, who will also figure prominently in these
pages, but as a ‘secondary character’.
Here is a brief summary of the book as a whole. Chapter 1 sets out the
reasons for considering attention morally at all, and then discusses the
two ‘axes’ upon which attention operates morally: the presence or
absence of attention, and the objects of attention. Chapters 2 and 3
engage with the role of the self in attention. If attention is truth-seeking,
it needs to remove our own projections and distortions. That is ‘unself-
ing’. In these chapters, I consider respectively a ‘tame’ or moderate ‘unself-
ing’, that is, the removal of self-concern, and a ‘radical’ unselfing, that is,
the removal of any idea of substantial and fixed self. Either way, the idea
that attending needs to be directed to reality and away from the self cre-
ates difficulties for self-knowledge, which I try to resolve in Chapter 4.
The last two chapters, Chapters 5 and 6, concern the consequences of
attention for moral perception, motivation, and action. There, I claim
that attention is necessary for moral perception, and can be sufficient for
motivation and action based on such perception.
Value is, Murdoch claims, both a real constituent of the world and a
ubiquitous constituent of consciousness. Both claims justify, indeed
require, the need for attention: attention is what discovers value in reality,
and it is itself a moral faculty. The apparent tension between value being
part of reality and of the structure of the mind has led to a lively discus-
sion about Murdoch’s brand of moral realism, and interpretations vary:
from Antonaccio’s (2000) ‘reflexive realism’, to the Platonic ‘earthy real-
ism’ supported by Robjant (2011), through Bagnoli’s (2012) constructiv-
ist reading. While I find the more robust form of realism more plausibly
attributed to Murdoch, which is the reading I will support in the book,
attention remains central on all of these readings. Whether value is there
independently of the activity of evaluation, or whether it is something
that is determined by such activity, attention enables the proper relation-
ship to the world where value, in various ways, is encountered. It not only
does so instrumentally (we need to know what is true to make good
choices), but also constitutively, removing obscuring influences (mostly,
arising out of self-concern) from the world we apprehend.
A non-anthropocentric ethics
This book takes a non-anthropocentric perspective, as much as I am capa-
ble of it given my humanity and socio-historical context. When I talk about
ethics, I do not assume that human beings are the primary objects of moral
thinking and feeling. Instead, unless specifically stated, I will be talking
generally about morality, taking for granted that it takes a number of dif-
ferent objects depending on different factors. Non-human animals figure
significantly in this book, and there are specific considerations that are
raised in relation to the ethics of relating to them, but that does not make
this into a book in applied ethics, insofar as applied ethics is concerned
with one specific field or group or problem only, separating it from moral-
ity generally. There are specificities about ethics in the case of non-human
animals, such as the fact that they are the group made to suffer and die by
humans more than any other; or that there are specific difficulties in think-
ing about, and attending to, other animals, which are partly different from
Introduction 9
the difficulties in relating to other humans. But only partly. Much of what
I will say about the ethics of attention is manifested in relation to other
people as well as other animals (and sometimes other living organisms).
I think it is time to at least ditch the assumption that moral thinking is
properly or primarily about humans. An assumption which, I believe, both
Murdoch and Weil made throughout most of their work. Yet, I use their
philosophy to develop a moral account along non-anthropocentric lines.
This is because I think the tools they offer are among the best for moral
thinking generally. One could go further, and claim—as Mick Smith (2011)
does—that Murdochian philosophy can offer tools for re-thinking human
dominance over nature: her notion of unselfing, the idea of giving up pos-
session and control, and the capacity to value what is other are all themes
that fit very well within an ecological ethic and, indeed, worldview. These
suggestions, at the same time, are, according to Smith, unintentional, inso-
far as Murdoch herself was not primarily or especially concerned with
either environmental or animal issues. I think that is true.6
Nonetheless, for its broad and adaptable nature, as well as for its abil-
ity to offer an alternative to mainstream theories that are felt by some as
increasingly unsatisfying, Murdoch’s ethics has been adopted not only by
environmental thinkers like Smith, but also by animal ethicists, who find
promise in the idea of attention to and love for other animals. In terms of
philosophical approach, Aaltola (2018: 194) stresses that Murdoch’s
emphasis on love, vision, and particularity is a better starting point than
many theories specific to animal ethics which are rationalistic and
abstract. By returning us to the individual, reality, and felt experience,
Murdoch’s ethics makes it easier both to approach animals, and to think
of ourselves as animals.
Attention, now
these are the kind of practices that now most need to be actively
engineered by faculty, because they simply are no longer available …
It is commonly assumed that vision is immediate … But what stu-
dents learn in a visceral way is that in any work of art there are
details and orders and relationships that take time to perceive.
(Roberts 2013: n.p.)
Introduction 11
There is a ‘depth’ to things, which is there, but also often not immediately
available. A central idea of Murdoch’s and Weil’s, and Plato’s too.
The need for recovering attention, again, is probably not specific to our
time, but it may be getting more acute. Perhaps it is for these reasons the
we are seeing in the West an increased interest in Buddhist practices,
which through meditation teach precisely to train the attention—and aim
for freedom from suffering which results from inattention and illusion.
The importance of attention is indeed central to Buddhist philosophy:
the Buddha gave prime importance to the ability to frame the issue of
suffering in the proper way. He called this ability yoniso manasi-
kara—appropriate attention—and taught that no other inner quality
was more helpful for untangling suffering and gaining release.
(Thanissaro Bhikkhu 2006: n.p.)
It is not surprising, then, that Murdoch flirted with Buddhism, and that
her friend and later biographer Peter Conradi is a Buddhist. She read
Sekida’s Zen Training, and engaged with it in MGM. Simone Weil too
was drawn to Eastern philosophy, but eventually found greater affinity
with Hinduism rather than Buddhism. Some of these influences will
return in this book.
After I briefly described Iris Murdoch’s thought to my friend Dae Gak,
a Zen master, he exclaimed: ‘She’s a Buddhist!’8 And he told me a Zen
story:
I feel that frustration too, as Dae Gak knows to his chagrin. Simone Weil
would say I am impatient, lacking precisely that attention which can stay
with mysteries and paradoxes, without trying to get out of them by my own
means. This whole book, as well, may show my misunderstanding of the
Buddhist message, by trying to say in six chapters, a coda, and one introduc-
tion, what Master Ichu says in three words. But perhaps, the master would
concede, these are meanderings of thought we need to go through, a
12 Introduction
necessary part of the path that may lead to knowing attention without ask-
ing questions. Paraphrasing Murdoch at the start of IP, there are instinctively
wise people and those that need to question and analyse, and as Zen recog-
nises, seeing things as they are may require a long pilgrimage in which we
lose familiarity with them. The wonder and loss of familiarity we experience
when we do philosophy may be understood in this context.9
Notes
1 For more accounts of this sort of experience, in the context of a sociological
reflection of the importance of the gaze in relation to homeless people, see
Kramer and Hsieh (2019).
2 On seeing someone as a something (or ‘reification’) and its opposite (‘recogni-
tion’) see Axel Honneth’s fundamental work (2007).
3 More recently, on her website, Adams writes about vegan-feminism as arising
precisely from attention: ‘Vegan-feminism … comes with an insistence “Pay
attention!” Pay attention, now. The process of objectification/fragmentation/
consumption can be interrupted by the process of attention/nowness/compas-
sion’ (Adams 2018: n.p.).
4 Typically: there are also other modes of attention, as we shall see in the final
sections of Chapter 1.
5 On attention as bodily, and on this aspect not being explicitly embraced by
Murdoch, see also the conclusion of Cordner’s essay (2016).
6 My discussion on Murdoch’s anthropocentrism, it should be noted, is based
on her philosophy and not her novels, like the rest of this book. Some have
suggested that Murdoch’s novels are useful sources of environmental ethical
thinking (see e.g. Oulton 2020). But what I am interested in here is what we
can learn from her philosophy.
7 See also MGM 110, 372 and 377.
8 But then came to the conclusion that she is not quite.
9 As Murdoch writes, ‘A study of philosophy may be likened to a catharsis, like
that of the Zen Buddhist who begins with rivers and mountains, doubts rivers
and mountains, then returns to rivers and mountains’ (MGM 189).
Bibliography
Aaltola, E. (2018) Love and Animals: Simone Weil, Iris Murdoch and Attention
as Love. In: Martin, A. M. (ed.) The Routledge Handbook of Love in
Philosophy. London, Routledge, pp. 193–204.
Adams, C. (1990) The Sexual Politics of Meat: A Feminist-Vegetarian Critical
Theory. New York, Continuum.
Adams, C. (2018) Why Vegan-Feminist. Available at: caroljadams.com/why-
vegan-feminist [Accessed 5-11-2021].
Antonaccio, M. (2000) Picturing the Human: The Moral Thought of Iris
Murdoch. New York, Oxford University Press.
Bagnoli, C. (2012) The Exploration of the Moral Life. In: Broackes, J. (ed.) Iris
Murdoch, Philosopher. Oxford and New York, Oxford University Press,
pp. 197–226.
Bauman, Z. and Donskis, L. (2014) Moral Blindness: The Loss of Sensitivity in
Liquid Modernity. Cambridge, Polity.
Introduction 13
BBC (2020) Homelessness: Rough Sleeping Figures ‘Unacceptable’ Says Boris
Johnson. BBC News. 27 February 2020. Available at: https://www.bbc.com/
news/uk-england-51646254 [Accessed 9-11-2021].
Cavell, S. (1979) The Claim of Reason: Wittgenstein, Skepticism, Morality, and
Tragedy. New York, Oxford University Press.
Cordner, C. (2016) Lessons of Murdochian Attention. Sophia. 55: 197–213.
Diamond, C. (2008) The Difficulty of Reality and the Difficulty of Philosophy. In:
Cavell et al. (ed.) Philosophy and Animal Life. New York, Columbia University
Press, pp. 43–91.
Honneth, A. (2007) Reification: A Recognition-Theoretical View. Oxford and
New York, Oxford University Press.
Joko Beck, C. (1993) Nothing Special. San Francisco, HarperSanFrancisco.
Kearney, R. (2021) Touch: Recovering our Most Vital Sense. New York, Columbia
University Press.
Kramer E. and Hsieh E. (2019) Gaze as Embodied Ethics: Homelessness, the Other,
and Humanity. In: Dutta M. and Zapata D. (eds.) Communicating for Social
Change: Meaning, Power, and Resistance. Singapore, Palgrave Macmillan,
pp. 33–62.
Mentock, A. (n.d.) Why I Always Look Homeless People in the Eye. Grotto.
Available at: https://grottonetwork.com/make-an-impact/heal/how-to-help-
the-homeless-by-making-eye-contact/ [Accessed 2-11-2021].
Murdoch, I. (1992) Metaphysics as a Guide to Morals [MGM]. London, Penguin.
Murdoch, I. (1998) In: Peter, Conradi (ed.) Existentialists and Mystics: Writings
on Philosophy and Literature. Harmondsworth, Penguin.
———, The Idea of Perfection [IP], pp. 299–336.
———, On ‘God’ and ‘Good’ [OGG], pp. 337–365.
Oberauer, K. (2019). Working Memory and Attention: A Conceptual Analysis
and Review. Journal of Cognition. 2 (1), 36.
Oulton, L. (2020) Loving by Instinct: Environmental Ethics in Iris Murdoch’s The
Sovereignty of Good and Nuns and Soldiers. Études britanniques contempo-
raines. 59 [Online]. https://doi.org/10.4000/ebc.10237
Roberts, J. (2013) The Power of Patience: Teaching Students the Value of
Deceleration and Immersive Attention. Harvard Magazine. Available from: http://
harvardmagazine.com/2013/11/the-power-of-patience [Accessed 1-10-2020].
Robjant, D. (2011) As a Buddhist Christian: The Misappropriation of Iris
Murdoch. Heythrop Journal. 52 (6), 993–1008.
Smith, M. (2011) Against Ecological Sovereignty: Ethics, Biopolitics, and Saving
the Natural World. Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press.
Thanissaro, Bhikkhu (2006) Untangling the Present: The Role of Appropriate
Attention. Dhammatalks. Available at: https://www.dhammatalks.org/books/
PurityOfHeart/Section0006.html [Accessed 1-12-2021].
Watzl, S. (2017) Structuring Mind: The Nature of Attention and How it Shapes
Consciousness. Oxford, Oxford University Press.
Wu, T. (2016) The Attention Merchants. New York, Alfred A. Knopf.
1 What is ethical about attention?
You may find it intuitively true that attention is important for morality. If
you have been immersed in Simone Weil’s world, or in Iris Murdoch’s, my
task of explaining why it is so will start from some common ground, and
the difficulties will lie in the specific reasons. But you may also find that
your understanding of what attention is, your experience of paying atten-
tion, has little to do with morality—with goodness or responsibility or
moral error.
We can say: we attend to a ladybird who has landed on our hand; we
attend with satisfaction to the embarrassing faux pas of someone who
had offended us; we attend to how our lower back feels as we lift a table
while helping a friend move; we attend to the betrayals and reconcilia-
tions of the characters in the soap opera on TV. These are all ordinary
uses of the verb ‘to attend’, some of them signalling a vicious activity,
others a morally neutral one. We can attend in so many ways, to so many
things. So what’s attention got to do with morality?
This is the kind of response I received as I attempted to explain the
topic of my book to friends and family. It represents an important
reminder that ordinarily we do not often think about attention as mor-
ally significant, and that the word ‘attention’, in noun, verb, or adverbial
form, is not generally used in ordinary language to convey something that
we find morally relevant.1
For this reason, some of the (few) contemporary philosophical defences
of the moral importance of attention have chosen to qualify attention.
Dorothea Debus (2015), for instance, finds value in what she calls ‘full
attention’, rather than attention tout court.2 This may appear to be a
strategy that the main philosophical proponent of the moral value of
attention, Iris Murdoch, also employs. So does Murdoch’s source for the
moral idea of attention, Simone Weil, who takes attention to have not
only a moral but primarily a metaphysical and religious value.
There are indeed passages in both Murdoch and Weil where the idea of
morally good attention is presented as attention which is qualified in
some way. For instance, in ‘The Idea of Perfection’ Murdoch writes that
DOI: 10.4324/9781003164852-2
What is ethical about attention? 15
‘Virtue is au fond the same in the artist as in the good man in that it is a
selfless attention to nature’ (IP 332), and elsewhere she talks about ‘just
attention’ and ‘respectful and loving attention’ (MGM 377). Weil, on her
part, offers a beautiful string of adjectives when describing ‘the sort of
attention which can attend to truth and to affliction’: it is an attention
that is ‘intense, pure, disinterested, gratuitous, generous’ and that is iden-
tified with love (HP 91–2); while in ‘Reflections on the Right Use of
School Studies’ she writes about ‘the highest part of the attention’ being
that which ‘makes contact with God’ (RSS 105).
So the first question arises: is there a specific form of attention—‘moral
attention’—which is morally relevant? Or, instead, are we ordinarily
blind to some important aspects of attention and their ramifications into
what we consider moral?
I think the latter is closer to the truth. There is a moral relevance—
sometimes obvious, more often subtle, even invisible—that is present
when we engage in what we ordinarily understand to be attention. One
fundamental aspect of attention which makes it morally relevant, indeed
morally good, is truth-seeking. While this element is not always consid-
ered to be present in all instances of what we call attention, it can be
revealed to be there. We attend because we want to find out. There is
something we don’t know. Our attention is captured by something that is
salient, that needs to be known. As Jonardon Ganeri (2017) puts it, dis-
cussing the work of Brian O’Shaughnessy (2002), attention is what makes
consciousness into a ‘reality-detector’ (Ganeri 2017: 10). Attentive
engagement with reality, whatever its other aims or mood or contexts,
seeks to discover something. Attention interrogates reality, it is stretched
in the direction of—a ‘tension towards’—reality. That is why Murdoch,
out of the various contrasts to attention one can draw (and, as we shall
see, there are several), mostly contrasts attention with fantasy: a form of
consciousness that projects, absorbs, or is uninterested in what is really
the case. Of course, paying attention may not be sufficient for discovering
what is true, and we may get things wrong despite our efforts. But atten-
tion’s aim is reality.3
It also matters what we attend to, in so many ways. Ignoring some-
thing or someone can harm. Attending to something or someone will
focus our care and actions on them, to the exclusion of other objects. Our
habitual objects of attention frame our world and interests around them.
And so on. The presence of attention (as truth-seeking) and its objects
will be the two ‘axes’ around which, in this chapter, I propose to analyse
the moral importance of attention. A ‘vertical’ axis and a ‘horizontal’ axis
respectively.
In what follows I aim to bring out the moral relevance of attention
compatibly, to a large extent, with how we ordinarily talk about it, but
also with psychological and other philosophical formulations beyond
16 What is ethical about attention?
ethics—although I draw implications that go beyond such uses. The con-
cept of attention under scrutiny mainly comes from Murdoch, and sec-
ondly from Weil. So do the ways I suggest the concept is expanded and
refined. Perhaps radically, I propose that attention thus understood is not
only morally relevant, but that it is morally good, and even that it is
fundamental to morality.
Such emphasis on the mostly invisible origin of all moral thought and
action struck a chord in Murdoch, who found an ally in her struggle
against contemporary English philosophy, as evident in her review of
Weil’s Notebooks:
I have used the word ‘attention’, which I borrow from Simone Weil,
to express the idea of a just and loving gaze directed upon an indi-
vidual reality. I believe this to be the characteristic and proper mark
of the active moral agent.
(IP 327)
Attention both characterises the active moral agent and it is the proper
and desirable feature of such agent. Attention is descriptive and norma-
tive. In cruder terms: good people are attentive; and those aspiring to
goodness should aim for greater attention.
But attention also has a meta-ethical role. It is introduced in that essay,
with the story of the mother-in-law ‘M’ overcoming prejudice and obtain-
ing a renewed and more truthful vision of her daughter-in-law ‘D’. The
story aims to show what the moral work is like for the individual, in the
context of an essay that raises doubts about the contemporary model of the
moral agent in Anglophone philosophy, in which all that seems to matter is
action and choice. Thinking about the moral relevance of attention,
Murdoch is here suggesting, helps not only the private individual but the
philosopher in her task of understanding where the knots of morality lie.
For Murdoch, they lie first and foremost in how we see the world and what
we see. Such a vision depends to a significant extent on the presence of
absence, and on the objects, of attention. These thoughts return in MGM,
through extended discussions of how a moral ‘world’ is shaped.
In ‘On God and Good’ attention takes centre stage as the proper atti-
tude to the good, developed based on the idea of God. Both are not just
occasional ‘objects of attention’, but they are defined through that role.
Here, as Murdoch writes, her debt to Simone Weil is evident. Acts of
attention reveal an aspiration to something ‘higher’, and in turn what is
absolute shows its existence in human life through attention.8 Attention
here is seen as crucial for morality because it reveals that there is some-
thing beyond ourselves (the whole world) which is always and necessarily
beyond us (Murdoch’s idea of the ‘transcendent’) because our capacity to
grasp reality is constantly perfectible. The realisation of this fact through
attention causes elation and provides a sense of direction, for we learn
that we can see better, more, more clearly, ad infinitum. Hence, attention
to God/Good is morally important because of the way it shapes, guides,
and inspires us (particularly at a time—which is also ours—where,
Murdoch felt, the empiricist idea that ‘this is all there is’ has been unduly
What is ethical about attention? 19
extended to discourage any search for what is invisible or not-yet-visible).
Attention in this sense is called a ‘technique’ which Murdoch, again fol-
lowing Weil, equates to prayer. Its effects are ‘the purification and reori-
entation of an energy which is naturally selfish’ (OGG 344). So attention
to God or to the good, for Murdoch, is not attention to a ‘thing’, but the
revelation of a distant (never clearly known) idea which both guides us in
all our encounters with the world, and changes us the more we are guided
by it. It is the Platonic Idea of the Good. (I will return to this in the section
‘The horizontal axis’ below.)
Murdoch’s Platonism, too, was influenced by Weil. For both, the idea
of the good as guiding light always ‘somewhere beyond’ (SGC 376) is a
moral but also a mystical one, although in a special sense for Murdoch.
There is something we intuit but cannot fully grasp, yet it transforms us
completely. An experience of the good is a periagoge, a turning around.
Weil reads Plato as a mystic (SA 70), and one of Murdoch’s central efforts
is to reintroduce mysticism into morality along the lines just sketched:
‘The background to morals is properly some sort of mysticism, if by this
is meant a non-dogmatic essentially unformulated faith in the reality of
the good, occasionally connected with experience’ (OGG 360).9 As this
quote suggests, Murdoch’s mysticism is not that of religious believers,
and it is also not quite Weil’s. Murdoch proposes a secular morality,
rejecting the idea of a personal God, and rejecting religion. Weil’s thought,
on the other hand, is grounded on a religious metaphysics. This has con-
sequences for the idea of attention. The first is that attention to reality is,
for Weil, attention to a world that was created by God. Practically, this
comes with an acceptance, indeed a love of the whole of reality, which is
easier to understand if everything bears the mark of divinity. Murdoch,
who did not believe in such a God-created world, had to move along dif-
ferent, sometimes metaphorical, paths. Second, without Weil’s metaphysi-
cal view of the world as created by God through self-withdrawal, where
human will is interference and its renunciation an imitation of God,
Murdoch’s idea of unselfing also becomes different from Weil’s idea of
decreation—despite being both concomitants of attention. When I attend,
the object fills my consciousness, and I am not there. This can ring true
for both. But the extent and exact meaning of such self-withdrawal differ
in Murdoch and Weil, with implications for how we think about atten-
tion. (I explore this difference in Chapters 2 and 3.)
The upshot is that, although Weil’s religious attention has an ethical
dimension, and although Murdoch’s secular attention has religious inspi-
rations, the large overlapping between their concepts of attention also
contains differences. Unfortunately for my project, it is on the back-
ground of Weil’s philosophy that the normativity of attention can be
explained more straightforwardly. If God created the world, then it
deserves our attention; then everything deserves our attention, indeed our
love; then we will act in accordance to the order of the world; and finally,
20 What is ethical about attention?
then our attention will imply a self-renunciation as an imitation of God
and an act of love, conforming our will to God’s.
Based on Murdoch’s secular philosophy, the necessity of attention is
more difficult to ground. Human life, Murdoch writes, ‘has no external
point or τελoς’ (SGC 364). This goes together with her stress on the chanc-
iness and messiness of life, and attention is no exception. There are revela-
tions, but there is mostly an ordinary, piecemeal effort. All this makes it
harder to explain why, as I argue, we ought to try to pay attention, and why
as philosophers we should re-consider the moral grounding of thoughts,
acts, and situations, and explore how they arise from attention, or the lack
thereof. But it is also what makes it worthwhile to attempt to clarify and
justify the great importance of attention for those who, like Murdoch, live
in a world without a personal, omnipotent, creator God.
Selectivity
One of the key questions asked in psychology refers to the ways in which
attention relates to information processing. Since there is a necessary
selectivity in what information we are conscious of, attention is used to
explain such selectivity. The mechanisms responsible for the selectivity of
attention have been central to the debate. For a long time, Donald
Broadbent’s (1958) model was the most influential one, according to
which attention depends on capacity limitations of the brain, which form
a ‘bottleneck’ through which selection occurs. Developments of this the-
ory include the suggestion that there is not a single bottleneck, but that
selectivity depends on various limitations occurring in different channels.
This model has been influentially criticised by Alan Allport (1993), who
argues that attention is not concerned with the limitation of processing
capacities, but rather it is a state of the whole organism which addresses
the necessity to integrate information, given our capacity to represent
more information than is needed. Allport’s positive suggestion (1987),
also put forth by Odmar Neumann (1987), is that attention is what
enables us to act coherently in a goal-directed way. This is the ‘selection
for action’ theory, developed in philosophy by Wayne Wu (2011), who
goes further and identifies attention and selection for action. Regardless
of the specific theory of attention, it is clear that selectivity is a central, if
not the central, feature of attention as researched in psychology, as well
as in some philosophical studies. The selectivity of attention is ethically
relevant, as we shall see, concerning the objects of attention (the horizon-
tal axis).
22 What is ethical about attention?
The faculties of attention
In the psychological literature, attention is often studied as visual or audi-
tory attention, and more generally as a perceptual phenomenon. But, as
Sebastian Watzl (2017) writes, we can also talk about varieties of atten-
tion depending on more than perception. Wu, as we have seen, broadens
attention beyond perception to agency. While according to Watzl, atten-
tion is a way of organising the mind, so that
If we use the word ‘attention’ in such a way that all conscious states
involve attention to some degree, even those idle, tuned-out states
that we naturally describe as instances of inattention, then we lose
our grip on the selectivity and directedness that our preliminary char-
acterization of attention took to be of its essence.
