(Routledge Revivals) Raymond Firth - Symbols - Public and Private-Routledge (2011)
(Routledge Revivals) Raymond Firth - Symbols - Public and Private-Routledge (2011)
(Routledge Revivals) Raymond Firth - Symbols - Public and Private-Routledge (2011)
Symbols
This book first published in 1973 offers a broad survey of the study of
symbolic ideas and behaviour.
Raymond Firth
§3 j Routledge
^ S m ,/ Taylor & Francis Group
First published in 1973
by George Allen & Unwin Ltd
This edition first published in 2011 by Routledge
2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon, OX14 4RN
Simultaneously published in the USA and Canada
by Routledge
711 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10017
Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business
© 1973 George Allen & Unwin Ltd
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or
utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now
known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any
information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the
publishers.
Publisher's Note
The publisher has gone to great lengths to ensure the quality of this reprint but
points out that some imperfections in the original copies may be apparent.
Disclaimer
The publisher has made every effort to trace copyright holders and welcomes
correspondence from those they have been unable to contact.
SYMBOLS
PUBLIC AND
PRIVATE
London
G E O R G E ALLEN & U N W I N L T D
RUSKIN HOUSE MUSEUM STREET
First published in 1973
ISBN o 04 573011 3
Introduction page 9
I
1. An Anthropologist's Reflections on Symbolic
Usage 15
2. A Question of Terms: Scope and Meaning of
'Symbol' 54
3. Development of Anthropological Interest in
Symbols 92
4. Crystallization of Problems of Symbol Theory 127
5. Modern Anthropological Views of Symbolic
Processes 165
6. Private Symbols and Public Reactions 207
II
7. Food Symbolism in a Pre-Industrial Society 243
8. Hair as Private Asset and Public Symbol 262
9. Bodily Symbols of Greeting and Parting 299
10. Symbolism of Flags 328
11. Symbolism in Giving and Getting 368
12. Symbol and Substance 403
References 429
Index 457
INTRODUCTION
9
10 INTRODUCTION
ERRATA
Symbols
Chapter i
AN ANTHROPOLOGIST'S
REFLECTIONS
ON SYMBOLIC USAGE
or religious change. But I think that for many of us the prime rele-
vance of an anthropological approach to the study of symbolism is
its attempt to grapple as empirically as possible with the basic
human problem of what I would call disjunction - a gap between the
overt superficial statement of action and its underlying meaning.
On the surface, a person is saying or doing something which our
observations or inferences tell us should not be simply taken at
face value - it stands for something else, of greater significance to
him.
I take an illustration from my own experience in the Pacific,
years ago.* I remember seeing a Tikopia chief in pagan times stand
up in his temple and rub the great centre post of the building with
aromatic leaves drenched in coconut oil. Now you can oil wood to
preserve it or give it a polish, as decoration. And in the Pacific
you can oil your body and scent it with leaves, when you decorate
yourself, as for a dance. But as the chief did this rubbing he mur-
mured: 'May your body be washed with power.' Now scrubbing a
baulk of timber with a hunk of oily leaves is not a very elevated
intellectual act. But think of the timber as a body and of the fragrant
oil as a decorative medium. Think too not of a material body, but of
an invisible body - not necessarily with the shape of a post, but in
another context, an anthropomorphic body, of a spiritual being,
believed to control crops and fish and the health of men. Think too
of washing as cleansing, and cleansing as a preface to adornment,
and adornment as pleasing to oneself as well as to others. So you
can see this act as symbolizing the anointing of the body of a god
with fragrant scents to express the status relations and emotions of
worship - and to render the god more amenable to the requests of
his worshippers. This may seem a very faraway symbolism. Yet
think further of Christ's washing of the feet of his disciples; the
anointing of Christ by Mary of Bethany; the symbolic value to
Christians of the Cross, with its synonyms of the Wood, the Tree;
and think also of conceptions of the Eucharist (Chap. 12), of the
Mystical Body of Christ, of the Glorified Body of the Virgin. It is
not difficult to see that what we are dealing with in the Tikopia
case is a set of symbolic counters which though superficially very
• F o r more details and related ritual operations see Raymond Firth, 1967a, 209-11,
218-20, 234, 245; 1970a, 117-19, pi. I.
AN ANTHROPOLOGIST'S REFLECTIONS 27
dissimilar to the Christian ones, share some of the same basic modes
of symbolic conceptualization and patterning. But the symbolic
arrangement is set in a social matrix of clans, chieftainship, modes of
bodily decoration, even of architectural design which need intensive
study for the symbolism to become fully intelligible.
The anthropological approach, fully applied, has as its objective
to provide a systematic description and analysis of such a symbolic
act in its verbal and non-verbal aspects; to distinguish those parts
of the action held to be significant from those which are incidental;
to mark the routine or standard elements as against those which are
personal and idiosyncratic; to get elucidation from actor, participants
and non-participants of the meanings they attach to the act; and to
set all this in its general conceptual and institutional framework, and
in the more specific framework of the statuses and group relation-
ships of the people concerned. This is a demanding task. But it has
been admirably done by many anthropologists - to mention here
only Audrey Richards, Monica Wilson and Victor Turner - whose
work I shall be examining in later chapters. Some anthropologists
have also studied change in symbolic idiom - as I myself have done
in the field of Tikopia religion (Firth, 1970a).
The study of symbolism, especially religious symbolism, is
fashionable now in social anthropology. There is a tendency to look
on this study as a totally new development, but in fact as I show in
Chapter 3, anthropological interest in symbols goes back at least
100 years, before the days of McLennan and Tylor. It is true that
until recently this interest was rarely intense, systematic or sustained,
and the modern interest is much more sophisticated, analytical and
highly focused.* I think there are several reasons for this delayed
development. Firstly, as a purely professional sequence of opera-
tions, systematic studies of symbolism have had to wait until a sub-
stantial measure of progress had been made in the more formal fields
of social structure, such as kinship and politics. Now that so much
groundwork has been laid we can build loftier constructions of
interpretation. Secondly, developments in the theory of communica-
tion and of semantics, of signs and their meanings, have focused
* In 1956 at the Philadelphia meeting of the International Ethnological Congress I myself
stated that little specific attention had been paid to symbolism by anthropologists. By con-
trast, Rodney Needham has recently written 'today, when there is an efflorescence of interest
in all forms of symbolism' (in Hocart, 1970, xxix).
28 SYMBOLS
E X P L O R A T I O N OF SYMBOLS I N LITERATURE
beliefs and its reliance on a world beyond the senses. So, while
Mallarme spoke of art as impersonal, by concentrating on his own
private visions the Symbolist stressed in effect the subjective charac-
ter of his art. Michaud, with his exhaustive documentation, has
pointed out the variety of Symbolist positions. But he has seen the
essential message of symbolism as providing a synthesis in the
simultaneous expression of different degrees or levels of reality, or
expressing truths which are valuable on different planes at once. So
the symbol is revelatory of an aspect of truth, of truth in its subjec-
tive aspect (1947, 414-20). And as Michaud has indicated, whatever
be the judgement as to the validity of the symbolist arguments, they
rendered a great service in bringing to the surface a consciousness of
the symbolic process.
This classical symbolist view in literature, which had its analogue
in painting (see later), made two kinds of statements about symbols
which in effect challenge much of the anthropological approach to
the subject. They asserted the primacy of the private recognition of
the symbolic; and they claimed that the referent or reality itself, can
be apprehended only through the symbol. An anthropologist is con-
cerned primarily with the public use of the symbolic, and his aim is
to separate symbol from referent so that he may describe the relation
between them. But while ostensibly about poetry or art in general,
such formulations have offered themes for stimulus and scrutiny to
anthropology.
The influence of the Symbolist movement was wide and enduring,
and in modified forms it attained a cosmopolitan status. Bowra
recognized its counterpart in England in the aesthetic movement,
with Rossetti, Pater and Oscar Wilde. But for Mallarme his 'great
idol' was Edgar Allan Poe, whom he translated 'admirably' and for
whom he wrote a lament - 'Le Tombeau d'Edgar Poe' (Verlaine,
1884, 54, 55; Bowra, 1943,9)-
The symbolism of nineteenth-century American writers such as
Poe, Melville and Henry James has been the subject of considerable
analysis by literary critics. Since various cultural assumptions are
built into such analysis, a confrontation between critics and anthro-
pologists might give it a greater flexibility and sensitivity, as well as
furnishing some new viewpoints for the anthropology of symbols. I
give here merely a hint of an anthropological tentative in this direction.
AN ANTHROPOLOGIST'S REFLECTIONS 33
SYMBOLS I N ART
reaction and change the situation. 'In proportion as the artist is pure,
he is opposed to all symbolism/ wrote Roger Fry. Yet even abstract
painting, while rejecting the traditional symbolism of conventional
representational art, acquired a symbolic value in the quality of the
response evoked in the viewer. Though it may be claimed that non-
objective art has broken through the process of symbolization itself
by confronting the viewer with a 'direct experience' of the forces
involved in the creation of the painting, this claim has proved hard
to maintain in its entirety. The language of identification with
creative forces of nature in which some exponents of abstract art
clothed their arguments; the influence of systems of mystical thought
on some abstract painters (for example theosophy on Kandinsky and
Mondrian); the attempt to give personal significance to formal struc-
tures - this has tended to involve symbolic forms of expresssion at
some stage. Michel Seuphor states that to Mondrian femininity is
symbolized by the vast horizontal receptacle of the sea; masculinity
is symbolized by the wooden pilings against which the waves break
and which protect the dunes from the sea. He argues that this
fundamental dualism became the basis of Neo-Plasticism, an aesthetic
system founded entirely upon the principle of the right angle,
roughly prefigured in nature by the opposition between sea-and-
horizon and dunes (1962, 37).*
Even where it is held that the conformations of non-objective art
are 'symbolic only of themselves', and the term 'metasymbolic' has
been introduced to discuss their achievement in analytical style, it has
been argued that what has been involved has been a spiritual revolu-
tion, and 'the history of the destruction of the outer world of
appearance signifies a gradual spiritualization of art, for it leads to
ever more symbolic statements' (Fingesten, 1970, 113). In an early
statement on the issues Herbert Read distinguished between symbol-
ism in the ordinary sense, employing concrete imagery, and
* Cf. Kandinsky on the Spiritual in Art. 'There is no form, there is nothing in the world,
which says nothing.* See also Jakob Rosenberg (1967, 225) who says of Kandinsky's Kleine
Welten series of lithographs where: *allusion to natural form is abandoned and geometrical
shapes are patterned by colour or black and white' - one may speak of a symbolic image that
conjures up a little cosmos {kleine Welt) filled with energy yet controlled by laws of attrac-
tion and repulsion. Compare also an opinion of de Kooning's 'Light in August', a study in
white and black, as a 'symbolist abstraction'. Dissociated from a source in nature the organic
shapes carry emotional charges of the same order as mathematical signs There is visual
metaphor in which motifs released from specific objects are thus able to strike a broader
resonance of associations (Harold Rosenberg, 1965, 115-16).
44 SYMBOLS
what I take it 'pop art' has tried to do. Or he may try to enforce the
recognition of a new code, perhaps of an order which putatively
belongs to some generic human understanding - which is what I
assume the various kinds of abstract art are trying to do.
