Beijing
Beijing
Gregory J. Galloway
Department of Mathematics
University of Miami
∗
Notes last modified: October 30, 2008. Please send typos to: [email protected]
1
Contents
1 Pseudo-Riemannian Geometry 3
1.1 Manifolds . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 3
1.2 Vector fields . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 4
1.3 Co-vectors and 1-forms . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6
1.4 Pseudo-Riemannian manifolds . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6
1.5 Linear connections . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 8
1.6 The Levi-Civita connection . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 9
1.7 Geodesics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 10
1.8 Riemann curvature tensor . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 11
1.9 Sectional curvature . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 13
4 Trapped surfaces 36
4.1 Trapped and marginally trapped surfaces . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 36
4.2 The Penrose singularity theorem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 38
4.3 The topology of black holes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 40
2
1 Pseudo-Riemannian Geometry
We begin with a brief introduction to pseudo-Riemmanian geometry.
1.1 Manifolds
Let M n be a smooth n-dimensional manifold. Hence, M n is a topological space (Haus-
dorff, second countable), together with a collection of coordinate charts (U, xi ) =
(U, x1 , ..., xn ) (U open in M ) covering M such that on overlapping charts (U, xi ),
(V, y i ), U ∩ V 6= ∅, the coordinates are smoothly related
y i = f i (x1 , ..., xn ), f i ∈ C∞ ,
i = 1, ..., n.
For any p ∈ M , let Tp M denote the tangent space of M at p. Thus, Tp M is the
collection of tangent vectors to M at p. Formally, each tangent vector X ∈ Tp M is a
derivation acting on real valued functions f , defined and smooth in a neighborhood
of p. Hence, for X ∈ Tp M , X(f ) ∈ R represents the directional deriviative of f at p
in the direction X.
If p is in the chart (U, xi ) then the coordinate vectors based at p,
∂ ∂ ∂
1
|p , 2 |p , ..., n |p
∂x ∂x ∂x
form a basis for Tp M . I.e., each vector X ∈ Tp M can be expressed uniquely as,
∂
X = Xi |p , X i ∈ R.
∂xi
Here we have used the Einstein summation convention: If, in a coordinate chart, an
index appears repeated, once up and once down, then summation over that index is
implied.
Note: We will sometimes use the shorthand: ∂i = ∂x∂ i .
Example. Tangent vectors to curves. Let σ : I → M , t → σ(t), be a smooth curve in
M.
σ : xi = xi (t), i = 1, ..., n.
dσ dxi ∂
(t0 ) = (t0 ) i |p ,
dt dt ∂x
i
i.e., dx
dt
(t0 ) are the components of dσ (t ). In fact every vector X ∈ Tp M can be
dt 0
expressed as the tangent vector to some curve through p.
The tangent bundle of M , denoted T M is, as a set, the collection of all tangent
vectors, [
TM = Tp M.
p∈M
where (x1 , ..., xn ) are the coordinates of the point p at which V is based, and
(V 1 , ..., V n ) are the components of V wrt the coordinate basis vectors ∂x∂ 1 |p , ... ∂x∂n |p .
By this correspondence one sees that T M forms in a natural way a smooth manifold
of dimension 2n. Moreover, with respect to this manifold structure, the natural
projection map π : T M → M , Vp → p, is smooth.
X
p ∈ M −→ Xp ∈ Tp M.
∂
Xp = X i (p) |p .
∂xi
This defines n functions X i : U → R, i = 1, ..., n, the components of X on (U, xi ) . If
for a set of charts (U, xi ) covering M the components X i are smooth (X i ∈ C ∞ (U ))
then we say that X is a smooth vector field.
Let X(M ) denote the set of smooth vector fields on M . Vector fields can be added
pointwise and multiplied by functions; for X, Y ∈ X(M ) and f ∈ C ∞ (M ),
(X + Y )p = Xp + Yp , (f X)p = f (p)Xp .
4
From these operations we see that X(M ) is a module over C ∞ (M ).
Given X ∈ X(M ) and f ∈ C ∞ (M ), X acts on f to produce a function X(f ) ∈
∞
C (M ), defined by,
X(f )(p) = Xp (f ).
With respect to a coordinate chart (U, xi ) , X(f ) is given by,
∂f
X(f ) = X i .
∂xi
Thus, a smooth vector field X ∈ X(M ) may be viewed as a map
X : C ∞ (M ) → C ∞ (M ) , f → X(f )
that satisfies,
(1) X(af + bg) = aX(f ) + bX(g) (a, b ∈ R),
(2) X(f g) = X(f )g + f X(g).
Indeed, these properties completely characterize smooth vector fields.
Given X, Y ∈ X(M ), the Lie bracket [X, Y ] of X and Y is the vector field defined
by
[X, Y ] : C ∞ (M ) → C ∞ (M ) , [X, Y ] = XY − Y X,
i.e.
[X, Y ](f ) = X(Y (f )) − Y (X(f )).
In local coordinates one sees that the second derivatives cancel out.
Exercise. Show that with respect to a coordinate chart, [X, Y ] is given by
∂Y j i ∂X
j
∂
[X, Y ] = (X i i
− Y i
) j
∂x ∂x ∂x
∂
= (X(Y j ) − Y (X j )) j .
∂x
It is clear from the definition that the Lie bracket is skew-symmetric,
[X, Y ] = −[Y, X].
In addition, the Lie bracket is linear in each slot over the reals, and satisfies,
(1) For all f, g ∈ C ∞ (M ), X, Y ∈ X(M ),
[f X, gY ] = f g[X, Y ] + f X(g)Y − gY (f )X.
5
1.3 Co-vectors and 1-forms
A co-vector ω at p ∈ M is a linear functional ω : Tp M → R on the tangent space at
p. A 1-form on M is an assignment to each p ∈ M of a co-vector ωp at p, p → ωp .
A 1-form ω is smooth provided for each X ∈ X(M ), the function ω(X), p → ωp (Xp ),
is smooth. Equivalently, ω is smooth provided for each chart (U, xi ) in a collection of
charts covering M , the function ω( ∂x∂ i ) is smooth on U , i = 1, ..., n.
Given f ∈ C ∞ (M ), the differential df is the smooth 1-form defined by
6
space is the number of minus signs in the signature. It can be shown that the index
is well-defined, i.e., does not depend on the choice of basis. The cases of most impor-
tance are the case of index 0 and index 1, which lead to Riemannian geometry and
Lorentzian geometry, respectively.
h, i
p −→ h , ip : Tp M × Tp M → R.
By ‘smooth assignment’ we mean that for all X, Y ∈ X(M ), the function hX, Y i,
p → hXp , Yp iP , is smooth.
Note: We shall also use the letter g to denote the metric, g = h , i.
If (U, xi ) is a coordinate chart then the metric components gij are the functions on
U defined by,
∂ ∂
gij = h i , j i, i, j = 1, ..., n .
∂x ∂x
If X, Y are vectors at some point in U then, by bilinearity,
hX, Y i = gij X i Y j .
∂
X = Xi |p
∂xi
∂
Y = Y i i |p ,
∂x
7
we have
hX, Y i = X · Y
Xn
= X iY i
i=1
= δij X i Y j ,
Ex. Minkowski space Mn+1 . This is the Lorentzian analogue of Euclidean space. We
equip Rn+1 with the Minkowski metric: Let (x0 , x1 , ..., xn ) be Cartesian coordinates
on Rn+1 . Then for X, Y ∈ Tp Rn+1 ,
∂ ∂
X = Xi |p , Y =Yi |p ,
∂xi ∂xi
we define,
n
X
0 0
hX, Y i = −X Y + X iY i
i=1
i j
= ηij X Y ,
(1) ∇f X Y = f ∇X Y ,
(2) ∇X f Y = X(f )Y + f ∇X Y .
∇X Y is called the covariant derivative of Y wrt X. It can be shown that for any
p ∈ M , ∇X Y |p depends only on the values of Y in a neighborhood of p and the value
of X just at p. In particular, it makes sense to write ∇X Y |p as ∇Xp Y . This can be
thought of as the directional derivative of Y at p in the direction of Xp .
8
In a coordinate chart (U, xi ) we introduce the connection coefficients Γkij , 1 ≤
i, j, k ≤ n, which are smooth functions on U defined by,
∇∂i ∂j = Γkij ∂k ,
∂
where, recall, ∂i = ∂xi
.
Exercise. Show that with respect to a coordinate chart (U, xi ) , ∇X Y can be expressed
as,
∇X Y = (X(Y k ) + Γkij X i Y j )∂k , (1.1)
where X i , Y i are the components of X and Y , respectively, wrt the coordinate basis
∂i .
Note that this coordinate expression can also be written as,
∇X Y = X i Y k ;i ∂k
Y k ;i = ∂i Y k + Γkij Y j .
Using the coordinate expression (1.1) for ∇X Y , one easily checks that a linear con-
nection ∇ is symmetric iff wrt each each coordinate chart, the connection coefficients
satisfy,
Γkij = Γkji , for 1 ≤ i, j, k ≤ n .
9
Comment on the proof. Using the symmetry and compatibility with the metric of the
connection, one derives the Kozul formula,
1
h∇X Y, Zi = [XhY, Zi + Y hZ, Xi − ZhX, Y i
2
− hX, [Y, Z]i + hY, [Z, X]i + hZ, [X, Y ]i].
This formula implies uniqueness, and in fact can serve to define a linear connection
that is symmetric and compatible with the metric.