(2011: 7)
Niklas Forsberg quotes this passage writing that ‘The “work of atten-
tion” is something that goes one continuously and it is not something
that can be, as it were, “switched off”’ (2013: 145) and then continues:
‘The “in between” [between moments of overt choice] is out of our con-
trol’ (146). This seems to suggest that attention is constant, and we have
What is ethical about attention? 31
no control over it. Both thoughts are problematic. In the section above,
we saw the problem with the latter.18 As for the omnipresence of atten-
tion, we would misunderstand Murdoch if we took her to mean that
attention is constantly at work. Its work is constant only if we read it as
‘task’ (as Murdoch elsewhere refers to attention): if every act of cognition
matters, then at every moment attention is at stake. But attention itself is
not constant, and it is in fact ‘off’ a lot of the time. Indeed, the ‘natural’
human state, for Murdoch, is one of inattention (fantasy), so switching
on the lights is the rare gift we should aspire to.
What does go on all the time—and can be mistaken for attention—is
the evaluative activity of consciousness. It is conceivable that readings of
Murdochian attention as constantly occurring result from taking the
attentive aspect of consciousness for the whole. It is central to Murdoch’s
moral psychology that our encounter with the world is always evaluative.
Whether or not we attend is part of such evaluative encounter: ‘one can-
not “philosophise” adequately upon the subject unless one takes it as
fundamental that consciousness is a form of moral activity: what we
attend to, how we attend, whether we attend’ (MGM 167, emphasis
added) and ‘We are all the time building up our value world and exercis-
ing, or failing to exercise, our sense of truth in the daily hourly minutely
business of apprehending, or failing to apprehend, what is real and distin-
guishing it from illusion’ (MGM 304). What cannot be ‘switched off’, as
Murdoch writes, is not attention, but ‘the moral life’ (IP 329).
If we are always in some sense morally active, succeeding or failing in
grasping what is real, then this form of omnipresence is exactly what
gives attention its importance. And that is also why we need to be able to
differentiate between lazy, biased, self-involved, inattentive states—and
attention:
I would like on the whole to use the word ‘attention’ as a good word
and use some more general term like ‘looking’ as the neutral word. …
Attention is the effort to counteract such states of illusion.
(IP 329)
It remains Plato’s (surely correct) view that the bad (or mediocre)
man is in a state of illusion … The instructed and morally purified
What is ethical about attention? 35
mind sees reality clearly and indeed (in an important sense) provides
us with the concept. The original role of the Forms was not to lead us
to some attenuated elsewhere but to show us the real world. It is the
dreamer in the cave who is astray and elsewhere.
(F&S 426–427)
There are at least two reasons why the truth-seeking of attention, and its
(degrees of) success, are good. One is that it brings us closer to reality.
The other is that such closeness is possible by removing the impediments
that, according to Murdoch, come from self-concern. These are, I suggest,
the two faces of attention: eros (joining) and unselfing (letting be). These
two aspects are interdependent: when we seek truth, our self recedes;
when our self recedes, attention can disclose truth. Reality and unselfing,
united in attention, are the instruments of moral change: ‘Moral change
comes from an attention to the world whose natural result is a decrease
in egoism through an increased sense of the reality of, primarily of course
other people, but also other things’ (MGM 52).20 Let’s look at each ‘face’
of attention in turn.
Attention helps us ‘join’ the world, which we already inhabit in the first
place, but which we escape all the time by distraction, denial, fantasy. An
inattentive mind, in this sense, is lonely. An attentive mind, which seeks
the real, is not always happy, but is, in a deep sense, joyful.21 Attention
removes a sense of separation of self and world, either by removing a
sense of self (Chapter 3), or more simply by removing illusions (Chapter
2). Attention, Murdoch tells us, is a way of knowing the world which is
engaged and imaginative, where imagination is not ‘making things up’,
but rather not stopping at the surface of things:
We use our imagination not to escape the world but to join it, and
this exhilarates us because of the distance between our ordinary
dulled consciousness and an apprehension of the real. … The author-
ity of morals is the authority of truth, that is of reality.
(SGC 374)
If I have been contemplating the stove, and then am told: but now all
you know is the stove, my result does indeed seem trivial. For this
represents the matter as if I had studied the stove as one among the
36 What is ethical about attention?
many things in the world. But if I was contemplating the stove it was
my world, and everything else colourless by contrast with it …
(Wittgenstein, Notebooks 1914–1916, 7, 8, 9 October 1916).
(MGM 26–7)
Debus also notes this reason for finding value in attention: ‘someone who
gives something her full attention gains … a heightened sense of reality,
and an increased openness to the object she attends to, and by extension
an increased openness to the world’. This is valuable because, Debus
writes, it is ‘very fulfilling’ (Debus 2013: 1179). But that is not where its
central value lies. Such openness does not always need to give rise to posi-
tive emotions. The breaking down of the self’s barrier, pleasurable or not,
is the main point here.
Finally, when attention is shared with another (‘joint attention’), the
potential of attention to let our consciousness come closer to reality also
has intersubjective implications. These are drawn particularly by Merleau-
Ponty, who claims that perception shows us a world that is shared: it is
attending to the same reality that shows us that there is, indeed, a reality
which is there for both of us. Antony Fredriksson develops this thought,
stressing the way in which ‘embodied orientations’ enable us to share
attention with other embodied beings, human or non-human. This shared
world revealed by attention, in turn, provides us with an immediate expe-
rience that runs against the claims of solipsism and relativism (Fredriksson
forthcoming: Chapter 4).
It remains Plato’s (surely correct) view that the bad (or mediocre)
man is in a state of illusion, of which egoism is the most general
name, though particular cases would of course suggest more detailed
descriptions. Obsession, prejudice, envy, anxiety, ignorance, greed,
neurosis, and so on and so on veil reality.
(F&S 426)
all just vision … is a moral matter … the same virtue (love) [is]
required throughout and fantasy (self) can prevent us from seeing a
blade of grass just as it can prevent us from seeing another person.
(OGG 357)
Beauty attracts the attention and yet does nothing to sustain it.
Beauty always promises, but never gives anything. There is nothing
to be desired, because the one thing we want is that it should not
change … if one does not seek means to evade the exquisite anguish
it inflicts, then desire is gradually transformed into love and one
begins to acquire the faculty of pure and disinterested attention.
(HP 28–9)
Beauty may be sui generis. The sensibility of the artist does not, for most
of us, represent a good model of knowledge or truthfulness. But even in
38 What is ethical about attention?
learning mathematics something similar needs to occur: we must recog-
nise a reality that is independent of our desires, keep our attention fixed
on it, and desire to see it for what it is.22
That is unselfing: the recognition of a reality that is not ours to distort,
even if only in imagination. That is why eros and unselfing go together in
attention. A non-attached desire for truth comes with a giving up of our
claims on it:
The man was no longer just a ‘murderer’ but a ‘complicated’ and even
‘caring’ young man. It matters that this change came after an apology.
One could say that the apology changed the facts, and that the person
who was forgiven was no longer, in a relevant sense, the same who per-
petrated the crime. But for Mangi it very much was. What she came to
consider was that the man was more than a killer, not something else. It
may also matter that Hamelmann was a Christian. Yet, in the letters he
received he was told that ‘Your intention has nothing to do with
Christianity’. Perhaps it matters that some of these people, like Candice
Mama, were moved by the desire to feel better. But that does not change
that she could see something else in her father’s killer: real liberation does
not come from sham forgiveness. What these (I think extraordinary)
people were able to do was to see the killers, in a compassionate but non-
sentimental way, as the individuals they were. Candice Mama describes
learning about the story of her father’s killer thus:
It almost forces you to step into their shoes for a little bit and say,
‘You know what, if I had been dealt this pair of cards, if I had been
raised by a militant father in a militant family, went to police acad-
emy, lived in an environment that told me that this was the enemy
and this is what’s right, and then I went on to be celebrated by my
friends, by my peer groups for being the best at what I do … I mean,
would I have turned out any different?’
(Wallis 2020: n.p.)
Attention as gift
These cases also show, perhaps too starkly, that attention also has value
for those who receive it. One is transformed by attending, but one is also
transformed by being the receiver of attention. The examples above,
however, can mislead into thinking that being attended to is good only
because it can lead to resolution, to forgiveness, to a new relationship.
What I want to say is more minimal and fundamental: attention is valu-
able for those who receive it because it amounts to acknowledging their
reality. That, as we have seen, requires a withdrawal of self-interest. In
that sense, attention is a gift. We confer value simply by attending. But
that requires that we see the value as already there. Weil’s description of
attention to the afflicted makes this point particularly clear. (I discuss it
further in Chapter 5.) In a letter to the poet Joë Bousquet, Weil writes that
attention is ‘the rarest and purest form of generosity. It is given to very
few minds to notice that things and beings exist’.25 Acknowledging
another’s reality is not natural, and requires attention (love and unself-
ing). A thought apparently absurd but utterly important, echoed by
Murdoch: ‘love is the extremely difficult realization that something other
than oneself is real’ (SBL 215).
Attention does not land on something we have no interest in. If our
sense of ourselves depends on others, receiving attention is necessary. But
more subtly, attention can have the value of acknowledgement even if the
object does not know about it. This is shown in practices such as holding
moments of silence for victims of oppressive regimes, or in the practice of
‘bearing witness’ to animals being killed, outside slaughterhouses.
Attention says: this is real, this deserves to be seen or known—and even
‘I am here’ to those who cannot hear it.
Substituting God for the Good, these possibilities are also present in Weil.
To this list, I add ‘good things’ and ‘what is present’, suggested by
Murdoch, and things for which we are directly responsible, a plausible
candidate but not suggested by Murdoch or Weil.
The good
Let us start with the good. The good as an object of attention is sug-
gested, after all, frequently by Murdoch, and throughout the whole essay
‘On God and Good’;33 Weil, too, tells us we should attend to something
perfect and transcendent, but for her that is God. But: God, for Weil, is
absent34; and for Murdoch, the good is not an object in the world, it is
only dimly perceptible in mostly mediated ways, it is indefinable, and we
may be completely wrong about its nature even when, perhaps especially
when, we think we’ve got it. That is our object of attention. One may feel
like replying: Thanks for nothing.
Except that attending to the good, or to God, is not like attending to
some object which, however, we cannot perceive. Nor is it attending
solely to something beyond, ignoring this world and what it contains,
which attention to the good as some kind of object would entail. This
possibility forms the basis for the objection famously raised by Gregory
Vlastos (1973) to Plato, and by others such as Martha Nussbaum (1996)
to Murdoch, or Peta Bowden (1998) to Murdoch and Weil: that attention
to the good bypasses the individual or uses them or it in order to get to
what really matters—the ideal.35 But that is not what attention to the
good, or God, is for either Weil or Murdoch. In fact, Murdoch writes, ‘the
direction of attention is … towards the great surprising variety of the
world, and the ability so to direct attention is love’ (SG 66). And, perhaps
more surprisingly, here is Weil:
We can attend to the good (or God), but such attention is different from
attention to any particular object, and it is not in competition with it:
instead, attention to the good is attention to reality, for that is the only
place in which the good manifests itself, it is where we learn about it.36 To
‘really see’ something or someone, or to see them lovingly (where love is
eros: desire for the good) amounts to this: seeing them through the good.
We might equally say that for Murdoch we are using the good in order to
get to the real. But that, too, would miss the closeness of the two. Look,
for instance, at someone with attention. After a little while, what you see
will be transformed, you may feel the joy and excitement that comes with
discovery, that you are making progress in understanding or vision, that
there is something familiar yet awe inspiring in that hand gesture or even
the pin in their hair. This is attention to reality and to the good together.
As the good is not an object, there is no other way to attend to it.
So Mark Hopwood is quite right when he writes that ‘on Murdoch’s
view, eros has two objects: the particular individual and the good … We
love particular individuals in the light of the good, and we love the good
through particular individuals’ (2017: 486).37 This is the idea of the good
as ‘incarnate’, in an ordinary way. In a beautiful piece, Janet Soskice
(1992) has shown how theologians can apply this idea, and find God not
only in monasteries and retreats, but changing diapers and cooking soup
for screaming children (MGM 460: ‘St Paul said we find God everywhere
in the world’). This world is not a passing place on the path to a more
fulfilling one, it is where spiritual insight can be found. Love, inspiring
attention, ‘joins us to Good and joins us to the world through the Good’
(SGC 384, emphasis added).
Good things
The good which inspires our attention is, according to Murdoch, discov-
ered thanks to the experience of its presence in the world. There are good
things that inspire us, and show us intimation of something better. Would
those be a more proper object of attention? Insofar as they help us, show
us the way, embody a model, yes: Murdoch writes that it is a ‘psychologi-
cal fact … that we receive moral help by focusing on valuable things’ and
quotes St. Paul: ‘whatsoever things are just, whatsoever things are pure,
whatsoever things are lovely, whatsoever things are of good report; if
there be any virtue, and if there be any praise, think on these things’
(OGG 345). The quote recurs in MGM, where Murdoch comments:
‘These “things” which are just and good assist our attention when we try
to make just and compassionate judgments of others or to judge and cor-
rect ourselves’ (MGM 301). Attending to Philip may fill my mind with
goodness, and perhaps remind me of how to be better when I need it.
This may be true, as Murdoch writes, if we consider our habitual
objects of attention (OGG 345): objects shape our consciousness more
deeply, the more we attend to them. But even so, what is good cannot
have privileged claim to attention. Attention needs to encompass more
than goodness, because clear perception of reality includes things that are
not good. In fact, difficulties and suffering and all sorts of things that
have little goodness in them are in many cases what merits attention most
urgently.38 It is true that one needs to have learnt, and continue to learn,
to distinguish what is good from what is not and in what degree, through
a constant and renewed sense of what the good involves. But what the
good does is to help to apprehend clearly a multifarious, often flawed,
reality.
What is ethical about attention? 47
Beauty
Something similar can be said of beauty. In nature (the autumn trees) or
in art, beauty is for Murdoch both an image of goodness and a proper
way in. In this too she follows Weil, and her idea that beauty is special,
because it arouses desire without possessiveness—a necessary element of
attention. Murdoch writes:
Beauty attracts the attention and yet does nothing to sustain it.
Beauty always promises, but never gives anything. There is nothing
to be desired, because the one thing we want is that it should not
change … if one does not seek means to evade the exquisite anguish
it inflicts, then desire is gradually transformed into love and one
begins to acquire the faculty of pure and disinterested attention.
(HP 28–9)
And yet like good things, beautiful things cannot override other possible
objects of attention, because attention is not only directed to what is
valuable, but to what is salient—to what needs our attention. And that,
sometimes, is not so good: climate change, animal (human or non-human)
suffering, and so on. Murdoch acknowledges this:
Art, though it demands moral effort and teaches quiet attention (as
any serious study can do) is a kind of treat … we have to make moral
choices, we do not have to enjoy great art and doubtless many good
people never do.
(FS 453–4)
Other people
What about ‘other people’, the first candidate for being an especially apt
object of contemplation mentioned by Chappell (2015) above? It is a fact
that Murdoch often returns to the importance of other people, and places
the moral importance of people above art (FS 417). So it is tempting to
think that, in my walk, I am being selfish if I am focused on my problem,
or on the leaves, or on the squirrel, and not on my grandmother. But what
48 What is ethical about attention?
makes the suggestion plausible, I think, is not her humanity. It is, on the
one hand, the fact that she is unwell, and needs support. And on the other,
the fact that we have a relationship, that she may rely on me, or that I
may have a special role in cheering her up. It is not, therefore, the human-
ity that is primary here, for we do not need to take for granted that it is
only another human who can have such needs and expectations from me.
Murdoch often just assumes that, other things being equal, other people
are more morally important than other objects: ‘Moral change comes
from an attention to the world whose natural result is a decrease in ego-
ism through an increased sense of the reality of, primarily of course other
people, but also other things’ (MGM 52).39 ‘Of course’? Helpfully, here
Murdoch also shows an awareness that ‘other things’ too can be morally
salient.40
Responsibility
In the previous section, I have indicated a form of responsibility that can
also be connected with the priorities of attention: the idea that by attend-
ing to my grandmother I may be motivated to call her, and therefore
cause her to feel better for a few moments. The possibility, then, is that
attention should prioritise that which we are responsible for, such as, and
most obviously, that which we can causally influence for better or worse.
Something ‘needs’ our attention, something that ‘surrounds and concerns
us’ (MGM 218). In the story, this is also connected, less hypothetically,
with my leather shoes: am I responsible to attend to the animals whose
lives my choice of shoes has affected? That seems like a reasonable sug-
gestion. It seems true, in any case, that at some point soon (and before my
next purchase) I ought to attend to that. But is that what is most salient
now? Or are we always required to attend to what we can be responsible
for, to what we can help or hinder? A view of morality which requires one
primarily to attend to what one is causally linked to appears not only to
be overly demanding, but also to exclude much of what is experienced as
making life valuable and worthwhile: the contemplation of nature and
the red leaves on the pavement, but also of art, of what has nothing to do
with us, and of the little ‘pointless’ but interesting details of one’s
surroundings.
Presence
Finally, what about attention to the squirrel, not only because she is a
living being, or because she is beautiful, but mainly—the aspect I now
want to bring out—because she is here with me, now? The intuition that
what is present takes precedence on our attention over what is not pres-
ent is a common one. Think of the Samaritan: no one would say to him,
‘How biased you are, why did you help this man over here, and not
What is ethical about attention? 49
someone else, equally suffering, miles away?’ OK, somebody might,
there’s always someone. But the mere fact that the sufferer is here now
gives him a claim to the Samaritan’s attention, from which his actions
arise. Or let’s return to the person focused on the phone instead of us. We
think we have a claim to their attention because we are here with them.
Are we right? Murdoch seems to think so, and emphasises the impor-
tance of presence. Chapter 8 of MGM opens with a lyrical passage by
Walter Pater, exalting the joy and value of being fully present, suggesting
something that Murdoch believes philosophy has unduly neglected: the
importance of ‘presence and encounter’ (MGM 112): ‘living in the pres-
ent: I really see the face of my friend, the playing dog, Piero’s picture’
(MGM 301). Attention and presence are closely linked:
But we can in general see and appreciate the difference between anx-
ious calculating distracted passing of time when the present is never
really inhabited or filled, and present moments which are lived atten-
tively as truth and reality. In selfish obsessional calculation or resent-
ment we are ‘always elsewhere’.
(MGM 395–6)41
Diffuse attention
So, how do we know? If attention has, as I have been arguing, an impor-
tance that is both inherent and also related to our further thoughts and
actions, it seems far from irrelevant what we attend to, yet we have found
no way to choose between the objects that compete for our attention.
Most of the ‘objects’ considered have some claim to our attention—
variously due to their inherent value, our relationships to them, the con-
text they are in.
And it is precisely the contextual, particular, embodied nature of atten-
tion that makes it impossible to decide, once and for all, what we should
direct attention to. This is both because the possible objects of attention
depend on context, and because attention operates contextually.
Nonetheless, there is still something that attention itself can do to help
us here. Without resorting to universal principles, or before doing that,
attention can play a role in selecting its own objects. To understand how
that is possible, however, we need to return to the plurality of attention,
and make a new distinction: between focused and diffuse attention.
While Murdoch emphasises the individual as the proper object of
attention, her idea of attention to the good, as we have seen, opens the
way to a form of attention that is not only focused on the particular, but
also at the same time open and receptive to what is not yet individuated.
And while Weil also argues for the importance of attention to particulars,
in her view of attention we find more clearly the possibility that attention
takes an object that is not (yet) specified. In both philosophers, the idea
that attention can be open, empty, waiting, is linked to the ‘unselfing’
movement of attention, which here takes precedence over the directed, or
‘erotic’ movement. Taking a step back, we focus on nothing, and wait
until something happens. ‘Something is apprehended as there which is
not yet known. Then something comes; as we sometimes say from the
unconscious. It comes to us out of the dark of non-being, as a reward for
loving attention’ (MGM 505). This is not focusing, but it is attention.
What is ethical about attention? 51
This form of attention is known in psychology as diffuse or distributed
attention: defined by psychologist Alison Gopnik (2009) as ‘lantern’
attention, as opposed to the more traditional ‘spotlight’ metaphor, and
explained by Adrienne Prettyman (2014) as attending to the night sky as
a whole (rather than to any particular star or area). No particular object
or property is the object of our focus.
If we return to Weil’s well-known definition of attention in RSS, we
will see that this ‘diffuse attention’ is precisely the mode of attention that
she is describing:
Is it possible, then, that the answer to our walking question is that, before
finding its object, attention needs to be open, or diffuse? I think it is. In
fact, it is necessary, morally speaking, that attention starts broader, ‘wait-
ing’ for salience to be revealed. And it is a point that Weil and Murdoch
emphasise. This is why selectivity, included in many definitions of atten-
tion, is absent from my working definition offered above.
Indeed, it seems that even with what we would describe as focused
attention, the possibility of narrowing down further is present, so we
need to be receptive to the various salience of, say, my upset friend’s
demeanour, or her eyes, or her words—and maybe not her shoes. The
capacity to be thus receptive is where, I believe, attention comes closer to
being a virtue, a sort of phronesis, a disposition to allocate attention
according to salience at a given moment. Then, particular items will
become salient as possible objects of attention (or as ‘attentional affor-
dances’—see McClelland 2021) and others will not. What differentiates
the initial open attention from an inattentive or fantasy-ridden state is
that what will become salient is, in the first case, less likely to be deter-
mined by my hopes and desires (more ‘unselfed’).
The distinction between these two types of attention is particularly
clear in the context of two of the main types of Buddhist meditation. One
is ‘Focused Attention (FA) [which] entails the voluntary focusing of atten-
tion on a chosen object. The other style, Open Monitoring (OM) medita-
tion, involves non-reactive monitoring of the content of experience from
52 What is ethical about attention?
moment to moment’ (Lutz et al. 2008: 1). In Open Monitoring attention
is, as Weil puts it, ‘suspended’. Experience as well as neuropsychological
studies have shown that this kind of meditation can train the mind to be
less reactive, and it has been associated with less subjective control,
reduced ‘top-down control and local competition [among alternative
thoughts] and, thus, [it] leads to a broader distribution of potential
resources’ (Colzato et al. 2012: 5) which is necessary to be receptive to all
the potentially salient objects that, as Murdoch puts it, ‘demand’ and
‘deserve’ our attention.42 Moreover, in the same study OM has been
found to increase detachment from autobiographical memory (a form of
unselfing, we may say) which helped develop a non-judgemental, non-
reactive attitude. Attention can be trained. It’s no wonder Murdoch rec-
ommended teaching meditation to children (MGM 337).
Notes
1 With the exception of the adjective ‘attentive’ used to describe a person,
rather than specific actions.
2 Debus takes inspiration from Simone Weil in her defence of the value of
attention, and derives from Weil the claims that attention is both ‘sufficient’
and ‘necessary’ for an activity to have value. This reading is, as Debus admits,
questionable as an exegesis of Weil, but she comments that her argument does
not depend on its correctness (2015: 1174 and Endnote 3). The argument,
indeed, works despite of a reading of Weil which, in my view, departs from
Weil’s thought in two respects: first, Debus takes an adverbial view of atten-
tion—something that modifies an action—while Weil takes attention to be an
activity in its own right; hence, and second, attention cannot be something
that bestows value upon what we are doing, as Debus suggests, because for
Weil the act of attention is value discovering, and not something that can be
applied to any activity. The actualization of ‘the authentic and pure values’
(GG 120) are a consequence of the act of attention.
3 This characterisation of attention as truth seeking allows for voluntary or invol-
untary switchings of focused attention among different objects, compatibly with
Merleau-Ponty’s phenomenological understanding of attention as what creates a
‘field’ which allows for the movements of consciousness (2012: 31). Some
instances of what we ordinarily call ‘distraction’ are just movements of attention
56 What is ethical about attention?
to something else, rather than absence of attention, so they can retain the truth-
seeking value. What attention is not compatible with is intentional or knowing
distortion of reality.
4 My treatment of Weil’s idea of attention, especially its religious context, is
necessarily cursory. For further discussions, some particularly including the
religious dimension of attention, see Vetö (1994: Chapter 2), Cameron (2003),
von der Ruhr (2006: Chapter 2), Rozelle-Stone and Stone (2013: 102–112).
Here is a brief summary of the background to her idea: Weil sees the universe
as deterministic, dominated by the ‘necessity’ which was determined by God
in God’s withdrawal. This is the idea of Tzimtzum, which comes from Isaac
Luria’s Kabbalistic doctrine. The Hebrew word ‘Tzimtzum’ has the dual
meaning of ‘withdrawal’ and ‘concealment’, and refers to the idea that the
world exists as a result of the withdrawal of the only true reality, that is God.