But what some modern artists are attempting, if I construe them
rightly, is to eliminate as far as possible the element of personality
from the interpretation of their creations. The individual, personal
component is ineradicably there, in the selective integrative act of
creation. But it is the individual as creator-artist only that it is in-
tended to be recognized; not the individual as a particular person
with sex, temperament, social background. The characteristics of the
individual painter or sculptor may be regarded by the artist as
irrelevant to the consideration of the work, distracting to the
recognition of the value of the experience provided by it. So a self-
effacing painter such as Bridget Riley can treat her work as an
attempt to stimulate by visual means, through combination of line
and mass by circle, dot, stripe, in colour or black and white, a kind of
personal experience in the viewer. The artist is the conceiving mind
behind the creation - not necessarily even the executant, since such
work may have been done by assistants following out the instruc-
tions minutely laid down (Robertson, 1971). Analogous mathemati-
cally derived sculptures and drawings have been produced by the
American artist Sol Lewitt. This is an attempt to reduce to a mini-
mum the overt involvement of the artist in the interpretative effort of
the spectator. It seems to be successful in that knowledge of the
precise personality of the artist, what kind of social and tempera-
mental figure he or she represents, does not appear relevant to
interpretation of the painting as part of the spectator's field of
experience. Here there emerges what I feel like calling 'muted sym-
bolism5. The artist says in effect: interpret the painting in your own
way, in terms of your own experience; let the combinations of line,
mass and colour convey their own message to you - or more strictly,
let them suggest to you some stirring of the sensibilities which will
make for you a cognizable experience, an 'event'. Symbolic meaning
in the more figurative sense is not expected - may be even denied.
There is a belief in a direct relation between the physical object and
the appreciation of the viewer so that the forms of the painting do
not 'stand for' something else than themselves. They are expected to
46 SYMBOLS
art forms which give the symbols their expressive power. The focus
here is not on what the symbols mean, for artist, for public; but on
what forms can be constructed so as to convey meaning most force-
fully, or most sensitively. (Presumably, 'pop art' could be defended
on the grounds that while its message may often be trivial, the forms
in which it is presented are powerful in suggestion.)
SYMBOLS IN RELIGION
Anthropologists may have been able to ignore what has been said on
symbolism by poets, artists or critics, but it has been harder for them
to leave aside discussion of symbols in religion. Some anthropolo-
gists indeed have directly used their interest in Western religious
symbolism to help them in the interpretation of primitive symbolism.
The symbolism of Oriental religions, especially Hinduism, is of
an unparalleled richness, and rests upon a very clear differentiation
between symbol and god, spirit being or cosmic force symbolized.
But for our preliminary inquiry here, a few reflections on the sym-
bolism of Christianity will suffice to illustrate the issues.
In the West the long and complex history of the term symbol itself
is much involved with religion. In Greek, originally sumbolos and
related words referred literally to the putting together of that which
had been divided. An example would be the production of two halves
of a token which had been broken and given to a pair of friends so
that they would share a mark of identification. Conversely, this token
served to differentiate them from other people who had no such
proof. It was in such sense that the early Christian church seems to
have adopted the term symbol. It came to be used for a formal
authoritative statement of religious belief, differentiating Christians
from non-Christians - a Creed. (It is suggested that it may have
also been used in mystery religions of the period, for an exterior sign
indicating the inner secrets of the cult.) In particular, the 'symbol'
applied to the confession of faith recited at baptism by a convert. In
the form of the so-called Symbol of the Apostles (Apostles' Creed)
this formal statement of belief was believed (apparently without
adequate historical evidence) to have been a joint profession of faith
drawn up by the disciples of Jesus after Pentecost. This 'symbol' be-
came then a kind of admission ticket to the new church. Now, not
48 SYMBOLS
A QUESTION OF TERMS:
SCOPE AND MEANING
OF 'SYMBOL'
54
A Q U E S T I O N OF TERMS 55
Historically, since the early period of Greek philosophy, epistemo-
logical problems have been concerned with the relation of particular
to universal, sense-perception to idea or 'form', finite to infinite; and
in the West have often taken a theological shape, as in theories of
analogy. Symbolism was one of the fields in which such problems of
knowledge were displayed, though as G. G. Coulton has pointed
out for the mediaeval period (1958, Chap. 13), symbolic interpreta-
tions were apt to be very much less systematic than those of re-
ligious doctrine in general. In such interpretation, the broad aim was
not only to accept the concrete as representative of the abstract but
to use it as a key in two ways - to explain the concrete by reference
to the abstract, the visible by the invisible; and to extract from the
concrete its hidden meaning for an understanding of the abstract.
As indicated in Chapter 1, such views were prominent in Christian
church art, but had a high development in some other religious
systems, notably that of the Jewish Kabbalah.
As part of symbolic inquiry, discussion of the relation between
names and things named has involved consideration of the nature of
words as symbols. This has meant, in Carnap's terms, a practical
distinction between language as an object of discussion and meta-
language, in which the discussion is carried out. But it has also led to
the invention of artificial languages, such as sets of symbols in
mathematics and science. The use of such symbols has allowed
operations to be performed with generality and brevity, in a way
that would not have been possible with ordinary language. 'Words
are the Signs and Symbols of Things,' wrote South in 1686 (OED).
But words, which can be flexibly handled in an almost infinite
variety of situations, are not precise enough to make fine distinc-
tions in 'the technical discussions associated with special activities in
a high state of development' (L. W. H. Hull, 1959, 101). Symbols
are not only more economical and more abstract than words; they
can also be made to conform to rules which allow of no irregulari-
ties. To quote Hull again: 'if the steps of an argument are symboli-
cally recorded, each step corresponds to a particular rearrangement
of the symbols.... We soon learn to recognize those symbolic
arrangements which correspond to valid reasoning processes. We
can then make such rearrangements automatically, without per-
petually considering their significance' (1959, 102).
56 SYMBOLS
many new ideas his writings about the classification of signs are
strewn with new words. (One such is ideoscopy, describing and
classifying the ideas that belong to experience without regard to
their validity or their psychology - a term that might serve anthro-
pologists engaged in 'cognitive anthropology' or 'ethnoscience'.)
Dodging the new words and much of the detailed analysis, one can
still find in Peirce several important points about symbols, first put
forward in a paper in the Proceedings of the American Academy of
Arts and Sciences in May 1867. There he defined logic as the doc-
trine of the formal conditions of the truth of symbols, that is the
reference of symbols to their objects. Later he saw that this involved
inquiry into all branches of the general theory of signs. Firstly, for
such an inquiry Peirce distinguished between index, icon and sym-
bol* An index in his view was a sign directly related in fact to what it
signified. If a hunter in pursuit of a lion sees a certain kind of foot-
print in the sand, this is an index to the passage of his game. A
proper name, a symptom of a disease, are indices in Peirce's sense.
An icon for him is a sign that represents its object by resembling it -
which is 'determined by its dynamic objective by virtue of its own
internal nature'. Peirce cited a curve of a distribution of errors; we
might regard the statue of a lion as iconic in having its form and
proportions determined by those of the animal. A symbol on the
contrary was defined by Peirce as a sign determined by its object
only in the sense that it will be so interpreted - an allocation depend-
ing on habit, convention or agreement, or natural disposition of the
interpreter. Following our example, a lion is a symbol of bravery by
convention. But as Peirce admitted, the characters of direct relation,
resemblance and convention are not completely exclusive. So an
icon - broadly equivalent to image - may have an element of con-
ventional recognition, as we may easily see in some of the mediaeval
figures termed lions at the porches of Romanesque churches.
A second point of interest made by Peirce was linked with his
pragmatism - it was his view that the meaning of a concept could be
completely understood only by discovering just what sort of general
habits of conduct a belief in the truth of the concept would reason-
ably develop. This was a doctrine that truth consists in future
* Peirce, 1958, 391, 395, 402-3; (C. Harteshorne and P. Weiss (eds)) 1931-5, vols II and
V; see also A. W. Burks, 1949.
62 SYMBOLS
SYMBOL AS INSTRUMENT
Expression
As instrument of expression symbols are to a supreme degree tools
of the artist. It is not surprising then that in her presentation of her
theory of art Susanne Langer has described symbol as 'a word
around which this whole book is built' (1953, x). In many contexts
an anthropologist too meets the symbolism of art - poetry, dancing,
sculpture - in many different types of society, clearly expressing
values regarded emotionally and intellectually as important by the
people who assert them. The art of Western societies poses a prob-
lem of the expressiveness of its symbolism which is not present to
the same degree in the societies normally studied by anthropologists,
namely, the gap that tends to exist between artist and public. Here
what the symbols express may be elite values, protest values, interest-
group values. Sometimes the expression provokes and leads a social
reaction, sometimes it seems to be tolerated as a kind of'radical chic'
which saves other members of the society from having to act more
positively themselves.
The instrumental nature of a symbol as a means of expression is
especially clear with political and religious symbols. Flag, national
anthem, church painting, scriptural text, national dress, even style of
headgear can evoke powerful emotions of identification with a group
and be used as rallying points for group action. This can be negative
as well as positive; symbols are convenient objects of hate as well as
of devotion (see Chap. 10 on Flags). An example of external criticism
has been the Palace of Culture in Warsaw, a building thirty-eight
storeys high which was a gift to Poland from Russia after the war. It
was intended to have both aesthetic and political significance.
Twenty years later, it was described in an American report as 'an
empty symbol', not because it was untenanted, but because of its
'hideous' outmoded Stalinist style {Time Maga^ine^ 16 November
1970), and possibly because it no longer represents to the Polish
recipients the same sense of solidarity as before. Architecture easily
* Questions concerning the primary character of the symbolic function in human thought,
such as have been considered by Claude Levi-Strauss as part of his inquiry into 'untamed
thought' in La Pens&e Sauvage and elsewhere, are not immediately relevant to this analysis.
78 SYMBOLS
Communication
A major function of symbols is in facilitating communication.
Utterance of words - a basic form of symbolic action - allows us to
dispense with many kinds of manual and bodily actions in providing
stimulus or conveying meanings (for Malinowski's views, see
p. 145). In a ritual field, performance of a symbolic act allows ideas
to be shared and reformulated without use of words, or with minimal
verbalization. When the Tikopia chief was rubbing his temple post
with scented leaves, this was a coded sign which both conveyed ideas
of respect to his people and gave them a focus for their own religious
acts. Symbols also serve as stores of meaning in communication. In
pagan times a Tikopia temple post was a permanent reminder of
religious and economic values; it commonly outlasted the lifetime of
an individual worshipper, and for successive generations stood as a
material symbol of an immaterial spiritual being. Among Christian
Tikopia the Cross serves an analogous function.
To turn to economic symbolization, in a monetary economy
coins or banknotes provide a store of public and private meanings.
They symbolize past achievements and transactions; they stand for
potentialities of acquisition; they can dramatize petty conquests of
desire through non-spending; they are reference-points for much
family conversation. In most cases it is the values or amounts rather
than the actual coins or notes which are the object of interest; it is
8o SYMBOLS
* I seem to remember that about twenty years ago only coins and one dollar bills carried
the legend 'In God We Trust*; notes of higher value made fiduciary reference only to the
Federal Reserve Bank and the United States Treasury.