Using the Kozul formula one can show that the connection coefficients of a Levi-
Civita connection are given by,
1
Γkij = g kl (∂i gjl + ∂j gil − ∂l gij ) ,
2
where [g ij ] = [gij ]−1 .
1.7 Geodesics
Let σ : I → M , t → σ(t), be a smooth curve in a pseudo-Riemannian manifold M .
Let X(σ) denote the collection of smooth vector fields X along σ,
X
t −→ X(t) ∈ Tσ(t) M
σ : xi = xi (t) , i = 1, ..., n
X(t) = X i (t)∂i |σ(t) ,
10
(2) for X ∈ X(M ),
D
X|σ(t) = ∇σ0 (t) X.
dt
In local coordinates we find that,
DX dX k dxi j
=( + Γkij X )∂k . (1.2)
dt dt dt
D
Also we note that the operator dt
obeys the metric product rule,
d DX DY
hX, Y i = h , Y i + hX, i.
dt dt dt
D dσ
Given a smooth curve t → σ(t) in M , dt dt
is the covariant acceleration of σ. In
local coordinates,
D dσ d2 xk dxi dxj
= ( 2 + Γkij )∂k ,
dt dt dt dt dt
dxk
as follows by setting X k = dt
in Equation (1.2).
Definition 1.6. A smooth curve t → σ(t) is a geodesic provided it has vanishing
covariant acceleration,
D dσ
=0 (Geodesic equation)
dt dt
The basic existence and uniqueness result for systems of ODE’s guarantees the
following.
Proposition 1.3. Given p ∈ M and v ∈ Tp M , there exists an interval I about t = 0
and a unique geodesic σ : I → M , t → σ(t), satisfying,
dσ
σ(0) = p , (0) = v .
dt
In fact, by a more refined analysis it can be shown that each p ∈ M is contained in
a (geodesically) convex neighborhood U , which has the property that any two points
in U can be joined by a unique geodesic contained in U . In fact U can be chosen so as
to be a normal neighborhood of each of its points; cf. [22], p. 129. (Recall, a normal
neighborhood of p ∈ M is the diffeomorphic image under the exponential map of a
star-shaped domain about 0 ∈ Tp M .)
11
R so defined is trilinear wrt to C ∞ (M ). That R is R-trilinear is clear. The key
point is the following.
Proposition 1.4. For f ∈ C ∞ (M ),
Proof. Exercise.
Proposition 1.4 implies that R is indeed tensorial, i.e., that the value of R(X, Y )Z
at p ∈ M depends only on the value of X, Y, Z at p; hence for (R(X, Y )Z)p we may
write R(Xp , Yp )Zp .
From the analytic point of view, the Riemann curvature tensor R may viewed
as a measure of the extent to which covariant differentiation fails to commute. This
failure to commute may be seen as an obstruction to the existence of parallel vector
fields. According to Riemann’s theorem, a pseudo-Riemannian manifold is locally
pseudo-Euclidean iff the Riemann curvature tensor vanishes.
Proposition 1.5. The Riemann curvature tensor has the following symmetry prop-
erties.
Rij = Rl ilj
12
Symmetries of the Riemann curvature tensor imply that the Ricci tensor is sym-
metric, Rij = Rji . By tracing the Ricci tensor, we obtain the scalar curvature,
R = g ij Rij ,
where [g ij ] = [gij ]−1 . The Einstein equation, with cosmological term, is the tensor
equation,
1
Rij − Rgij + Λgij = 8πTij , (1.4)
2
where Λ is the cosmological constant and Tij is the energy-momentum tensor.
13
For X ∈ Tp M ,
timelike if hX, Xi < 0
X is null if hX, Xi = 0
spacelike if hX, Xi > 0 .
forms a double cone Vp in the tangent space Tp M , called the null cone at p. Timelike
vectors point inside the null cone and spacelike vectors point outside.
A subspace W of Tp M may be assigned a causal character as follows,
(1) W is spacelike if h , i|W has index 0, i.e., is positive definite.
|hX, Y i| ≥ |X||Y |
14
(2) (Reverse triangle inequality) For all causal vectors X, Y that point into the same
half cone of the null cone at p,
|X + Y | ≥ |X| + |Y | .
Proof. Exercise.
The Reverse triangle inequality is the source of the twin paradox.
Let γ : I → M be a smooth curve in M . γ is said to be timelike (resp., spacelike,
null, causal) provided γ 0 (t) is timelike (resp., spacelike, null, causal) for all t ∈ I.
Heuristically, in accordance with relativity, information flows along causal curves,
and so such curves are the focus of our attention. The notion of a causal curve
extends in a natural way to piecewise smooth curves. The only extra requirement
is that when two segments join, at some point p, say, the end point tangent vectors
must point into the same half cone of the null cone Vp at p. We will normally work
within this class of piecewise smooth causal curves. Finally, note since geodesics γ
are constant speed curves (hγ 0 , γ 0 i = const.), each geodesic in a Lorentzian manifold
is either timelike, spacelike or null.
The length of a causal curve γ : [a, b] → M , is defined by
Z b Z bp
0
L(γ) = Length of γ = |γ (t)|dt = −hγ 0 (t), γ 0 (t)i dt .
a a
If γ is timelike one can introduce arc length parameter along γ. In general relativity,
a timelike curve corresponds to the history of an observer, and arc length parameter,
called proper time, corresponds to time kept by the observer.
Certain geometric and causal features of Minkowski space that may fail to hold in
the large in a general Lorentzian manifold, nontheless hold locally. Let U be a convex
neighborhood in a Lorentzian manifold. Hence for each pair of points p, q ∈ U there
exists a unique geodesic segment from p to q in U , which we denote by pq.
Proposition 2.2 ([22], p. 146). Let U be a convex neighborhood in a Lorentzian
manifold M n+1 .
(2) If pq is timelike then L(pq) ≥ L(γ) for all causal curves γ in U from p to q.
Moreover, the inequality is strict unless, when suitable parametrized, γ = pq.
Thus, within a convex neighborhood, null geodesics are achronal, i.e., no two
points can be joined by a timlike curve, and timelike geodesics are maximal, i.e., are
causal curves of greatest length. Both of these features can fail in the large.
Vp , the null cone at p, consists of two half-cones Vp+ and Vp− (see the figure on the
previous page). We may designate one of the half cones, Vp+ , say, as the future null
15
cone at p, and the other half cone, Vp− , as the past null cone at p. The assignment of a
future cone and past cone to each point of M n+1 can always be done in a continuous
manner locally. If the assignment can made in a continuous manner over all of M
then we say that M is time-orientable. The following figure illustrates a Lorentzian
manifold that is not time-orientable.
There are various ways to make the phrase “continuous assignment” precise, but
they all result in the following fact.
Fact 2.3. A Lorentzian manifold M n+1 is time-orientable iff it admits a smooth
timelike vector field U .
If M is time-orientable, the choice of a smooth time-like vector field U fixes a time
orientation on M . For any p ∈ M , a causal vector X ∈ Tp is future directed (resp.
past directed) provided hX, U i < 0 (resp. hX, U i > 0). Thus X is future directed if
it points into the same null half cone at p as U .
By a spacetime we mean a connected time-oriented Lorentzian manifold (M n+1 , h , i).
Henceforth, we restrict attention to spacetimes.
(1) p q means there exists a future directed timelike curve in M from p to q (we
say that q is in the timelike future of p),
(2) p < q means there exists a future directed causal curve in M from p to q (we
say that q is in the causal future of p),
16
The causal relations and < are clearly transitive. Also, from variational con-
siderations, it is heuristically clear that the following holds,
if p q and q < r or if p < q and q << r then p r .
The above statement is a consequence of the following fundamental causality result;
see [22, p. 294] for a careful proof.
Proposition 2.4. In a spacetime M , if q is in the causal future of p (p < q) but is
not in the timelike future of p (p 6 q) then any future directed causal curve γ from p
to q must be a null geodesic (when suitably parameterized).
Given any point p in a spacetime M , the timelike future and causal future of p,
denoted I + (p) and J + (p), respectively are defined as,
I + (p) = {q ∈ M : p q} and J + (p) = {q ∈ M : p ≤ q} .
Hence, I + (p) consists of all points in M that can be reached from p by a future
directed timelike curve, and J + (p) consists of the point p and all points in M that
can be reached from p by a future directed causal curve. The timelike and causal pasts
of p, I − (p) and J − (p), respectively, are defined in a time-dual manner in terms of
past directed timelike and causal curves. Note by Proposition 2.4, if q ∈ J + (p)\I + (p)
(q 6= p) then there exists a future directed null geodesic from p to q.
If p is a point in Minkowski space Mn+1 , then I + (p) is open, J + (p) is closed and
∂I + (p) = J + (p) \ I + (p) is just the future null cone at p. I + (p) consists of all points
inside the future null cone, and J + (p) consists of all points on and inside the future
null cone. We note, however, that curvature and topology can drastically change the
structure of ‘null cones’ in spacetime. Consider the example depicted in the following
figure of a flat spacetime cylinder, closed in space. For any point p in this spacetime
the future ‘null cone’ at p, ∂I + (p), is compact and consists of the two future directed
null geodesic segments emanating from p that meet to the future at a point q. By
extending these geodesics beyond q we enter I + (p).
17
In some situations it is convenient to restrict the causal relations and < to
open subsets U of a spacetime M . For example, I + (p, U ), the chronological future
of p within U , consists of all points q in U for which there exists a future directed
timelike curve within U from p to q, etc. Note that, in general I + (p, U ) 6= I + (p) ∩ U .