Thus God is necessarily concealed from creation, which has the character of
negation. Human beings also partake of the necessity of God-created reality
except, Weil holds, for one spark of freedom: their autonomy to desire neces-
sity or not to desire it. Such desire of obedience is attention.
5 See ‘Forms of the Implicit Love of God’ in WG.
6 Other striking ideas that Murdoch inherits from Weil are: the idea that atten-
tion is prayer; the identification, in some places, of attention and love; the
attention to God and the good; the Platonic inspiration, also seen as mystical;
the idea that attention to beauty is the clearest and most accessible form of
defeated yet eros-like desire; the connection of attention with intellectual dis-
ciplines like mathematics or learning a language; the recommendation to
teach attention in schools.
7 Regarding Murdoch’s main Weilian heritage, Sissela Bok (2005) stresses obe-
dience, Sabina Lovibond (2011) attention and obedience, Kate Larson (2009)
love. These concepts are, as we shall see, closely tied together, so that these
differences are indeed a matter of emphasis.
8 An idea elaborated through St. Anselm’s Ontological Proof in MGM
Chapter 13.
9 See also this passage, where Murdoch connected mysticism with morality and
Plato’s cave: ‘Mystics of all kinds have usually known this and have attempted
by extremities of language to portray the nakedness and aloneness of Good, its
absolute for-nothingness. One might say that true morality is a sort of uneso-
teric mysticism, having its source in an austere and unconsoled love of the
Good. When Plato wants to explain Good he uses the image of the sun. The
moral pilgrim emerges from the cave and begins to see the real world in the
light of the sun, and last of all is able to look at the sun itself’ (SGC 375–6).
10 Above I quoted Weil’s idea that ‘the highest part of the attention only makes
contact with God’. Yet she also continues: ‘but the whole attention is turned
toward God’ (RSS 105, emphasis added).
11 The negotiation and re-negotiation of concepts is also, after all, part of ordi-
nary linguistic activities. ‘That’s not love!’ we can say to someone obsessively
scouring their spouse’s social media. My point is not to establish whether in this
case we would be right, but only that ordinary language is not a tyrant. And it
could not be: within it there are contradictions that a philosophical exploration
of attention would have to take seriously. Sebastian Watzl, making a stronger
claim, argues for our freedom to modify the ordinary concept of attention, if
exploration and reflection take us there, saying that ‘ordinary judgments about
attention … are not sacrosanct’ (2017: 9). He also comments: ‘ordinary under-
standing is both subtly influenced by popular science and often draws on intro-
spection of the first-person case’ (2017: 9). Murdoch herself gives us similar
reasons to take seriously but not entirely bow to ordinary language, observing
that politics and cultural climate influence the concepts we have.
What is ethical about attention? 57
12 This idea is in harmony with Watzl’s account of attention as subject-level
phenomenon, as opposed to a subpersonal state, property, or process (2017:
33–37). This understanding allows for a phenomenological account of atten-
tion. Moreover, unlike ‘personal level’, the subject-level allows for an account
of attention that includes other animals (34).
13 Cf. also OGG 354.
14 Even ‘deliberately falling out of love’, in Murdoch’s example, ‘is not a jump of
the will, it is the acquiring of new objects of attention and thus of new ener-
gies as a result of refocusing’ (OGG 345).
15 ‘Imagining is a doing’ (DPR 199).
16 See Murdoch’s famous ‘kestrel’ example in SGC 369.
17 Mole defends the agency involved in attention through a similar example:
one’s attention being ‘caught involuntarily by a sudden sound at the window’.
But he considers it a genuine case of attention only ‘If the way in which that
episode of looking to the window unfolds is guided by one’s understanding of
what it is that one is doing in looking to the window’ (2011: 53). What
Murdoch is suggesting with the kestrel story, instead, has no such restriction.
In fact, it is precisely when attention is not so consciously guided, for
Murdoch, that it bears its truth-revealing and unselfing fruits.
18 Indeed, Murdoch writes about fantasy, even more clearly: ‘the ego is indeed
unbridled. Continuous control is required’ (MGM 260).
19 See also Watzl, although relating to more overt forms of intentionality: ‘What
makes watching something different from looking at it is the aim or goal a
subject has while attending: you are watching something when you are visually
attending to it with the aim of knowing what that thing is doing’ (2017: 45).
20 As explained in the introduction, I question that ‘of course’, but that’s not the
main point here.
21 See RSS 110.
22 See RSS.
23 See Chapter 5.
24 On the vulnerability of attention, see also Laverty 2007: 100.
25 Letter, 13 April 1942, in Pétrement 1988: 462.
26 See e.g. OGG 353: ‘True vision occasions right conduct …’ and MGM 39:
‘reality emerges as the object of truthful vision, and virtuous action as the
product of such vision’.
27 See also this passage where Murdoch, reading Plato, is not shy of moralising the
objects of consciousness: ‘each subject has the object he deserves’ (MGM 167).
28 Watzl goes further than we need to go here, and defines attention in terms of
its role in structuring consciousness around specific objects. Murdoch’s and
Weil’s definition of attention, as we have seen and shall see, includes other
elements that are not fully concordant with this definition—that is why I left
‘selectivity’ out of my working definition earlier in this chapter. But this does
not imply that for them attention is never selective nor that selectivity is mor-
ally unimportant.
29 On attention as configuring consciousness in phenomenology, see also
Merleau-Ponty (2012: Chapters 3–4), and Aron Gurwitsch (1964).
30 It is our mental states, not the objects themselves, for Watzl, that thus organ-
ise attention: visually attending to a leaf means prioritising our seeing of the
leaf in our field of consciousness. The same goes with intellectual attention,
where attending to a particular thought structures consciousness around it.
This point could be at odds with Murdoch’s view, where attention is not
reflexive. But Watzl is not arguing that attention is directed at mental states,
only that mental states are what is made salient. This could still be a problem,
particularly for Weil. Nonetheless, regardless of this distinction, the point on
relative salience and structuring of consciousness holds.
58 What is ethical about attention?
31 See also James: ‘My experience is what I agree to attend to. Only those items
which I notice shape my mind’ (1890, v.1: 402).
32 Chappell here uses the word ‘contemplation’ but for the purposes of this
discussion it can be interchangeable with attention, which Chappell includes
as a more generic form of contemplation (2015: 300).
33 And it is part of the definition of both the good and God as a ‘a single, perfect,
transcendent, non-representable, necessarily real object of attention’ (OGG 344).
34 Albeit manifest precisely through such absence.
35 Bowden praises Martha Nussbaum for being able to do justice to the embodied
and particularistic kind of attention, the ‘central presence of unique human per-
sons’, that, according to him, is missing in both Murdoch and Weil, who instead
‘focus on the transcendent potential in particular attachments’ (1998: 67).
36 With due differences, which I do not have the space to spell out here. Primarily,
while Murdoch’s Good is real only as an idea, or Idea, Weil’s God has a more
substantial ontology, and her idea of attention is more frequently, though not
always, of something devoted only to God and away from the world.
37 Chappell defends both Murdoch and Plato on similar grounds (2015: 319).
38 See Chapters 5 and 6, for instance, on the importance of attending to suffer-
ing and affliction.
39 See also SBR 282, and AIN 257: ‘Other people are … the most interesting
features of our world …’.
40 See also: ‘the view which I suggest … connects morality with attention to
individuals, human individuals or individual realities of other kinds’ (IP 329).
41 See also, with reference to Weil: ‘Some or much of the time when we are
“aware” we do not have any vivid sense of presentness. Simone Weil expressed
her wish for a lively present by saying that she wanted to be able to perceive
without reverie. An inability to be fully present is something which we often
feel’ (MGM 212).
42 Interestingly, given Murdoch’s focus on art as a model and mode of goodness
and attention, Bence Nanay (2016: Chapter 2) has argued that diffuse or
distributed attention plays an important role in aesthetic experience.
43 See Chapter 5.
44 See Blum (1994: Chapter 3) on moral perception and judgement.
45 There are many studies on the political and sociological aspects of attention.
Choosing one, I recommend Yves Citton’s (2017) comprehensive book.
46 ‘It matters how we see other people. Such looking is not always dialogue,
indeed it is rarely mutual …’ (MGM 463).
47 Some of these worries have been raised in relation to the ethics of care—which
has embraced the ethical significance of attention—by Joan Tronto (1989).
48 See Panizza (2021) on cases where attending to evil may be the wrong thing
to do, or just ‘impossible’.
Bibliography
Allport, A. (1987) Selection for Action: Some Behavioural and Neurophysiological
Considerations of Attention and Action. In: Sanders, A. and Heuer, H. (eds.)
Perspectives on Perception and Action. Hillsdale, NJ, Lawrence Erlbaum
Associates, pp. 395–419.
Allport, A. (1993) Attention and Control: Have We Been Asking the Wrong
Questions? A Critical Review of Twenty-five Years. In: Meyer, D.E. and
Kornblum, S. (eds.) Attention and Performance XIV: Synergies in Experimental
Psychology, Artificial Intelligence, and Cognitive Neuroscience. Cambridge,
MA, MIT Press, pp. 183–218.
What is ethical about attention? 59
Bok, S. (2005) Simone Weil and Iris Murdoch: The Possibility of Dialogue.
Gender Issues. 22 (4), 71–78.
Bowden, P. (1998) Ethical Attention, Accumulating Understandings, European
Journal of Philosophy. 6 (1), 59–76.
Broadbent, D. (1958) Perception and Communication. Oxford, Pergamon Press.
Cameron, S. (2003) The Practice of Attention: Simone Weil’s Performance of
Impersonality. Critical Inquiry. 29 (2), 216–252.
Campbell, J. (2002) Reference and Consciousness. Oxford, Oxford University
Press.
Chappell, S. G. (2015) Knowing What to Do: Imagination, Virtue, and Platonism
in Ethics. Oxford, Oxford University Press.
Citton, Y. (2017) The Ecology of Attention. Cambridge, Polity.
Cohen, M. A. et al. (2012) The Attentional Requirements of Consciousness.
Trends in Cognitive Sciences. 16 (8), 411–417.
Colzato, L., et al. (2012) Meditate to Create: The Impact of Focused-Attention
and Open-Monitoring Training on Convergent and Divergent Thinking.
Frontiers in Psychology. 3 (116): 1–5.
Cordner, C. (2016) Lessons of Murdochian Attention. Sophia. 55: 197–213.
Debus, D. (2015) Losing Oneself: On the Value of Full Attention. European
Journal of Philosophy. 23 (4), 1174–1191.
Forsberg, N. (2013) Language Lost and Found: On Iris Murdoch and the Limits
of Philosophical Discourse. London and New York, Bloomsbury.
Fredriksson, A. (forthcoming in 2022) Attention and the Unfamiliar: A
Phenomenology of Encounters with the Unknown. London, Palgrave
Macmillan.
Ganeri, J. (2017) Attention Not Self. New York, Oxford University Press.
Gopnik, A. (2009) The Philosophical Baby. New York, Farrar, Straus and Giroux.
Gurwitsch, A. (1964) The Field of Consciousness. Pittsburgh, Duquesne University
Press.
Heinemann, L. (2020) My Grandfather’s Whole Family Were Murdered—But He
Found a Way to Forgive the Killers. The Guardian. 11 January 2020. Available at:
https://www.theguardian.com/lifeandstyle/2020/jan/11/my-grandfathers-whole-
family-murdered-but-he-forgave-killers#navigation [Accessed 5 November 2021].
Hopwood, M. (2017) ‘The Extremely Difficult Realization that Something Other
Than Oneself Is Real’: Iris Murdoch on Love and Moral Agency. European
Journal of Philosophy. 26 (1), 477–501.
James, W. (1890) The Principles of Psychology. New York, Henry Holt.
Jiang, Y. et al. (2006) A Gender-and Sexual Orientation-Dependent Spatial
Attentional Effect of Invisible Images. Proceedings of the National Academy of
Science. 103, 17048–17052.
Kentridge, R. (2011) Attention Without Awareness: A Brief Review. In: Mole, C.,
Smithies, D. and Wu, W. (eds.) Attention: Philosophical and Psychological
Essays. Oxford, Oxford University Press, pp. 228–247.
Larson, K. (2009) ‘Everything Important is to do with Passion’: Iris Murdoch’s
Concept of Love and its Platonic Origin. Uppsala, Universitetsbiblioteket.
Laverty, M. (2007) Iris Murdoch’s Ethics: A Consideration of her Romantic
Vision. London: Continuum.
Lovibond, S. (2011) Iris Murdoch, Gender and Philosophy. London and
New York, Routledge.
60 What is ethical about attention?
Lutz, A. et al. (2008) Attention Regulation and Monitoring in Meditation. Trends
in Cognitive Science. 12 (4): 163–169.
Mack, A. and Rock, I. (1998) Inattentional Blindness. Cambridge, MA, MIT
Press.
McClelland, T. (2021) Attentional Affordances. Unpublished manuscript.
Merleau-Ponty, M. (2012) Phenomenology of Perception. New York, Routledge.
Mole, C. (2011) Attention Is Cognitive Unison: An Essay in Philosophical
Psychology. Oxford and New York, Oxford University Press.
Mole, C. (2021) Attention. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by
Edward N. Zalta. Available at: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/attention/
[Accessed 1-6-2021].
Murdoch, I. (1992) Metaphysics as a Guide to Morals [MGM]. London, Penguin.
Murdoch, I. (1998) In: Peter Conradi (ed.) Existentialists and Mystics: Writings
on Philosophy and Literature. Harmondsworth, Penguin.
———, Knowing the Void [KV], pp. 157–160.
———, The Darkness of Practical Reason [DPR], pp. 193–202.
———, Art is the Imitation of Nature [AIN], pp. 243–257.
———, The Sublime and the Beautiful Revisited [SBR], pp. 261–286.
———, Against Dryness [AD], pp. 287–295.
———, The Idea of Perfection [IP], pp. 299–336.
———, On ‘God’ and ‘Good’ [OGG], pp. 337–365.
———, The Sovereignty of Good over other Concepts [SGC], pp. 363–385.
———, The Fire and The Sun: Why Plato Banished the Artists [F&S],
pp. 386–463.
Nanay, B. (2010) Attention and Perceptual Content. Analysis. 70, 263–270.
Nanay, B. (2016) Aesthetics as Philosophy of Perception. Oxford, Oxford
University Press.
Neumann, O. (1987) Beyond Capacity: A Functional View of Attention. In:
Sanders, A. and Heuer, H. (eds.) Perspectives on Perception and Action,
Hillsdale, NJ, Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, pp. 361–394.
Nussbaum, M. (1996) Love and Vision: Iris Murdoch on Eros and the Individual.
In: Antonaccio, M. and Schweiker, W. (eds.) Iris Murdoch and the Search for
Human Goodness. Chicago, University of Chicago Press, pp. 29–53.
O’Shaughnessy, B. (2002) Consciousness and the World. Oxford, Oxford
University Press.
Panizza, S. (2021) Forms of Moral Impossibility. European Journal of Philosophy.
Online First. https://doi.org/10.1111/ejop.12651
Pashler, H. E. (1998) The Psychology of Attention. Cambridge, MA and London,
MIT Press.
Pétrement, S. (1988) Simone Weil: A Life. New York, Schocken Books.
Prettyman, A. (2014) Attention and Conscious Perception. PhD thesis. University
of Toronto.
Prinz, J. (2011) Is Attention Necessary and Sufficient for Consciousness? In:
Mole, C., Smithies, D. and Wu, W. (eds.) Attention: Philosophical and
Psychological Essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 174–203.
Prinz, J. (2012) The Conscious Brain: How Attention Engenders Experience.
New York, Oxford University Press.
What is ethical about attention? 61
Prinzmetal, W. et al. (1998) Phenomenology of Attention: I. Color, Location,
Orientation, and Spatial Frequency. Journal of Experimental Psychology:
Human Perception and Performance. 24 (1), 261–282.
Robjant, D. (2011) Is Iris Murdoch an Unconscious Misogynist? Some Trouble
with Sabine Lovibond, the Mother in Law, and Gender. Heythrop Journal. 52
(6), 1021–1031.
Rozelle-Stone, A. R. and Stone, L. (2013) Simone Weil and Theology. London and
New York, Bloomsbury.
Schoenberg, N. (2017) Mom Forgives the Man in Letter at Prison. Chicago
Tribune. 26 December 2017. Available at: https://www.chicagotribune.com/
lifestyles/sc-fam-mother-forgives-murderer-0116-story.html [Accessed
12-11-2021].
Shiffrin, R. M. (1988). Attention. In: R. C. Atkinson, Lindzey, G. and Luce, R. D.
(eds.). Stevens Handbook of Experimental Psychology. Vol. 2. Learning and
Cognition (2nd ed.) New York, Wiley & Sons, pp. 738–811.
Sohlberg, M. M. and Mateer, C. A. (1989) Introduction to Cognitive Rehabilitation.
New York, Guildford Press.
Soskice, J. M. (1992) Love and Attention. Royal Institute of Philosophy
Supplement. 32, 59–72.
Styles, E. A. (2006) The Psychology of Attention. 2nd ed. New York and Hove,
Psychology Press.
Tronto, J. (1989) Women and Caring: What Can Feminists Learn About Morality
from Caring. In: Jaggar, A. and Bordo, S. (eds.) Gender/Body/Knowledge:
Feminist Reconstructions of Being and Knowing. New Brunswick, NJ, Rutgers
University Press, pp. 172–187.
Vetö, M. (1994) The Religious Metaphysics of Simone Weil. Translated by J.
Dargan. Albany, SUNY Press.
Vlastos, G. (1973) The Individual as an Object of Love in Plato. In: Platonic
Studies. Princeton, Princeton University Press.
von der Ruhr, M. (2006) Simone Weil: An Apprenticeship in Attention. London,
Continuum.
Wallis, L. (2020) I Hugged the Man Who Murdered My Father. BBC World
Service. 18 October 2020. Available at: https://www.bbc.com/news/sto-
ries-52539314 [Accessed 10-11-2021].
Ward, J. (1885) Psychology. Encycloaedia Britannica. (9th ed.) Edinburgh, Adam
and Charles Black.
Ward, J. (1918). Psychological Principles. Cambridge, Cambridge University
Press.
Watzl, S. (2017) Structuring Mind: The Nature of Attention and How it Shapes
Consciousness. Oxford, Oxford University Press.
Weil, S. (1951) Waiting for God [WG]. Translated by Emma Craufurd. New
York, Harper and Row.
———, Spiritual Autobiography [SA], pp. 61–83.
———, Reflections on the Right Use of School Studies with a View to the Love of
God [RSS], pp. 105–116.
———, The Love of our Neighbour [LN], pp. 139–157.
Weil, S. (1956) The Notebooks of Simone Weil [N]. 2 vols. Translated by Arthur
F. Mills. New York, Putnam.
62 What is ethical about attention?
Weil, S. (1968) On Science, Necessity and the Love of God [SN]. Translated by
Richard Rees. Oxford, Oxford University Press.
Weil, S. (2002) Gravity and Grace [GG]. Translated by Emma Crawford and
Mario von der Ruhr. London and New York, Routledge.
———, (2005) Simone Weil: An Anthology. Edited by Siân Miles. London,
Penguin.
Weil, S. Human Personality [HP], pp. 69–98.
Winch, P. (1989) Simone Weil: ‘The Just Balance’. Cambridge, Cambridge
University Press.
Wu, W. (2011) Attention as Selection for Action. In: Mole, C., Smithies, D. and
Wu, W. (eds.) Attention: Philosophical and Psychological Essays. Oxford:
Oxford University Press, pp. 97–116.
Yeshurun, Y. and Carrasco, M. (1998) Attention Improves Or Impairs Visual
Performance by Enhancing Spatial Resolution. Nature. 396, 72–75.
2 Attention without self-concern
DOI: 10.4324/9781003164852-3
64 Attention without self-concern
for morality, and for moral philosophy, what kind of picture we make; it
also matters whether we can find some truth or justification to that pic-
ture as such.1
Depending on what we think we are doing in attention, and how we
think of ourselves as agents of attention, our attention will change. Are we
separate and substantial entities taking in a world that is alien to us? Are
we fundamentally interrelated with the world we observe, shaping it and
being shaped, and essentially one? Are we, as Simone Weil thought, an
interference in the tissue of creation? Different conceptions can go hand in
hand with different responses: we can punish and repress the self; we can
think of the self as divided, and try to keep only a part; we can think of the
self as to be ignored, or to be removed. The motivation for attending, the
quality of attention, its results, all this cannot be separated from our under-
standing—explicit, or assumed and unquestioned—of what we are doing.
In this chapter and the next I will look at the metaphysical and practi-
cal questions of the self in attention together. I am not going to engage in
the colossal task of explaining what the self is, but rather, what kind of
self is implied or needed by the idea of attention that we are working
with, suggested by Murdoch and inspired by Weil. However, on this point
Murdoch and Weil seem to come apart. Therefore, I am going to discuss
the self in attention going down two different paths. Each explores a pos-
sible understanding of the self, its role in attention, and the practical
consequences and theoretical implications of holding that view. While
Murdoch fits more easily with the first solution, we will see that she is
also tempted by the second.
The first path takes the self to be something substantial and with some
degree of unity, identified with the moral subject, also the subject of atten-
tion; attention is then understood, on this view, as personal, its structure
and outcomes inescapably shaped by the individual. If there is something
to change and remove, it is only a portion of the self. The self as such is
necessary, and can be good. Because the self here is only changed or par-
tially reduced, and an intuitive or common-sense notion (again, in some
parts of the world, and in the current era) of the self as a substantial ‘I’ is
retained, I shall call this the ‘Tame View’ [TV]. The second path takes more
literally Murdoch’s idea of ‘unselfing’ as accompanying attention, and
takes a closer look at Simone Weil’s influence, including her idea of ‘décréa-
tion’, which is what Murdoch—perhaps not very accurately, as we shall
see—translates as ‘unselfing’. Here there is something about the self that is
fundamentally absent in attention. I will call this the ‘Radical View’ [RV] of
unselfing. This chapter defends the former. The next chapter will defend the
latter, and will end with an evaluation of the two possible views in relation
to the ethical role of attention, and in Murdoch’s thought.
The questions raised in this chapter are, as I said, important for under-
standing attention, its moral role, and something about us and about
morality through attention; but they are also important in the context of
Attention without self-concern 65
Murdochian exegesis, because some unclarity has been evidenced around
unselfing, even a ‘tension’ in Murdoch’s thought. The tension—which
roughly corresponds to the division between the TV and the RV—is
between a rich and substantial conception of the self, and passages that
seem to suggest that the self should be radically modified or even removed
in order to attend and, more generally, in order to be good. That is a ten-
sion that preoccupies, for instance, Maria Antonaccio’s early and influen-
tial book on Murdoch, Picturing the Human (2000). More generally,
Antonaccio observes this tension in Murdoch’s presentation of the indi-
vidual as in some way separate and substantial (qua individual), but also
as partly determined by, and significantly merged with, a transcendent
reality (Antonaccio 2000: 139–143); or, as Peter Conradi notes (but in
relation to Murdoch’s novels), ‘between a spiritual and a secular or
worldly view of the moral agent’ (1986: x quoted in Antonaccio 2000:
141).
The resolution of difficulties in Murdoch’s philosophical writings is, of
course, relevant in this book, and I hope to offer something in that direc-
tion in this chapter and the next one. But exegetical work is useful also
because it helps us understand attention and the moral task thereof. That
is our main concern here. So the question, ‘What did Murdoch think
about the self in attention?’ is raised in relation to the question ‘What can
and should we think about the self in attention?’ In this task, Simone
Weil’s thought will have the role, as we shall see, of pushing Murdochian
insights further, in a direction which Murdoch was wary to take, but
which offers a view that, I believe, we should not discount.
Unselfing
If the self is to be preserved, as part of experience and as a unity of a
particular kind, then why is the self a problem for attention, so that we
need to ‘unself’ in order to attend, love, and be good (or, well, better)?
The general answer: the self stands in the way of reality. How?
In the moral life the enemy is the fat relentless ego. Moral philosophy
is properly, and in the past has sometimes been, the discussion of this
ego and of the techniques (if any) for its defeat.
(OGG 342)
This seems easy. It is not the self that is the problem, but ego and fantasy.
Fantasy is a ‘bad use of the imagination’ (DPR 202), ‘the proliferation of
blinding self-centred aims and images’ (OGG 354), and it is something
produced by the ego, which is only a part of the self, not the whole self.
Ego impedes attention, making us see what we want to see—or what we
fear, depending on how masochistically inclined we are.