A QUESTION OF TERMS 8l
Knowledge
A proposition that symbols are instruments of knowledge raises
epistemological issues which anthropologists are not trained to
handle. That symbolization helps us to know cannot I think be
easily denied. But what comes to be known thereby is another
question. What the process of symbolic representation presumably
does is to abstract some quality common to both referent and symbol
and allow one to perceive more clearly, more imaginatively, a
A QUESTION OF TERMS 83
particular type of relationship, uncluttered by details of the referent,
or reduced in magnitude to comprehensible dimensions. That
symbolization is a way of knowing beyond this, a mode of know-
ledge in itself basically different from other ways of knowledge, is a
view I do not share. Eliade has argued - like some of the Symbolists
(p. 31)-that the symbol reveals certain aspects of reality, the
deepest aspects, which defy any other means of knowledge (1969,
12). But I think that this, like other assertions of similar order, is to
be looked at in the light of the general aesthetic and philosophical
position of the speaker.
Most anthropologists tackle the matter rather differently. They
concern themselves more with the knower than with the known,
with the social position of claimant and claim rather than with the
question of the objective reality of what is claimed. Yet one strand in
the complex modern interest in symbolism - even among anthro-
pologists - is a hope of identifying 'real' underlying phenomena in
an increasingly confusing world. From particle physics to personality
disorders come suggestions that the 'inner knowledge is symbolic
in character'. I think the issue for anthropologists here is not one of
Truth or Inner Reality, but of spheres of relevance, and of effects.
As an anthropologist I am sure that I am not entitled to overlook
the social context of such claims. Assertions that symbols provide a
unique way of knowing the truth seem to be often equivalent to
defence-mechanisms. A powerful way of arguing that 'what I say is
true' is to assert that 'I have a unique way of getting at the truth
which is inaccessible to ordinary knowledge.' This has been the
route of the mystic in all ages. A claim that symbolization offers a
unique path to truth not only has no validity in itself; it invites
consideration of why such a claim has been made. As anthropologists
we are bound to consider such a claim in its social context if we are
to comment upon its position in the theory of knowledge. And what
anthropologists have done for almost a century, from the studies of
James Mooney on the Ghost Dance for example, is to attempt to
contextualize such claims as have come within their purview
(cf. Chap. 12).
Control
Consideration of symbols as instruments of control, or more bluntly,
84 SYMBOLS
S P I N - O F F FROM THE R O M A N T I C M O V E M E N T
one, but quite a few would be needed.' 'When people tell their
dreams properly, that will allow their character to be divined sooner
than from their faces.' 'Dreams can be of use, in that they produce
unbiased results about our whole being, without the compulsion
of often feigned reflection. This thought deserves to be taken to
heart.' 'A dream often alters our resolution, assures our moral
foundations better than all teaching, as it goes by a roundabout way
into the heart When in dream I argue with someone, and he
refutes me and enlightens me, it is I who enlighten myself; so I
reflect. This reflection has come under the form of conversation.' It
is clear from such statements that Lichtenberg realized the expressive
symbolic function of dreams, and regarded them as having an 'auto-
diagnostic' value (Lichtenberg, 1764-70, in Grenzmann (ed.), 1949,
92-3,102-9; Beguin, 1939,14). Karl-Philipp Moritz had some analo-
gous views. Grappling with the rationalism of the Berlin school,
disturbed by interior conflict, a wanderer across the face of Europe,
a novelist and a friend of Goethe, Moritz tried through the study of
dreams and other symbolic images to come to terms with his own
inner tensions. Dying of tuberculosis in 1793 at the age of 36,
Moritz was much concerned with the prophetic quality of dreams,
and impressed by his disagreeable memory of them, since they
created disorder in his daily thoughts. Afraid of dreams, he never-
theless advocated exploration of them in order to understand better
what goes on in ourselves. A character in one his novels - specific-
ally termed 'psychological'-questions reality in a solipsist way by
virtue of dreams. Since his dreams were very realistic and vivid,
could he be dreaming in the full light of day? Could the people he
saw around him be purely creations of his imagination? Such sugges-
tions of the merging of dreaming and waking life, of the confound-
ing of inner sensation with external reality, clearly link with
Lichtenberg's views-and could be taken as forerunner to some
present day anthropological approaches to experience. More broadly,
Moritz's second major novel Andreas Hartknopf (1786) with its
sequel (both with portrait of a sphinx on the title page) have been
claimed as essentially symbolic in quality, in the way in which he
used the phenomena of nature to describe aspects of his self-analysis.
But Moritz himself described the novel as an allegory, and did not
generally use the term symbol (Langen, 1962; Schrimpf, 1968,
96 SYMBOLS
THE C O N T R I B U T I O N OF B A C H O F E N
The early interest in symbols and their meanings had been wide-
spread among intellectuals; but its specific developments had been
primarily on the part of classicists, allied with theologians and philo-
sophers. But the field of ideas expressed in myth attracted scholars of
many kinds, and took on a more definite comparative aspect. An
outstanding example here was J. J. Bachofen, a jurist by training and
a pupil of the very influential Savigny. From the ordinary view-
point of the history of anthropology Bachofen is usually regarded as
the author of a highly speculative, generally discredited work on
mother-right which nevertheless has the merit of having opened up
* A later work by Cams on 'life-magnetism' and magical operations generally is not of
great interest anthropologically (1857). Among his many commentators Johannes Volkelt
(1873) places him with Edouard von Hartmann as one of the few philosophers who had given
clarity of expression to the notion of the unconscious, and stressed its importance, especially in
its biological relationships; Christoph Bernoulli (1925) argued in similar strain. Erwin Wasche
(1933) held that while preoccupation with the unconscious was a mark of nearly all the
Romantics, Carus was perhaps the first to be so outspoken about it in non-poetic fashion.
Wolf Farbenstein (1953) wrote of Carus as a forerunner of Freud, while Artur Krewald
(1939) in a publication for the Wehrmacht Psychology centre, tried to bring out his interest
for racial studies.
104 SYMBOLS
the whole subject. But Bachofen was also, indeed primarily, con-
cerned with symbolism. He regarded himself basically as an historian
of antiquity, dealing with a period before the emergence of written
history, and therefore dealing with a different kind of material,
namely myth. He saw no breach of continuity between myth and
history (a position akin to that which for other reasons, Levi-Strauss
has advanced against Sartre). He stressed the importance of myth as
a guide to the truth of past conditions. But, he held, to understand
this guidance and grasp the historical meaning, myth had to be
analysed in its own terms; the scholar had to comprehend the spirit
of the times in which it was created. For Bachofen, the key to the
interpretation of the ancient myths was the theme of gynaecocracy,
the rule of women. Here lay the significance he attached to the idea of
symbol. He had been much impressed when in Italy by the care which
the ancients had given to the monuments of their dead, and in 1859
he published his Versuch uber die Grabersymbolik der Alten. In this
he interpreted the symbolism of the grave monuments as a most
ancient cult of fertility. He thought it presented the image of the
creative force residing in the earth, with the phallus, the symbol of
fructification, as a common design. He entitled his study of mother-
right 'an inquiry into the gynaecocracy of the ancient world, accord-
ing to its religious and legal nature', and he carried his symbolic
interpretations very far in pursuit of these aims. Even anterior to the
phallus Bachofen saw the egg (depicted on various monuments)
as primal, the beginning of all creation. In religion the egg was the
symbol of the material source of all things. The phallic god himself
springs from the darkness of the maternal womb; he stands son to
feminine matter; the bursting shell of the egg discloses the mystery
of phallic masculinity, hitherto hidden within it; the egg is the symbol
of matrimonial consecration. Bachofen also identified all bull forms
appearing in the classical mythology as symbols of maleness, of the
life-awakening side of the power of nature (1897, 39; 1925, 130).
He went into detail on the symbolism of the use of hands and fingers,
as in counting, and tried to relate symmetry and asymmetry of hand
use to indications of femaleness and motherhood (1925, 173-4). In
all this, though Bachofen did not apparently draw much directly
from Dulaure and Creuzer, he was following a recognized scholarly
tradition, but he gave it his own particular flavour.
DEVELOPMENT OF ANTHROPOLOGICAL INTEREST 105
PARALLEL INQUIRIES
Quietly proceeding parallel to the theoretical inquiries of Bachofen
and less anthropologically-oriented thinkers about symbolism were
the empirical studies of symbolic behaviour by the more perceptive
ethnographers. A good example of this is given in the work of
Lewis H. Morgan, who about the time Bachofen was studying
grave monuments in Italy was paying some attention to the sym-
bolism of sacrifice among the Iroquois. He did not call it symbolism,
but he was concerned to explain what he termed the 'true principle'
involved in a well-known Iroquois rite, the burning of a White Dog
at the celebration of the New Year, in mid-winter. A dog was
selected, pure white if possible and free from blemish, and ritually
* There is an extensive literature on Bachofen, much of it of little anthropological relevance.
I have drawn here mainly upon his two major works: Versuch iiber die Grdbersymbolik der
Alten (1859) 1925 edn; and Das Mutterrecht: Eine Untersuchung iiber die Gynaikokratie der
Alten Welt (1861) second edn, 1897; and upon the writings of Alfred Baeumler 1965, E. K.
Winter, 1928, Adrien Turel, 1938,1939. See also C. A. Bernoulli, 1924 and Joseph Campbell,
1967.
DEVELOPMENT OF ANTHROPOLOGICAL INTEREST 107
strangled, care being taken not to break the bones or shed the
blood. The dog was then spotted with red paint, ornamented with
feathers and white wampum (or in more modern times, vari-
coloured ribbons), hung up, and finally burned. Morgan argued that
earlier explanations of such sacrifice, in terms of expiation of sin, or
transference of guilt to a scapegoat, as among the Hebrews, were
erroneous. He explained that the burning of the dog had nothing
to do with the sins of the people, since Iroquois had no recognition
of atonement or forgiveness of sins - once done, an act was regis-
tered beyond the power of change. What the sacrifice represented
was a much simpler idea - to send up the spirit of the dog as a
messenger to the Great Spirit to convey thanks for the harvest and
other benefits of the year. For this a dog was peculiarly appropriate
because of his fidelity to man and his companionship in the hunt.
White was the emblem of purity and faith. The ornaments placed
upon the dog's body were voluntary offerings, each being regarded
as a gift for which the spirit would make return. The spirit of the dog
was believed to ascend in the flames, and the Iroquois used the
dog's spirit 'in precisely the same manner as they did the incense of
tobacco, as an instrumentality through which to commune with their
Maker' (Morgan (1851) 1962, 210-21).
I find several points of particular interest about this account. One
is the succinctness with which various points of theoretical interest,
including that of the reciprocity theme of offering, have been
incorporated into what is primarily a descriptive account. Another
is that the account clearly rests firmly upon empirical data, some at
least from personal observation. (Morgan mentions once in Feb-
ruary 1846 counting nine different-coloured ribbons on a white dog
hung up at Tonawanda by Senecas - though he does not say if this
was the only occasion he saw the rite.) Again, Morgan was cham-
pioning a communion theory of sacrifice, though he did so in con-
crete not abstract terms, and not involving commensality, as did
Robertson Smith more than a generation later. And in a way which
foreshadows Radcliffe-Brown's treatment, Morgan adopted a com-
parative interpretation of symbolic behaviour: he equated the flaming
consumption of the dog with that of the smoking of tobacco - using
'the incense of tobacco' - and saw them both as filling the same
ritual role as instruments of communication.
io8 SYMBOLS
So the latter part of the century saw more careful consideration for
the immediate ethnographic context of symbols, more interest in
what the people who used the symbols might say about them, more
concern for a possible range of interpretation of a particular item of
symbolism. While curiosity about symbols was not necessarily
abated, it was taking a more disciplined form - and it was tending to
be satisfied within a broader framework of social studies, in which it
assumed a subordinate place. So to Bachofen's successors, mother-
right was more important as an institution than as a symbol. This
more mundane approach appears in the work of McLennan, and
even more so in that of Fustel de Coulanges and Tylor.