In general the sets I + (p) in a spacetime M are open. This is heuristically rather
clear: A sufficiently small smooth perturbation of a timelike curve is still timelike. A
rigorous proof is based on the causality of convex neighborhoods.
Proposition 2.5. Let U be a convex neighborhood in a spacetime M . Then, for each
p ∈ U,
Points on the dashed line are not in J + (p), but are in the closure J + (p).
For any subset S ⊂ M , we define the timelike and causal future of S, I + (S) and
J + (S), respectively by
[ [
I + (S) = I + (p) and J + (S) = J + (p) .
p∈S p∈S
Thus, I + (S) consists of all points in M reached by a future directed timelike curve
starting from S, and J + (S) consists of the points of S, together with the points in
M reached by a future directed causal curve starting from S. Since arbitrary unions
of open sets are open, it follows that I + (S) is always an open set. I − (S) and J − (S)
are defined in a time-dual manner.
Although in general J + (S) 6= I + (S), the following relationships always hold be-
tween I + (S) and J + (S).
18
Proposition 2.6. For all subsets S ⊂ M ,
(1) int J + (S) = I + (S),
(2) J + (S) ⊂ I + (S).
Proof. Exercise.
Achronal sets play an important role in causal theory. A subset S ⊂ M is achronal
provided no two of its points can be joined by a timelike curve. Of particular impor-
tance are achronal boundaries. By definition, an achronal boundary is a set of the
form ∂I + (S) (or ∂I − (S)), for some S ⊂ M . We wish to describe several important
structural properties of achronal boundaries. The following figure illustrates nicely
the properties to be discussed. It depicts the achronal boundary ∂I + (S) in Minkowski
3-space M3 , where S is the disjoint union of two spacelike disks; ∂I + (S) consists of
S and the merging of two future light cones.
19
We denote by edge S the set of edge points of S. Note that S \ S ⊂ edge S ⊂ S.
If edge S = ∅ we say that S is edgeless.
Claim: An achronal boundary ∂I + (S) is achronal and edgeless.
Proof of the claim: Suppose there exist p, q ∈ ∂I + (S), with q ∈ I + (p). By
Lemma 2.8, q ∈ I + (S). But since I + (S) is open, I + (S) ∩ ∂I + (S) = ∅. Thus,
∂I + (S) is achronal. Moreover, Lemma 2.8 implies that for any p ∈ ∂I + (S), any
timelike curve from I − (p) to I + (p) must meet ∂I + (S). It follows that ∂I + (S) is
edgless.
Proposition 2.7 now follows from the following basic result.
Proposition 2.9. Let S be achronal. Then S \ edge S, if nonempty, is a C 0 hyper-
surface in M .
Proof. We sketch the proof; for details, see [22, p. 413]. It suffices to show that in a
neighborhood of each p ∈ S \ edge S, S \ edge S can be expressed as a C 0 graph over
a smooth hypersurface.
Fix p ∈ S \ edge S. Since p is not an edge point there exists a neighborhood U
of p such that every timelike curve from I − (p, U ) to I + (p, U ) meets S. Let X be a
future directed timelike vector field on M , and let N be a smooth hypersurface in U
transverse to X near p. Then, by choosing N small enough, each integral curve of X
through N will meet S, and meet it exactly once since S is achronal. Using the flow
generated by X, it follows that there is a neighborhood V ≈ (t1 , t2 ) × N of p such
that S ∩ V is given as the graph of a function t = h(x), x ∈ N (see the figure below)
20
The proof uses a standard tool in causal theory, namely that of taking a limit of
causal curves. A technical difficulty arises however in that a limit of smooth causal
curves need not be smooth. Thus, we are lead to introduce the notion of a C 0 causal
curve.
Definition 2.3. A continuous curve γ : I → M is said to be a future directed C 0
causal curve provided for each t0 ∈ I, there is an open subinterval I0 ⊂ I about t0 and
a convex neighborhood U of γ(t0 ) such that given any t1 , t2 ∈ I0 with t1 < t2 , there
exists a smooth future directed causal curve in U from γ(t1 ) to γ(t2 ).
Thus, a C 0 causal curve is a continuous curve that can be approximated with
arbitrary precision by a piecewise smooth causal curve.
We now give a version of the limit curve lemma (cf., [3, p. 511]). For its statement
it is convenient to introduce a background complete Riemannian (positive definite)
metric h on M . Observe that any future inextendible causal γ will have infinite length
to the future, as measured in the metric h. Hence, if parameterized with respect to
h-arc length, γ will be defined on the interval [0, ∞).
Lemma 2.11 (Limit curve lemma). Let γn : [0, ∞) → M be a sequence of future
inextendible causal curves, parameterized with respect to h-arc length, and suppose
that p ∈ M is an accumulation point of the sequence {γn (0)}. Then there exists
a future inextendible C 0 causal curve γ : [0, ∞) → M such that γ(0) = p and a
subsequence {γm } which converges to γ uniformly with respect to h on compact subsets
of [0, ∞).
The proof of this lemma is an application of Arzela’s theorem; see especially the
proof of Proposition 3.31 in [3]. There are analogous versions of the limit curve lemma
for past inextendible, and (past and future) inextendible causal curves.
Remark: We note that C 0 causal curves obey a local Lipschitz condition, and hence
are rectifiable. Thus, in the limit curve lemma, the γn ’s could be taken to be C 0
causal curves. We also note that the “limit” parameter acquired by the limit curve γ
need not in general be the h-arc length parameter.
Proof of Proposition 2.10. Fix p ∈ ∂I + (S) \ S. Since p ∈ ∂I + (S), there exists a
sequence of points pn ∈ I + (S), such that pn → p. For each n, let γn : [0, an ] → M
be a past directed timelike curve from pn to qn ∈ S, parameterized with respect to
h-arc length. Extend each γn to a past inextendible timelike curve γ̃n : [0, ∞) → M ,
parameterized with respect to h-arc length. By the limit curve lemma, there exists a
subsequence γ̃m : [0, ∞) → M that converges to a past inextendible C 0 causal curve
γ : [0, ∞) → M such that γ(0) = p. By taking a further subsequence if necessary
we can assume am ↑ a, a ∈ (0, ∞]. We claim that γ|[0,a] (or γ|[0,a) if a = ∞) is the
desired null geodesic (see the figure).
21
Fix t ∈ (0, a). Eventually am > t, and so for large m we have γ̃m (t) = γm (t) ∈
I + (S). Hence, since γ(t) = limm→∞ γm (t), it follows that γ(t) ∈ I + (S). Suppose
γ(t) ∈ I + (S). Then there exists x ∈ S such that x γ(t) < p. This implies
p ∈ I + (S), contradicting that it is on the boundary. It follows that γ(t) ∈ ∂I + (S).
Thus we have shown that γ|[0,a) ⊂ ∂I + (S). Suppose for the moment γ|[0,a) is piecewise
smooth. Since ∂I + (S) is achronal, no two points of γ can be joined by a timelike
curve. It then follows from Proposition 2.4 that γ is a null geodesic. But using the
fact that C 0 causal curves can be approximated by piecewise smooth causal curves,
one can show in the general case that γ|[0,a) is a null geodesic. (Exercise: Show this.)
Finally, we consider the two cases a < ∞ and a = ∞. If a < ∞, then by the
uniform convergence, γ(a) = limm→∞ γm (am ) = limm→∞ qm ∈ S, since S is closed.
Thus, we have a null geodesic from p contained in ∂I + (S) that ends on S. If a = ∞
then we have a null geodesic from p in ∂I + (S) that is past inextendible in M .
22
Exercise: Construct a spacetime that satisfies the chronology condition but not the
causality condition.
A spacetime that satisfies the causality condition can nontheless be on the verge
of failing it, in the sense that there exist causal curves that are “almost closed”, as
illustrated by the following figure.
Strong causality is a condition that rules out almost closed causal curves. An open
set U in spacetime M is said to be causally convex provided no causal curve in M
meets U in a disconnected sets. Given p ∈ M , strong causality is said to hold at p
provided p has arbitrarily small convex neighborhoods, i.e., for each neighborhood V
of p there exists a causally neighborhood U of p such that U ⊂ V . Note that strong
causality fails at the point p in the figure above. In fact strong causality fails at all
points along the dashed null geodesic. It can be shown that the set of points at which
strong causality holds is open.
M is said to be strongly causal if strong causality holds at all of its points. This
is the “standard” causality condition in spacetime geometry, and, although there are
even stronger causality conditions, it is sufficient for most applications. There is an
interesting connection between strong causality and the so-called Alexandrov topology.
The sets of the form I + (p) ∩ I − (q) form the base for a topology on M , which is the
Alexandrov topology. This topology is in general more coarse than the manifold
topology of M . However it can be shown that the Alexandrov topology agrees with
the manifold topology iff M is strongly causal.
The following lemma is often useful.
Lemma 2.13. Suppose strong causality holds at each point of a compact set K in a
spacetime M . If γ : [0, b) → M is a future inextendible causal curve that starts in K
then eventually it leaves K and does not return, i.e., there exists t0 ∈ [0, b) such that
γ(t) ∈
/ K for all t ∈ [t0 , b).
Proof. Exercise.
23
In referring to the property described by this lemma, we say that a future inex-
tendible causal curve cannot be “imprisoned” or “partially imprisoned” in a compact
set on which strong causality holds.