68 Attention without self-concern
But wait. While in the quotes above it is the ego that is seen as respon-
sible for fantasy and hence for lack of attention and moral failure, else-
where Murdoch talks about ‘self’ and ‘psyche’ as operating in the same
way (e.g. MGM 147). The self, then, is not so obviously off the hook: ‘the
self, the place where we live, is a place of illusion’ (SGC 376).
There’s something about our selves that distances us from reality, for
which we need attention and unselfing as part of it. The claims about the
self-protective and distorting nature of the mind are presented as empiri-
cal claims, partly meant to conform to ordinary observation, and partly
derived from Freud. Appealing to what she sees as ‘true and important’ in
Freud, Murdoch paints a picture of humanity as moved by ‘quasi-
mechanical’ forces, with the overall aim of protecting the self and with
the consequence of obscuring reality. Here Murdoch talks about the
‘psyche’ as that aspect of the self that causes problems:
Jill could, for instance, remind herself that her insecurities often lead her
to expect others to be critical of her actions (self-knowledge); she may
wonder if Jack’s ongoing tension with his partner is making him look
particularly worn out these days (empathy); she may remember that there
are many other significant factors, besides herself, influencing Jack’s emo-
tions (humility). These are ways of using her own specific resources to
improve her understanding, yet removing the pernicious influences of the
self, which may lead to a different perception.
This view of cognition and concepts, then, comes with a different view
of objectivity, where the world is not the ‘impersonal world of facts: the
hard objective world’ (IP 319), but a world understood and perceived
(but not constituted) by individuals through their imagination. On this
view, there is not one single possible way of understanding or perceiving
reality, but several compatible ways, depending on the individual’s
imaginative faculties. On the other hand, there are also ways of seeing
reality which are not correct. This model accounts for the necessary
limitation of individuals, occupying a particular position and having
limited faculties, and for the impossibility of occupying a perspective
from nowhere. At the same time, the proposed model does not reject the
notion of objectivity, but broadens it to include various compatible
individual perspectives, as well as the evaluative process through which
reality is apprehended.
What makes the suppression of any contribution of the self in atten-
tion appear plausible, then, is not the requirement of objectivity itself,
but a particular understanding of objectivity.13 The interpretation of
‘unselfing’ as elimination of any personal factor in perception assumes
precisely the ‘scientific’ view of objective knowledge that Murdoch criti-
cises. Only if objective knowledge and correct perception are conceived
as being completely independent of the perceiving individual is the elimi-
nation of the self both possible and desirable. But if Murdoch is correct
that the individual is ineliminable in perception and that objectivity and
truthfulness in fact involve a personal element, then the unselfing of
Attention without self-concern 75
attention cannot require elimination of the self’s contribution to percep-
tion. Only part of the self needs to go. Which part exactly, and how?
Just as God, being outside the universe, is at the same time the center,
so each man imagines he is situated in the center of the world. The
illusion of perspective places him at the center of space; an illusion of
the same kind falsifies his idea of time; and yet another kindred illusion
arranges a whole hierarchy of values around him. This illusion is
extended even to our sense of existence, on account of the intimate
connection between our sense of value and our sense of being; being
seems to us less and less concentrated the farther it is removed from us.
(LOW 158–9)
Julia T. Meszaros, reading Murdoch, seems to defend this idea: that what
needs to be removed in unselfing is, primarily, ‘an illusion, a fantasy,
about oneself’ (2016: 141, emphasis added). This is the fantasy of cen-
trality. But in order to keep, as Meszaros wants to do, both a view of the
self as a ‘mechanism of attachments’ and as something substantial, the
illusion to be defeated has to be that of the ego, a part or specific perspec-
tive of the self, and not, as Meszaros suggests, the common-sense under-
standing of self (2016: 148, 166) which Murdoch, in fact, defends more
than once.15
Forms of self-concern
To realise that we are not the centre of value and being means giving up
illusions about ourselves and—if our understanding of value organises all
our perceptions—about the world. So fantasy takes the shape of a dual
distortion. On the one hand, there is a distortion about ourselves, about
the place that we occupy in the world: instead of conceiving of ourselves
as occupying a point like any other in the universe, we live and think as
if we were at the centre, inflating our own importance and taking our
point of view to have special relevance. This leaves little room for any-
thing else to truly matter. Second, distortion about the world follows
from this: if self is taken to be central, the external world will be unseen
in its reality, given that self fills most of the field of vision. This is why
both Murdoch and Weil claim that the self is the negation of the other
(N 213), and that the self’s ‘violent contraction’ can only ‘crush’ what it
encounters.20 That is also why Murdoch and Weil insist, in a way that
only makes sense in this context, on the importance to recognise the exis-
tence of what is other than me; Murdoch famously claiming, for instance,
that ‘love is the extremely difficult realization that something other than
Attention without self-concern 79
oneself is real’ (S&G 215) and Weil, with characteristic intensity: ‘if mur-
derers knew their victims really existed, they would not be able to thrust
their knives into them. Not to see obstacles is the terrible secret of the
carnage of the victorious warrior, and of the misdeed of the criminal’
(N 109). Self-concern, therefore, can be either direct or indirect. While it
is probably easier to identify the former (‘am I fantasising about being
praised by my boss, again?’), the latter is more insidious, because it shows
that just trying to redirect our focus will not necessarily achieve libera-
tion from fantasy.
Direct self-concern
Direct self-concern, too, may appear at any point, even when we are (or
think we are) entirely engrossed in something external and beautiful.
Following Murdoch, let’s take art as an example, in this case literature. In
the short story Je ne parle pas francais, Katherine Mansfield describes the
experience of an egotistical artist in a café in Paris, who happens to read
a sentence which gives him an intense aesthetic experience. But immedi-
ately his mind turns back upon himself.
quite suddenly, at the bottom of the page, written in green ink, I fell
on to that stupid, stale little phrase: Je ne parle pas francais.
There! It had come—the moment—the geste! And although I was so
ready, it caught me, it tumbled me over; I was simply overwhelmed.
And the physical feeling was so curious, so particular … But, ah!
The agony of that moment! How can I describe it? I didn’t think of
anything. I didn’t even cry out to myself. Just for one moment I was
not. I was Agony, Agony, Agony.
Then it passed, and the very second after I was thinking: ‘Good God!
Am I capable of feeling as strongly as that? But I was absolutely
unconscious! I hadn’t a phrase to meet it with! I was overcome! I was
swept off my feet! I didn’t even try, in the dimmest way, to put it
down!’
And up I puffed and puffed, blowing off finally with: ‘After all I must
be first-rate. No second-rate mind could have experienced such an
intensity of feeling so … purely.’
(Mansfield 1953: 87–8)
Notes
1 ‘We see how deep metaphysical imagery goes down into the human soul.
Farther than we can see?’ (MGM 85).
2 Two kinds of ‘automatic’ processes emerge as connected with attention, in
this chapter and in Chapter 6. On the one hand, the ‘automaticity’ of fantasy,
which means, for Murdoch, simply that fantasy is natural and spontaneous.
Attention without self-concern 83
On the other, as we shall see, there is the automaticity of responses arising
from attentive correct perception. The first comes from obeying the self, or an
illusion of the self; the second from obeying the world. In both cases, the
process is in fact also, to some extent, under the subject’s control, but one
level up: through the redirection of attention (involving, as Murdoch puts it,
‘psychic energies’ which create the quality of consciousness from which these
processes emerge, and depending on the objects that attention takes).
3 See for instance Murdoch’s remarks about the psyche: ‘it is reluctant to face
unpleasant realities’; ‘Its consciousness is not normally a transparent glass’
(SGC 374). But ‘reluctant’ and ‘normally’ do not mean ‘incapable’ and ‘never’.
4 A similar point is made by Samantha Vice (2007: 65), who observes that since
for Murdoch the moral life is a matter of educating the self (or, in the context
of my argument, of making the self more attentive and thus more truthful), if
the self were only a fantasy mechanism, the attempt to become morally better
would not get off the ground.
5 Aristotle, for instance, urges to keep care for the self or ‘philautia’ (as such
potentially virtuous) within the limits of moderation; Kant recognise the
claims of the ‘dear self’ as the main impediment to following duty: and mov-
ing from self-other asymmetry to symmetry, most forms of utilitarianism, in
the principle of equal consideration of interests, cut across the natural ten-
dency to regard one’s own interests as special.
6 ‘One may fail to see the individual … because we are ourselves sunk in a
social whole which we allow uncritically to determine our reactions, or
because we see each other exclusively as so determined’ (S&G 216).
7 See also Holland (2012: 260).
8 Abandoning deeply ingrained social distortions is very hard but, let’s stress
again, not impossible: think of the first feminists moving against patriarchy,
or the animal liberationists moving against human supremacy.
9 Pylyshyn here argues that perception, not early vision, is cognitive penetrable.
10 Pylyshyn defines it as a rational relation, Siegel as a causal one. For my pur-
poses the latter is sufficient.
11 Note that the concept of attention in the quote is not the same as the one
developed in this book, and closer to the psychological concept as described
in the Introduction. This is not a problem, for that is not the relevant part of
the quote.
12 Murdoch acknowledges that science itself does not necessarily rely on the
idea of impersonal and mind-independent reality which she is attacking:
When she calls for ‘the liberation of morality, and of philosophy as a study of
human nature, from the domination of science’, she adds: ‘or rather from the
domination of inexact ideas of science’ (IP 320). Yet at other times ‘science’
appears in Murdoch like a shorthand for the inexact (but perhaps popular)
understanding of it.
13 ‘it is perfectly obvious that goodness is connected with knowledge; not with
impersonal quasi-scientific knowledge of the ordinary world, whatever that
may be, but with a refined and honest perception of what is really the case’ (IP
330, emphasis added); see also Antonaccio (2000: 139): ‘far from equating
realism with the empiricist assumptions of the scientific gaze, Murdoch makes
it clear that realism is always keyed to a personal vision … Yet moral objectivity
or realism is not divorced from the perceiving subject; rather, these terms only
make sense within the deeply personal field of human moral vision.’
14 And (reading Schopenhauer): ‘Our personality and temperament, and the
daily momently quality of our consciousness, our ability to look at particu-
lars, must be thought of as an organic part of our morals, and soaked in
value’ (MGM 167).
84 Attention without self-concern
15 See e.g. MGM 153 quoted above, and the remarks against Hume’s attack on
the self: she calls out philosophers for the abstraction and inapplicability of
their views by noting how they can mostly just be held ‘in their study’, as she
does with Hume’s idea of the self as an illusion (MGM 166).
16 This point also strikes me as explaining why Maria Antonaccio’s (2000) pro-
posal of defining Murdoch’s thought as ‘reflexive realism’ has received some
strong backlash, e.g. from Robjant (2012) and Hämäläinen (2013). While
Antonaccio defines reflexivity primarily as vision of reality passing through
consciousness, the word ‘reflexivity’ carries the inevitable meaning of return-
ing or referring back to self.
17 Samantha Vice argues, instead, for the desirability of self-concern within
Murdoch’s ethical framework. However, what she means by ‘self-concern’ is
different, and includes ‘firstly, our conception and experience of self and, sec-
ondly, self-reflection, self-knowledge and their intended fruits in practical
conversion’ (2007: 60).
18 What may be lacking, in both Weil’s and Murdoch’s picture of attention, and
which may do justice to Bowden’s concern, is not passion, but reciprocity. But
that is not the question here.
19 My translation.
20 Murdoch metaphorically, and Weil a bit less so, characterise this state as the
illusion of being God (but which, for Weil, leads to a complete withdrawal—
decreation—as we shall see in the next chapter).
21 This also, incidentally, reminds us of Murdoch’s suspicion of self-centredness
after half-approvingly quoting Walter Pater at the beginning of Chapter 8 of
MGM.
22 Andrea Dworkin also notes the connection with Murdoch’s idea of fantasy in
her reading of Madame Bovary (1987: 134).
23 The quality of the novels Emma reads shows a fantasy within the fantasy.
They are books that lack imagination and realism, aimed at satisfying specific
desires in the reader, themselves lacking in the moral quality of attention to
reality on the part of the authors. But also relevant is the attitude of the
reader, who only focuses on what gratifies her in the fiction. Although Emma’s
own tendencies are partly to blame, if Murdoch is right that attention does
not come naturally to us, the novels also show how little it takes to send us
spinning in the direction of fantasy, while training attention is harder.
24 The theory of defence mechanisms was developed by Anna Freud (1992). She
identifies the following: repression, regression, reaction formation, isolation,
undoing, projection, introjection, turning against one’s own person, reversal,
sublimation, or displacement. All these are incompatible with attention.
25 ‘“Neurosis” is characterised, almost in a popular sense defined, by a mechani-
cal repetitive imprisoning of the mind’ (MGM 139).
26 This is an insight that Michael Lipson and Abigail Lipson (1996) share in a
short paper proposing a psychotherapy approach that works on shifting
attention as a form of moral concern in order to treat cases of performance
anxiety, drawing explicitly on Murdoch and Weil.
Bibliography
Antonaccio, M. (2000) Picturing the Human: The Moral Thought of Iris
Murdoch. New York, Oxford University Press.
Antonaccio, M. (2012) A Philosophy to Live By: Engaging Iris Murdoch.
New York, Oxford University Press.
Attention without self-concern 85
Blum, L. (2012) Visual Metaphors in Murdoch’s Moral Philosophy. In: Broackes,
J. (ed.) Iris Murdoch, Philosopher. Oxford, Oxford University Press,
pp. 307–324.
Bowden, P. (1998) Ethical Attention; Accumulating Understandings. European
Journal of Philosophy. 6 (1), 59–76.
Colman, A. M. (2009) Oxford Dictionary of Psychology. New York, Oxford
University Press.
Conradi, P. (1986) Iris Murdoch: The Saint and the Artist. New York, St. Martin’s
Press.
Dworkin, A. (1987) Intercourse. New York, Free Press.
Flaubert, G. (2012) Madame Bovary. Translated by Lydia Davis. London,
Penguin.
Freud, A. (1992) The Ego and the Mechanisms of Defence. London, Karnac
Book.
Freud, S. (1990) The Ego and the Id. New York: W. W. Norton & Co.
Gaydukevych, D. and Kocovski, N. L. (2012) Effect of Self-focused Attention on
Post-event Processing in Social Anxiety. Behaviour Research and Therapy.
50 (1), 47–55.
Hämäläinen, N. (2013) Symposium on Iris Murdoch. The Heythrop Journal. 54,
1007–1011.
Hämäläinen, N. (2015) Reduce Ourselves to Zero?: Sabina Lovibond, Iris
Murdoch, and Feminism. Hypatia. 30 (4), 743–759.
Holland, M. (2012) Social Convention and Neurosis as Obstacles to Moral
Freedom. In: Broackes, J. (ed.) Iris Murdoch, Philosopher. Oxford, Oxford
University Press, pp. 255–274.
Jordan, J. (2008) Iris Murdoch’s Genealogy of the Modern Self: Retrieving
Consciousness Beyond the Linguistic Turn. PhD Dissertation, Baylor University.
Leopardi, G. (1921) Pensieri di varia filosofia e di bella letteratura. Firenze, Le
Monnier.
Lipson, M. and Lipson, A. (1996) Psychotherapy and the Ethics of Attention. The
Hastings Center Report. 26 (1), 17–22.
Lyons, J. C. (2016) Inferentialism and Cognitive Penetration of Perception.
Episteme. 13 (1), 1–28.
Mansfield, K. (1953) Je ne Parle pas Français. In: Selected Stories. Oxford, Oxford
University Press, pp. 84–112.
Meszaros, J. T. (2016) Selfless Love and Human Flourishing in Paul Tillich and
Iris Murdoch. Oxford, Oxford University Press.
Murdoch, I. (1992) Metaphysics as a Guide to Morals [MGM]. London, Penguin.
Murdoch, I. (1998) Existentialists and Mystics: Writings on Philosophy and
Literature. Edited by Peter Conradi. Harmondsworth, Penguin.
———, Vision and Choice in Morality [VCM], pp. 76–98.
———, The Darkness of Practical Reason [DPR], pp. 193–202.
———, The Sublime and the Good [S&G], pp. 205–220.
———, The Idea of Perfection [IP], pp. 299–336.
———, On ‘God’ and ‘Good’ [OGG], pp. 337–365.
———, The Sovereignty of Good over other Concepts [SGC], pp. 363–385.
Plato (1956) Republic. Translated by B. Jowett. New York, Charles Scribner’s
Sons.
86 Attention without self-concern
Pylyshyn, Z. (1999) Is Vision Continuous with Cognition? The Case for Cognitive
Impenetrability of Visual Perception. Behavioural and Brain Sciences. 22,
341–365.
Robjant, D. (2012) The Earthy Realism of Plato’s Metaphysics, or: What Shall We
Do with Iris Murdoch? Philosophical Investigations. 35, 43–67.
Shapiro, D. (1965) Neurotic Styles. New York, Basic Books.
Siegel, S. (2012) Cognitive Penetrability and Perceptual Justification. Noûs.
46 (2), 201–222.
Sodré, I. (1999) Death by Daydreaming: Madame Bovary. In: Bell, D. (ed.)
Psychoanalysis and Culture: A Kleinian Perspective. London and New York,
Routledge, pp. 49–63.
Todd, A. R. et al. (2015) Anxious and Egocentric: How Specific Emotions
Influence Perspective Taking. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General.
144 (2), 374–391.
Vice, S. (2007) The Ethics of Self-Concern. In: Rowe, A. (ed.) Iris Murdoch:
A Reassessment. London, Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 60–71.
Weil, S. (1951) Waiting for God [WG] Translated by Emma Craufurd. New York,
Harper and Row.
———, Love of the Order of the World [LOW], pp. 158–181.
Weil, S. (1956) The Notebooks of Simone Weil [N]. 2 vols. Translated by Arthur F.
Mills. New York, Putnam.
3 Attention without self
The exposition of the Tame View (TV) has shown that attention can be
compatible with a substantial view of the self, one in which the self does
not need to be a metaphysically fixed entity, but something that is sub-
stantial and continuous enough to constitute personal identity and an
individualised background to specific thoughts, emotions, perceptions,
and actions. Interests, knowledge, experience, and most importantly a
sense of value are, while changeable, components of the self which build
up one’s unique identity. As we have seen, this view is ‘tame’ insofar as it
does not require entirely giving up the personal element of perception,
nor a familiar sense of selfhood which we ordinarily, at least in Western
cultures, hold. Unselfing, on this view, contrary to what the word may
lead us to expect, means not a removal or suppression of the self, but only
of self-concern or ego, in other words, of the ‘parts’ or tendencies in us
which lead to fantasy. This view is also compatible with most of what
Murdoch says about the self and moral progress, and with some of what
Weil says.
DOI: 10.4324/9781003164852-4
88 Attention without self
means to say that we experience the self as ‘not there’.) Second, if atten-
tion requires suppressing part of the self, this may lead to self-focus in
order to discover and fight the ‘bad self’, a battle which only reinforces its
hold. The third worry relates to the possibility of reinforcing the self not
by fighting it, but by thinking about improving it: if we hold that atten-
tion is something that improves our selves, which is in fact one of the
reasons to hold the TV, we may face yet another paradox by making our
selves into the object of moral progress.
That is why it is worth considering an alternative view that, while giv-
ing rise to different problems, can account for the worries just raised.
That task will require exploring the possibility that the self is not as sub-
stantial and continuous as we think and that attention may reveal an
alternative, emptier view of the self in experience. On the TV, we saw that
an illusion about the self—the illusion of centrality—was the source of
illusion about the world (fantasy). Here, we consider the possibility that
it is a more radical illusion about the self that precludes attention, and
that it is not just fantasy that blocks the view.
Attending to improve me
Murdoch suggests that in moral philosophy and in the moral life the
questions to ask are: ‘What is a good man like? How can we make our-
selves morally better? Can we make ourselves morally better?’ (OGG 342).
Attention is meant to be one way to answer the ‘how’. But if we take
attention seriously as an answer, we may disagree with the questions.
Even if these questions arise naturally, and may be of help to the phi-
losopher trying to understand goodness, or to the individual trying to
decide who is a good role model, they cannot guide the first-personal
effort to attend. Attention, as we have seen, is animated by eros and
enabled by unselfing. That means that nothing but the desire to see what
is true, and do what is right, should be guiding the quest. Rather than
‘How can I be better?’ we should ask ‘What is really happening?’, ‘What
are you?’, or ‘What do you need?’
To take attention as a path to the moral improvement of the subject, as
the TV encourages us to do, and compatibly with Murdoch’s interests
and stated goals, can be dangerous for attention itself, and therefore for
moral progress. This means that it may be better for us not to think of the
self as substantial and real, and not to think about it at all. In other
words, an alternative, more radical no-self view of unselfing may more be
suitable for the purpose of attending.
The ‘sneaky’ manifestations of self-concern and fantasy—what Maria
Antonaccio more elegantly calls ‘the paradoxes of askesis’ (2012: 164–
166)—can be understood precisely as part of an attempt to attend which
allows for a substantial self and which takes self-improvement as one of
its goals. Paradoxes: attention can fail precisely because we are trying to
exercise it; so it matters how we try and why.
The present worry is not only about the strength of the self, and its
capacity to return us to self-concern without us even noticing. That kind
of danger is beautifully described in Murdoch’s reading of Plato’s cave,
where the initial liberation from the chains and the shadows is replaced
by the comforting fire, which Murdoch interprets as the self, making us
unwilling to move further (F&S 444) (This reading of Plato is of course
controversial, but what matters for us now is Murdoch’s view of the self,
aided by the imagery.) The present worry, rather, is that a view of the self
Attention without self 91
as substantial and engaged in attention can make it almost impossible to
leave the cave; to stick with the imagery: we may feel that we need to take
the fire with us, even if there’s a much stronger light out there. The danger
is intensified if, enabled by the substantial view of the self, we take our
quest, as individuals, not philosophers, to be about the moral improve-
ment of our selves. Spiritual literature, as Antonaccio reminds us, is rife
with such examples of self-defeat, precisely because we aim to make
progress, and then because we feel we are doing so. Saint John of the
Cross (2003), whose work interested both Murdoch and Weil, famously
re-wrote the seven deadly sins as potential sins of the spiritual beginner.
I am paying attention. I am making progress and seeing the situation
more justly. ‘I am making progress.’ ‘I am making progress!’ ‘So, I am
better than I used to be.’ ‘It feels nice to be attentive and improved.’ ‘See
how inattentive all these other people are?’ Sadly that’s not an unfamiliar
pattern.3 But what if we have no sense of a self that is being improved?
May I disappear in order that those things that I see may become
perfect in their beauty from the very fact that they are no longer
things that I see.
I do not in the least wish that this created world should fade from my
view, but that it should no longer be to me personally that it shows
itself. To me it cannot tell its secret which is too high. If I go, then the
creator and the creature will exchange their secrets.
To see a landscape as it is when I am not there …
(GG 42)
On this view, the ‘original sin’, an idea that Murdoch wants to recover
(GG 338), is not that we are selfish, but that we are selves.
92 Attention without self
The RV is an attempt to make sense of the idea expressed above by
Weil. The view starts from attention and moves towards an understand-
ing of the self based on attention, without the other movement that is
instead also present in the TV, that is, understanding the self is something
we ‘need’, in order to make sense of moral progress, leading to a concep-
tion of what happens to it in attention. This exploration will lead, as we
shall see, to a reconfiguration of the self, where ‘dissolving’ or ‘disappear-
ing’ are more apt descriptions than ‘suppressing’ or ‘removing’. The
resulting conception of self, inspired by Weil and Indian and Chinese
philosophies, is that a solid self was never there in the first place. Attention
is the realisation of such nothingness. Conversely, the illusion of self, by
enabling the reflexive concern we saw above, is the beginning of both
fantasy and all forms of distance from reality.
Like attention, the concept of unselfing comes to Murdoch from Weil.
With the introduction of Weil, the idea that the self can be an obstacle to
truth takes on a second aspect: earlier we had Freud’s psychology; now
we have Weil’s metaphysics. But, looking at Weil, we notice a first striking
difference in vocabulary: the word Weil uses is ‘decreation’ (Fr. décréa-
tion), which Murdoch translates with apparent innocence as ‘unselfing’.
But the move may not be so innocent. On the one hand, Murdoch’s trans-
lation is correct insofar as, according to Weil, the method to remove error
is through the removal of the self. On the other hand, (a) removing self
and de-creating differ insofar as the latter suggests a return to a previous
state, the former does not; and (b) if we understand ‘unselfing’ as simply
the removal of selfishness, ego, or self-concern, then the radical and all-
embracing meaning of decreation is lost. Weil is tamed.
The will, when it is not obedience, gives rise to the illusion of selfhood.