But Tylor was not content merely to study the equation of symbol
and referent - to find out that what a represented was b; he also
wanted to know what kind of relation was believed to exist between
them. He was much concerned with religious images - 'idols'. He
pointed out that eidulos - 'the visible' in Greek - has come to be
restricted to images of spiritual beings. He argued as others have
done before and since,* that such an 'idol' enables the savage to give
a definite existence and personality to vague ideas of higher beings,
which his mind can hardly grasp without some material aid (1878,
109). As Marett put it much later, primitive thought 'finds it hard to
divorce the intelligible from the visible' (1935, n o ) . But, said
Tylor, an idol may tend to be confounded with the idea of which it
was the symbol, and thus become 'the parent of the grossest super-
stition and delusion' (1878, n o , 120). He pointed out that the line
between cases in which the connection between object and figure was
supposed to be real, and those in which it was known to be imaginary,
was very often difficult to draw. He cited the images of saints beaten
and abused for not granting the prayers of worshippers; and the
symbolical sacrifices of models of men and animals, including the
'economical paper-offerings' of the Chinese, as instances in which
symbol tended to be identified with reality (1878,121,122). Hanging
and burning in effigy, he thought, in civilized countries at least,
comes fairly out into pure symbolism. The idea that the burning of
a straw or rag body should act upon the body of the original per-
haps hardly comes into the mind of anyone who assists at such a
performance. But if Tylor had been writing in a modern context, say
after a campus demonstration, he would surely have added that
burning an effigy is a mode of action in its own right - a kind of
relief in the midst of frustration. While not conceived as affecting the
Drums' of Africa much has been written. For an illuminating brief article from a social
anthropological viewpoint see Robert G. Armstrong, 'Talking Drums in the Benue-Cross
River Region', Phylon, xv (1954), 355-63 (Atlanta University, Ga.).
* For example Salomon Reinach (1942, 9) cited G. F. Creuzer's statement that in very
remote ages a sacerdotal caste imbued with lofty religious and moral ideas thought to make
these more accessible to the multitude by disguising them under symbols, which were then
taken literally, as in Greek polytheism and the ancient mysteries. Paul Frankl has quoted
A. Wilhelm von Schlegel, lecturing in the University of Berlin in 1801, as stating 'the beauti-
ful is a symbolical representation of the infinite; because then it will be at the same time clear
how the infinite can become apparent in the finite . . . The infinite can only be made apparent
symbolically, in images and signs' (Frankl, i960, 452). A. F. Bernhardi wrote to similar
effect about that time; the same theme appears in Bachofen, as I have shown already.
DEVELOPMENT OF ANTHROPOLOGICAL INTEREST 115
argued that the Arabic words for friendship, affection, blood, leech
or blood-sucker were but variations from a common root - a study
of concepts highly commendable in a Doctor of Divinity, even one
who had been a missionary! Trumbull pursued this blood symbolism
theme further in studies of threshold covenants and covenants with
salt, both of which he thought were based upon equivalences with
blood and the notion that a sharing of blood meant a sharing of life,
with approval from the gods. (He also produced a smug superficial
study of'Friendship, the Master-Passion'.) But his set of lectures on
Oriental social life (1894) contained some interesting personal
observations from his travels in Arabia, Egypt and Palestine, and
some pithy remarks on the sharing of food and drink as symbolic of
covenant, and on the symbolism of Oriental weddings and of pil-
grimage. An essay on 'the Oriental idea of father' illustrated very
well from empirical data the representative role of the head of a non-
kin related group of travellers. Trumbull's work serves to illustrate
the kind of contribution made to the study of symbolism by an
untrained but shrewd observer equipped with knowledge in a re-
lated field to anthropology, and fired by a ruling idea of a moral
order.
* This work is cited in this chapter because though its publication was post-war, the
original texts were collected, with commentary, in 1931 and 1935 and their interpretation
should be credited to this pre-war period.
DEVELOPMENT OF ANTHROPOLOGICAL INTEREST 121
S T I M U L U S A N D M Y O P I A OF F R A Z E R
ETHNOGRAPHIC DEVELOPMENTS
fornian tribes, Clark Wissler among the Sioux and Blackfeet, and
H. H. St Clair among the Shoshone. One of the contributions of
such work was to show in detail how abstract ideas such as a battle,
or a path to a destination, could be indicated by geometric patterns
in colour. Illustrative of some phases of this work was Kroeber's
doctoral thesis on decorative symbolism of the Arapaho (1901) in
which he put forward a strongly-worded argument against pre-
suming either realistic pictography or symbolic conventionality as
the origin of the art themes. With his characteristic caution, Kroeber
was against the search for origins and isolated causes; but he was in
favour of the study of those general tendencies which he thought to
be inherent in the mind of man as a social and cultural being. Prob-
lems of the relation of meaning to form were preoccupying many
students of primitive art and received evolutionary solution - as
A. C. Haddon showed in tracing geometrical shapes in New Guinea
art back to realistic forms such as crocodile or frigate-bird. Boas
himself was more eclectic. He noted the range of interpretation that
could be obtained about the meaning of a particular design, even
among the people of one community, and he made suggestions for
systematizing such data in field inquiries. He also injected into his
treatment of primitive art some remarks on symbols more generally.
Referring to the symbolism of national flags, he pointed out that
they are not only ornamental but also possess a strong emotional
appeal. They call forth feelings of national allegiance and their values
cannot be understood on a purely formal basis; they are founded on
the association of form with definite fields of our emotional life.
Boas also referred to the swastika (cf. p. 120) as a symbol of anti-
semitism, and to the Star of David as a Jewish symbol in Germany
at that time (before the rise of the Nazis to power!). He pointed out
that these symbols had a very definite political significance, and were
apt to excite most violent passions when used for decorative pur-
poses. Owing to their strong emotional value such symbols, as also
military insignia and students' emblems, tended to be restricted to
special classes of objects or reserved for privileged classes or indi-
viduals (1927, 100-1). Here, though briefly, Boas was making a
significant general point about collective symbols of a sacred or
quasi-sacred order, akin to the view put forward by Durkheim.
I think this is worth noting because in general Boas seems to have
I30 SYMBOLS
THE D U R K H E I M I A N LEGACY
with a painful reality, for Durkheim they were means whereby one
could more fully embrace a satisfying reality. Both attached great
importance to the significance of such symbolic representations, but
the difference of their objectives led each to stress a different aspect
of the symbolic process. In the anthropological study of symbols it
has been the viewpoint of Durkheim that until recently has carried
more weight, in line with the effect of his more general social theory.
But despite the protestations of some anthropologists about the
need to avoid psychology, the views of Freud, supplemented by their
transformation in the work of Carl Jung, have affected the anthropo-
logical treatment of symbols to a growing degree.
There is no need to dwell on the magnitude of Durkheim's con-
tribution to the understanding of symbolic behaviour. In strong
contrast to the nineteenth-century studies of symbols, which tended
to treat them as discrete entities, having their meaning hidden within
themselves or sharing it with symbols of the same class on a com-
parative basis, Durkheim advocated the need to relate symbol to
social factors. In arguing that not nature, only society, offered
sufficient basis for the development of a religious symbolism Durk-
heim firmly turned his back on the last vestiges of the Romantic
movement. His positivism alienated him from interest in symbolism
of the poetic kind. He was not concerned with the claims of the
Symbolists to attain an inner reality; nor did he attempt too seriously
to unravel the genesis of symbols. He looked primarily at symbols
as modes of expression, and wished to examine their effect upon
other members of a society. For this purpose the study of religious
symbols seemed most suitable to him. His study of religious sym-
bols took the rather surprising form of an examination of the
'elementary' class of totemic emblems, in Australia. Pushing much
further the idea put forward by Tylor, that it is simpler to consider
a concrete object than an abstract idea, Durkheim demonstrated very
clearly the relation between symbol, religious sentiment and society.
He drove home the idea of society as a system of active forces
involved in and conditioned by the symbolizing process. In con-
sidering the problem of ritual, defined by things sacred, he concluded
that the relation between sacred things and their source was sym-
bolic, not intrinsic. Without symbols, the social sentiments could
have only a precarious existence. Enduring symbols were needed to
I32 SYMBOLS
SYMBOLS A N D M E A N I N G : MALINOWSKI
comment on Malinowski's semantic theory see J. R. Firth, 1957; and for general criticism see
T. D. Langendoen, 1968.
* There is some difference of opinion about this. Langendoen has argued that the 'later
Malinowski', a much more radical behaviourist, attached overweening importance to the
contextual theory of meaning, to the detriment of all other determinants. Moreover, he has
stressed what he sees as a shift in Malinowski's position on magical language: in the Argonauts
Malinowski described magical language as a special kind of language unlike ordinary narra-
tive style, whereas in the Problem of Meaning article he regarded it not as a special kind of
language use but an exemplification of the primary use of language, as a mode of action. This
opinion is counter to that of Jack Berry, who in his introduction to the Indiana University
Press reprint of Coral Gardens and their Magic holds that the view of language Malinowski
presented in this work was substantially the same as that contained in his earlier works, with
little or no development (1965, xi). My impression coincides with this view.
142 SYMBOLS
the whole human form (1937, 221, etc.; 1952, 159, 166).* What
Freud did in psychoanalysis was to expose particularly the relation
of the dream symbolism to the latent dream-thought and the
operations of the unconscious mind. His technique of dream inter-
pretation included a review of the chronological order of dream
events, of the 'day's residues', and of markedly striking events in the
dream; as well as a patient examination of the 'free associations' of
the dreamer. Then if in proceeding to an interpretation of the latent
dream-thoughts resistance was met, this was a sign of conflict
which had to be investigated. The interpretation as Freud admitted,
rested on certain postulates about the meaning of dream symbolism
and its associations, but while more cautious than many of his
critics allowed, he held that most of these postulates were justified
by the analytical evidence. For instance, he held that the number
of things represented symbolically in dreams is not great-the
body, parents, children, siblings, birth, death, nakedness, sexual
organs and processes - and that a large part of the symbolism is an
unconscious expression of the sex impulses. But he pointed out that
he had never put forward the thesis that all dreams are of a sexual
nature. And while he admitted that why certain objects have become
male sexual symbols is not easy to understand, he maintained that it
was unquestionable that hats and cloaks were such - and even argued
that this was backed up by some experimental data! Freud also
pointed to the widespread nature of symbolic usage, in myth, jokes,
poetry, religion, art and language in general. He held that light could
be thrown on such phenomena, especially myth, by the interpreta-
tion of the symbolism of dreams, but he emphasized that the inter-
pretation is by no means confined to sexual themes.