We now come to a fundamental condition in spacetime geometry, that of global
hyperbolicity. Mathematically, global hyperbolicity is a basic ‘niceness’ condition that
often plays a role analogous to geodesic completeness in Riemannian geometry. Phys-
ically, global hyperbolicity is connected to the notion of (strong) cosmic censorship
introduced by Roger Penrose. This is the conjecture that, generically, spacetime solu-
tions to the Einstein equations do not admit naked singularities (singularities visible
to some observer).
Definition 2.4. A spacetime M is said to be globally hyperbolic provided
(1) M is strongly causal.
(2) (Internal Compactness) The sets J + (p) ∩ J − (q) are compact for all p, q ∈ M .
Condition (2) says roughly that M has no holes or gaps. For example Minkowski
space Mn+1 is globally hyperbolic but the spacetime obtained by removing one point
from it is not.
We consider a few basic consequences of global hyperbolicity.
Proposition 2.14. Let M be a globally hyperbolic spacetime. Then,
(1) The sets J ± (A) are closed, for all compact A ⊂ M .
(2) The sets J + (A) ∩ J − (B) are compact, for all compact A, B ⊂ M .
Proof. We prove J ± (p) are compact for all p ∈M, and leave the rest as an exercise.
Suppose q ∈ J + (p) \ J + (p) for some p ∈ M . Choose r ∈ I + (q), and {qn } ⊂ J + (p),
with qn → q. Since I − (r) is an open neighborhood of q, {qn } ⊂ J − (r) for n large. It
follows that q ∈ J + (p) ∩ J − (r) = J + (p) ∩ J − (r), since J + (p) ∩ J − (r) is compact and
hence closed. But this contradicts q ∈ / J + (p) . Thus, J + (p) is closed, and similarly
−
so is J (p).
Analogously to the case of Riemannian geometry, one can learn much about
the global structure of spacetime by studying its causal geodesics. Locally, causal
geodesics maximize Lorentzian arc length (cf., Proposition 2.2). Given p, q ∈ M ,
with p < q, we wish to consider conditions under which there exists a maximal future
directed causal geodesic γ from p to q, where by maximal we mean that for any future
directed causal curve σ from p to q, L(γ) ≥ L(σ).
For this purpose it is convenient to introduce the Lorentzian distance function,
d : M × M → [0, ∞]. For p < q, let Ωp,q denote the collection of future directed
causal curves from p to q. Then, for any p, q ∈ M , define
(
sup{L(σ) : σ ∈ Ωp,q }, if p < q
d(p, q) =
0, if p 6< q
24
While the Lorentzian distance function is not a distance function in the usual
sense of metric spaces, and may not even be finite valued, it does have a few nice
properties. For one, it obeys a reverse triangle inequality,
25
Let γ̄ = γ|[0,a] . γ̄ is a future directed C 0 causal curve from p to q. Moreover, by
the upper semi-continuity of L,
L(γ̄) ≥ lim sup L(γm ) = d(p, q) ,
m→∞
and so L(γ̄) = d(p, q). Hence, γ̄ has maximal length among all future directed causal
curves from p to q. This forces each sub-segment of γ̄ to have maximal length.
Using Proposition 2.2 (part (2) of which remains valid for C 0 causal curves) and
Proposition 2.4, one can then argue that each sufficiently small segment of γ̄ is a
causal geodesic. (Exercise: Argue this.)
Remarks: There are simple examples showing that if either of the conditions (1) or
(2) fail to hold in the definition of global hyperbolicity then maximal segments may
fail to exist. Moreover, contrary to the situation in Riemannian geometry, geodesic
completeness does not guarantee the existence of maximal segments, as is well il-
lustrated by anti-de Sitter space which is geodesically complete. The figure below
depicts 2-dimensional anti-de Sitter space. It be can be represented as the strip
M = {(t, x) : −π/2 < x < π/2}, equipped with the metric ds2 = sec2 x(−dt2 + dx2 ).
Because the anti-de Sitter metric is conformal to the Minkowski metric on the strip,
pasts and futures of both space times are the same. It can be shown that all future
directed timelike geodesics emanating from p refocus at r. The points p and q are
timelike related, but there is no timelike geodesic segment from p to q.
Global hyperbolicity is closely related to the existence of certain ‘ideal initial value
hypersurfaces’, called Cauchy surfaces. There are slight variations in the literature
in the definition of a Cauchy surface. Here we adopt the following definition.
Definition 2.5. A Cauchy surface for a spacetime M is an achronal subset S of M
which is met by every inextendible causal curve in M .
26
From the definition it is easy to see that if S is a Cauchy surface for M then
S = ∂I + (S) = ∂I − (S). It follows from Proposition 2.7 that a Cauchy surface S is a
closed achronal C 0 hypersurface in M .
Theorem 2.17. Consider a spacetime M .
Proof. We make a couple of comments about the proof. To prove (1), one introduces
a measure µ on M such that µ(M ) = 1. Consider the function f : M → R defined
by
µ(J − (p))
f (p) = .
µ(J + (p))
Internal compactness is used to show that f is continuous, and strong causality is used
to show that f is strictly increasing along future directed causal curves. Moreover,
if γ : (a, b) → M is a future directed inextendible causal curve in M , one shows
f (γ(t)) → 0 as t → a+ , and f (γ(t)) → ∞ as t → b− . It follows that S = {p ∈ M :
f (p) = 1} is a Cauchy surface for M . To prove (2), one introduces a future directed
timelike vector field X on M . X can be scaled so that the time parameter t of each
integral curve of X extends from −∞ to ∞, with t = 0 at points of S. Each p ∈ M
is on an integral curve of X that meets S in exactly one point q. This sets up a
correspondence p ↔ (t, q), which gives the desired homeomorphism.
As we discuss in the next subsection, the converse to (1) above holds. Thus, a
spacetime M is globally hyperbolic iff it admits a Cauchy surface S. Along similar
lines to (2) above, one has that any two Cauchy surfaces in a given globally hyper-
bolic spacetime are homeomorphic. Hence, in view of Theorem 2.17, any nontrivial
topology in a globally hyperbolic spacetime must reside in its Cauchy surfaces.
The following fact is often useful.
Proposition 2.18. If S is a compact achronal C 0 hypersurface in a globally hyperbolic
spacetime M then S must be a Cauchy surface for M .
The proof will be discussed in the next subsection.
27
In physical terms, since information travels along causal curves, a point in D+ (S)
only receives information from S. Thus if physical laws are suitably causal, initial
data on S should determine the physics on D+ (S) (in fact on all of D(S)).
Below we show a few examples of future and past domains of dependence.
The figure in the top right shows the effect of removing a point from M . The bottom
figure shows the future domain of dependence of the spacelike hyperboloid t2 −x2 = 1,
t < 0, in the Minkowski plane.
If S is achronal, the future Cauchy horizon H + (S) of S is the future boundary of
D+ (S). This is made precise in the following definition.
Definition 2.7. Let S ⊂ M be achronal. The future Cauchy horizon H + (S) of S is
defined as follows
The past Cauchy horizon H − (S) is defined time-dually. The (total) Cauchy horizon
of S is defined as the union, H(S) = H + (S) = H − (S).
We record some basic facts about domains of dependence and Cauchy horizons.
28
Proposition 2.19. Let S be an achronal subset of M . Then the following hold.
(1) S ⊂ D+ (S).
The achronality of H + (S) follows almost immediately from the definition: Suppose
p, q ∈ H + (S) with p q. Since q ∈ D+ (S), and I + (p) is a neighborhood of q, I + (p)
meets D+ (S), contradicting the definition of H + (S).
Cauchy horizons have structural properties similar to achronal boundaries, as
indicated in the next two results. From Proposition 2.9 and Parts (4) and (5) of
Proposition 2.19, we obtain the following.
Proposition 2.20. Let S ⊂ M be achronal. Then H + (S) \ edge S, if nonempty, is
an achronal C 0 hypersurface in M .
In a similar vein to Proposition 2.10, we have the following.
Proposition 2.21. Let S be an achronal subset of M . Then H + (S) is ruled by null
geodesics, i.e., every point of H + (S) \ edge S is the future endpoint of a null geodesic
in H + (S) which is either past inextendible in M or else has a past end point on
edge S.
Comments on the proof. The proof uses a limit curve argument. Consider the case
p ∈ H + (S)\S. Since I + (p)∩D+ (S) = ∅, we can find a sequence of points pn ∈
/ D+ (S),
such that pn → p. For each n, there exists a past inextendible causal curve γn that
does not meet S. By the limit curve lemma there exists a subsequence γm that
converges to a past inextendible C 0 causal curve γ starting at p. Near p this defines
the desired null geodesic (see the figure).
The case p ∈ S\edge S is handled somewhat differently; for details see [28, p. 203].
29
The following basic result ties domains of dependence to global hyperbolicity.
Proposition 2.22. Let S ⊂ M be achronal.
(2) Internal compactness holds on int D(S), i.e., for all p, q ∈ D(S), J + (p) ∩ J − (p)
is compact.
Comments on the proof. With regard to (1), first observe that the chronology con-
dition holds on D(S). For instance, suppose there exists a timelike curve γ passing
through p ∈ D+ (S), and take γ to be past directed. By repeating loops we ob-
tain a past inextendible timelike curve γ̃, which hence must meet S. In fact, it will
meet S infinitely often, thereby violating the achronality of S. A similar argument
shows that the causality condition holds on int D(S). Suppose for example that γ
is a past directed closed causal curve through p ∈ int D+ (S). By repeating loops
we obtain a past inextendible causal curve γ̃ starting at p. Thus γ̃ meets S, and
since p ∈ int D+ (S), will enter I − (S). This again leads to an achronality violation.