That is the illusion of being able to interfere with reality, and the illusion
of being a centre (a centre of being, value, and space). Having a perspective
is inevitable, as we are situated in space and time, but we must not believe
our partial and limited perspective to be the true one, and avoid the fur-
ther crucial step of thinking that self is equally substantial and centred
(LOW 158–9). Like Weil, Murdoch believes that we have a natural ten-
dency to think of ourselves as thus centred and central, and think and act
accordingly. That’s why we need attention. What attention does is not only
‘counteracting the system’ of egocentrism, but showing the unreality of the
belief that grounds the system. Weil’s conception of self is beautifully and
effectively described by Miklós Vetö (Murdoch’s former student) thus:
In such a work all that I call ‘I’ has to be passive. Attention alone—
that attention which is so full that the I disappears—is required of
me. I have to deprive all that I call ‘I’ of the light of my attention and
turn it onto that which cannot be conceived.
(GG 118)
The notion of achieving a pure cognitive state where the object is not
disturbed by the subjective ego, but where subject and object simply
exist as one is here made comprehensible through a certain experi-
ence of art and nature. (Dualism is overcome: not such an arcane
idea after all.) A discipline of meditation wherein the mind is alert
but emptied of self enables this form of awareness, and the disci-
plined practice of various skills may promote a similar unselfing, or
‘décréation’ to use Simone Weil’s vocabulary. Attend ‘without think-
ing about’.
(MGM 254)
the notion of no-self, that is, the notion of no substantial, fixed self-
hood, does not indicate the mere lack or absence of self, as an anni-
hilationist may suggest, but rather constitutes a standpoint which is
beyond both the eternalist view of self and the nihilistic view of
no-self.
(1997: 68) (See Saṃyutta Nikāya 4.10)
This is the view, Abe writes, that is inherited by Zen. And, fitting the
content, the form of the teaching is not propositional, but experiential. In
attention, we find no self. It is only through reflexivity (the opposite of
unselfing) that we begin objectifying the self, and a substantial concep-
tion of self is born (1997: 69). Or again, as Murdoch writes in MGM,
reading Sekida, the idea that ‘subject and object simply exist as one is
here made comprehensible through a certain experience of art and nature’
(MGM 245).
The primacy of experience is the reason for starting with attention if
we want to understand the self, and not vice versa. This view is known as
Attentionalism: the idea that attention has explanatory priority. Jonardon
Ganeri’s (2017) exploration of attention and self takes this perspective,
seeking to rethink the self from the point of view of attention combining
Attention without self 101
Western philosophy of mind and Buddhism. His account, however,
engages not with Zen, but with Theravāda Buddhism, which in offering
a perhaps less ‘austere’ view of self comes yet a little bit closer to Murdoch.
According to the view of consciousness of this tradition, Ganeri explains,
‘there is a “space” or “frame” of awareness (citta) which is in fact nothing
more than a range of experiential, attentive, and agentive functions (ceta-
sika) that take place within it’ (9). The mistake, which leads to a substan-
tial and fixed idea of the self, is to think that this space is an entity, rather
than a ‘system of experiences’. If there is any cohesion, it is given by the
‘ongoing structure of experience and action’ which depends on attention
itself (12). While attention, as formulated above, enables the object to
occupy our minds, the metaphor easily misleads us to think that there is
something before and apart from such experience. That’s the mistake: to
think that the self is ‘like the space of a canvas or stage’ which precede the
painting and the actors. In the case of consciousness, instead, nothing
‘precedes and outlives its occupants’ (O’Shaughnessy 2002: 288, in
Ganeri 2017: 11).
The Theravāda Buddhist concept of no-self, Ganeri stresses, does not
deny that there is some connection between experiences which we may call
self, nor that there is a perspective, necessarily given by the living organism
or ‘minded body’—while for Zen and Weil, in truth-seeking attention, the
aim is to move outside perspective. What the Theravāda philosophy denies,
through observation of attention, is only that there is a separate self that
either contemplates or acts upon the world. As Ganeri puts it, ‘anatta, the
famous Buddhist thesis of no-self’ is only ‘a rejection of the idea that a
detached agent acts in the centre of a space of action, or that a detached
witness watches from the centre of a space of experience’ (9–10). The idea
of no-self, like Murdoch’s stress on attention, is in opposition to the idea
that there is a completely free agent who influences the world through the
will, a rational observer who merely contemplates reality through the
senses. Attention shows that we are more closely engaged with our envi-
ronment than this picture allows. That we are, for instance, not ‘so strangely
separate from the world at moments of choice’, for if we are, ‘are we really
choosing at all, are we right indeed to identify ourselves with this giddy
empty will?’ (IP 36). The idea of a self detached from the rest of reality is
what attention shows to be mistaken, according to Ganeri following
Buddhaghosa, and that is also the idea that Murdoch rejected in the phi-
losophy of her time, from Kant to Sartre. Between complete freedom and
complete determinism, Murdoch thought that we could find a third way ‘if
we simply introduce into the picture the idea of attention’ (IP 329). The
isolated self is similarly rejected in both philosophies.
This does not mean of course that what is left, after the detached and
independent self view is challenged, is the same for Murdoch and for
Theravāda Buddhism. But the Theravāda view, as explained by Ganeri in
connection with Western philosophy of mind, comes a little closer to
102 Attention without self
some of the requirements of the TV: it is more accepting of the existence
of continuing self than Zen and Weil, while still denying the existence of
a self independent of current experience. There are two main similarities
between Theravāda philosophy and Murdoch. First, the two conceptions
of what the self is not are strikingly close, as is the fact that a detached
self is denied thanks to the connecting (truth-seeking) nature of attention.
The second similarity is based on Murdoch’s description of the self as a
‘mechanism of attachments’ (OGG 357). If we take that to be a defining
characteristic of what we think of as the self, it means that self is consti-
tuted by the moment-to-moment objects that it attaches itself to, for bet-
ter or worse—and it is, therefore, centre-less, and not unitary. If the self is
mainly constituted by what consciousness ‘attaches’ itself to, that is com-
patible with a no-self view according to which there is no self before or
after the movement of consciousness, but such movement can constitute
a web of interrelated moments of consciousness.4 The TV, however (and
I think Murdoch), takes the self to be more than this, and that is why the
Theravāda view still belongs to the RV.
The pervasiveness of attachment also explains why the illusion of a
substantial self arises in the first place, and why it leads to error. Buddhist
ethics sees the root of all ills in ignorance (avidyā),5 primarily the igno-
rance of the true nature of self.6 One begins to chip away at this form of
ignorance by noticing the impermanence of all the things we identify with
self (body, character traits, beliefs …). The impermanent nature of reality
is also stressed by Murdoch, as something particularly resistant to atten-
tion, precisely because it threatens a soothing picture of unity and perma-
nence (including, and primarily, the unity and permanence of self).
Murdoch, in her own way, brings an aspect of the Buddhist teaching to
life, the terror we feel when facing impermanence, and the quick retreat
into illusion: we struggle to sustain attention on such things. But if we
can, somehow, accept impermanence, and not look away, many other
insights and practical changes come cascading down. Experience leads to
insight and vice versa, so that in Buddhism, as Christopher Gowans
stresses in a comparison with Murdoch, ‘that metaphysics is a guide to
morals is a central motif’ (forthcoming, n.p.). In the same way, as I’ve
been arguing, attention becomes different, better, if one gives up the idea
of a substantial permanent self. The root of suffering, as explained by the
Buddha in the Second Noble Truth, is craving, the attachments and frus-
tration of attachments that arise from a sense of self. The idea of what is
mine, what is owed to me, the things that I desire and that I reject, all
stem from the idea of self and attendant ‘cravings’: ‘The central idea is
that belief that one is a self generates a possessive attitude toward life,
interpreting everything from the perspective of what is “me” and “mine”,
and this results in suffering’ (Gowans, forthcoming). So no-self makes
detachment possible, and detachment makes true vision possible, which
is the essence of attention. I cannot see clearly if I want something from
Attention without self 103
the object. That is why Weil stresses detachment (e.g. GG 12–15) and the
extinction of desire, except from desire without attachment which is—as
it is for Murdoch—desire for the Good:
This waiting is attention. Desire, not for myself, but for what is. This is
eros, or love that is purified or ‘refined’ (SGC 384). ‘To love Good for
nothing’ (MGM 344, emphasis added).
Notes
1 This is a kind of distinction which Murdoch, rightly, reminds us of time and
again.
2 This is why, while Antonaccio (2012: 168) is right that ‘the solution to the
problem of egoism cannot simply be to renounce the countless mechanisms by
which human beings picture reality’, I do not agree with her that the solution is
‘reflexivity’, or working with the self to overcome its dangerous tendencies.
3 Even serious reflection upon the morality of one’s actions can, in a matter of
seconds, tilt towards excessive interest in oneself, while the situation being
considered, the true object of attention, becomes secondary to the morality of
one’s own behaviour. (For instance: a friend asks for help looking after their
children for an afternoon. You have a previous engagement and refuse.
Afterwards you realise the friend’s need for help was more important than
keeping the engagement. You spend some time wondering why you did oth-
erwise and what features of your personality got in the way of understanding
the appropriate thing to do. This may seem morally commendable and appro-
priately self-critical. Yet all the while, worries about your moral character
overshadow considerations about the difficulty the friend had to face because
of your actions. As Murdoch writes in OGG 355: ‘one’s self is interesting, so
one’s motives are interesting, and the unworthiness of one’s motives is inter-
esting’.) Or, as Bernard Williams (1981) has observed, the refusal to perform
a particular action because it is morally wrong, while knowing that if we
don’t do it, it will be performed by someone else, can be a matter of integrity,
but also of ‘moral self-indulgence’.
4 This is the other side of my disagreement with Meszaros (2016), as presented
in the previous chapter, whose account, I fear, is trying to harmonise too
much. We cannot accept as part of a coherent Murdochian view the defense
of common-sense idea of the self, a definition the self in terms of attachments,
and a recovery a substantial view of self all at the same time. Murdoch does
gesture in different directions, but they are not unproblematic together.
5 Note the common root of ‘vision’, where a-vidya is absence of vision, also
suggesting a non-intellectualistic idea of knowledge.
6 On the role of ignorance and craving in Buddhist ethics, see Conway (2018).
7 As she writes of the Theory of Forms, quoting Myles Burnyeat, the dispute
often involves ‘temperamental as well as intellectual factors’ (MGM 10).
108 Attention without self
8 ‘However, Sartre’s own temperament and talent (which also make him a good
novelist) lead him to linger fondly with this “inner”, developing a rich vocab-
ulary in his account of its states’ (MGM 154).
9 Murdoch writes: ‘[t]he more the separateness and differentness of other peo-
ple is realized, and the fact seen that another man has needs and wishes as
demanding as one’s own, the harder it becomes to treat a person as a thing’
(OGG 353–4). But it needs to be stressed that separateness is here contrasted
with the idea of the self engulfing the other, not with the unity in which the
two are the same.
10 Thanks to Davide Rizza for feedback on this chapter.
Bibliography
Abe, M. (1997) Zen and Comparative Studies. Basingstoke and London,
Macmillan.
Antonaccio, M. (2012) A Philosophy to Live By: Engaging Iris Murdoch.
New York, Oxford University Press.
Conway, M. (2018) Ethics in Pure Land Schools. In: Cozort, D. and Shields, J. M.
(eds.) The Oxford Handbook of Buddhist Ethics. Oxford, Oxford University
Press, pp. 184–204.
Freeman, M. (2015) Beholding and Being Beheld: Simone Weil, Iris Murdoch, and
the Ethics of Attention. The Humanistic Psychologist. 43, 160–172.
Ganeri, J. (2017) Attention Not Self. New York, Oxford University Press.
Gowans, C. (forthcoming) Murdoch and Buddhism. In: Hopwood, M. and
Caprioglio Panizza, S. (eds.) The Murdochian Mind. London, Routledge.
John of the Cross, St. (2003) Dark Night of the Soul. Translated by Mirabai Starr.
New York, Riverhead Books.
Meszaros, J. T. (2016) Selfless Love and Human Flourishing in Paul Tillich and
Iris Murdoch. Oxford, Oxford University Press.
Murdoch, I. (1992) Metaphysics as a Guide to Morals [MGM]. London, Penguin.
Murdoch, I. (1998) Existentialists and Mystics: Writings on Philosophy and
Literature. Edited by Peter Conradi. Harmondsworth, Penguin.
———, T.S. Eliot as a Moralist [TSE], pp. 161–170.
———, Against Dryness [AD], pp. 287–296.
———, The Idea of Perfection [IP], pp. 299–336.
———, On ‘God’ and ‘Good’ [OGG], pp. 337–365.
———, The Sovereignty of Gooed over other Concepts [SGC], pp. 363–385.
———, The Fire and The Sun: Why Plato Banished the Artists [F&S],
pp. 386–463.
O’Shaughnessy, B. (2002) Consciousness and the World. Oxford, Oxford
University Press.
Robjant, D. (2011) As a Buddhist Christian: The Misappropriation of Iris
Murdoch. Heythrop Journal. 52 (6), 993–1008.
Seidler, V. J. (forthcoming) Murdoch and Jewish Thought. In: Hopwood, M. and
Caprioglio Panizza, S. (eds.) The Murdochian Mind. London, Routledge.
Sekida, K. (1975) Zen Training. New York, Weatherhill.
Suzuki, S. (2011) Zen Mind, Beginner’s Mind. Boston and London. Shambala.
Vetö, M. (1994) The Religious Metaphysics of Simone Weil. Translated by Joan
Dargan. Albany, SUNY Press.
Attention without self 109
Weil, S. (1951) Waiting for God [WG]. Translated by Emma Craufurd. New York,
Harper and Row.
———, Spiritual Autobiography [SA], pp. 61–83.
———, Reflections on the Right Use of School Studies with a View to the Love of
God [RSS], pp. 105–116.
———, Love of the Order of the World [LOW], pp. 158–181.
Weil, S. (2002) Gravity and Grace [GG]. Translated by Emma Crawford and
Mario von der Ruhr. London and New York, Routledge.
Weil, S. (2005) Simone Weil: An Anthology. Edited by Siân Miles. London,
Penguin.
———, Human Personality [HP], pp. 69–98.
Williams, B. (1981) Persons, Character and Morality. In: Moral Luck. Cambridge,
Cambridge University Press, pp. 1–19.
4 Self-knowledge
DOI: 10.4324/9781003164852-5
Self-knowledge 111
However, all sorts of obstacles can stand in the way even of genuine
efforts and real desire. Those obstacles may come from our history (a his-
tory of privilege may make us blind to subtle discrimination; a history of
discrimination may incline us to expect the worst), our character (anything
that’s not a virtue is connected with fantasy), our mental state at a given
moment (especially affective states, such as fear, irritability, excitement,
desire), and so on. And if Murdoch is right about the naturalness in which
we distort reality, indeed about the rarity of true perception, together with
the self-protective beliefs that ‘we’re good people, really’ and that our per-
ceptions are reliable, then we will see that some kind of effort of self-
knowledge may be necessary to give attention a better chance. Fantasy is at
work more often than we realise, as Murdoch strongly puts it: ‘The ego is
indeed “unbridled”. Continuous control is required’ (MGM 260).
Self-knowledge is not necessary for attention: there are spontaneously
virtuous saints, spontaneously attentive moments, and kestrels who catch
us off guard. But most of us, much of the time, do need self-knowledge
for attention. This is particularly true on the TV, where it is part of the
self that gets in the way, and we want to know which part. Overall, most
of the discussion in this chapter will seem more easily accommodated by
the TV. But on both views, we need to know what interferes with atten-
tion, whether it is part of the self or a false idea thereof. This is important
to note: the requirement of self-knowledge does not commit us to a view
of the self as substantial. What is required is that we know what inter-
feres with attention, and such interference is related to what we ordinar-
ily call ‘self’. Self does not need to refer to an object, or be permanent or
substantial, for that to be true; self can merely be a cluster of experiences,
the embodied outcome of a causal chain, but it is also possible, on the RV,
to conceive of self-knowledge as precisely involving knowledge of the
illusion of a substantial self.
Here is the problem that motivates this chapter. Knowledge of self, or
the illusory self, seems necessary for attention. Yet if we understand atten-
tion as what encourages and enables reality to manifest itself as fully as
possible in our consciousness, as what, in a sense, joins us with the world,
then there is no room for self-knowledge in attention. Murdoch repeat-
edly tells us that ‘The direction of attention is … outward, away from the
self’ (OGG 354), and Weil tells us that we have to ‘deprive all that I call
“I” of the light of my attention and turn it on to that which cannot be
conceived’ (GG 118)—or turn it onto that which I do not (not yet, and
never fully) know or understand, and therefore that which attention may
partly reveal. And this seems true: while we attend, all we can do is turn
our whole being toward the object. So that, if the question ‘Am I attend-
ing?’ arises at all in attention, the answer is probably ‘No’.
This incompatibility of self-knowledge and the time of attention does
not need to be a problem. We can conclude that we cannot obtain self-
knowledge while we attend, but we still can and should seek it in order
112 Self-knowledge
to attend. Self-knowledge does not need to be concomitant with attention
to work in its favour. So the question is not ‘Am I attending?’ but rather
‘What is it about me that could interfere with attention, generally and in
this situation/in relation to this object?’, and related questions, such as
‘When should I try harder?’ ‘Should I look again at this?’, and so on. In
Murdoch’s example, the progress of the mother-in-law M, in her percep-
tion of the daughter-in-law D, occurs precisely after some self-examina-
tion on M’s part. M is described as ‘capable of self-criticism’, and it is
awareness of the influence of her social status, her jealousy, her prejudice
that prompts the moment of attention. Now, we may ask what in turn
prompted such awareness. Perhaps a nagging feeling of discomfort, per-
haps an unpleasant memory of her attitude towards D. But the discom-
fort or memory could have been dismissed, without self-knowledge, and
the moment of attention avoided. The suspicion of some bias in herself,
instead, acts both as spur and as guidance in the act of attention.
However, to claim that self-knowledge is not present when we attend
to something does not resolve the tension. To obtain self-knowledge, at
any point, we need to attend to ourselves. And self-directed attention
seems to be ruled out by the very definition of attention that Murdoch,
following Weil, offers. Therefore, far from the Socratic ‘know thyself’, a
view of morality that revolves around attention appears to make the
imperative to know oneself morally problematic, as well as creating dif-
ficulties within the very task of attention. Can that be right?
Christopher Mole (2007) has identified this tension in Murdoch’s
philosophy:
Against introspection
However, based on these considerations, what seems to be impossible in
attention is not any knowledge of the self—whatever that may be—but
the knowledge that is obtained by turning our consciousness inward.
‘Inwardly directed attention’, as the ‘process of inquiry directed at mental
states’, is introspection (Goldman 2006: 246). So it seems that what is
problematic, and what cannot be done, is not self-knowledge, but self-
knowledge through introspection. Introspection cannot answer the
Self-knowledge 115
question ‘Am I attending to this story, or failing to?’ because if I am
attending, the story is filling my consciousness, and there is no space for
questions about what I am doing. As Weil explains:
The enemies of art and of morals, the enemies that is of love, are the
same: social convention and neurosis. One may fail to see the indi-
vidual … because we are ourselves sunk in a social whole which we
allow uncritically to determine our reactions, or because we see each
other exclusively as so determined. Or we may fail to see the
Self-knowledge 119
individual because we are completely enclosed in a fantasy world of
our own into which we try to draw things from the outside, not
grasping their reality and independence, making them into dream
objects of our own.
(S&G 216)
But a sincere comparison with others’ perception is not the same as con-
vention, and it can alert us of the need to look again—whether we will
then change our perception as a result or not. This is true, starting from
the very concepts we employ. While Murdoch wants to defend the pos-
sibility of a personal use and personal deepening of concepts, this does
not deny that concepts also have a shared and public aspect. In fact, in
her view, both the personal and public aspects of concepts are related to
their contextual development and use. Individuals, words, and the object
are all necessary for concept-development, enabling the exercise of joint
attention:
[t]he art critic can help us if we are in the presence of the same object
and if we know something about his scheme of concepts. Both con-
texts are relevant to our ability to move towards ‘seeing more’,
towards ‘seeing what he sees’. Here, as so often, an aesthetic analogy
is helpful for morals. M could be helped by someone who both knew
D and whose conceptual scheme M could understand or in that con-
text begin to understand.
(IP 325)
Again, checking our perceptions and concepts against others’ does not
necessarily lead to greater clarity. As Murdoch knows, some conversa-
tions can occasion change for the worse, and ‘certain ways of describing
120 Self-knowledge
people can be corrupting and wrong’ (IP 325). Other people can be just
as blind as we are, and the blindness of a large group of people is in fact
extremely seductive (this is one of Weil’s complaints against the social,
and one reason she thought attention required solitude—see HP 75).3
Once again, it matters why we compare our perceptions with others,
what motives animate us, and that we are alert to the possibility of failure
both in ourselves and in others. But when done with this awareness and
the right intention, learning about others’ perceptions can be a powerful
way to critique our own.
Bridget Clarke’s (2012) suggestion for ‘critical moral perception’ fol-
lows this strategy. Clarke uses the example of sexism to show how it can
be done. In the case of gender, our perception is likely to be biased in
ways we do not even realise, so deep and old they are. We may feel dis-
comfort in some situations, but we do not know why. In this case, what
alerts us to the fact that our perceptions may not be truthful, that more
attention is needed, cannot come only from us. Taking inspiration from
feminist philosopher Marilyn Frye (1983, 1992), Clarke suggests that the
tools and prompts to query our perceptions can come from a particular
form of engagement with others, comparing our perceptions to theirs in
order to identify patterns:
Frye has argued that in order to break sexism’s grip on one’s percep-
tions—in order to perceive individuals or situations clearly—one
must be careful to relate the particulars of the moment, such things
as the individual man’s conscious intention and the individual wom-
an’s conscious perception of the event, to larger, systematic patterns
of behaviour and meaning. She identifies the discovery and articula-
tion of such patterns as the principal aim of feminist philosophy.
(Clarke 2012: 246)
One context in which this pattern-discovery can occur is, Frye suggests,
‘consciousness-raising’ conversations. These exchanges have the explicit
aim of discovering whether something may be amiss, whether my percep-
tion may be complacent, or whether your discomfort may be due to a
form of discrimination that only emerges by comparing our experiences.
Murdoch’s triangulation of concepts and experience makes this possibil-
ity available beyond the specific contexts of social discrimination. Again,
there is no guarantee of progress, but it is a way, and one that also brings
self-knowledge through engagement with what is outside.
Transparency
One of Murdoch’s descriptions of human consciousness is as a ‘system
of energy’ with a particular direction, of something that is ‘naturally
124 Self-knowledge
attached’ to the object (OGG 344). This suggests that, in order to
understand our inner states, it is necessary to understand their object. If
we take this thought further, we may ask whether it may even be enough,
in order to know our inner states, to direct our consciousness to the
object. This suggestion, known as the ‘transparency view’, is receiving
attention in philosophy of mind, and is helpfully developed by Richard
Moran (2001). Moran builds on Gareth Evans, credited with having
first suggested the transparency view. In a much-quoted passage, Evans
writes:
What is here called ‘the process of introspection’, we must note, is not the
standard meaning of ‘introspection’, as we have been using the word. It
refers, rather, to the process of understanding one’s inner state, which is
conducted, instead, by examining the object of one’s emotions. So self-
examination here appears not to be a matter of introspection at all. Mole,
in the essay discussed at the start of the chapter, makes the same point in
more general terms: ‘the features of ourselves that we learn about through
Self-knowledge 125
introspection are features that are morally salient only on account of
their relationships to things outside the self’ (2007: 83).
This method, importantly, preserves the inwardness and first personal
access to one’s inner states that Murdoch cares about. On the transpar-
ency account, self-knowledge is both non-inferential and privileged (see
Fernández 2013): by thinking about an object, we can discover our atti-
tudes towards it, but not somebody else’s. Privacy is preserved, but not a
logical or metaphysical kind of privacy which separates the inner from
the outer. Indeed, this account allows precisely the possibility that the
‘“inner” can … fuse with “outer” and not be lost’ (MGM 280). So even
when Murdoch writes that ‘It is into ourselves that we must look’, such
look can take place through an attempt to attend to the world. Indeed, in
the same page she continues: ‘This is not to advocate constant self-obser-
vation or some mad return to solipsism … much of our self-awareness is
other awareness’ (MGM 495).
If we try to understand an inner state in isolation, the state (the jeal-
ousy, the love, the resentment) in fact loses its identity (its ‘attachment’ as
Murdoch might say) as a state about something or someone, and is no
longer that of which knowledge can be obtained. To return to Weil’s
remarks quoted above, introspection does not yield self-knowledge, but
in fact distorts that about which it tries to acquire knowledge. The object
of introspection is an inner state (or indeed a character trait), but such
inner states are about something in the world.