Freud's specific interpretations of symbolism were clearly culture-
bound. Obviously, in the ethnographically 'primitive' fields, um-
brellas and revolvers could not be expected as penis symbols, nor
apples and peaches as breast symbols; nor is dying likely to be sym-
bolized by travelling on a train. Freud never really faced this anthro-
pological dilemma, as is evidenced by the way he blithely cites a
Beduin marriage rite with a cloak as evidence which 'I hope will
* Schemer examined general characteristics of dreams, for example as a 'field for strife', and
as reproductive, a source of originality. Dividing dreams into eleven classes, he considered
what he regarded as their basic symbolic formations. Schubert and Volkelt are also cited by
Freud.
PROBLEMS OF SYMBOL THEORY 149
impress you5 that in a (Western) woman's dream a cloak stands for
a man (1964, 24). But Freud was always less interested in the specific
symbol than in the mental process it represented. So, it could be
argued, the equivalent pointed, rounded, covering objects could
occur in any culture to serve as sex symbols. Moreover, Freud
himself emphasized in various contexts the major importance he
attached to the study of the 'dream-work'- the process by which the
latent dream-thoughts are transformed into the manifest dream. He
isolated processes of condensation, displacement and secondary
elaboration as especially relevant for understanding of the symbolism.
But he looked back continually at the clinical problems so the sym-
bolism was significant for him as a factor in dream-distortion, which
in turn gave clues to the nature of neurosis. Indeed he sometimes
went so far as to say that the mechanism of the dream-work is a
kind of model for the formation of neurotic symptoms, or even that a
dream itself is a neurotic symptom, occurring in all healthy people. In
the early part of the twentieth century, Freud's views on symbolism
were among the most articulate, forceful, systematic and theoretical,
so it became difficult for the more thoughtful anthropologist to ignore
them, however much he might criticize their sweeping assumptions,
lack of cultural sophistication and dogmatic presentation.
One can only indicate, not summarize, the effect of Freud's
views upon social anthropologists' concern with symbolism in
the early part of this century, and I mention only a few points.
Concepts of deep, unconscious motivation existed before Freud, but
it was his brutal insistence upon the force and the generality of such
motives that led to an almost unwilling recognition of their signifi-
cance. Concepts of manifest and latent content, resistance, am-
bivalence and repression exemplified the need to interpret behaviour
with an eye to more than its superficial qualities. The frank, overt
discussion of sexual elements in dream and neurosis reinforced the
rather apologetic examination of phallic cults, premarital intercourse,
ritual defloration and other exotic material which anthropologists
had felt it necessary to present in order to convey a realistic picture
of the cultures they studied. The focus on nuclear family as the core
of social action and basic beliefs sent anthropologists back again to a
scrutiny of detailed behaviour and ideas over a range of institutions
from child-training to the role of the mother's brother.
150 SYMBOLS
* For example Seligman discussed in detail the former Vedda custom of a groom giving a
lock of hair to his bride, questioned its ornamental value, stressed how the bride prized it, but
did not examine the symbolism (1911, 98-100). Rivers likewise described the Toda bow-and-
arrow ceremony at a woman's first pregnancy, to establish the social fatherhood of the child,
but did not explore the symbolic aspects. His only mention of symbolism I can find among the
Todas refers to the swinging of a corpse over a fire, which 'would be symbolic of its destruc-
tion by fire', with the 'symbolic burning* having the advantage of not destroying valuable
property (1906, 319-22, 363). (Seligman's reference to an arrow symbol is a quotation from
an earlier writer.)
f Jackson Steward Lincoln, psychologist and anthropologist, who had also been psycho-
analysed, drew considerably upon Seligman's ideas in his The Dream in Primitive Cultures,
1935. My own study of dreams in Tikopia was in response to Seligman's interest (Firth,
1967b) but was not along lines directly suggested by him.
PROBLEMS OF SYMBOL THEORY 151
First, if all symbolism is unconscious, as orthodox theory seems to
require, in order to interpret it, an anthropologist is involved in
much more manipulation of spoken evidence and more imputation of
motivation, than he ordinarily regards as justified. Then there is the
question of sexuality. Few field anthropologists would wish to deny
the great importance of sexual factors in the whole field of symbolic
behaviour they study, from poetry to magic and myth recital. But
as Rivers argued, they tend to identify referents of symbols in social
relationships as well as in sexual relationships, and even when in
sexual relationships, they see other than genital elements as of prime
relevance. Again, in his Totem and Taboo (1912) Freud had put
forward views that were naive and distorted by most anthropological
opinion: not only had he taken up the discarded primal horde
hypothesis of J. J. Atkinson, but he also argued that there was
analogy between much of the social, especially ritual, behaviour of
primitive peoples and the individual behaviour of neurotics. Taken
in conjunction with Levy-Bruhl's parallel assertion of the pre-
logicality of the primitive,* there is little wonder that anthropologists
reacted vigorously against this last view.
In this turbulent intellectual situation Freud's views on symbols
had defenders and interpreters in the anthropological sphere. For
instance, working from literary sources, J. S. Lincoln regarded the
Freudian theory of symbolism as a most useful and accurate means
of approaching latent dream meanings, and interpreted Amerindian
data accordingly. A major, if idiosyncratic, figure here was Geza
Roheim, by training a psychoanalyst, who also carried out field
research of anthropological type in Central Australia and Nor-
manby island (near the Trobriands) and among the Yuma of Cali-
fornia. R6heim made a special study of shamans or medicine-men,
including their dreams. He was at pains to emphasize that most of
these men whom he met were not neurotic; on the contrary they
were healthy, capable hunters and leaders, whose symbolism might
be conscious as well as unconscious. But their dreams revealed to
R6heim's interpretation of their latent content some of the classic
analytical elements. When a Ngatatara would-be medicine-man
* Freud used Le Bon's Psychologie des Foules (1895) as his source for identification of
group mind with primitive, both characterized by lack of conflict in the presence of logical
contradiction. He went on to equate this with aspects of unconscious mental life of individuals,
including neurotics (Freud, 1965, 15).
152 SYMBOLS
begins by eating his totem, a yam, that is 'the oral introjection of the
father'. Since the dream that followed was very like the conception
dreams of women (in which the latent content was held to be coitus
with the father), except that mouth was substituted for womb, 'we
may therefore suspect a female attitude with regard to the father as
latent in the mental make-up of the medicine man'. Similarly,
R6heim saw the 'latent significance' of agriculture, in terms of
Trobriand and Normanby island myth and magic, as being symbolic
body destruction and restitution fantasies connected with the mother.
He acknowledges that anthropologists will probably object very
strongly to all this, saying inter alia that yams are cultivated because
of their usefulness, and these are only the unconscious aspects of an
economical, purposeful activity. But he sternly refutes such argu-
ments, holding that all the occupations in the 'seemingly practical
core of group-living' are more or less distorted or projected equiva-
lents of the infantile situation (Roheim, 1971, 4-6, 69-76, 93, 127).
Roheim's general conclusion, a modification of Freud's view, is that
culture is really composed of psychic defence systems against
anxiety, and that therefore specific cultures are structurally similar
to specific neuroses (1971, 106). But while many anthropolo-
gists have not accepted the general propositions resulting from
R6heim's filial piety, some have found his specific interpretation of
symbols in their manifest field context as very suggestive.
In the inter-war period other anthropologists such as Kroeber,
Sapir, Goldenweiser, Prince Peter of Greece and Jules Henry en-
gaged with psychoanalysis, either as a personal experience or as an
intellectual problem, to a marked degree, and some of their findings
emerged in reflections upon symbolism. Others, such as Linton and
Malinowski, were more guarded. In The Study of Man (1936), a
work which effectively began in anthropology the fruitful study of
status and role, Linton pointed to the widespread though not univer-
sal development of symbols in society, and mentioned the flag, the
cross and the swastika as examples. He stressed the culturally-
patterned character of symbols and their frequent lack of intrinsic
importance. But he adopted a curiously limited viewpoint in holding
that when we find in uncivilized societies symbolic meanings
attached to animals, objects or natural phenomena we usually call
them totems - ignoring a great range of religious and political
PROBLEMS OF SYMBOL THEORY 153
symbols to which the totemic label was not attached (1936, 424-6).
Linton stated specifically that he had not been impressed by the
orthodox Freudian explanations of cultural data he had read in the
period between his expeditions to the Marquesas and to Madagascar
in the 1920s; he had adopted instead Abraham Kardiner's view of
'basic personality structure' as giving a focal point for social inte-
gration (1939, xviii). By implication then, Linton was mainly
concerned with other aspects of psychological process than the
symbolic.
Malinowski's reaction was of a different order. Intrigued intellec-
tually by the complex arguments about mental process, in so many
ways an advance in sophistication on the psychology of Wundt,
and even of Shand, with which Malinowski was well acquainted, he
was repelled by the naivety and grossness of some of the Freudian
interpretation in the cultural field. Malinowski was convinced of
the significance of unconscious factors in mental process; he also
accepted the view that such factors came to overt expression in
symbolic forms such as ritual and myth. But his concern for the
empirical evidence, his belief in the importance of cultural condi-
tioning, and his own theses about functional inter-relation of ele-
ments of culture made him question the universality of some of the
cardinal themes of the Freudian argument. He held that the symbolic
form in which the fundamental conflicts of family relationships would
emerge must be directly correlated with the particular structure of
family, itself an outgrowth of complex historical conditions. In his
own previous work on the family among the Australian aborigines
he had spent considerable analytical skill in disproving notions of
indiscriminate or communal sharing of wives and in bringing out the
significance of the forces of co-operation in marital and filial rela-
tions. His Trobriand fieldwork had reinforced these ideas. So in the
Trobriand matrilineal descent system, with denial (he called it
ignorance) of physiological paternity, and overt assumption of
authority by mother's brother, he saw the fundamental struggle
within the family as between mother's brother and sister's son, not
between father and son, and incestuous longing not between son and
mother but between brother and sister. He indicated that this came
to overt expression in an appropriate type of myth. In The Father in
Primitive Psychology and more extensively in Sex and Repression in
F
154 SYMBOLS
tion' rather than in the character of the symbol and its object.*
In a sense, since symbols were a product of repression, and Freud's
aim was to relieve people as far as possible from the suffering of
repression by leading them to understand its roots, he wished to
free them from the tyranny of their symbols. In the history of depth
psychology Carl Jung took up Freud's concepts and made a virtue
out of necessity; he embraced symbolism. As Rieff has put it, Jung
transposed the forms and figures of earlier systems of symbolism
into psychology. So in the very symbols from which Freud wanted
to free mankind, Jung saw the principle of man's salvation (Rieff,
1963, 17). Freud himself saw this inversion very clearly-and
bitterly. In his History of the Psychanalytical Movement he discusses
how the 'symbolism in the language of dreams' slowly became
clear to him, and how Jung distorted the interpretation of dreams by
representing them as means for producing attempted solutions of
'the life-task'. He objected strongly to what he saw as Jung's concept
of 'symbolic' as equivalent to 'having no real existence', and to
replacement of 'all that is disagreeable in the family complexes' by
bland abstract ideas of a 'merely symbolic' order. Freud accused
Jung of 'approximation to the demands of the multitude' and of
creating a new religious-ethnical system, ignoring the sexual roots
of the symbolic forms he studied (Freud, 1963, 53-4, 92-8). But he
did not foresee how far in modern times Jung's views on symbolism
would 'justly claim to be a liberation for youth' (Freud, 1963, 92).