By more refined arguments, using the limit curve lemma, one can show that strong
causality holds on int D(S). With regard to (2), suppose there exist p, q ∈ int D(S),
such that J + (p) ∩ J − (p) is noncompact. We want to show that every sequence qn
in J + (p) ∩ J − (p) has a convergent subsequence. Without loss of generality we may
assume {qn } ⊂ D− (S). For each n, let γn be a future directed causal curve from p
to q passing through qn . As usual, extend each γn to a future inextendible causal
curve γ̃n . By the limit curve lemma, there exists a subsequence γ̃m that converges to
a future inextendible C 0 causal curve γ starting at p. One can then show that either
the sequence of points qm converges or γ does not enter I + (S).
Putting several previous results together we obtain the following.
Proposition 2.23. Let S be an achronal subset of a spacetime M . Then, S is a
Cauchy surface for M iff D(S) = M iff H(S) = ∅. Hence, if S is a Cauchy surface
for M then M is globally hyperbolic.
Proof. Exercise.
We now give a proof of Proposition 2.18 from the previous subsection.
Proof of Proposition 2.18. It suffices to show that H(S) = H + (S) ∪ H − (S) = ∅.
Suppose there exists p ∈ H + (S). Since S is edgeless, it follows from Proposition 2.21
that p is the future endpoint of a past inextendible null geodesic γ ⊂ H + (S). Then
since γ ⊂ D+ (S) ∩ J − (p) (exercise: show this), we have that γ is contained in the
set J + (S) ∩ J − (p), which is compact by Proposition 2.14). By Lemma 2.13 strong
causality must be violated at some point of J + (S) ∩ J − (p). Thus H + (S) = ∅, and
time-dually, H − (S) = ∅.
30
We conclude this subsection by stating several lemmas that are useful in proving
some of the results described here, as well as other results concerning domains of
dependence.
Lemma 2.24 ([22], p. 416). Let γ be a past inextendible causal curve starting at p
that does not meet a closed set C. If p0 ∈ I + (p, M \C), there exists a past inextendible
timelike curve starting at p0 that does not meet C.
Proof. Exercise.
Lemma 2.25. Let S be achronal. If p ∈ int D+ (S) then every past inextendible causal
curve from p enters I − (S).
Proof. This follows from the proof of the preceding lemma.
Lemma 2.26. Let S be achronal. Then p ∈ D+ (S) iff every past inextendible timelike
curve meets S.
Proof. Exercise.
In particular,
(2) [Kp ]⊥ = Tp S.
31
Thus, every null hypersurface S gives rise to a future directed null vector field K,
K
p ∈ S −→ Kp ∈ Tp S,
[K, X] = ∇K X − ∇X K = 0
To study the ‘shape’ of the null hypersurface S we study how the null vector field
K varies along S. Since K is actually orthogonal to S, this is somewhat analogous
32
to how we study the shape of a hypersurface in a Riemannian manifold, or spacelike
hypersurface in a Lorentzian manifold, by introducing the shape operator (or Wein-
garten map) and associated second fundamental form. We proceed to introduce null
analogues of these objects. For technical reasons one works “mod K”, as described
below.
We introduce the following equivalence relation on tangent vectors: For X, X 0 ∈
Tp S,
X 0 = X mod K if and only if X 0 − X = λK for some λ ∈ R .
Let X denote the equivalence class of X. Let Tp S/K = {X : X ∈ Tp S}, and
T S/K = ∪p∈S Tp S/K. T S/K, the mod K tangent bundle of S, is a smooth rank
n − 1 vector bundle over S. This vector bundle does not depend on the particular
choice of null vector field K.
There is a natural positive definite metric h on T S/K induced from h , i: For each
p ∈ S, define h : Tp S/K × Tp S/K → R by h(X, Y ) = hX, Y i. A simple computation
shows that h is well-defined: If X 0 = X mod K, Y 0 = Y mod K then
hX 0 , Y 0 i = hX + αK, Y + βKi
= hX, Y i + βhX, Ki + αhK, Y i + αβhK, Ki
= hX, Y i .
The null Weingarten map b = bK of S with respect to K is, for each point p ∈ S,
a linear map b : Tp S/K → Tp S/K defined by b(X) = ∇X K.
e = f K, f ∈ C ∞ (S), is
Exercise: Show that b is well-defined. Show also that that if K
any other future directed null vector field on S, then bK̃ = f bK . It follows that the
Weingarten map b = bK at a point p is uniquely determined by the value of K at p.
Proposition 3.2. b is self adjoint with respect to h, i.e., h(b(X), Y ) = h(X, b(Y )),
for all X, Y ∈ Tp S/K.
Proof. Extend X, Y ∈ Tp S to vector fields tangent to S near p. Using XhK, Y i = 0
and Y hK, Xi = 0, we obtain,
33
totally geodesic, the restriction to S of the Levi-Civita connection of M defines a
linear connection on S. Null hyperplanes in Minkowski space are totally geodesic, as
is the event horizon in Schwarzschild spacetime.
The null mean curvature (or null expansion scalar) of S with respect to K is the
smooth scalar field θ on S defined by, θ = tr b. θ has a natural geometric interpreta-
tion. Let Σ be the intersection of S with a hypersurface in M which is transverse to
K near p ∈ S; Σ will be a co-dimension two spacelike submanifold of M , along which
K is orthogonal.
Let {e1 , e2 , · · · , en−1 } be an orthonormal basis for Tp Σ in the induced metric. Then
{e1 , e2 , · · · , en−1 } is an orthonormal basis for Tp S/K. Hence at p,
n−1
X n−1
X
θ = tr b = h(b(ei ), ei ) = h∇ei K, ei i.
i=1 i=1
= divΣ K . (3.5)
where divΣ K is the divergence of K along Σ. Thus, θ measures the overall expansion
of the null generators of S towards the future.
It follows from the exercise on the preceeding page that if K
e = f K then θe = f θ.
Thus the null mean curvature inequalities θ > 0, θ < 0, etc., are invariant under
positive rescaling of K. In Minkowski space, a future null cone S = ∂I + (p) \ {p}
(resp., past null cone S = ∂I − (p) \ {p}) has positive null mean curvature, θ > 0
(resp., negative null mean curvature, θ < 0).
We now study how the null Weingarten map propagates along the null geodesic
generators of S. Let η : I → M , s → η(s), be a future directed affinely parameterized
null geodesic generator of S. For each s ∈ I, let
b(s) = bη0 (s) : Tη(s) S/η 0 (s) → Tη(s) S/η 0 (s) (3.6)
be the Weingarten map based at η(s) with respect to the null vector K = η 0 (s). We
show that the one parameter family of Weingarten maps s → b(s), obeys a certain
Ricatti equation.
We first need to make a few definitions. Let s → Y(s) be a T S/K vector field
along η, i.e., for each s ∈ I, Y(s) ∈ Tη(s) S/K. We say that s → Y(s) is smooth if,
at least locally, there is a smooth (in the usual sense) vector field s → Y (s) along
η, tangent to S, such that Y(s) = Y (s). Then define the covariant derivative of
s → Y(s) along η by, Y 0 (s) = Y 0 (s), where Y 0 is the usual covariant differentiation.
Exercise: Show that Y 0 is independent of the choice of Y .
34
Then the covariant derivative of b along η is defined by requiring a natural product
rule to hold. If s → X(s) is a vector field along η tangent to S, b0 is defined by,
Proposition 3.3. The one parameter family of Weingarten maps s → b(s), obeys
the following Ricatti equation,
b0 + b2 + R = 0 , (3.8)
where R : Tη(s) S/η 0 (s) → Tη(s) S/η 0 (s) is the curvature endomorphism defined by
R(X) = R(X, η 0 (s))η 0 (s).
Proof. Fix a point p = η(s0 ), s0 ∈ (a, b), on η. On a neighborhood U of p in S we
can scale the null vector field K so that K is a geodesic vector field, ∇K K = 0, and
so that K, restricted to η, is the velocity vector field to η, i.e., for each s near s0 ,
Kη(s) = η 0 (s). Let X ∈ Tp M . Shrinking U if necessary, we can extend X to a smooth
vector field on U so that [X, K] = ∇X K − ∇K X = 0. Then,
35
Proof. Suppose θ < 0 at p ∈ S. Let s → η(s) be the null generator of S passing
through p = η(0), affinely parametrized. Let b(s) = bη0 (s) , and take θ = tr b. By the
invariance of sign under scaling, one has θ(0) < 0. Raychaudhuri’s equation and the
NEC imply that θ = θ(s) obeys the inequality,
dθ 1 2
≤− θ , (3.10)
ds n−1
and hence θ < 0 for all s > 0. Dividing through by θ2 then gives,
d 1 1
≥ , (3.11)
ds θ n−1
4 Trapped surfaces
In this section we introduce the important notions of trapped and marginally trapped
surfaces, which are associated with gravitational collapse and black hole formation.
As applications of these notions, we present the classical Penrose singularity theorem
and discuss the topology of black holes.
36
Thus, under suitable orientation assumptions, Σ admits two smooth nonvanishing
future directed null normal vector fields K+ and K− .
K{ K+
Hence, θ+ and θ− are smooth scalars on Σ that measure the overall expansion of the
outward going and inward going light rays, respectively, emanating from Σ.
For round spheres in Euclidean slices of Minkowski space, with the obvious choice
of inside and outside, one has θ− < 0 and θ+ > 0.