Engaged self-knowledge
The discussion in this chapter has suggested that there is more than one
way of obtaining knowledge about the self that can be needed in atten-
tion, without attempting introspection understood as logically private
attention to an inner datum. If we want to know if we are perceiving our
friend’s new partner justly or whether ‘we’ are getting in the way of atten-
tion, then, how do we do it? We will look at, or think about, this person.
And then perhaps we will see that we focus much of our attention on
their negative traits, look at the particulars we do not like; or we will feel
a tension in our stomach, a sensation like discomfort or anger, which, if
we follow Wittgenstein, is not something we ‘know’, but something we
have.4 And so on. Then we’ll start to get a hint that perhaps our discom-
fort is a sign of bias.
These are instances that show us that something is going wrong in our
attention to this new person. And here we come to the final important
point about self-knowledge in attention. If, as we saw earlier, attention is
being ‘filled’ by the object, there is no room for thoughts about ourselves
even indirectly. So the self-knowledge we gain by trying to attend to an
object is through failed attention. We learn about ourselves when we get
in the way. But that is exactly the self-knowledge we need, for
126 Self-knowledge
self-knowledge is necessary for attention precisely when something about
us interferes with it. Not all inner states are relevant to attention. Not all
self-knowledge is needed.
Here we return to the importance of the motive we have for seeking
self-knowledge, which alone can avoid the self-satisfied spectatorial
attitude Murdoch cautions us against. Moran suggests an important
distinction that helps to clarify the problem. He distinguishes two pos-
sible attitudes to self-knowledge: a ‘theoretical’ and a ‘deliberative’ one.
The theoretical approach to self-knowledge is described as a kind of
self-indulgence, common in sentimental literature, where the scrutiny of
one’s inner life is ‘a contemplative one, separate from questions about
the world that those states of [ours] are presumably directed upon’
(Moran 2001: 58). Separately from the object of one’s inner state, it is
questionable whether our enquiry can constitute self-knowledge, and
indeed Moran comments that the inner state in question ‘is likely to be
inapt or fixated’. In cases like these, the attempt to gain self-knowledge
takes the form of ‘looking inward’. Understood thus, ‘in the sense of a
minute understanding of one’s own machinery’, Murdoch has reasons
to claim that ‘“self-knowledge” seems to me … usually a delusion’
(OGG 355).5 To gain self-knowledge, Moran concludes, we need a
‘deliberative’ attitude, which asks what is the appropriate response we
should have to the object, and takes the knower as an agent rather than
a spectator (2001: 63). The self-knowledge required by attention is
‘deliberative’, in Moran’s vocabulary, because it involves a concern
which is directed not to the self, but to the object of one’s inner states,
including a concern to discover which response the object merits. So the
key question that we can (and often should) ask about ourselves in
attention is this: ‘Am I being just to x?’—where knowledge of ourselves
is dependent on a grasp of the object.6
The reconciliation of self-knowledge and outward-directed attention
that I have offered does not deny that in obtaining self-knowledge there
is also a gaze that is directed towards ourselves, but it changes what
‘towards ourselves’ means. What transparency avoids is, on the one
hand, a direction of consciousness to some inner thing conceived of as
sealed off from the world. By doing that, it also, and on the other hand,
avoids an idle contemplative attitude to that illusory object, the inner
datum, which is for Murdoch more morally problematic than just onto-
logically misleading. So, of course, ‘Do I think there’s going to be a Third
World War?’ is a question that is not only about world politics but also
about me, what I believe. And similarly, beyond beliefs, ‘Am I being just
to A?’ is a question about me, and not only about A; so is the question
‘Am I jealous of A?’; and so on. Insofar as successful attention to the
object does not allow attention to me, the question of my belief or jeal-
ousy does not arise at the same time as the attentive question about the
object. The self-knowledge required for attention is obviously about us,
Self-knowledge 127
but it is obtained through an effort to attend to the object. We gain self-
knowledge, but the goal and the means of it must be placed away from
the self.
Notes
1 The ‘picture’ Murdoch is here referring to is the one in which fantasy is natu-
ral and liberation comes from love and true vision.
2 This story also, incidentally, shows how devastating loss of fantasy can be.
For a brief moment at the end of therapy, Thelma is liberated from her love
fantasy. But she does not find reality appealing, and falls into an even worse
depression. Truth is not as such more enjoyable, unless we desire it. What this
also shows, it seems to me, is that liberation from fantasy ought not to be
forced on us by someone else.
3 Weil’s ideas regarding the corrupting influence of ‘the social’ are found in
many places, as a critique, for instance, of the Roman Empire, and of political
parties. See e.g. ‘The Great Beast’ (GG 164–9); Oppression and Liberty
(2001); and On the Abolition of All Political Parties (2014).
4 This is known as Wittgenstein’s ‘expressivist thesis’, which is used to support
‘neo expressivist’ accounts of self-knowledge such as Bar-On’s (2004).
5 That is also, although not quite fair, an important part of Murdoch’s suspi-
cion of psychoanalysis, the other part being the possibility that the patient’s
thoughts and perceptions are reconfigured according to what is useful and
what ‘works’ for her mental health, rather than according to what is true.
6 Quassim Cassam (2015) reminds us of the inevitable possibility that, even in
this way, we may be failing to obtain self-knowledge. Vices, particularly intel-
lectual ones, are ‘stealthy’ because they cannot be discovered without intel-
lectual virtues. A vicious circle is formed, where close mindedness, for
instance, makes its own defeat near impossible in self-reflection. Hence,
Cassam suggests that we use other tools beyond self-reflection, and I agree.
The suggestions in the earlier part of this chapter are not to be considered as
last resort alternatives, but supplements to transparent self-reflection.
Bibliography
Bar-On, D. (2004) Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge. Oxford,
Oxford University Press.
Cassam, Q. (2015) Stealthy Vices. Social Epistemology Review and Reply
Collective. 4 (10), 19–25.
Christensen, A. M. S. (2019) ‘I Think I Disagree’: Murdoch on Wittgenstein and
Inner Life. In: Hämäläinen, N. and Dooley, G. (eds.) Reading Metaphysics as a
Guide to Morals. Cham, Switzerland, Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 145–161.
Clarke, B. (2012) Iris Murdoch and the Prospects for Critical Moral Perception.
In: Broackes, J. (ed.) Iris Murdoch, Philosopher. New York, Oxford University
Press, pp. 227–254.
Evans, G. (1982) The Varieties of Reference. Oxford, Oxford University Press.
Fernández, J. (2013) Transparent Minds: A Study of Self-Knowledge, Oxford,
Oxford University Press.
Frye, M. (1983) The Politics of Reality: Essays in Feminist Theory. Trumansburg,
NY, The Crossing Press.
128 Self-knowledge
Frye, M. (1992) Willful Virgin: Essays in Feminism. Freedom, CA, The Crossing
Press.
Goldman, A. (2006) Simulating Minds. Oxford, Oxford University Press.
Hampshire, S. (1959) Thought and Action. London, Chatto and Windus.
Hampshire, S. (1963) Disposition and Memory. International Journal of Psycho-
Analysis. 42, 59–68.
Mole, C. (2007) Attention, Self and The Sovereignty of Good. In: Rowe, A. (ed.)
Iris Murdoch: A Reassessment. London, Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 72–84.
Moran, R. (2001) Authority and Estrangement. Princeton, NJ, and Oxford,
Princeton University Press.
Murdoch, I. (1992) Metaphysics as a Guide to Morals [MGM]. London, Penguin.
Murdoch, I. (1998) Existentialists and Mystics: Writings on Philosophy and
Literature. Edited by Peter Conradi. Harmondsworth, Penguin.
———, Thinking and Language [T&L], pp. 33–42.
———, Nostalgia for the Particular [NP], pp. 43–58.
———, The Sublime and the Good [S&G], pp. 205–220.
———, The Idea of Perfection [IP], pp. 299–336.
———, On ‘God’ and ‘Good’ [OGG], pp. 337–365.
———, The Fire and The Sun: Why Plato Banished the Artists [F&S],
pp. 386–463.
Ryle, G. (1949) The Concept of Mind. Chicago, University of Chicago Press.
Ryle, G. (1951) Thinking and Language, Part III. Proceedings of the Aristotelian
Society. 65, 65–82.
Weil, S. (1995) Lectures on Philosophy [LP]. Translated by Hugh Price. Cambridge,
Cambridge University Press.
Weil, S. (2001) Oppression and Liberty [OL]. Translated by A. Wills and J. Petrie.
London and New York, Routledge.
Weil, S. (2002) Gravity and Grace [GG]. Translated by Emma Crawford and
Mario von der Ruhr. London and New York, Routledge.
Weil, S. (2014) On the Abolition of All Political Parties [APP]. Translated by
Simon Leys. New York, New York Review.
Wittgenstein, L. (2009) Philosophical Investigations. 4th ed. Translated by G. E.
M. Anscombe, P. M. S. Hacker and J. Schulte. Oxford, Wiley-Blackwell.
Yalom, I. D. (2012) Love’s Executioner & Other Tales of Psychotherapy.
New York, Basic Books.
5 Moral perception
DOI: 10.4324/9781003164852-6
130 Moral perception
by a mind that always operates through its orientation to the idea of the
good. At most, the distinction between the moral and non-moral is a
practical one, determined by our contextual practices and goals. Moral
perception is not a special kind of perception. I will return to this.
Perceiving smartly
We have seen how anything can be morally significant, and how the per-
ceptions of meat and suffering can be properly considered instances of
moral perception. It is still to be shown exactly how successful perception
of a moral reality occurs directly, or in non-mediated fashion, but with
the input of knowledge, experience, and specific value-orientation,
through attention.
Murdoch, typically, starts with experience and common sense. In many
situations (though of course not all) we say that we do ‘see’ cruelty, we
‘see’ that something is wrong; we also ‘see’ that the cow is suffering. That
is rather obvious in everyday life or, as Murdoch puts it, ‘outside the labo-
ratory, or untroubled by philosophy’ (MGM 278). Throughout her work,
Murdoch shows us various ways in which our experience of reality is
moral. What interests her mainly is the how, more than the why, of evalu-
ative experience in general (‘How do we come to see things this or that
way? ‘How do we purify our consciousness?’), and both the how and the
why of attentive truthful experience in particular.
I have already introduced Murdoch’s main argument for moral percep-
tion: perception occurs on the background of a consciousness that is
structured by value, by what we take to be good. Our knowledge, experi-
ence, concepts—which are, for her, guided by the imagination—shape
perception in many ways (without being ‘add-ons’). In this respect,
Murdoch was anticipating arguments more recently offered by McDowell
(2006) for the concept-ladenness of perception, by Gallagher (2008) for
its ‘smartness’, and by Dancy (2010) for its determination by knowledge
and prior experience. In this section I will expand Murdoch’s argument
introduced above with the help of some of these contemporary ideas.
When we successfully see suffering or injustice, we are able to identify
them as ‘suffering’ and ‘injustice’ because we are capable of grasping
together certain parts of the world in specific ways, and of making con-
nections with similar past experience and knowledge; the same is true of
seeing a red car. Where suffering, injustice, and red cars differ in percep-
tion is in how much knowledge and experience are required for identify-
ing them. In order of complexity, suffering is the simplest object of
perception (infants can detect emotions at around 5–7 months of age).12
Red cars come after. And injustice is last, because it takes more time with
the concept, more situations encountered, to know what it is. At the same
time, according to Murdoch’s perfectionist view, suffering and injustice
(perhaps red cars too) are all infinitely perfectible concepts, so their
Moral perception 139
perception can be constantly refined and deepened. This—and not some
kind of subjectivism or relativism—is the reason for the ‘personal’ nature
of experience that Murdoch defends. We can grasp the world from differ-
ent angles, as long as it’s the same world; but it may take some time.13
Here, opposers of moral perception would say that if you need knowl-
edge, concepts, or skills to perceive something, you are not perceiving but
inferring. But first, once again, that would be true of seeing a red car as
well, and we would have to conclude we are not seeing, but inferring, that
there is a red car over there. Second, there are features of the world which
we all agree are there, available to perception, and yet we cannot perceive
them unless we have acquired some knowledge or training.
Jonathan Dancy has pointed out that while moral perception sceptics
‘suppose that training, knowledge and experience cannot alter the way in
which things look, sound or feel to us’ (2010: 111), that cannot be true:
a car mechanic, in his example, can be properly represented as hearing
the malfunctioning of the water pump. Or: think about someone listening
to a piece of music and hearing the suspended chord (I couldn’t); or tast-
ing citrus in a wine (I can after I’m told). The idea that the ‘primary, or
basic object of perceptual awareness must be things for the sensing of
which no training, knowledge or experience is necessary’ (111) seems,
Dancy argued, like an assumption, and a wrong one, for it would prevent
us from talking about seeing, hearing, smelling, in the ways that we do.
Beyond supervenience
Like Dancy, Murdoch argues that it makes no sense to look ‘behind’ per-
ceptions of reality to find the ‘facts’ upon which moral perception may
depend. ‘Training, knowledge, and experience’ and, Murdoch would add,
concepts and imagination, are needed in all cases. Therefore, there is no
greater primacy in the case of cars than in the case of kindness. To put it
bluntly: if we can see a chair, we can also see kindness; and while the lat-
ter use of ‘see’ can be metaphorical, it is not always nor necessarily so.14
The fact and value distinction, then, is further eroded. This leads to a
Murdochian view of moral perception that, as I mentioned, is more radi-
cal than most arguments for moral perception, because by denying a fact-
value dichotomy, it denies that values supervene on facts. Even some
defences of Murdochian moral perception, such as A. E. Denham’s
(2001), fail to see this, by attributing to Murdoch a supervenience account
that is based on an ontological distinction between moral and non-moral
facts.15 Murdoch writes:
all just vision … is a moral matter … the same virtue (love) [is]
required throughout and fantasy (self) can prevent us from seeing a
blade of grass just as it can prevent us from seeing another person.
(OGG 357)
However, it seems more difficult to say that, in the case of the car mechanic
and the wine taster, self-concern is the problem. Knowledge, effort, and
training determine the perception, but why should moral qualities enter
into detecting the smell of a wine? Yet here, too, the two explicitly moral
elements of attention—unselfing and eros—play a part. We will be less
likely to taste the citrus fruit if we assume we know everything, and refuse
to learn from the sommelier, nor will we taste the full bouquet if we are
absorbed in our own world, lacking the desire to perceive what is there.
Concepts, knowledge, and imagination can be used more or less ‘trans-
parently’. Perception and what shapes it, such as concept-use or memory,
do not operate in the void. They can either latch on to something in the
world, or not. The more they are dictated by interests other than truth-
seeking, the thicker the veil between us and reality. Such poor use of the
tools of perception does not need to be conscious. Experience, habit,
instinctive responses can arm us with distorting tools (e.g. a previous
negative experience with a member of a particular group will create
‘knowledge’ that distorts the perception of the other members). This is
not at all easy to avoid, indeed impossible to avoid entirely, but attention
helps at least somewhat. If attention is, minimally, a truth-seeking turning
away from self-concern (as we saw in Chapters 2 and 3), and may even
involve some self-knowledge (as we saw in Chapter 4), it is more likely
that the tools will be transparent. Let us return to our examples and look
at this difference in a concrete case.
Moral perception 141
Direct perception of the cow’s suffering
Perceiving a cow suffering means perceiving her subjective experience,
including not only her physical but also her mental states. Similarly to the
other forms of perception just discussed, and, significantly, similarly to the
perception of explicitly moral properties such as cruelty, perceiving mental
states occurs non-inferentially but can be helped (or hindered) by previous
experience and other capacities, such as empathy. In order to see that this
cow is in pain, or that her situation is cruel, we need to access something
more than a mass of sense-data such as shapes and colours. That, however,
as we saw, does not need to mean that we make an inference. Attention can
help us use these tools to enrich and sharpen perception, but also to remove
impediments to enable a simpler, more immediate perception.
Contemporary defences of direct perception of mental states also
appeal to the fact that experience and knowledge inform perception non-
inferentially, on the model of moral perception just seen. Shaun Gallagher,
one of the earliest proponents of the ‘direct perception theory of mental
states’, argues that perception can be ‘smart’ when a significant amount
of knowledge is available in the content of perceptual experience. When
we see anger in another’s face, we are not inferring. This applies to the
perception of the mental states of non-human animals too (Morris 2017),
and vice-versa: other animals directly perceive our mental states (Paradiso,
Gazzola, and Keysers 2021).
Perception of mental states or social perception is, for Gallagher, ‘very
smart’ (2008: 538), for it can make use of a rich array of knowledge and
experience in an unmediated way. This is a recent development of an old
idea, one indeed that Murdoch would attribute to the common sense of
the individual ‘uncorrupted by philosophy’. One philosopher who tried
to be uncorrupted by philosophy is Wittgenstein, whom Gallagher also
quotes, for instance, here:
Animals who are entirely at the disposal of others, in this sense, do not
exist. Their non-instrumental value is invisible to anyone, including
themselves. If you have seen a picture of animals in production facilities,
laboratories, or slaughterhouses, the mark of affliction will be easily
apparent. Their eyes are empty, spent. The joy of being alive is absent.
Compare these images to those of animals in sanctuaries, who have been
rescued from affliction. Their eyes now bear the mark of their individual
personality, there is a spark, energy in their faces and movements.
Something that was not there previously is now present.
One of the central causes of affliction, Weil argues, is force. In her reading
of the Iliad, she defines force as ‘that X that turns anybody who is subjected
to it into a thing … It will surely kill, it will possibly kill, or perhaps it merely
hangs, poised and ready, over the head of the creature it can kill, at any
moment, which is to say at every moment’ (IPF 185). Force does not need to
exercise violence to annihilate its object. It is enough that the object is fully
at its mercy. Force means being able to do what we want with those who are
subject to it, who have no power over us. That is the condition of animals as
human property in farms, labs, circuses, and so on, across the world.17 Like
Weil’s remarks about a loan in ‘Essay on the Notion of Reading’ (2020), here
‘clarity about the nature of the animal’ in attention means recognising that
another living being, however afflicted and hence deprived of will and dig-
nity, is properly not an object merely to be possessed and used.
Attention—the attention that may have led to the rescue, and the nurs-
ing back to health, of the sanctuary animals mentioned above—is thus
creative. In the languages of possibilities, the possibility of seeing them as
individual subjects may have had to be actualised for the very first time. In
that sense, it was a creation. No one had seen that before, and acted accord-
ingly. That is not only the outcome of attention. The very act of attention—
animated by love and justice, or the desire to see, and the openness to being
affected by the other’s value—is a recognition that what we attend to mat-
ters. Otherwise we would just be passing them by.18
Notes
1 In my discussion of animals I am applying arguments that are made by Murdoch
and Weil with respect to human beings. They did not make these claims about
other animals, certainly not primarily. But it is both possible and helpful to use
these ideas in relation to the value of lives that are not only human.
2 I talk about suffering rather than pain in order to include both the experience
of physical pain and psychological suffering, which are both frequent in ani-
mals used for human purposes, and the latter is often present even in the
Moral perception 147
absence of physical pain (e.g. the separation of calves from their mothers in the
dairy industry, or the confinement in most cases, or the psychological suffering
of laboratory animals). For a detailed discussion of the concepts of pain and
suffering, in relation to other animals, see DeGrazia and Rowan (1991).
3 ‘At [a] primitive level, appetitive and aversive behavioral responses are modu-
lated by specific neural circuits in the brain that share common neuroarchi-
tecture among mammals … At the behavioral level it is evident from the
descriptions of comparative psychologists and ethologists that behaviors
homologous to empathy can be observed in other mammalian species’
(Decety and Moriguchi 2007: 2).
4 Most non-human animals are bred for human food: 94% of all mammal
biomass (excluding humans) is livestock (Bar-On, Phillips, and Milo 2018); a
smaller but far from insignificant number, for clothing, scientific experiments,
company and entertainment.
5 As this quote could be misleading, notice the ‘and’: vision is not only a
metaphor.
6 Scott Clifton (2013) argues for Murdochian moral perception as the morality
in perception. While that view is to be found in Murdoch, it is incomplete; in
fact, if one meaning should be prioritised it is moral perception as referring to
moral quality of what we perceive, because morality in perception matters
insofar as what we perceive matters. The very idea of attention as just vision
of reality would make little sense if reality itself did not matter.
7 For a recent good psychological defense of cognitive penetration, see Newen
and Vetter (2017).
8 The mind, in order to perceive correctly, needs to be attuned to the same idea
of perfection which determines specific moral facts and properties. The mind
is attuned to the idea of the good, which can only be thought of as real. See
Murdoch’s discussions of Anselm’s Ontological proof, and of Plato’s idea of
the Good.
9 To say we engage with reality for ‘specific reasons’ does not entail an instru-
mental approach. The reason or goal could be simply to see what is there,
which is in fact the underlying driver of attention.
10 Thus Megan Laverty attributes to Murdoch a philosophy of the ‘third way’,
‘between absolutism (an objective impersonal unified truth) and subjectivism
(proliferating, plural subjective “truths”)’ (2007: 9), where the mind is pic-
tured neither as a ‘mirror’ nor a ‘lamp’, but as a ‘lens’, which grasp a reality
external to itself but, necessarily, with its own resources, which order and
form it in such a way as to make it available to us.
11 While I am mostly talking, in both cases, about visual perception (it is practically
easier, after all, than to ask you to go and place your hand on a cow’s back), it is
important that perception of suffering, especially of animal suffering, occurs
through other senses too, and perhaps even more easily through touch.
12 See Walker 1982.
13 Cf. Weil in ‘Essay on the Notion of Reading’ (2020), where she notes that,
while only God can have the absolutely correct view of a situation (which she
calls ‘readings’), human beings can achieve at least partially correct views, so
that it makes sense of think of possible criteria of correctness, however diffi-
cult the attempt to find them is.
14 Metaphors, moreover, are not understood by Murdoch as merely saying
something in place of something else, as if there were a different, ‘literal’ way
of expressing the same thought (cf. MGM 177–8).
15 I have defended a non-supervenience-based account of moral perception in
Murdoch in Panizza 2020, where I develop some of the present arguments on
moral perception.
148 Moral perception
16 See also Chappell 2018: 103–105.
17 This is also one of the key claims of the ‘abolitionist approach’ in animal eth-
ics which, despite other controversial aspects, is right about this: having the
kind of mastery over animals given by property is inherently wrong, regard-
less of how we then decide to treat them.
18 The idea that being attended to creates us finds some support in cognitive
science: as Vasudevi Reddy (2003) has argued, awareness of self develops in
early infants through mutual attention.
Bibliography
Adams, C. (1990) The Sexual Politics of Meat: A Feminist-Vegetarian Critical
Theory. New York, Continuum.
Audi, R. (2013) Moral Perception. Princeton, Princeton University Press.
Bagnoli, C. (2012) The Exploration of the Moral Life. In: Broackes, 197–226.
Bar-On, Y. M., Phillips, R. and Milo, R. (2018) The Biomass Distribution on
Earth. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 115 (25),
6506–6511.
Broackes, J. (2012) Introduction. In: Broackes, J. (ed.) Iris Murdoch, Philosopher.
Oxford and New York, Oxford University Press, pp. 1–92.
Chappell, T. (2008) Moral Perception. Philosophy. 83 (4), 421–437.
Chappell, S. G. (2018) Love and Knowledge in Murdoch. In: Browning, G. (ed.)
Murdoch on Truth and Love. Cham, Switzerland, Palgrave Macmillan.
Clifton, S. (2013) Murdochian Moral Perception. The Journal of Value Inquiry.
47, 207–220.
Dancy, J. (2010) Moral Perception. Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume.
84 (1), 99–117.
Decety, J. and Moriguchi, Y. (2007) The Empathic Brain and its Dysfunction in
Psychiatric Populations: Implications for Intervention Across Different Clinical
Conditions. BioPsychoSocial Medicine. 1 (22).
Faraci, D. (2015) A Hard Look at Moral Perception. Philosophical Studies. 172
(8), 2055–2072.
DeGrazia, D. and Rowan, A. (1991) Pain, Suffering, and Anxiety in Animals and
Humans. Theoretical Medicine. 12, 193–211.
Denham, A. E. (2001) Envisioning the Good: Iris Murdoch’s Moral Psychology.
Modern Fiction Studies. 47 (3), 602–629.
Gallagher, S. (2008) Direct Perception in the Intersubjective Context.
Consciousness and Cognition. 17, 535–543.
Harman, G. (1977) The Nature of Morality: An Introduction to Ethics. Oxford,
Oxford University Press.
Holland, M. (1998) Touching the Weights: Moral Perception and Attention.
International Philosophical Quarterly. 38 (3), 299–312.