Indeed a considerable vogue for Jung in student circles, including
anthropologists, would seem to be linked with a general search for
reassurance in personal and social life rather than with a specific
intellectual curiosity as such about symbolism and analytical proce-
dures.
Jung's contributions to the study of symbolism have been mani-
fold, stimulating, doctrinaire, sometimes portentous and obscure.
His Psychological Types', with its notions of introversion and extra-
version, was an important and analytically novel work in the 1930s
for anthropologists, though there was much disagreement with it.
Jung's 'analytical psychology' attempted to reach deep layers of the
human mind by focusing less on logical formulation than on sym-
* For example Freud (1921) 1965, 17, 49, 95; cf. also his view of people's apparently pur-
poseless, chance acts as 'symptomatic actions' (1914) 1963, 117.
PROBLEMS OF SYMBOL THEORY 157
bol, and by regarding the latter as the product of a range of rela-
tively impersonal factors, not of personal family relations in the
Freudian manner. For Jung the symbol was always extremely
complex, neither rational nor irrational but with one side that accords
with reason and another that is inaccessible to reason; stimulating
sensation as well as thought. In the creator of a new symbolism the
highest mental achievement is demanded as well as the lowest and
most primitive motions of the psyche. Jung was prepared to admit
consciously-designed material as symbolic - even a scientific theory -
but he focused on the referent of the symbol as being relatively (or
at times, he said, essentially) unknown. A symbol for Jung was the
best way of expressing a thing, the nature of which is withheld
from present knowledge. So for him the Cross as a representation of
Divine Love is not a symbol but semiotic (meaningful directly),
because Divine Love is an apt description of the fact; whereas that
description of the Cross is symbolic which puts it above all imaginable
explanations, regarding it as an expression of an unknown and as
yet incomprehensible fact of a mystical or transcendent character
(1926, 601-10). Important in such a scheme is the well-known
notion of the archetype - a symbolic image of great power, part of
the psychic content that has not yet undergone conscious treatment,
but which can emerge from the unconscious with dynamic force,
and be used as part of the redemptive process which the mind fashions
for itself when the proper conditions are present. The archetypes
are the content of the collective unconscious, and as such are uni-
versal, not individual in character. Jung has argued: 'a symbol is not
an arbitrary or intentional sign standing for a known and conceivable
fact, but an admittedly anthropomorphic - hence limited and only
partly valid - expression for something suprahuman and only partly
conceivable* (1958, 152). Such a characterization of symbol can
appeal to those of a religious or mystical turn of mind, as Freud
saw, and it has drawn criticism from those psychologists who feel
safer with a personal unconscious than a collective unconscious.
As J. A. C. Brown has put it, they regard it as 'certainly unorthodox
in science to describe the partly known in terms of the wholly
unknown' (1961, 44-5). But Jung's influence has grown neverthe-
less.
One of the earliest anthropologists to be influenced by Jung was
158 SYMBOLS
R E C O G N I T I O N OF SYMBOLIC FORMS
* Levi-Strauss (1962,105-12) gave qualified approval to this interpretation but put Tallensi
totemic symbolism, together with that of Tikopia, on a much more general plane. For com-
ment on his view see Fortes, 1966, 9-14, Firth, 1970b, 280-94.
MODERN ANTHROPOLOGICAL VIEWS I 69
M E A N I N G OF S Y M B O L S FOR S O C I A L RELATIONS
SYMBOLISM OF RITUAL
respect, anxiety, desire which are put into ritual form because they
are thought not to be capable of expression in other form. But ritual
may also be regarded as a symbolic understatement of the 'real*
situation, going so far as the human officiant can go in terms of his
capacity, but recognized as inadequate, a kind of'token communica-
tion'. It may also be seen as a kind of symbolic disguise (see Fortes,
1966a, 409-22), a statement which alludes indirectly to 'reality' not
by exposing it but by evading it or representing it as other than it is.
Or again, the symbol idiom of ritual may allow statements to be
made in terms less brusque, more protracted, more tempered by
involvement with other acts, than in ordinary language (cf. Firth,
1967a, 21-5).
Ritual has therefore been one of the great fields for the study of
symbolic behaviour, and many modern social anthropologists have
contributed to its interpretation. Their primary search for the mean-
ing of symbolism in ritual has focused upon social relations. But it is
to be noted that in two of the major areas of theoretical concern -
what can be reasonably inferred about unstated aims and functions;
and what is the relation of public to private, or social to personal
meanings - the treatment and conclusions of different analysts have
varied considerably.* I take here for consideration mainly British
studies, with which I am more familiar.
An enlivening essay on the symbolism of ritual came from Max
Gluckman in 1954 (1963). Using the vivid and impressive account
by Hilda Kuper (1947) of the Swazi Incwala, often termed a first-
fruits ceremony, Gluckman examined the symbolism of political
catharsis in the songs and dances of hostility which form part of the
complex ritual. Under the title which by now he has made well known,
of 'rituals of rebellion', he pointed out that the ritual was organized
to exhibit the co-operation and conflict which make up the political
system. In the traditional Swazi system the political and social order
itself was not questioned, but communal interest, including that
* For contrast may be noted a recent overt preoccupation of some artists with *ritual*,
in which they take as subject some common theme that characterizes human behaviour, and
in which they believe they can discern a kind of basic human experience of moral or didactic
value. So, Romare Bearden has used as theme what he has termed T h e Prevalence of Ritual'
to express in painting and collage deep emotion about life's problems, especially in the life
style of American Blacks. For illustration and brief discussion of a Museum of Modern Art,
New York, exhibition see Carroll Greene, Romare Bearden; The Prevalence of Ritual
(Museum of Modern Art, New York, 1971).
178 SYMBOLS
SYMBOLS IN T R A N S I T I O N RITES
of the girl but the virility of the bridegroom which was emphasized;
and she indicates how the symbolism fitted the matrilineal structure
of the society. The bride belonged to the matrilineage and the groom
was allowed access to her to make her fertile - to produce a further
asset for her group. In daily life he was submissive to his in-laws and
worked under their orders; in the chisungu he appeared symbolically
as a roaring lion, a lion-killer, a crocodile, a hunter, a warrior, a
chief. So symbolic status as a procreator and impressive figure was
a compensation for the pains of everyday life.
The symbolism of these rites expressed themes of significance
both for the society and for individual initiates. Richards holds that
the rites symbolized the values and beliefs of the group, expressed,
reinforced and taught tribal norms, promoted social cohesion - all in
a complex way. So mortuary ritual could symbolize the performers'
duty to their chief or the values set on economic activities, as well as
grief for the dead man. But she makes two important qualifications.
The correspondence between the total value system of a group and
its symbolic expression in ritual is never exact - some basic values
are dramatically represented, others not. And some weighty rites are
just as often an occasion of group division as of union — a statement
which she refers back to her analysis of social differentiation at Bantu
meals long before (1932, 71-2; 1956, 117-18).
As a brief digression I would observe in this connection that the
notion of'group division' in relation to ritual symbolism can refer to
several types of situation. One type is that of social differentiation in
the sense of Richards's Bantu meal analysis; she points out how from
an early age males and females, seniors and juniors eat in separate
groups though their food may come from a common household.
This is a recognized expression of socially approved norms of struc-
tural kind, in direct symbolic form. Another type of symbolic ex-
pression of group division is where the rites do not tend to maximize
but to minimize the social differentiation. Segmentary groups, each
with its own competing interest, are brought together in a com-
munity of action which may either have the effect of promoting
co-operation and positive sentiments of unity or at least of'papering
over the cracks' of disunity to allow of some broad achievement of
common policy. Another type of symbolism concerned with divi-
sion is the ritual expression of hostility which may be roused because
MODERN ANTHROPOLOGICAL VIEWS 185
'A F O R E S T OF S Y M B O L S '
tion would seem to cover, say, the most careful scientific meteoro-
logical description of the state of the weather at the North Pole, a
relatively unknown fact, but certainly existing on any ordinary
plane of conceptualization.) In this connection I think the point of
'symbol' may be, not the element of the unknown in the referent,
but the degree to which the meaning of the sign which refers to it is
capable of intellectual, aesthetic and emotional development.
But I think that in the Jungian formulation, and in Turner's use of
it, we are back to the classical antithesis in another form - the idea
of the known as key to comprehension of the unknown, the material
as key to the immaterial. It would seem that it has had some of this
value for Victor Turner, when he discusses Ndembu symbolism.
'There are religious depths here that cannot be fathomed by the
analysis of observational data. The symbols I have discussed have a
fathomless lucidity of meaning which men of every grade of cultural
complexity can grasp intuitively if they wish' (1962,172). This is the
language of faith. In such statements, as in others about the 'numi-
nous simplicity' of presentation of sacra (1967, 108), one is led
towards a religious dimension of symbolism. Yet it seems as if
Turner does not wish to obtrude this but rather bring down the
argument to the level of the difficult and complex relationships
between the overt and the submerged, the manifest and latent pat-
terns of meaning, as interpreted in terms of behaviour in social
contexts. If we can agree to understand him in such sense, then
we can accept his series of vivid formulations about the positive
nature of symbols in social situations. With a permissible amount of
reification, he points out how symbols, with their complex meanings,
unite the organic with the socio-moral order, over and above the
conflicts within that order. Powerful drives, associated with human
physiology, especially of reproduction, are endowed by the ritual
process with a normative quality, and reinforce this, so being made
to appear obligatory. So symbols are both resultants and instigators
of this process and encapsulate its properties (1969, 52-3). At the
same time they have important structural relationships, both as
series and as representing elements of harmony, integration, tension
or conflict, in the operations of the society.
There is one aspect of Turner's methodology which I think is
open to question, not in its results so much as in its claims: I refer to
194 SYMBOLS
A P L E T H O R A OF INTERPRETATIONS
raises a basic problem in our whole inquiry, significant for the general
study of religion: the manner in which the beliefs and practices of the
cults can be regarded as symbolic at all. Are these beliefs and prac-
tices in fact not 'representations' but direct expressions of a reality
which the anthropologist can do no more than accept? There is, in
my view, a certain amount of dodging around this issue. Burridge,
for instance, in a very thoughtful general review of the theory of
millenary activities, is dissatisfied with descriptions of them as
'symbolic means' of dealing with problems - 'true, if it is not wholly
a truism', and 'ethnocentric'. He allows that Monsignor Knox's
'authoritative' study of eighteenth-century millenarian movements
referred the historic events to 'his own and his subjects' view of the
symbolic system' and adopted much the same approach as many
anthropologists, particularly Stanner. But Burridge still stresses the
inadequacy of 'ethnographic' explanations and in the end plumps for
a 'Hegelian' approach which attempts to make use of a total ex-
perience to explain itself as well as other kinds of social order,
experience or tradition. Such a 'Hegelian' explanation 'admits the
operation of a transcendent power'. In recognizing the existence of a
force whose nature we do not yet understand, a 'Hegelian' explana-
tion 'is clearly exploratory and therefore potentially fruitful' (1969,
120-37). Such putative suspension of judgement about the symbolic
quality of the cult phenomena presumably corresponds to a personal
commitment of a broader kind about the nature of reality (cf. I. M.