µ{ < 0 µ+ > 0
In fact, this is the case in general for large “radial” spheres in asymptotically flat
spacelike hypersurfaces. However, in regions of spacetime where the gravitational
field is strong, one may have both θ− < 0 and θ+ < 0, in which case Σ is called a
trapped surface. As discussed in the following subsection, under appropriate energy
and causality conditions, the occurrence of a trapped surface signals the onset of
gravitational collapse [24].
Focussing attention on just the outward null normal, we say that Σ is an outer
trapped surface if θ+ < 0, and is a marginally outer trapped surface (MOTS) if
θ+ = 0. MOTSs arise in a number of natural situations. For example, compact cross
sections of the event horizon in stationary (steady state) black hole spacetimes are
MOTSs. (Recall, from Proposition 3.4, that in general one has θ ≥ 0 on the event
horizon, but in the steady state limit this goes to zero.)
µ+ = 0
§
37
For dynamical black hole spacetimes, MOTS typically occur in the black hole
region, i.e., the region inside the event horizon.
+
µ =0
While there are heuristic arguments for the existence of MOTSs in this situation,
based on looking at the boundary of the ‘trapped region’ [19, 28] within a given
spacelike slice, a recent result of Schoen [27] rigorously establishes their existence
under natural conditions.
There has been a lot of recent work done concerning properties of MOTSs. In
large measure, this is due to renewed interest in quasi-local notions of black holes,
such as dynamical horizons [2], and to connections between MOTSs in spacetime
and minimal surfaces in Riemannian manifolds. In fact, if Σn−1 is a hypersurface
in a time-symmetric (i.e, totally geodesic) spacelike hypersurface V n , then, with K +
suitably normalized, θ+ = H, where H is the mean curvature of Σ within V . Thus, a
MOTS contained in a totally geodesic spacelike hypersurface V n ⊂ M n+1 is simply a
minimal hypersurface in V . Despite the absence of a variational characterization of
MOTs like that for minimal surfaces, MOTS have been shown to satisfy a number of
properties analogous to those of minimal surfaces. As a case in point, in Subsection 4.3
we describe recent work with Rick Schoen [14], in which we generalize to higher
dimensions a classical theorem of Hawking on the topology of black holes.
38
In studying an isolated gravitating system, such as the collapse of a star and
formation of a black hole, it is customary to model this situation by a spacetime
which is asymptotically flat (i.e., asymptotically Minkowskian). In this context, the
assumption of the Penrose singularity theorem that spacetime admit a noncompact
Cauchy surface is natural.
The key concept introduced by Penrose in this singularity theorem is that of the
trapped surface (discussed in the previous subsection). What Penrose proved is that
once the gravitational field becomes sufficiently strong that trapped surfaces appear
(as they do in the Schwarzschild solution) then the development of singularities is
inevitable.
Theorem 4.1. Let M be a globally hyperbolic spacetime with noncompact Cauchy
surfaces satisfying the NEC. If M contains a trapped surface Σ then M is future null
geodesically incomplete.
Proof. Suppose that M is future null geodesically complete. We show that the
achronal boundary ∂I + (Σ) is compact. Since ∂I + (Σ) is closed, if ∂I + (Σ) is non-
compact, there exists a sequence of points {qn } ⊂ ∂I + (Σ) that diverges to infinity
in M , i.e., that does not have a convergent subsequence in M . Since, by Proposi-
tion 2.14, J + (Σ) is closed, we have,
Hence, by Proposition 2.4, there exists a future directed null geodesic ηn ; [0, an ] → M
from some point pn ∈ Σ to qn , which is contained in ∂I + (Σ). In particular, ηn must
meet Σ orthogonally at pn (otherwise qn ∈ I + (Σ)). By passing to a subsequence if
necessary, we may assume that each ηn is ‘outward pointing’ (ηn0 (0) = Kp+n ).
Since Σ is compact there exists a subsequence {pm } of {pn }, such that pm → p ∈ Σ.
It follows that the sequence {ηm } converges in the sense of geodesics to a future
complete outward pointing normal null geodesic η : [0, ∞) → M , starting at p, which
is contained in ∂I + (Σ). By Equation (4.12), there can be no timelike curve from a
point of Σ to a point of η. This implies that no outward pointing null normal geodesic
can meet η, for they would have to meet in a corner. A point further out on η would
then be timelike related to Σ. On similar grounds, there can be no null focal point to
Σ along η, i.e., no point on η where nearby outward pointing null normal geodesics
cross η “to first order” ([22, Prop. 48, p. 296]). This implies that the exponential
map, restricted to the null normal bundle of Σ, is nonsingular along η (see [22], Prop.
30, p. 283 and Cor. 40, p. 290). It follows that for any a > 0, the segment η|[0,a] , is
contained in a smooth null hypersurface S, generated by the outward pointing null
normal geodesics emanating from a sufficiently small neighborhood of p in Σ. Since
Σ is a trapped surface, θ+ (p) < 0. Choose a > |θn−1
+ (p)| .
39
in an affine parameter time ≤ |θn−1
+ (p)| < a, contradicting the smoothness of S in a
neighborhood of η|[0,a] .
Thus we have shown that if M is future null geodesically complete then ∂I + (Σ)
is compact. It now follows from Propositions 2.7 and 2.18 that ∂I + (Σ) is a compact
Cauchy surface for M , contrary assumption.
H = @I {(I+)
§ ¼ S2
Remark: Let M be a spacetime that satisfies the Einstein equations (1.4) with Λ = 0.
Then we say M obeys the DEC if T (X, Y ) = Tij X i Y j ≥ 0 for all future directed
causal vectors X, Y .
With impetus coming from the development of string theory, Myers and Perry in
a 1986 paper [21] constructed a natural higher dimensional generalization of the Kerr
solution, which, in particular, has spherical horizon topology. Perhaps one might
have expected black hole uniqueness to extend to these higher dimensional models.
40
But any such expectations were quelled by the remarkable example of Emparan and
Reall [7], published in 2002, of a 4 + 1-dimensional AF vacuum stationary black hole
spacetime with horizon topology S 2 × S 1 , the so-called“black ring”.
The question then naturally arises as to what, if any, are the restrictions on the
topology of black holes in higher dimensions. This was addressed in a recent paper
with Rick Schoen [14], which I would like to describe here. We obtained a natural
generalization of Hawking’s black hole topology theorem to higher dimensions. Our
result implies many well-known restrictions on the topology, some of which we shall
review here.
I want to recall briefly the idea behind Hawking’s proof of Theorem 4.2. The proof
is variational in nature. As in the following figure,
§
µ+ = 0
µ+ < 0
let Σ be a cross section of the event horizon H. Thus Σ is a co-dimension two compact
spacelike submanifold contained in H. The null generators of H are orthogonal to Σ
at points of intersection. Since the spacetime is stationary, the null generators have
vanishing expansion. It follows that Σ is a MOTS, θ+ = 0.
If Σ is not topologically a 2-sphere, i.e., if it has genus g ≥ 1 then using the
Gauss-Bonnet theorem and the DEC, Hawking shows how to deform Σ along a past
null hypersurface to a strictly outer trapped surface, θ+ < 0, outside the black hole
region. But the existence of an outer trapped surface outside the black hole region is
forbidden by standard results.
Remarks:
(1) Actually, the torus (g = 1) is borderline for Hawking’s argument. But this can
occur only under special circumstances.
(2) Hawking showed by a variation of his original argument, that the conclusion of
his theorem also holds for ‘outer apparent horizons’ in black hole spacetimes that
are not necessarily stationary. This will be the context for the generalization of
Hawking’s theorem described below.
(3) In higher dimensions, one cannot appeal to the Gauss-Bonnet theorem. This is
one of the complicating the issues.
41
Let Σn−1 be a closed hypersurface in V n , and assume that Σn−1 separates V n into an
“inside” and an “outside”. Let N be the outward unit normal to Σn−1 in V n , and let
U be the future directed unit normal to V n in M n+1 . Then K = U + N is an outward
null normal field to Σn−1 , unique up to scaling.
U K Vn
§n{1
N
U
outside
(1) a spherical space (i.e., a homotopy 3-sphere, perhaps with identifications) or,
(2) S 2 × S 1 , or
42
and K(π, 1) manifolds (manifolds whose universal covers are contractible). But as Σ
admits a metric of positive scalar curvature, it cannot have any K(π, 1)’s in its prime
decomposition.
Thus, the basic horizon topologies in dim M = 4 + 1 are S 3 and S 2 × S 1 , both of
which are realized by nontrivial black hole spacetimes.
K Kt = U +Nt
§ Nt
U §t
Vn
where,
L(φ) = −4φ + 2hX, ∇φi + Q + div X − |X|2 φ ,
(4.14)
1 1
Q = S − T (U, K) − |b|2 , X = tan (∇N U ) , (4.15)
2 2
S is the scalar curvature of Σ, and h , i now denotes the the induced metric on Σ.
L is a second order linear elliptic operator, associated with variations in θ, anal-
ogous to the stability operator of minimal surface theory [1]. In fact, in the time-
symmetric case (V totally geodesic) the vector field X vanishes and L reduces to the
stability operator of minimal surface theory. Note, however, that L is not in general
self-adjoint (with respect to the standard L2 inner product on Σ).