Laverty, M. (2007) Iris Murdoch’s Ethics. A Consideration of her Romantic
Vision. London, Continuum.
Leibler J. H., Janulewicz, P. A. and Perry, M. J. (2017) Prevalence of Serious
Psychological Distress Among Slaughterhouse Workers at a United States Beef
Packing Plant. Work. 57 (1): 105–109.
McDowell, J. (2006) Conceptual Capacities in Perception. In: Abel, G. (ed.)
Kreativität. Hamburg, Felix Meiner Verlag.
Moral perception 149
Morris, P. (2017) Direct Perception of Animal Mind. Animal Sentience 14 (5).
Murdoch, I. (1992) Metaphysics as a Guide to Morals [MGM]. London, Penguin.
Murdoch, I. (1998) Existentialists and Mystics: Writings on Philosophy and
Literature. Edited by Peter, Conradi. Harmondsworth, Penguin.
———, Thinking and Language [T&L], pp. 33–42.
———, Vision and Choice in Morality [VCM], pp. 76–98.
———, The Darkness of Practical Reason [DPR], pp. 193–202.
———, The Idea of Perfection [IP], pp. 299–336.
Newen, A. and Vetter, P. (2017) Why Cognitive Penetration of Our Perceptual
Experience Is Still the Most Plausible Account. Consciousness and Cognition.
47, 26–37.
Panizza, S. (2020) Moral Perception Beyond Supervenience: Iris Murdoch’s
Radical Perspective. The Journal of Value Inquiry. 54, 273–288.
Paradiso, E. Gazzola, V. and Keysers, C. (2021) Neural Mechanisms Necessary
for Empathy-related Phenomena Across Species. Current Opinion in
Neurobiology. 68, 107–115.
Reddy, V. (2003) On Being the Object of Attention: Implications for Self–other
Consciousness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences. 7 (9), 397–402.
Robjant, D. (2012) The Earthy Realism of Plato’s Metaphysics, or: What Shall We
Do with Iris Murdoch? Philosophical Investigations. 35, 43–67.
Väyrynen, P. (2018) Doubts about Moral Perception. In Bergqvist, A. and Cowan,
R. (eds.) Evaluative Perception. Oxford, Oxford University Press.
Walker A. S. (1982) Intermodal Perception of Expressive Behaviors by Human
Infants. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology. 33, 514–535.
Weil, S. (1951) Waiting for God [WG] Translated by Emma Craufurd. New York,
Harper and Row.
———, The Love of Our Neighbour [LN], pp. 139–158.
Weil, S. (1956) The Iliad or the Poem of Force [IPF]. Translated by Mary
McCarthy. Wallingford, Pennsylvania, Pendle Hill.
Weil, S. (2005) Simone Weil: An Anthology. Edited by Siân, Miles. London,
Penguin.
———, Human Personality [HP], pp. 69–98.
Weil, S. (2020) Essay on the Notion of Reading. Translated by Chris Fleming. The
Journal of Continental Philosophy. 1 (1), 9–15.
6 Motivation and action
To talk about the ‘links’ between attention and action is not to presup-
pose a radical distinction between the two, a distance that needs to be
bridged. Nor does my focus on action here go against the grain of
Murdoch’s well-known rehabilitation of the inner life as morally signifi-
cant in itself. In fact, Murdoch’s emphasis on the inner life is a reaction
not only to an undue focus on action in ethics, and on behaviour in phi-
losophy of mind, but also against any sharp division between inner and
outer, consciousness and action. The goal is not so much to replace action
with consciousness in ethics, but rather to consider how closely they are
related. The inner life matters. What we do matters as well. One leads to
the other, at times with a sense of inevitability or necessity that makes any
clear separation between inner and outer seem artificial.
In line with Murdoch’s overall project, the concept of ‘action’ that is
the end point of the attentive process is itself very different from the
concept used in the anti-realist ethical model that Murdoch is opposing,
DOI: 10.4324/9781003164852-7
Motivation and action 151
where action arises out of an independent will that surveys the situation
and chooses. Instead, attention leads to action in a way that makes action
a natural outcome of attention, sometimes even an accompaniment or
manifestation of attention: what Murdoch, following Weil, calls ‘obedi-
ence’ to reality as revealed by attention. We will see how intense attention
can lead to this experience of necessity, or having no choice but to do
something, where the question of what to do does not even arise.
Importantly, the demand that comes through attention is experienced as
a demand that comes not from ourselves, not from our will, not from
reason, but from reality. A reality of which we are part.
Since the argument follows from the previous chapter, I will also retain
the case study: attention to animals, here with the aim of showing how
attention to animal suffering leads to certain actions, and away from oth-
ers. To that end I will continue to expand on, as explained in the
Introduction, Murdoch’s and Weil’s arguments about human beings, to
include other animals: although their focus is the human, their arguments
work, and indeed work powerfully, in the case other animals too.
This capacity can cut across species, both in our ability to perceive the
inner states of other animals, and in their capacity to perceive our own
(De Waal 2008 in Aaltola 2018a p. 25.)
Obstacles to empathy
If is this so, however, what’s the use of attention? If empathy is some-
thing we are all capable of, and if empathy to suffering also involves a
negative experience, which comes with the desire to avoid it, isn’t that
enough? The fact that sometimes perception of (animal) suffering does
not yield this response means it is not. In what follows, I will suggest
that, when motivation to remove suffering is absent, something in the
perception of suffering has been blocked, thwarted, dampened. And that
we need attention to restore the fulness and truthfulness of that
perception.
Motivation and action 155
As Murdoch cautions us again and again, the main problem in such
cases, and in most moral situations, is not that the action needed is miss-
ing or difficult, but that there are many imperceptible ways in which what
is there is cancelled or distorted. The ego, Murdoch reminds us, is always
alert, and more alert than we are. There are two particularly problematic
ways such blocking can happen. The first is that often, when we see suf-
fering, we look away precisely because we empathise: we feel bad, and we
want that feeling to stop, so we stop looking. The other is the fact that
perceiving suffering can give rise not to empathy, but to enjoyment. But
since these are outcomes of perception, don’t they also function as objec-
tions to my claim that attention to animal suffering naturally generates
an empathetic response which includes the desire for that suffering to
end? I will argue that they do not. Those are outcomes of perception, not
of attention. Which entails that the perception itself, in these cases, is not
clear, complete, or direct.
Looking away
The first case just mentioned is indeed very common. In fact, I think it is
probably the most common way of relating to animal suffering, espe-
cially human-caused animal suffering. Here, the perception of animal suf-
fering probably starts out as attentive and truthful: this engenders the
empathetic response, including our own suffering. But at that moment,
attention stops. Truth becomes hard to bear. We are suffering. And then
we look away. This is the moment, Murdoch would say, when the ego
takes over. And that is why attention ends: our own suffering, not the
suffering of the animal, takes centre stage, and that is what motivates the
reaction to look away (physically, or metaphorically, to stop thinking
about it). The reaction does not follow the direct perception of the reality
we are seeing, but it follows our own emotional state in response to it. In
other words, if attention is directed outward, this reaction takes the
wrong object. The problem, here, is with sustained attention.
This response to animal suffering is everywhere: it is visible in the ten-
dency to ascribe lower levels of mental capacities to the animals consid-
ered appropriate for human consumption, or even deny minds to those
animals when we are reminded of the fact that meat production involves
the suffering of those animal (as the psychological studies by Bastian et
al. 2012 have found). If attention reveals an uncomfortable reality, some-
thing about that reality must go, and attention ends there. The self-pro-
tective work of the ego begins, and it takes many forms: to protect us in
our immediate empathetic suffering (‘that is not really happening, this
animal is not really suffering’); to protect our self-image (‘I am a good
person’); to preserve the self-image of humanity in general (‘we are a
good species, our most common practices must be acceptable’); even to
maintain the perhaps necessary comfort that there is an overall
156 Motivation and action
preponderance of goodness in the world, and nothing disrupts the reality
of good in unbearable ways—a need and a worry that Murdoch addresses
repeatedly in MGM, beginning from the reflections on the desire for
‘form’ and ‘unity’ in Chapter 1.
The variety of these motives for removing attention shows that they
are not only individual responses, but also shaped by culture, practices,
social norms. The perceived normality of the human use of animals plays
a large role in removing attention, making the reality of the suffering
hard to ‘square’ with a good society, which also routinely uses those ani-
mals. A merely instrumental use of someone else, as Murdoch knew, can-
not coexist with attention (OGG 353–354). Does that someone else need
to be human? We unreflectively recognise other animals as ‘others’, as
Derrida knew (2002). In animal ethics, Josephine Donovan (1996) was
among the first to draw out the implications of Murdochian attention for
animals. In an essay arguing for the importance of attending to animal
suffering, she quotes Brian Luke, who
Social, political and economic forces are at work all the time to direct,
thwart and blunt our attention, as we are increasingly aware.5 And
Murdoch was too (although most of her arguments target the individual),
suggesting that ‘Modern industrial mass-productive society impairs our
power to perceive’ (MGM 377).
That is not to say that anyone who is not overtly contributing to a
given form of suffering is immune to looking away. Empathy with suffer-
ers is, by definition, painful, and whether or not we have all the motives
above, we have this one. Attending to suffering is hard, and when suffer-
ing is so widespread, relentless and extreme as the second-by-second suf-
fering of animals at human hands, it can be so hard that sometimes one
wishes to say, ‘The hell with attention and moral progress, this is not the
world I want to live in, “I return my ticket”’, and at that point, fantasy
can feel like a warm embrace:6
Motivation and action 157
there is the almost insuperable difficulty of looking properly at evil
and human suffering. It is very difficult to concentrate attention upon
suffering and sin, in others or in oneself, without falsifying the pic-
ture in some way while making it bearable.
(OGG 359)
This is what happens, according to Weil, when the Samaritan looks at the
man by the side of the road. He sees him as someone who suffers. ‘This
way of looking is first of all attentive’ (RSS 115).
Enjoying suffering
The second objection was that, far from being sure that when we see suf-
fering we will feel empathy and compassion, a non-negligible amount of
people in fact enjoy the spectacle. Perhaps we do not admit it, but some-
times, for some of us, there’s something attractive, not aversive, in the
perception of suffering. This phenomenon is exemplified in the common
objection to the ethics of attention raised with the example of the ‘tor-
turer’: someone who wants to inflict suffering, and for the sake of the
example who also enjoys doing so, and who pays intense and focused
attention to the victim precisely in order to get more suffering out of her.
The torturer looks closely, asking: ‘What are her weak spots? Which gri-
mace in her face tells me that this is a particularly painful touch, so I need
to press further?’ Here, inflicting suffering is possible not because the
torturers look away, but on the contrary because they look closely. And
they like it. But torturers and grand sadists aside, ‘everyday sadism’ is a
real and very common phenomenon. Chances are, we have experienced it
ourselves at some point (Buckels et al. 2013).
Like compassion, this positive focus on others’ suffering can also be
trained, in an undesirable way. Studies on violent video games have
shown (not shockingly) that it was not only the case that everyday sadists
are more drawn to violent games, but also that ‘repeated exposure to
violent video games predicts everyday sadism over time’ (Greitemeyer
and Sagioglou 2017: 238). Here we see from the other side the truth of
Murdoch’s stress on building habits of attention, and how such habits
shape us, partly determining our future objects of attention, which in
turn determine what we will be sensitive to, in what ways, and what we
will ignore.
Motivation and action 159
Does the apparent existence of ‘sadistic attention’ invalidate the claim
that attention is something fundamental to morality, and inherently desir-
able? There are two ways to cast doubt on the idea that the sadist can
properly be said to be exercising attention. The first has to do with the
scope of the sadist’s vision; the second with its quality.
What is the sadist attending to? Not the individual human or animal.
That would yield the vision of a creature who is not only suffering, but
who has desires (right now, the desire to stop suffering), is probably
afraid, has a past and (if allowed) a future, has played a role in someone
else’s life, and so on. Instead, the sadist’s gaze is razor thin. It selects
something about the object—the suffering—to the exclusion of every-
thing that is not relevant to it. In this way, then, they are not attending to
the individual. They are not seeing the individual, because a narrow focus
on an aspect of an individual distorts the whole understanding of that
individual.
Well, but can’t we say the sadist is not attending to the individual, may
not be seeing the individual at all, but is still properly attending to the
suffering? In one sense, no, for suffering is someone’s suffering, and not
seeing the individual distorts the suffering too. But there is another rea-
son, connected to the truthfulness of attention, that denies the idea of
sadistic attention. If attention, as I have been suggesting following
Murdoch, is properly directed upon the world and upon the truth of that
portion of the world it is taking for its object, then the sadist’s attention
is not truly attention because its aim is not fully object-directed. In sadism,
the filtering of the self is at peak level: the goal is not to seek what is true
but to gain enjoyment. So the intention that animates it is highly self-
concerned, not world-concerned (i.e., it is not at all eros).
This is a point also made by Dorothea Debus (2013), defending atten-
tion precisely against the torturer objection.8 Debus uses the selectivity of
attention to argue that if we are attending (fully, she adds) to the suffer-
ing individual, there is no room for our egocentric desires: in her words,
our desires can have no ‘phenomenal salience’ in (full) attention. This is
based on the observation that attention can be correctly described accord-
ing to a ‘Synchronic Exclusivity Claim’, which states that ‘in order for
someone to be said to give her full attention to an object (or event) at
some particular time, it is necessary that she do pay attention to the
particular object (or event) at the time, and that she do not pay any atten-
tion to anything else at the same time’ (2013: 1183). To put it with
Murdoch, in Sovereignty, in these cases ‘nothing exists except the things
which are seen’ (OGG 353).
On the other hand, when the object is scanned, so to speak, in order to
detect pleasure-bringing suffering, it is not only the desire or goal, but the
act itself, that is not truthful, insofar as it is seeking something specific.
Such seeking is contrasted with the openness of attention, whose truthful
element consists not only in wanting to see what is there, but to be willing
160 Motivation and action
to receive it, whatever it is. So the sadistic scanning of the other’s experi-
ence is on this count the opposite of attentive perception. We see this
point clearly in Weil’s famous formulation of attention, in which ‘all our
thought should be empty, waiting, not seeking anything, but ready to
receive in its naked truth the object which is to penetrate it’ (RSS 112).
The object that penetrates our consciousness, in our example, is a suf-
fering animal. If attention is directed upon the object, it is also directed at
the experience of the individual. The openness of attention, also found in
Weil’s quote, is a complete openness, intellectual but also affective. So if
enjoyment of another’s suffering can be said to involve empathy—needed
in order to recognise and exploit that suffering—it is only the ‘cognitive’
kind. In fact, as Wai and Tiliopoulos (2012) have found, this skewing
towards purely cognitive empathy affects not only sadists, but also all the
‘dark triad personalities’ (Psychopathy, Narcissism, and Machiavellianism)
who are ‘associated with deficits in affective empathy, but show little evi-
dence of impairment in cognitive empathy’ (794). Cognitive empathy, as
Aaltola (2018a) points out, allows us to manipulate others, while affec-
tive empathy—which is the kind that is connected with attention—is the
kind that sustains moral understanding and behaviour.
Perceiving possibilities
Attention to suffering, then, enables a successful perception of suffering
which comes with an aversive response. As Murdoch writes: ‘The details
of our world deserve our respectful and loving attention … With this goes
a perception of the reality and real nature of suffering and a horror of
cruelty’ (MGM 377). Our primary response is that the suffering should
stop. This is enough to produce motivation to act accordingly, but we
also need to know how to act—what the specific action required of us
may be. Attention shows us what is there: the suffering that should not
be. But it also shows us something else: what is possible. This is the sec-
ond explanatory step from perception to action. Attention consists in
imaginative engagement that brings possibilities out. As Murdoch writes,
the imagination is ‘a type of reflection on people, events … which builds
detail, adds colour, conjures up possibilities in ways which go beyond
what could be said to be strictly factual’ which is also ‘a sort of personal
exploring’ (DPR 48, emphasis in the original). As we know, all percep-
tion, for Murdoch, requires some amount of imagination.9 Attention
involves a truth-seeking use of the imagination.
Murdoch’s account of perception, as we have seen, makes room for the
individual’s contribution to it. Through attention, that contribution is
imaginative and creative, insofar as attention allows us to bring out
something which is there, but not available without moral effort. As
Murdoch writes, ‘clear vision is a result of moral imagination and moral
effort’ (IP 329). The subject is active and involved in perception, where
Motivation and action 161
the subject and the world are involved in a sort of collaboration. If we use
the imagination to see what is there, according to Murdoch, we can also
see, at the same time, what is possible for us in the situation—what pos-
sibilities a situation, justly perceived, affords us.
We now have two further crucial elements of attentive perception: that
we can see certain possibilities, and that doing so includes the ways in
which we can be involved in actualising these possibilities. This gives rise
to two questions about attention: why does attention show some possi-
bilities and not others, and how are we involved in their actualization?
Affordances
In contemporary psychology, the idea that there are perceptual possibili-
ties is theorised under the name of affordances. Introduced by James
Gibson (1979), affordances describe the way in which we perceive objects
in terms of the possibilities they afford, or ‘opportunities for action’. The
apple is eat-able, pick-able, cut-able, and so on. Importantly, Gibson does
not limit the perception of affordances to humans, but includes other
animals. Like in Murdochian moral perception, and like the perception
of mental states, affordances are directly perceptible (Gibson 1979: 127),
that is, not inferred. And they are based on real properties, ‘out there’ in
the world, to which we can latch on or not (Gibson 1979: 133). My sug-
gestion is that attention allows us to see some affordances that we other-
wise would not.
A suffering animal, with her relative need not to suffer, affords helping
her: ‘social affordances’, when ‘a person or an animal shows up to an
observer not as a physical object but as an agent with the capacity to
reciprocate’ (Brancazio 2020: 9–10), are for Gibson ‘the richest and most
elaborate affordances of the environment’ (Gibson, quoted in de Carvalho
2020: 2). We see possibilities in others, and these possibilities are of a
special kind thanks to our perception of them as subjects. This applies to
other animals, including, as it does,
Action
Attention, in our example, shows us a need, and possibilities related to
that need, with an immediacy that is typical of perception, and not of
reflection. Because of its focus, and the exclusion of what is not relevant
to the object (including, and in fact primarily, ego-driven motivations),
attention leaves no space for ‘What if?’, ‘Should I really?’, ‘Do I want to?’,
and so on. In this respect, attention is different from moral thinking as
ordinarily conceived, because there is no room, nor need, for delibera-
tion. At the same time, it also satisfies a traditional requirement of moral
properties (maintained, for instance, by Mackie, but which led him to a
very different conclusion): that moral properties should be motivating.
For Mackie, that is the reason to think that moral properties cannot
really exist in the world; nothing can be a fact and intrinsically motivat-
ing at the same time. For Murdoch, that means that everything is in some
sense a moral fact: everything pushes and pulls us in some direction.
Motivation and action 163
But it matters how we look. We can be pulled in wrong directions, driven
by our own desires or false perceptions. Or we can be pulled by the world,
and conform our desires to it, if we pay attention.
Motivational internalism
According to Weil and Murdoch, the perception yielded by attention is
motivating and action-producing. In contemporary terminology, they are
defending a strong and unusual form of motivational internalism. The
most common understanding of motivational internalism is defined by
Bjorklund et al. (2012) in the following way:
This position gives rise to all sorts of familiar problems: first among
them is represented by the case of the amoralist, who makes moral
judgements but lacks the related motivation to carry out their implica-
tions (they ‘know’ what’s right, they’re just indifferent), and the weak
willed, who lack self-control (‘that’s good but I can’t bring myself to
do it’). In response, various modified versions of motivational internal-
ism have been proposed. But these problems arise because motivational
internalism claims a connection between judgements and motivation.
The difficulty arises on a view of judgements as abstract, rational, non-
affective, which then needs to be linked to the embodied, affective ele-
ment of motivation and action. Attention, on the other hand, primarily
yields perception, not judgements (it can yield judgements too, but
they are secondary now). And linking perception and motivation does
not incur in the above difficulties: perception is already embodied,
already affective. The motivational internalism of attentive perception
is better explained by the disjunctivist view of motivational internal-
ism, as supported by Antti Kauppinen (2015) (who, however, talks
about intuitions as quasi-perceptual states, rather than perception).
On this view, moral beliefs are only contingently related to motivation,
but moral intuitions (‘spontaneous and compelling non-doxastic
appearances of right or wrong’) and, I add, perceptions, are internally
related to motivation, which for Kauppinen is due to their inclusion of
emotive content, or their ‘emotional manifestations of moral senti-
ments’ (238).12
Let us recap. We pay attention to a suffering animal. We see the suffer-
ing. The perception is aversive. We perceive the suffering of this cow as
something that should not be. This is the first stirring of motivation,
although it is not specific: it is a magnetism, in the opposite direction.
What is already clear is that our action will go in the direction of ending
164 Motivation and action
the suffering. What we need to see is how this motivation takes a specific
shape, and becomes our action.
Once again, with Weil,
Perceptual motivation
As Tom McClelland and Marta Jorba (2021) have argued, affordances
help us explain how motivation for action can be derived directly from
perception. Unlike other accounts of perceptual motivation, the affor-
dance account satisfies the three criteria for perceptual motivation that
McClelland and Jorba set out: having direct motivational force (indepen-
dent of beliefs and desires); having non-obligatory force (where ‘obliga-
tory’ refers to something like a reflex, such as blinking—this may seem
like a denial of ‘obedience’, but the view accepts that in some cases affor-
dances are indeed compelling); and having intention-independent influ-
ence. These criteria are satisfied by Weil’s and Murdoch’s account of the
motivational nature of attentive perception. Importantly, attentional
motivation is direct—not inferred, as we saw in the previous chapter—
and not ‘up to us’, insofar as the actions following perception do not
depend on our desires.
The idea of motivation as coming from what we perceive is also con-
sistent with our experience of some situations and objects as motivating
Motivation and action 165
unless we activate our will against them—hence interrupting atten-
tion. As McClelland and Jorba argue, ‘agential phenomenology’ is
such that ‘when you are perceptually motivated to φ it does not seem
as though one’s φ-ing depends on you intending to φ. Instead, it seems
as though one will φ unless one resists doing so’ (n.p.). Here, parallel
considerations to the ones above regarding resisting motivating empa-
thetic perception can be offered. When we attend, and feel the demand
placed on us by the world, we can indeed escape it, which means first
of all stopping attention. But if we do not, it will happen: attention
means allowing it to move us. What is up to us, then, at least to some
extent, is the paying or sustaining of attention. The point is that, in
these cases, actions require no reflection; the space for deliberation is
closed: ‘To know that this man who is hungry and thirsty really exists
as much as I do—that is enough, the rest follows of itself” (Weil,
GG 108).
If we attend, the possibilities that the situation affords us, as we have
seen, will be limited in the direction of the need of the object of our atten-
tion, and away from our instrumental uses of it. That’s why attending to
an animal does not show us something to exploit, but someone to help,
interact with, and so on. The more intense and successful the attention,
the more limited these possibilities will be, by showing us with clarity the
real need, and shutting down everything else. In order words, nothing else
is salient. This is how, according to Murdoch and Weil, we get to the
‘ideal situation’ where deliberation is unnecessary, indeed the question of
what to do does not even arise, for we see (and feel in our bones) what is
required of us. Weil writes:
I think we know enough about Weil by now to also know what that state
is.
Obedience
This view of perceptual motivation is deeply Weilian. It connects to the
idea that the will is more like an interruption, rather than an aid, to good-
ness. Murdoch mostly agrees, but is more tolerant. The will has some
role, although generally a negative one (refraining from doing some-
thing).14 This view depends, in turn, on Weil’s mystical, and Murdoch’s
moral psychological, view of reality as normative. Weil writes that the
166 Motivation and action
realisation of moral necessity occurs through obedience, which is the out-
come of sustained and intense attention to reality:
Murdoch echoes: ‘If I attend properly I will have no choices and this is
the ultimate condition to be aimed at’. And continues: ‘The idea of a
patient, loving regard, directed upon a person, a thing, a situation, pres-
ents the will not as unimpeded movement but as something very much
more like ‘obedience’ (IP 331).15 Obedience is the manifestation of the
intimate connection between the clear and intense perception enabled by
attention, the motivation to act according to what we perceive, and the
actions that follow.