Lewis, 1971, 28).
The study of Australian aboriginal religion by W. E. H. Stanner
examined ritual symbolism in an equally penetrating, but more
positive, way. Agreeing with Nadel that 'uncomprehended' symbols
are not of concern for the anthropologist, Stanner makes the impor-
tant point that if this means 'unaccompanied by intellectual concep-
tions' it cannot be simply inferred from wordlessness. Moreover, a
methodical search for congruence between ritual facts of different
orders may show that an implicit and apparently uncomprehended
symbolism of one order is formulated explicitly in another order.
But even then, some 'going beyond the facts of observation' is
intrinsic to the act of study in every anthropological field, and not
even theoretically separable from it. So, in the several levels of
awareness of ritual symbolism, a few symbols are clearly recognized
202 SYMBOLS
as such, but the vast majority of rites are practised without clear
recognition of their symbolical character. Yet the symbolisms are
constituents of collective acts of mutuality, with a logical structure,
a detectable range of meanings, and an aesthetic appeal as well as a
'premial' place in the social development of individuals. Stanner
pointed out that the rites involve anything from scores to hundreds
of men, in unguided co-ordination, with no master of ceremonies as
such; hence the spatial patterns of ritual are of cardinal importance.
At the place of congregation, Stanner recognized four systems of
symbolism in congruence - spatial configuration, gesture, language,
music - and was impressed by the practical, logical and expressive
efficacy of the form (i960, 61-4). With a combination of field
observation, theoretical rigour and imaginative insight Stanner was
able to demonstrate and interpret cogently and systematically the
development of symbolic forms in aboriginal ritual. His broad con-
clusion was that the Murinbata aborigines among whom he worked
were in the given rite expressing outwardly a complex sense of their
dependence on a source outside themselves - that by an 'inner
paradigm' of setting apart, destruction, transformation and return,
much of it unverbalized, they were intimating a mystery 'of good-
with-suffering, of order with tragedy' (i960, 70, 77). And yet Stan-
ner was prepared to argue that a full understanding of the religious
symbolism was to be gained only by a thorough morphemic analysis
of the whole language, and while this remains unfulfilled we have not
penetrated 'the true inwardness of the stuff of symbolism'.
With this analysis may be compared that of Nancy Munn. In an
early study of Walbiri graphic signs she meticulously interpreted
aboriginal totemic designs as devices for conveying narrative mean-
ing, and has had a general interest in iconography. In a study of the
effectiveness of symbols in Murngin rite and myth (1969) she drew
inferences about the way in which collective symbolic forms could
transform subjective experience. Though working along very dif-
ferent lines from those of Stanner, with reported, not observed
material, she also emphasizes the relation between narrative code and
system of ritual action, and in somewhat parallel fashion, sees the
myth as conveying body destruction images which the ritual con-
verts into feelings of well-being. But whereas Stanner is much con-
cerned with the symbolic significance of actual spatial forms as
MODERN ANTHROPOLOGICAL VIEWS 203
CARE I N CLASSIFICATION
really the more private, even eccentric symbolism? For instance, the
explanation that the milk tree is not only mother's milk but also the
matrilineage, 'brought out most clearly in a text (I) recorded from
a male ritual specialist' (1967, 21) occurs also in a text cited from the
ritual specialist Muchona. But Turner adds the possibly significant
note that this man's accounts and glosses were always fuller and
internally more consistent than those of other specialists (1967, 134-
5). He had evidently pondered long on the mysteries of his profes-
sion, says Turner, collating material given to him in the course of his
own instruction, in critical review. Here then it seems pretty clear
that public and private symbolism have got fairly well intertwined.
I repeat, this is a dilemma which confronts all field anthropologists.
But the serious problem for social anthropologists is not so much
to demonstrate how one arrives at a general statement of any piece of
public symbolism, as to work out how public and private symbol-
isms impact upon each other. How far do public symbols really
condition the forms of private symbolization? What kind of con-
tribution does private symbolism make to the formation or modifica-
tion of public symbols? In what way, if at all, does private symbolism
have an effect in social action? How far does the existence of clusters
of private symbols, if known or suspected, disturb the community
when they do not seem capable of public utilization but imply social
action with which the community may have to deal? Such questions
are relevant, though often hard to answer.
A very pertinent field for the study of the inter-relation of private
and public symbolization is art. Creativity in an artist is the display of
a personal vision, in which symbolization may play an important,
perhaps vital part. The symbols must be personal, individual,
unique, stamped with the artist's own imaginative power, if he is to
generate positive reaction in other people. (As modern examples
Paul Klee or Pablo Picasso clearly qualify.) Yet if the symbolism
remains purely private, unrecognized, the stimulus of the creative
act is lost to the community. Communication is the keynote. There
must somehow be enough communication between artist and public
for the initial recognition of something of the artist's vision to be
caught, absorbed, generate emotional and intellectual reaction, and
stimulate further aesthetic reaction. Private symbolism must be able
to be communicated to become public symbolism. A symbolic form
2l6 SYMBOLS
INTERPRETATION OF D R E A M S
personal thing, and its symbolism is private in the sense that the
ultimate clues to its meaning depend in some part upon the peculiar
circumstances and mind of the dreamer. Yet to some extent its
symbols are public in that many of them are clearly derived from
shared social experiences, and are recognizably of common form, in
'type-dreams'. In Edmund Leach's categorization, their aim is ex-
pressive for the individual dreamer, as representations of unconscious
mental process; but it is also communicative, since many dreams are
verbally described to other people and indeed are known primarily
by such mechanism. Moreover, their symbols become public in that
they are often the source of social action. It is not surprising then
that anthropologists even before Tylor paid attention to the subject
of dreams and recorded instances which seemed to throw light on
mental process, belief and individual and public reaction. As I have
shown in Chapter 3 (p. 101) study of the symbolism of dreams by
others than anthropologists, with attention to unconscious process,
was a serious subject for much of the nineteenth century.
Many questions about dream symbols may be raised in psycho-
logical anthropology, which do not concern us here.* But apart from
establishing norm and variation in dream content and interpretation
in different types of society, social anthropologists have been con-
cerned with three main questions in relating these private symbols to
the public sphere. First is the significance of dream material as an
index to the degree of social commitment, or social involvement.
I have referred already to Ronald Berndt's material on dreams of
aboriginal men participating in the Kunapipi cult (p. 208). Berndt
collected hundreds of dreams from about thirty men, and found that
while they ranged over a wide variety of themes, many were con-
cerned with indigenous religion, and were regarded as very impor-
tant by the people themselves. Men 'dreamed out' the meanings of
their sacred ritual, coming into contact spiritually, they thought,
with their Ancestral Beings. In dreams they performed ritual, used
sacred emblems in unconventional ways, and dreamed additions to
their totem designs and rites. This private symbolism has public
effect in that, Berndt points out, many sacred designs are altered
because of dreams, and sacred songs too are influenced thereby. In
* For example the relation between manifest content and latent content, see M. J. Field,
i960.
H
2l8 SYMBOLS
sweeping the shrine yard he had picked up a small gold trinket and
kept it instead of handing it in; so he had incurred the god's anger.
After a ritual purification he was discharged, free of disturbance.
There is a view which has received some popular support that
madness is created by society, in that society determines the criteria
by which certain types of behaviour of individuals are categorized
as madness, and treated accordingly. In a formal sense this is correct.
But I doubt if many anthropologists would agree with the formula-
tion in a substantial sense. They see a high degree of individual
reaction to social circumstances and social norms, varying with
complex combinations of personality elements. They see behaviour
disorder for the most part proceeding from the initiative of the
person concerned, not enforced upon him by society. To the sufferer
from mental illness the traps to personality set by the social order
no doubt appear unavoidable, just as 'odd' behaviour seems a
natural reaction to them. But to other members of the society the
symbolic presentations of the mentally ill person are only one of a
number of alternative avenues out of a circumscribing social situa-
tion. This is the basis of the treatment - to find out where the social
pressures are and what alternatives exist, so that the patient can
make another behavioural choice. In the case just cited, the patient
had the initial choice of handing in the found object. In other cases,
often of domestic difficulty, the choices may not be so simple, but
some resolution is often open for suggestion. Even with the fantasies
described by schizophrenics, which may have no apparent basis in
objective reality, their private symbolic expressions can often be
interpreted in terms of more general social theses.
What is suggested by some of the literature, and what I would
support from personal field experience, is that so-called primitive
and non-industrial societies are often more tolerant of the private
symbolism of mental illness than are our own societies, more willing
to try and enter a dialogue with the patient in comparable symbolic
terms, and more successful in alleviating a condition of mental
strain.
Another type of behaviour, which may be classed as an alternative
order of personality rather than a personality disorder, is that of
trance, usually identified in psychological terms as dissociated
personality. The complexities of this phenomenon are considerable,
P R I V A T E SYMBOLS A N D P U B L I C R E A C T I O N S 225
of the 'other' being of an entity whose full mind and powers are
unknown. And what gives the symbolism much of its importance is
that to some degree it is 'private'; there is an element of unpredict-
ability in it precisely because it stems from an individual, with his
own personal background. If what a medium or prophet said was
automatic, with no element of uncertainty, much of its value would
disappear. But if it was purely personal, it would be meaningless. In
the institutions of spirit mediumship and allied phenomena it is the
combination of public and private symbolisms that gives them force.
S Y M B O L I S M OF THE B O D Y
Use of the human body as basic symbolic material has been dis-
cussed by anthropologists and analysts in allied disciplines, from
Birdwhistell and Gombrich to Mary Douglas and Mircea Eliade.
From this and much other treatment one can perceive at least four
kinds of body symbolism in vogue.
As a symbolic instrument, a person may use his own body as a
means of communication, to indicate by bodily action or reference
some more abstract idea. When a person kneels in prayer he is
symbolizing his humility before what he conceives as a higher
personality, a god; when he says to someone else 'I bow to your
opinion', he symbolizes his deference to authority. These are simple
instances, but there are many more subtle ways of using one's body
to express a social relationship. As Mauss put it: 'The body is the
first and most natural instrument of man' (1950, 372). In Chapter 8 I
show how people put their bodies to symbolic as well as pragmatic
use in situations of greeting and parting.
A more general kind of body symbolism refers not to any concrete
entity but to a set of abstract constituents. A man is the head of a
family; the backbone of his team. A social unit is conceived as
analogous to a human body, in some of its major parts. Bodily parts
in themselves can represent the whole man, or his abstract qualities.
He can be weak-headed or swollen-headed, indicating not physical
condition but character defects; he can have no backbone or plenty
of backbone, indicating similarly degree of resolution. Size of
bodily parts can convey other qualities: big-hearted for generosity;
big-mouthed for volubility; broad-shouldered for responsibility
PRIVATE SYMBOLS AND PUBLIC REACTIONS 227
Mary Douglas is one of the most recent of those who have suggested
that the human body is a symbolic medium which is used to express
particular patterns of social relationships (1970, xiii). She has en-
* For discussion on a comparable miracle, that of the bleeding Host of Bolsena, see
Malinowski, 1936, 48, with some general remarks on relation between physical event and
supernatural force.