Although L is not in general self adjoint, its principal eigenvalue (eigenvalue with
smallest real part) λ1 (L) is real, and one can choose a principal eigenfunction φ which
is strictly positive, φ > 0. Using the eigenfunction φ to define our variation, we have
from (4.13),
∂θ
= λ1 (L)φ . (4.16)
∂t t=0
43
The eigenvalue λ1 (L) cannot be negative, for otherwise (4.13) would imply that ∂θ
∂t
<0
on Σ. Since θ = 0 on Σ, this would mean that for t > 0 sufficiently small, Σt would
be outer trapped, contrary to our assumptions. Hence, λ1 (L) ≥ 0.
Now consider the “symmetrized operator”,
Setting u = ln φ, we obtain,
Absorbing the Laplacian term 4u = div (∇u) into the divergence term gives,
−ψ 2 Q + ψ 2 |Y |2 + ψ 2 λ1 (L) = ψ 2 div Y
= div (ψ 2 Y ) − 2ψh∇ψ, Y i
≤ div (ψ 2 Y ) + 2|ψ||∇ψ||Y |
≤ div (ψ 2 Y ) + |∇ψ|2 + ψ 2 |Y |2 .
The claim now follows from the well-known Rayleigh formula for the principal eigen-
value applied to the operator (4.17).
Thus, we have that λ1 (L0 ) ≥ 0 for the operator (4.17), where Q is given in (4.15).
We have in effect reduced the situation to the time-symmetric (or Riemannian) case,
where standard arguments become applicable.
44
Let f ∈ C ∞ (Σ) be an eigenfunction associated to λ1 (L0 ); f can be chosen to be
strictly positive. Consider Σ in the conformally related metric h̃ = f 2/n−2 h, where h
is the induced metric. The scalar curvature S̃ of Σ in the metric h̃ is given by,
n − 1 |∇f |2
−n/(n−2)
S̃ = f −24f + Sf +
n−2 f
n − 1 |∇f |2
−2/(n−2) 2
=f 2λ1 (L0 ) + 2T (U, K) + |B| + , (4.23)
n − 2 f2
where, in the second equation, we have used (4.17), with φ = f , and (4.15).
Since all terms in the parentheses above are nonnegative, (4.23) implies that S̃ ≥ 0.
If S̃ > 0 at some point, then by well known results [20] one can conformally rescale
h̃ to a metric of strictly positive scalar curvature. If, on the other hand, S̃ vanishes
identically, then (4.23) implies: λ1 (L0 ) = 0, T (U, K) ≡ 0, B ≡ 0 and f is constant.
Equations (4.17) and (4.15) then imply that S ≡ 0. One can then deform h in the
direction of the Ricci tensor of Σ to obtain a metric of positive scalar curvature, unless
(Σ, h) is Ricci flat (see [20]).
Remark: A drawback of Theorem 4.3 is that it allows certain ‘exceptional circum-
stances’. For example note that Theorem 4.3 does not rule out the possibility of
a vacuum black hole spacetime with toroidal horizon topology. More recently, we
have succeded in ruling out these exceptional cases in a number of natural situations;
see [13].
45
Theorem 5.1. Let S1 and S2 be smooth null hypersurfaces in a spacetime M . Sup-
pose,
(1) S1 and S2 meet at p ∈ M and S2 lies to the future side of S1 near p, and
Then S1 and S2 coincide near p and this common null hypersurface has null mean
curvature θ = 0.
The heuristic idea is that since the generators of S1 are (weakly) diverging, and
the generators of S2 , which lie to the future of S1 are (weakly) converging, the two
sets of generators are forced to agree and form a nonexpanding congruence.
Proof. We give a sketch of the proof; for details, see [10]. S1 and S2 have a common
null direction at p. Let Q be a timelike hypersurface in M passing through p and
transverse to this direction. By taking Q small enough, the intersections,
Σ1 = S1 ∩ Q and Σ2 = S2 ∩ Q
where H is the mean curvature operator on spacelike graphs over V in Q. (The lower
order terms involve the second fundamental form of Q.) Thus θ is a second order
quasi-linear elliptic operator. In the present situation we have:
Then Alexandrov’s strong maximum principle for second order quasi-linear elliptic
PDEs implies that u1 = u2 . Thus, Σ1 and Σ2 agree near p. The null normal geodesics
to Σ1 and Σ2 in M will then also agree. This implies that S1 and S2 agree near p.
46
The usefulness of Theorem 5.1 is somewhat limited by the fact that the most
interesting null hypersurfaces arising in general relativity, e.g., event horizons, Cauchy
horizons, and observer horizons, are in general rough, i.e., are C 0 , but in general not
C 1 . The key point, however, is that Theorem 5.1 extends to C 0 null hypersurfaces,
suitably defined. Roughly, a C 0 null hypersurface is a locally achronal C 0 hypersurface
in spacetime that is ruled, in a suitable sense, by null geodesics. The null portions
of achronal boundaries, ∂I ± (S) \ S, are the basic models for C 0 null hypersurfaces
(recall Propositions 2.7 and 2.10). Although C 0 null hypersurfaces do not in general
have null mean curvature in the classical sense, they, nonetheless may obey null mean
curvature inequalities in a certain weak sense, namely in the sense of support null
hypersurfaces [10, 12]. Thus, the null mean curvature inequalities, θ2 ≤ 0 ≤ θ1 , can
hold for C 0 null hypersurfaces in the support sense.
The upshot of these comments is that Theorem 5.1 extends, in an appropriate
manner, to C 0 null hypersurfaces; see [10, Theorem III.2]. It is this maximum prin-
ciple for C 0 null hypersurfaces that is actually needed to prove the null splitting
theorem.
1
Establishing this rigidity remains an important open problem; see, for example the discussion
in [3, p. 503ff].
47
Null lines arise naturally in causal arguments; recall, for example, that sets of the
form ∂I ± (S) \ S, S closed, are ruled by null geodesics which are necessarily achronal.
Null lines have arisen in various situations in general relativity, for example in the
proofs of the Hawking-Penrose singularity theorem, topological censorship and certain
versions of the positivity of mass.
Every null geodesic in Minkowski space and de Sitter space is a null line. At the
same time, both of these spacetimes obey the null energy condition. In general, it
is difficult for complete null lines to exist in spacetimes which obey the null energy
condition. The null energy condition tends to focus congruences of null geodesics,
which can lead to the occurence of null conjugate points. But a null geodesic con-
taining a pair of conjugate points cannot be achronal. Thus we expect a spacetime
which satisfies the null energy condition and which contains a complete null line to
be special in some way, to exhibit some sort of rigidity. The null splitting theorem
addresses what this rigidity is.
Theorem 5.2 ([10]). Let M be a null geodesically complete spacetime which obeys
the NEC. If M admits a null line η then η is contained in a smooth properly embedded
achronal totally geodesic null hypersurface S.
Recall from Section 3, ‘totally geodesic’ means that the null second form of S van-
ishes, B ≡ 0, or equivalently that the null expansion and shear, θ and σ, repectively,
vanish on S. This implies that the metric h defined on the vector bundle T S/K is
invariant under the flow generated by K; it is in this sense that S ‘splits’.
The simplest illustration of Theorem 5.2 is Minkowski space: Each null line ` in
Minkowski space is contained in a unique null hyperplane Π.
Proof. The proof is an application of the maximum principle for C 0 null hypersurfaces.
For simplicity we shall assume M is strongly causal; this however is not required; see
[10] for details.
By way of motivation, note that the null plane Π in Minkowski space determined
by the null line ` can be realized as the limit of the future null cone ∂I + (x) as x goes
to past null infinity along the null line `.
Π can also be realized as the limit of the past null cone ∂I − (x) as x goes to future
null infinity along the null line `. In fact, one sees that Π = ∂I + (`) = ∂I − (`).
48
Thus, in the setting of Theorem 5.2, consider the achronal boundaries S+ =
∂I (η) and S− = ∂I − (η). By Proposition 2.7, S+ and S− are closed achronal C 0
+
49
There has been increased interest in recent years in de Sitter space, and space-
times which are asymptotically de Sitter, due, firstly, to observations supporting an
accelerated rate of expansion of the universe, suggesting the presence in our universe
of a positive cosmological constant, and due, secondly, to recent efforts to understand
quantum gravity on such spacetimes (see [4] and references cited therein).
We use Penrose’s notion of conformal infinity [23] to make precise what it means
for spacetime to be asymptotically de Sitter. Recall, this notion is based on the
way in which the standard Lorentzian space forms, Minkowski space, de Sitter space
and anti-de Sitter space, conformally imbed into the Einstein static universe (R ×
S n , −du2 + dω 2 ).
Under the transformation u = tan−1 (et ) − π/4, the metric (5.27) becomes
1
ds2 = (−du2 + dω 2 ) . (5.28)
cos2 (2u)
Thus, de Sitter space conformally imbeds onto the region −π/4 < u < π/4 in the
Einstein static universe.
(3) I is spacelike.
50
Definition 5.2. An asymptotically de Sitter spacetime is asymptotically simple
provided every inextendible null geodesic in M has a future end point on I+ and a
past end point on I− .
Thus, an asymptotically de Sitter spacetime is asymptotically simple provided
each null geodesic extends to infinity both to the future and the past. In particular,
such a spacetime is null geodesically complete.
It is a fact that every inextendible null geodesic in de Sitter space is a null line.
As discussed below, this may be understood in terms of the causal structure of de
Sitter space. As the following result shows, the occurrence of null lines is a very
special feature of de Sitter space among asymptotically simple and de Sitter vacuum
spacetimes.