Attention can bring about epiphanies which stay with us, like Alyosha’s
ecstatic experience in Dostoevsky’s Brothers Karamazov, which instils in
him a love for the world which marks him for the rest of his life. It hap-
pens to him one night, as he walks out of the convent, onto the grass
under the starry sky, and feels an overwhelming joy and a compulsion to
drop to his knees:
Conclusion
In this chapter I have done my best to offer arguments as to why atten-
tion leads to action, including descriptions of what that is like. But these,
like other considerations in the rest of the book, are at best approxima-
tions to something that we can find out, quite vividly, if we actually expe-
rience such attention to a suffering animal, and what happens in us as a
result. Attention to suffering—in anyone—will show us what Murdoch
meant by placing vision at the centre of the moral life, and also what Weil
meant, in ‘Human Personality’ and in her recounting of the story of the
Samaritan: we do not help others because they have rights, or because we
judge them to be worthy based on criteria they have satisfied. We help
them because they need our help.
The whole enterprise of seeking criteria for moral value, in fact, seems
almost corrupt, if it aims to establish a hierarchy of who matters more
and who less, who matters and who does not. It is a telling sign of the
refusal to pay attention that much debate on animal ethics has, mostly at
its inception as academic discipline but even now, revolved around just
this: how do we know who has value, and among those who have value,
who has more? We do not save lives because they matter enough, or more
than others. We save them because they need saving, and because we can.
The love of our neighbour in all its fullness simply means being able
to say to him: ‘What are you going through?’ It is a recognition that
Motivation and action 169
the sufferer exists, not only as a unit in a collection, or a specimen
from the social category labelled ‘unfortunate’, but as a man, exactly
like us, who was one day stamped with a special mark by affliction.
For this reason it is enough, but it is indispensable, to know how to
look at him in a certain way.
This way of looking is first of all attentive. The soul empties itself
of all its own contents in order to receive into itself the being it is
looking at, just as he is, in all his truth.
Only he who is capable of attention can do this.
(RSS 115)
Notes
1 This could include the perception of ourselves ‘from the outside’ which, as we
saw in Chapter 4, is compatible with the outward focus of attention. Being a
participant in a specific situation does not involve any inward gaze, but sim-
ply a complete apprehension of all the elements of the situation.
2 See the section on agency in Chapter 1.
3 See Read and Szokolszky (2020) for an exploration of the differences between
enactivism and ecological psychology.
4 This may be unfair, but ‘endearing’ makes Schopenhauer sound like an over-
sensitive pet. Regardless, Murdoch acknowledges animal value but in pass-
ing, and in a way that does not assign special value to non-human animals as
opposed to plants. There is an assumption of a dichotomy of human vs non-
human, and while the latter can be worthy of love and attention, there is a
clear boundary drawn around humans, but little between animals and other
forms of life, or even inanimate objects.
5 See e.g. the books by Citton (2017) and Lanham (2007).
6 See Ivan’s speech in Dostoevsky’s Brother Karamazov.
7 The training, partly based on Buddhist metta meditation, involved three ele-
ments: envisioning suffering, mindful attention to reactions to suffering, and
cultivating compassion. This is also a good example of the way in which, as
we saw in previous chapters, our own reactions and states of mind in the
context of attention can be at the service of, rather than detrimental to, the
reality that we are confronting, without challenging the importance of atten-
tion as fundamentally other-directed.
8 With the difference, as we have seen, that for her it is ‘full attention’ that can
defy the objection; while in the present account, attention is enough.
9 Let us not be misled by the mention of ‘beyond the factual’ to think that
imagination is a kind of projection or ‘making things up’ (that is the role of
‘fantasy’). Murdoch is clear that imagination is what allows us to approach
the world, not to take distance from it: it is part of perception, the ordering
and sense-making faculty that shows us chairs and tables, and freedom and
love. What is ‘strictly factual’, then, is not what is ‘factual’. The former is the
‘surface of things’, the impersonal world (which, in Murdoch’s view, is not the
world at all). The latter is what is real, but available only to attentive imagina-
tion. Which, at its peak, is found in the work of the artist—although in this
sense we’re all artists: ‘[the] “ordinary” truth is also the truth of art, as it
170 Motivation and action
emerges when the artist, confronted by the independent other, imagines, that
is, thinks’ (MGM 377).
10 Diffuse attention is characterised by a far lesser degree of selectivity, as we
saw in Chapter 1.
11 As Gibson puts it, ‘an affordance is not bestowed upon an object by a need of
an observer and his act of perceiving it’ (Gibson 1979: 139). Once again, this
is in accord with Murdoch’s critique of the perception plus desire model.
12 Motivational internalism is also supported by an ‘evolutionary argument’, as
Timothy Chappell shows (2008: 434), where the link between perception and
motivation is common to humans and other animals. The first and most
important objects that humans recognised were those that required specific
responses or actions, where the perception was intrinsically tied to the impor-
tant role the object played for them (i.e. they played the role of affordances):
‘something to flee from’, ‘something to eat’, etc. Chappell treats moral proper-
ties as patterns with this kind of motivational force and provides this argu-
ment as a moral realist response to Mackie’s puzzle: ‘the general schema for
such motivating representations will be: Pattern P in context C mandates
response R from X’ (2008: 434). An example of perceptions that are manifest
through the automatic response that they are tied to comes from the vervet
monkeys, whose three calls, relating to the presence of eagles, leopards, and
snakes, generate the response of fleeing in specific ways and directions
(Cosmides and Tooby 1994).
13 This kind of participation, it may be worth repeating, is very different from
interfering with our ‘selves’ in the given reality.
14 See e.g. MGM 302 and the section on agency in Chapter 1.
15 And in MGM, again reading Weil: ‘Obedience is the freedom wherein the
good man spontaneously helps and serves others’ (MGM 109).
16 Josephine Donovan quotes Max Scheler who ‘maintains that an individual
encounter with suffering should make us aware of suffering in general; thus,
“the pure sentiment of fellow-feeling is released as a permanent disposition,
spreading far beyond the occasion which first inspired it, towards everybody
and every good thing” (60)’ (Donovan 1996: 90). The above-cited study by
Weng et al. (2018) also shows how compassion meditation on specific indi-
viduals, over time ‘can generalize to behavioral domains by impacting social
behavior outside of the training context. Furthermore, greater altruistic
responses were correlated with training-related changes in the neural response
to suffering, providing evidence for functional neuroplasticity in the circuitry
underlying compassion and altruism’ (Weng et al. 2018: 7).
17 The passivity here does not need to contradict the account of attention I am
proposing, and indeed Chappell quotes Murdoch as one of her examples of
epiphany. Rather, passivity in attention is related to its letting the object be,
and to its receptivity; but we have seen how, in other ways, perception through
attention is not at all passive.
Bibliography
Aaltola, E. (2018a) Varieties of Empathy: Moral Psychology and Animal Ethics.
London, Rowman and Littlefield.
Aaltola, E. (2018b) What is Empathy? Medium. Available at: https://medium.
com/colloquium/what-is-empathy-80d80f9250fd [Accessed 5-8-2021].
Bastian, B. et al. (2012) Don’t Mind Meat? The Denial of Mind to Animals Used
for Human Consumption. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin. 38 (2),
247–256.
Motivation and action 171
Brancazio, N. (2020) Being Perceived and Being ‘Seen’: Interpersonal Affordances,
Agency, and Selfhood. Frontiers in Psychology. 11, 1750.
Buckels, E. et al. (2013) Behavioral Confirmation of Everyday Sadism.
Psychological Science. 24 (11), 2201–2209.
Chappell, T. (2008) Moral Perception. Philosophy. 83, 421–437.
Chappell, S. G. (2019) Introducing Epiphanies. ZEMO. 2, 95–121.
Citton, Y. (2017) The Ecology of Attention. Cambridge, Polity.
Cosmides, L. and Tooby, J. (1994) Origins of Domain Specificity: The Evolution
of Functional Organisation. In: Hirschfeld, L. and Gelman, S. (eds.) Mapping
the Mind. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
Debus, D. (2013) Losing Oneself: On the Value of Full Attention. European
Journal of Philosophy. 23 (4), 1174–1191.
de Carvalho, E. M. (2020) Social Affordance. Encyclopedia of Animal Cognition
and Behavior. Cham, Springer.
Decety, J. (2014) The Neural Pathways, Development and Functions of Empathy.
Current Opinions in Behavioural Science. 3, 1–6.
Derrida, J. (2002) The Animal that Therefore I Am (More to Follow). Critical
Inquiry. 28(2), 369–418.
Diamond, C. (1978) Eating Meat, Eating People. Philosophy. 53 (206),
465–479.
Donovan, J. (1996) Attention to Suffering: A Feminist Caring Ethic for the
Treatment of Animals. Journal of Social Philosophy. 27 (1), 81–102.
Dostoevsky, F. (1992) The Brothers Karamazov. Translated by Richard, Pevear.
London, Vintage Classics.
Gallagher, S. (2017) Empathy and Theories of Direct Perception. In: Maibom, H.
(ed.) The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Empathy. London, Routledge.
Gibson, J. (1979) The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. New York,
Psychology Press Classic Editions.
Greitemeyer, T. and Sagioglou, C. (2017) The Longitudinal Relationship Between
Everyday Sadism and the Amount of Violent Video Game Play. Personality and
Individual Differences. 104, 238–242.
Grondahl, P. (2015) Former Pig Farmer Becomes Vegetable-growing Vegan Who
Laments Slaughter in ‘The Last Pig’. Times Union. 20 November. Available at:
https://www.timesunion.com/tuplus-local/article/Former-pig-farmer-becomes-
vegetable-growing-vegan-6647551.php [Accessed 13-8-2021]
Haile, M., Jalil, A. Tasoff, J. and Bustamante, A. V. (2021) Changing Hearts and
Plates: The Effect of Animal-Advocacy Pamphlets on Meat Consumption.
Frontiers in Psychology. 12, 668674.
Kauppinen, A. (2015) Intuition and Belief in Moral Motivation. In: Björnsson, G.
(ed.) Moral Internalism. Oxford, Oxford University Press.
Lanham, R. (2007) The Economics of Attention: Style and Substance in the Age
of Information. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Leibler, J. and Perry, M. (2017) Self-reported Occupational Injuries among
Industrial Beef Slaughterhouse Workers in the Midwestern United States.
Journal of Occupational and Environmental Hygiene. 14 (1), 23–30.
Maturana, H. R., and Varela, F. J. (1988) The Tree of Knowledge: The Biological
Roots of Human Understanding. Boston, MA, Shambhala Publications.
McClelland, T. and Jorba, M. (2021) Perceptual Motivation for Action.
Unpublished manuscript.
172 Motivation and action
Murdoch, I. (1992) Metaphysics as a Guide to Morals [MGM]. London, Penguin.
Murdoch, I. (1998) Existentialists and Mystics: Writings on Philosophy and
Literature. Edited by Peter Conradi. Harmondsworth, Penguin.
———, The Darkness of Practical Reason [DPR], pp. 193–202.
———, The Idea of Perfection [IP], pp. 299–336.
———, Murdoch, I. On ‘God’ and ‘Good’ [OGG], pp. 337–365.
———, The Sovereignty of Good over other Concepts [SGC], pp. 363–385.
Read, C. and Szokolszky, A. (2020) Ecological Psychology and Enactivism:
Perceptually-Guided Action vs Sensation-Based Enaction. Frontiers in
Psychology. 11, 1270.
Wai, M. and Tiliopoulos, N. (2012) The Affective and Cognitive Empathic Nature
of the Dark Triad of Personality. Personality and Individual Differences. 52 (7),
794–799.
Weil, S. (1951) Waiting for God [WG]. Translated by Emma Craufurd. New
York, Harper and Row.
———, Reflections on the Right Use of School Studies with a View to the Love of
God [RSS], pp. 105–116.
———, The Love of Our Neighbour [LN], pp. 139–158.
Weil, S. (2002) Gravity and Grace [GG]. Translated by Emma Crawford and
Mario von der Ruhr. London and New York, Routledge.
Weil, S. (2005) Simone Weil: An Anthology. Edited by Siân, Miles. London,
Penguin.
———, Human Personality [HP], pp. 69–98.
Weng, H. Y., Lapate, R. C., Stodola, D. E., Rogers, G. M., and Davidson, R. J.
(2018). Visual Attention to Suffering After Compassion Training Is Associated
with Decreased Amygdala Responses. Frontiers in psychology. 9, 771.
Willemsen, M. (2019) Schopenhauer and the Mystical Solution of the Riddle
(MGM Chapter 3). In: Hämäläinen, N. and Dooley, G. (eds.) Reading
Metaphysics as a Guide to Morals. Cham, Switzerland, Palgrave Macmillan,
pp. 79–92.
Zahavi, D. (2008) Simulation, Projection and Empathy. Consciousness and
Cognition. 17, 514–522.
Zahavi, D. (2014) Self and Other: Exploring Subjectivity, Empathy, and Shame.
Oxford, Oxford University Press.
Coda
I think I am one of those people, and I think so was Murdoch, and so was
Weil, although Murdoch is here talking about one vision of the world.
That is the vision in which attention is a constant possibility, even a con-
stant task, and the reward is closeness to a reality to which we belong,
which is immense and astonishing, but which we do not often see so
well.2 We take distance, we remove ourselves, both from the world and
from ourselves in it, because, somehow, reality is difficult, being what we
are is difficult for us.
In celebration of the centenary of Murdoch’s birth in 2019, artist
Eimearjean McCormack created a print inspired by The Sea, The
DOI: 10.4324/9781003164852-8
174 Coda
Sea (1978).3 There, a man’s head with the brain exposed, growing out of
flowers, is encased in a bell jar, among other jars we can only glimpse; the
whole is sunk into dark, deep blue. The print offers another, less positive
way of thinking about being in water. Imagine being deep under water,
where everything is muffled, your ordinary life and concerns removed,
where there is only you and fishes and seaweed for unfathomable stretches
of space. This could be (and I think it likely to be) an exhilarating, spiri-
tual experience, a liberating, inward, honest, purifying one. But it could
also represent something very different. Fantasies may take hold there,
with the demands of ordinary life not pressing upon us, a salty fluid sepa-
rating us from what’s around us and what’s outside. The mind can roam,
and it can do so in ways that enclose us even further into a world of our
own making. That is what the artwork suggests, I think, as a reading of
Murdoch’s novel, and that’s not swimming; it is sinking.
Back to the swimmer, and to the image of a woman philosopher
immersing her body in the summer river, we are not enveloped in our-
selves, but in what’s around us. Moving through the water, we are sharing
a space where other creatures move too, our home and theirs, both liter-
ally and, if you like, metaphysically. Being held by water means not being
anything special in this landscape, but participating. Then our attention
is easily drawn to the landscape, and the other creatures that share it:
The joy of attention is the joy that at any moment we can open our eyes,
and we can experience the astonishing realisation that the world, the sea,
the grains of sand, this seagull, the shoal of sardines, the other swimmers,
the glimmer of light on the water—that all of that exists.
Notes
1 Readers of Murdoch’s fiction may find these images reminiscent of passages
in The Sea, the Sea (1978).
2 See also AD 290.
3 https://www.philosophybypostcard.com/eimearjean-mccormack/
4 Thanks to Maude Ouellette-Dubé for making this concern salient.
Bibliography
Murdoch, I. (1978) The Sea, The Sea. London, Chatto & Windus.
Murdoch, I. (1992) Metaphysics as a Guide to Morals [MGM]. London, Penguin.
Murdoch, I. (1993) Taking the Plunge. Review of Haunts of the Black Masseur by
Charles Sprawson. The New York Review. 4 March. Available at: https://www.
nybooks.com/articles/1993/03/04/taking-the-plunge/ [Accessed 08-07-2021].
Murdoch, I. (1998) Existentialists and Mystics: Writings on Philosophy and
Literature. Edited by Peter Conradi. Harmondsworth, Penguin.
———, Vision and Choice in Morality [VCM], pp. 76–98.
———, Against Dryness [AD], pp. 287–296.
———, The Sublime and the Beautiful Revisited [SBR], pp. 261–286.
Rozelle-Stone, R. (2021) Fatigue: Obstacle Or Necessary Counterpart to Moral
Attention? ABC Religion and Ethics. Available at: https://www.abc.net.au/religion/
simone-weil-fatigue-and-moral-attention/13299758 [Accessed 27-10-2021].
Sprawson, C. (1993) Haunts of the Black Masseur: The Swimmer as Hero.
London, Vintage.
Tolstoy, L. (1993) Confession. Translated by David Patterson. New York, Norton.
Weil, S. (1951) Reflections on the Right Use of School Studies [RSS] In: Waiting
for God. Translated by Emma Craufurd. New York, Harper and Row.
Index
absolute 7, 18, 103, 113, 175 compassion 40, 46, 137, 153–154,
action 2–4, 15–18, 21, 23–29, 41–42, 157–158, 162, 166, 170n16
88, 112–115, 129–131, 150–170 consciousness 2, 4–5, 7, 9–10, 15, 17,
activism 39, 136, 144, 153, 166–167 19, 21–25, 29–33, 35–36, 42–43,
activity 5, 7, 28–29, 31, 122–123, 46, 49, 57n28, 57n30, 65–67,
133, 135, 175 69–70, 75, 77, 82, 94–95, 97–98,
affliction 15, 41, 130–131, 145–146, 101–106, 110–111, 113–115,
169; see also suffering 122–124, 133–135, 137–138,
affordances 51, 161–164, 150–151, 153, 160
170n11–170n12 consequentialism 53; see also
agency 22, 26–29, 57n17, 143 utilitarianism
animals, non-human 2, 6, 8–9, 34, 41, conversion 84n17, 167
47–49, 57n12, 52, 83n8, 95, 116, creation 16, 64, 93, 99, 145–146
129–131, 136–138, 141–148, creativity 28, 70, 88, 95, 130,
151–170 145–146, 160
art 10, 47–48, 58n42, 79, 95, 98, 100,
104, 169n9; see also literature decreation 16, 19, 63–64, 84n20,
attention: diffuse 50–51, 58n42; 92–93, 98–99, 110, 157; see also
divided 9, 21, 25; joint 36, 119, unselfing
142; sustained 9, 21, 25, 28, 97, 99, defence mechanism 80–81, 84n24
102, 143, 145, 155, 157, 165–166 deliberation 3, 24, 126, 162, 165
desire 8, 22, 28, 32–34, 37–38, 45–47,
beauty 6, 17, 37, 44–49, 79, 91 51, 53, 56n4, 56n6, 68, 73, 77–78,
Bhagavad-Gıt̄ a 37, 100 80, 89–90, 94, 102–104, 110–111,
Buddhism 7, 11, 29, 51, 90, 99–103, 117–118, 130, 134, 140, 143–146,
105, 107n6, 169n7; Theravāda 153–159, 163–164
101–102; Zen 11–12, 95–102, 105 Diamond, C. 6, 167
Dostoevsky, F. 34, 168
change, moral 19, 22–23, 27, 35, 39–42, dualism 29, 98, 104–105
48, 104–105, 119, 138, 166–167
choice 3–5, 17–18, 26, 30, 33, 42, ecology 9, 106
47–48, 53, 101, 144, 151, 166–167, ecological psychology 151–152
169n7 ego 6, 28, 36, 47, 66–68, 70–71,
Christianity 40, 100, 175 76–77, 81, 87–89, 92, 97–98, 111,
cognitive penetration 71–73, 75, 133 143, 155, 162
178 Index
emotions 1, 22, 36, 39, 72–73, 77, 81, James, W. 20, 22, 26, 29–30, 161
87, 115, 124, 130, 138, 141–142,
144, 154–155, 157, 163 literature 5, 79, 126
empathy 40–41, 73–74, 141–142, love 7, 9, 15–17, 19–20, 32–34,
152–160, 166; see also sympathy 36–41, 44–47, 77–78, 88, 91–93,
enactivism 151–152 95–96, 103–105, 117–118,
epiphany 167–168, 170n17 124–125, 130, 132, 137, 140,
eros 8, 25, 32–38, 45, 78, 90, 95, 103, 145–146, 166, 168; see also eros
134, 140, 159; see also love
M&D 4, 18, 27, 39, 69, 94, 112, 113
failure 2, 5, 25, 42, 68–70, 78, 80–81, market 9–10
112, 120, 124, 175 meat 2, 136–138, 142, 144–145, 155
fantasy 10, 15, 24, 27, 30–31, 35, 37, meditation 11, 17, 51–52, 90, 97–98,
43, 51, 53, 67–81, 87–92, 111, 117, 157, 169n7, 170n16
113–114, 117–119, 140, 156–157, metaphysics 16, 19, 63, 92, 102, 105
174 motivation, moral 3, 25, 41–42, 64,
feminism 12n3, 120 75, 106, 113, 129–131, 144, 150,
force 146 151–154, 157, 160, 162–167
forgiveness 39–41 motivational internalism 163, 170n12
freedom 11, 53, 56n4, 101, 170n15 mysticism 7, 19, 34, 56n6, 56n9,
Freud, A. 81, 84n24 105–106, 165
Freud, S. 68, 76, 80
necessity 27, 56n4, 68, 93, 129,
gaze 1, 12n1, 18, 55, 78, 83n13, 114, 150–151, 166
116–117, 126, 159, 161 neurosis 36, 80–81, 84n25, 118
gift 31, 41, 165, 175
God 15–16, 18–20, 33, 44–45, 56n4, obedience 17, 56n4, 56n7, 68, 93,
76, 88, 92–93, 99–100, 105 151, 164–166
grace 68, 82, 110 ordinary language 14, 20, 23–24, 30,
38, 56n11
habit 2, 6, 15, 27, 29, 32, 46, 53,
96–97, 132, 137, 140, 157–158 painting 10, 95
Hinduism 11, 99–100 particularity see individual
passivity 4, 8, 22, 28–29, 94, 168,
imagination 2, 17, 22, 28, 35, 38, 41, 170n17
67, 73–74, 80, 97, 134–135, perception: direct 141, 152, 154–155;
137–143, 160–161, 169n9 moral 3, 5–7, 89, 120, 129–146,
impersonality 4–5, 33, 38–39, 70–74, 151–152, 161, 166
88–89, 95, 97, 103, 105–106, 116, personality 70, 83n14, 94–97, 146,
134, 143, 152, 169n9 168
individual 2, 4–5, 9–10, 18, 22, 24, phronesis 51
34, 38–40, 43–45, 50, 54, 64–76, Plato 6–8, 11, 19, 22, 25, 32–34, 36,
78, 81, 87–88, 95–97, 103, 105– 44, 56n6, 56n9, 76, 90, 95, 100,
106, 116, 118–120, 131–132, 134, 113, 118, 134–135, 174
137, 140–143, 146, 156, 159–160, psychotherapy 84n26, 127n5
162, 166–167
inner datum 121, 125–126 realism, (moral) 4–5, 27, 38, 72,
inner life 4, 17, 24, 41, 66, 70, 105, 83n13, 84n16, 89, 95, 104, 133,
115–116, 121–123, 126, 150, 144, 152, 170n12
162, 167 religion 14, 16, 19, 56n4, 92, 94, 99,
introspection 114–115, 120–121, 105–106, 110, 175
124–125
intuition, moral 163 sadism 131, 137, 158–160
Index 179
salience 15, 23–25, 32, 40, 43, 47–48, truth-seeking 3, 10, 15, 24–25, 32–36,
51–53, 75, 125, 135, 142–143, 157, 101–102, 110, 113, 129, 135, 140,
159, 162, 165 143, 160
Samaritan 16, 48–49, 130, 145, 158,
168 unselfing 3, 9, 17, 19, 35–39,
selectivity 21, 24–25, 30, 32, 43, 51, 41, 50–52, 54–55, 63–65,
57n28, 159 67–68, 70–77, 82, 87, 89, 90–92,
slaughterhouse 136, 153, 156 94–95, 98, 100, 104, 110,
subjectivism 73, 139, 147n10 134, 140
subjectivity 71, 94, 98, 103, 145, 158 utilitarianism 130; see also
success 31–32, 35, 37, 54, 90, 110, consequentialism
115, 126, 131, 134, 136, 138, 143,
150, 160, 165 value: inherent 5–6, 25, 50;
suffering 6, 8, 11, 38–39, 41, 46–47, instrumental 5, 32–33, 131
49, 102, 106, 115, 129–131, veganism 12n3, 153, 166–167
136–138, 141–147 vision, moral 7–10, 18, 23, 37–42,
sympathy 2, 153; see also empathy 53, 66, 68–69, 78, 82, 83n13, 88,
swimming 43, 173–174, 176 97, 105–107, 100, 118, 140,
168, 173
Tolstoy, L. 174 virtue 15, 37–38, 51–52, 73, 77,
touch 7–8, 98, 142 111–113, 134, 140, 153
transparency view 123–126
truth 2, 7, 15, 17, 25, 28, 31, 32–39, waiting 8, 10, 17, 28, 50–51, 103
50–53, 67, 88, 94, 103–104, 106, water 98, 173–174
127n2, 129, 155, 159–160, 169, will 26–28, 93, 101, 165–166
169n9 Wittgenstein 34–36, 121–125, 141