Theorem 5.3 ([11]). Let (M, g) be a 4-dimensional asymptotically simple and de
Sitter spacetime satisfying the vacuum Einstein equations (5.25). If M contains a
null line then M is isometric to de Sitter space.
This theorem can be interpreted in terms of the initial value problem in the
following way: Friedrich’s work [9] on the nonlinear stability of de Sitter space shows
that the set of asymptotically simple solutions to the Einstein equations with positive
cosmological constant is open in the set of all maximal globally hyperbolic solutions
with compact spatial sections. As a consequence, by slightly perturbing the initial
data on a fixed Cauchy surface of dS 4 we get in general an asymptotically simple
solution of the Einstein equations different from dS 4 . Thus, by virtue of theorem 5.3,
such a spacetime has no null lines. In other words, a small generic perturbation of the
initial data destroys all null lines. This suggests that the so-called generic condition
of singularity theory [19] is in fact generic with respect to perturbations of the initial
data.
As discussed in [14], Theorem 5.3 may also be interpreted as saying that no other
asymptotically simple and de Sitter solution of the vacuum Einstein equations besides
dS 4 develops eternal observer horizons. By definition, an observer horizon A is the
past achronal boundary ∂I − (γ) of a future inextendible timelike curve γ, thus A is
ruled by future inextendible achronal null geodesics. In the case of de Sitter space,
observer horizons are eternal, that is, all null generators of A extend from I+ all the
way back to I− .
Since the observer horizon ∂I − (γ) is the boundary of the region of spacetime
that can be observed by γ, the question arises as to whether at one point γ would
be able to observe the whole of space. More precisely, we want to know if there
exists q ∈ M̃ such that I − (q) would contain a Cauchy surface of spacetime. Gao
and Wald [16] were able to answer this question affirmatively for globally hyperbolic
spacetimes with compact Cauchy surfaces, assuming null geodesic completeness, the
null energy condition and the null generic condition. Thus, as expressed by Bousso
[4], asymptotically de Sitter spacetimes satisfying the conditions of the Gao and Wald
result, have Penrose diagrams that are “tall” compared to de Sitter space.
51
Though no set of the form I − (q) in dS 4 contains a Cauchy surface, I − (q) gets
arbitrarily close to doing so as q → I+ . However, notice that de Sitter space is
not a counterexample to Gao and Wald’s result, since dS 4 does not satisfy the null
generic condition. Actually, the latter remark leads us to interpret theorem 5.3 as a
rigid version of the Gao and Wald result in the asymptotically simple (and vacuum)
context: by dropping the null generic hypothesis in [16] the conclusion will only fail
if (M̃ , g̃) is isometric to dS 4 .
Proof of Theorem 5.3. We present some comments on the proof; see [11, 15] for fur-
ther details. The main step is to show that M has constant curvature. Since M is
Einstein, it is sufficient to show that M is conformally flat.
Let η be the assumed null line in M . By Theorem 5.2, η is contained in a smooth
totally geodesic null hypersurface S in M . By asymptotic simplicity, η acquires a
past end point p on I− and a future end point q on I+ . Let us focus attention on the
situation near p. By the proof of Theorem 5.2, and the fact that p is the past end
point of η, we have that,
S = ∂I + (η) = ∂I + (p, M̃ ) ∩ M .
in which Np plays the role of an initial characteristic hypersurface, then shows that
the conformal tensor of g vanishes on the future domain of dependence of Np ,
i
Cjkl = 0 on D+ (Np , M̃ ) ∩ M . (5.29)
i
In a time-dual manner one obtains that Cjkl vanishes on D− (Nq , M̃ ) ∩ M . Since it
can be shown that M is contained in D+ (Np , M̃ ) ∪ D− (Nq , M̃ ), we conclude that M
is conformally flat. Together with equation (5.25), this implies that M has constant
curvature = +1. Moreover, further global arguments show that M is geodesically
52
complete and simply connected. It then follows from uniqueness results for Lorentzian
space forms that M is isometric to de Sitter space.
Remark: It has recently been shown that the conclusion of Theorem 5.3 applies under
much more general circumstances. The assumption of asymptotic simplicity can
be substantially weakened, and one can allow a priori for the presence of certain
matter fields; see [15]. The arguments make use of the fact that the null splitting
theorem does not require full null geodesic completeness. As the proof of the null
splitting theorem shows, if η is the given null line, it is sufficient to require that the
generators of ∂I − (η) be future geodesically complete and the generators of ∂I + (η) be
past geodesically complete.
References
[1] Lars Andersson, Marc Mars, and Walter Simon, Local existence of dynamical and
trapping horizons, Phys. Rev. Lett. 95 (2005), 111102.
[2] Abhay Ashtekar and Badri Krishnan, Dynamical horizons and their properties,
Phys. Rev. D (3) 68 (2003), no. 10, 104030, 25. MR MR2071054 (2005c:83030)
[3] John K. Beem, Paul E. Ehrlich, and Kevin L. Easley, Global Lorentzian geometry,
second ed., Monographs and Textbooks in Pure and Applied Mathematics, vol.
202, Marcel Dekker Inc., New York, 1996. MR MR1384756 (97f:53100)
[4] Raphael Bousso, Adventures in de Sitter space, The future of the theoretical
physics and cosmology (Cambridge, 2002), Cambridge Univ. Press, Cambridge,
2003, pp. 539–569. MR MR2033285
[5] Mingliang Cai and Gregory J. Galloway, On the topology and area of higher-
dimensional black holes, Classical Quantum Gravity 18 (2001), no. 14, 2707–
2718. MR MR1846368 (2002k:83051)
[7] Roberto Emparan and Harvey S. Reall, A rotating black ring solution in five
dimensions, Phys. Rev. Lett. 88 (2002), no. 10, 101101, 4. MR MR1901280
(2003e:83060)
[8] Helmut Friedrich, Existence and structure of past asymptotically simple solutions
of Einstein’s field equations with positive cosmological constant, J. Geom. Phys.
3 (1986), no. 1, 101–117. MR MR855572 (88c:83006)
53
[9] , On the existence of n-geodesically complete or future complete solutions
of Einstein’s field equations with smooth asymptotic structure, Comm. Math.
Phys. 107 (1986), no. 4, 587–609. MR MR868737 (88b:83006)
[10] Gregory J. Galloway, Maximum principles for null hypersurfaces and null split-
ting theorems, Ann. Henri Poincaré 1 (2000), no. 3, 543–567. MR MR1777311
(2002b:53052)
[11] , Some global results for asymptotically simple space-times, The conformal
structure of space-time, Lecture Notes in Phys., vol. 604, Springer, Berlin, 2002,
pp. 51–60. MR MR2007041 (2004k:53105)
[12] , Null geometry and the Einstein equations, The Einstein equations and
the large scale behavior of gravitational fields, Birkhäuser, Basel, 2004, pp. 379–
400. MR MR2098922 (2006f:83015)
[13] , Rigidity of outer horizons and the topology of black holes, (2006), gr–
qc/0608118.
[14] Gregory J. Galloway and Richard Schoen, A generalization of Hawking’s black
hole topology theorem to higher dimensions, Comm. Math. Phys. 266 (2006),
no. 2, 571–576. MR MR2238889
[15] Gregory J. Galloway and Didier A. Solis, Uniqueness of de sitter space, Classical
Quantum Gravity (2007), 3125–3138.
[16] Sijie Gao and Robert M. Wald, Theorems on gravitational time delay and related
issues, Classical Quantum Gravity 17 (2000), no. 24, 4999–5008. MR MR1808809
(2001m:83077)
[17] Robert Geroch, Domain of dependence, J. Mathematical Phys. 11 (1970), 437–
449. MR MR0270697 (42 #5585)
[18] Mikhael Gromov and H. Blaine Lawson, Jr., Positive scalar curvature and the
Dirac operator on complete Riemannian manifolds, Inst. Hautes Études Sci.
Publ. Math. (1983), no. 58, 83–196 (1984). MR MR720933 (85g:58082)
[19] S. W. Hawking and G. F. R. Ellis, The large scale structure of space-time, Cam-
bridge University Press, London, 1973, Cambridge Monographs on Mathematical
Physics, No. 1. MR MR0424186 (54 #12154)
[20] Jerry L. Kazdan and F. W. Warner, Existence and conformal deformation of
metrics with prescribed Gaussian and scalar curvatures, Ann. of Math. (2) 101
(1975), 317–331.
[21] R. C. Myers and M. J. Perry, Black holes in higher-dimensional space-times,
Ann. Physics 172 (1986), no. 2, 304–347. MR MR868295 (88a:83074)
54
[22] Barrett O’Neill, Semi-Riemannian geometry, Pure and Applied Mathematics,
vol. 103, Academic Press Inc. [Harcourt Brace Jovanovich Publishers], New York,
1983, With applications to relativity. MR MR719023 (85f:53002)
[24] Roger Penrose, Gravitational collapse and space-time singularities, Phys. Rev.
Lett. 14 (1965), 57–59. MR MR0172678 (30 #2897)
[26] R. Schoen and S. T. Yau, On the structure of manifolds with positive scalar
curvature, Manuscripta Math. 28 (1979), no. 1-3, 159–183.
[28] Robert M. Wald, General relativity, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL,
1984. MR MR757180 (86a:83001)
[29] Shing Tung Yau, Survey on partial differential equations in differential geometry,
Seminar on Differential Geometry, Ann. of Math. Stud., vol. 102, Princeton Univ.
Press, Princeton, N.J., 1982, pp. 3–71. MR MR645729 (83i:53003)
55