P R I V A T E SYMBOLS A N D P U B L I C R E A C T I O N S 231
IHS it is given to the 'Jesuit saints' and some others. The popular
form, depicting a heart with a wound, encircled with a crown of
thorns and a small cross above, the whole radiating light, did not
appear till the end of the seventeenth century. Since then, says the
Catholic Encyclopaedia fastidiously, 'statues and paintings of dis-
putable taste, often of vulgar sentiment repulsive to educated sensi-
bilities' proliferated from the beginning of the nineteenth century.
Now for some general points, on this recognition of a bodily organ
as a representative of human and divine love, in terms of public and
of private symbolism.
The first point is that the object of devotion (let us call it worship)
is conceived as something quite material in origin. 'In the devotion
to the Sacred Heart the special object is Jesus's physical heart of
flesh as the true natural symbol of his threefold love ' says the
Catholic Encyclopaedia. Now assuming that there was an historical
Jesus, and so a fleshly heart, it is obvious that unlike many of the
relics of the saints, there is certainly now no concrete object of
adoration; the physical, fleshly heart is only a conceptual object,
which has been re-translated into material form by the icono-
graphers. It would seem a reasonable suggestion that it needed the
ecstatic private experience of the nun to provide that dimension of
concreteness, that illusion of physicality desirable to win acceptance
of the heart of Jesus as vehicle of a public symbolic message. Again,
the symbolism is conceived to have begun in terms of physical
communication. Marie Alacoque saw her heart being received into
that of Jesus, illumined there by the flames of its charity, and after
these celestial pyrotechnics, returned again to her breast - experience
clearly generative of acute physical sensation.*
Secondly, the heart of Jesus is very much of a condensation
symbol, in Victor Turner's use of the term. The material object, of
red cloth or paint on canvas or what not, is a symbol of a symbol -
it stands for an abstract, conceptual heart, which in turn represents a
* An interesting analogy was provided by the principal leader of the Ghost Dance among
the Caddo, a man known as John Wilson, about 1890. When Mooney met him he explained
that an amulet on his breast, consisting of a polished end of a buffalo horn, surrounded by a
circlet of downy red feathers within another circle of badger and owl claws, was the source of
his prophetic and clairvoyant inspiration. The buffalo horn was 'God's heart', the red feathers
contained his own heart, and the circle of claws represented the world. When he prayed for
help, his heart communed with 'God's heart' and he learned what he wished to know (Mooney,
1965, 162).
PRIVATE SYMBOLS AND PUBLIC REACTIONS 235
THE V A L I D A T I O N PROBLEM
the facts - the analyst conniving with the patient instead of diagnos-
ing or interpreting him (1949, 610-11; 1969, 490-2). Yet in his own
essay analysing the efficacy of a Cuna shaman's treatment of a sick
woman he argues 'that the mythology of the shaman does not corres-
pond to an objective reality does not matter. The sick woman believes
in the myth and belongs to a society which believes in it' (1958,217
1963, 197). I am not concerned with the question of the efficacy of
myth; I merely wish to make the point again that the private ex-
periences of dream, sick person's fantasies, shaman's trance, each
with symbolic components, all embody recognizably socially-
engendered material, upon which their interpretation mainly de-
pends.
But the problem of interpretation of the symbolism may have a
double significance. The symbols may be regarded as means whereby
the individuals simply express their own experiences or feelings and
attempt to communicate these by comprehensible images to other
people. Any question about the validity of the symbols then relates
to the degree to which they are thought to reflect accurately the
experiences and feelings signified. The meaning of the symbols is
the clue they give to the state of mind of the person who expresses
them. Quite another significance of the private symbols may be
thought to lie in the degree to which they express experiences or
feelings of what may be called the audience. The dream, trance
presentation or other symbolic form is regarded as relevant not
only to the individual's situation but also to that of those to whom it is
communicated. It is thought to correspond to their feelings, be
explanatory of their circumstances, even be predictive of future
events. Other types of semi-private symbolic formation, engendered
in discussion and controversy, such as a new scientific theory or a
new theological statement, may also be regarded from a similar
standpoint.
A central problem here is what secures public acceptance of the
validity of private experience conveyed symbolically? To some ex-
tent, conformity with fresh increments of experience - as with many
scientific theories, up to a point, and with many dream and vision
symbolisms. We may recall the case of the New Guinea prophetess
cited by Peter Lawrence (p. 222) whose supporters trickled home
again after the dream-symbolized flood did not occur. But other
PRIVATE SYMBOLS AND PUBLIC REACTIONS 239
as key features in ritual (cf. p. 86). Victor Turner has argued that
Ndembu dominant symbols refer to values that are regarded as ends
in themselves, axiomatic values. He also has pointed out that there
may be discrepancy, even contradiction between many of the
meanings given by informants to a dominant symbol when it is
regarded as a unit of the total symbolic system; and that such dis-
crepancy is a quintessential property of the great symbolic domi-
nants in all religions (1967, 20, 43). Now food in general has
certainly an axiomatic value to all Tikopia, and was a prime symbolic
element in the traditional religion. But I do not think there was any
basic 'quintessential' discrepancy between the views of Tikopia
informants as to its basic significance in the symbolic system. I
suspect that there may be variation in this as between different kinds
of symbols, if not among different kinds of ritual or symbolic
systems. But for Tikopia I think this problem does not emerge if one
looks upon the issue of dominance in a somewhat different light, as
referring to relationships, not objects. I doubt if it would be ade-
quate to speak of food as being a dominant symbol in Tikopia, though
as I shall show it enters into every ritual situation; I think it prefer-
able to speak of the symbolization of food as a dominant - or at
least prominent - theme. At the same time the symbolic relation-
ships of food in Tikopia society can function side by side with non-
symbolic, quite pragmatic relationships. Food is not wasted in
Tikopia, as one may imagine from the care taken to conserve it; so
food which serves a symbolic purpose also serves the purpose of a
meal. The symbolic and the non-symbolic relationships are inter-
twined.
chiefs, are described as vai. Such gifts to men of rank are recipro-
cated (tongoi, the appropriate category term for a food-to-food
transaction) later on in no particularly prescribed style. But mourners'
vai are reciprocated on the last night of the feeding by non-food
goods (koroa, in the category fahapenu) and the obligation of the
transaction is carried on until in due course another funeral offers an
opportunity of repayment. The reason for this double transaction
would seem to be that the mourner's vai is not just a gift of food to
someone who can go out and get his own food; it is the service of a
meal to someone who has been fasting and inhibited from going
abroad to sustain himself. Now what underlies this nomenclature of
calling solids 'liquid' is the symbolic concept that in status situa-
tions where food is an instrument of social policy liquid rates lower
than solid. But it is also more complex. The recipients know they are
getting solid food - and incidental to my argument here, though not
to Tikopia, the solid food should be of high quality, containing
pudding and ideally fish. With people of acknowledged rank, such
as chiefs, the power recognition is evident - commoners are afraid
of seeming to boast lest they suffer for it. But with mourners the
situation is in reverse - they are the disadvantaged ones, and the
bringers of food do not wish to seem to boast lest the mourners be
shamed. The motivational part of my interpretation follows Tikopia
explanations, but the rating of solid over liquid is an inference which
the Tikopia did not overtly cite.
In the symbolic field where food is made to serve social relation-
ships, then, the concept of kai as solid food opposed to vai as liquid
food can be intellectually manipulated and emotionally supported
in a distortion.
An even more startling distortion occurs in the field of edible
and non-edible. Kai is the word for 'edible' in all general contexts.
One asks of fish, fruit and many other things e kai} and one is told
e kail or sise e kai, edible or inedible accordingly. There are several
categories of inedible objects recognized by the Tikopia. There are
objects or substances which are not edible by their physical nature,
because they cannot be masticated or cannot be digested or their
flavour is antipathetic: earth, wood, grubs, some marine fauna, etc.
Then there are others which are inedible because of their social
nature - certain fine fish and other good foods which a person in
FOOD SYMBOLISM 249
mourning 'cannot' eat because of restrictions conventionally imposed
or voluntarily assumed. (This is the condition in which a person is
known aspali to such foods - Firth, 1966b.) Finally, there are other
objects which are inedible because of their spiritual nature - most
birds and certain fish, in particular eels, which traditionally have been
regarded as material representations or emblems of spirits. Such
objects, some of which in other circumstances might be considered
as food, are tapu, taboo. Linked with this last category are other
things ordinarily very definitely in the food category, such as coco-
nuts, which are tapu and therefore theoretically inedible, because
they have been temporarily reserved for consumption by a chief or
other man of rank. ('Theoretically' inedible because such tapu was
not infrequently broken in time of food shortage.)
Now high in the inedible category of the first order, physically
antipathetic, is human excrement. It is regarded as disgusting, and
though excretion on the beaches is common, or in the sea, this is
treated by the Tikopia as a sanitary measure not calling for remark
but not lessening their distaste. Some of the most filthy - and most
frequent - Tikopia curses invoke the father or other kinsman of the
cursed to eat excrement, to eat the inedible. Excrement is taey and
favoured epithets begin kai tae In metaphorical terms the cursed
one is invited to bring together the incompatible ideas of eating and
non-edible, a conjunction supposed to imply frustration, shame and
degradation.
What then is one to make of the many Tikopia ritual invocations
to gods and spirits which begin with an announcement by the priest:
'I eat your excrement' or more fully 'I eat ten times your excrement'.
In an address to the gods above all, on a most formal occasion, when
people sit around in strained attention in a temple heavy with sacred-
ness, why should the priest bring together eating and the non-edible
in such a clashing, putatively disgusting way? The first thing to re-
mark is that whereas a curse by ordering to eat excrement is taken
laughingly or regarded as offensive, this formal statement in a prayer
was simply accepted, without comment, as part of the ritual proce-
dure. I have sat through many temple rites and seen the congrega-
tion pay no more attention to it than does say a Christian congrega-
tion to the opening words of the Lord's Prayer. When asked to
explain, both officiants and congregation members made little of it;
1
250 SYMBOLS
formal social occasion tends to have its own type of food transaction,
often with a special name. I have described many types of such
transaction in my various publications on Tikopia, and select only a
few here to demonstrate some main points about food symbolism.
But first a general theme running through all these transactions -
that food is the major mechanism whereby the kinship ties which are
basic to the structure of Tikopia society are given concrete expres-
sion. Since food is so important pragmatically to Tikopia one of the
best ways in which kinship can be shown to be meaningful is to
help with food - to assist in providing the raw materials, to help
with labour in preparing it, to give supplies of food ready to eat.
One of the most stringent and well-kept rules of the Tikopia social
system is that which requires men who have married women of a
lineage to attend any formal ceremony of the lineage as cooks. They
are known collectively as 'firewood' or 'oven stones', and their job
is apt to be hard, hot and dirty. Each man comes with his bundle of
firewood and bunch of coconuts, while his wife carries their raw
food contribution, a backload of taro, bananas, etc. This raw food is
the Jiuri, a term applied to any contribution of green food brought
or sent to a formal oven. Its normal reciprocity is a share of the
proceeds, some eaten as a meal on the spot and some borne off in a
basket to be consumed at home. Fiuri and its normal reciprocal,
taumafa - raw contribution and cooked share - symbolize the net-
work of kin relations of Tikopia society.
A special relationship, political and formerly ritual as well, is that
with the chiefs of the clans, who receive acknowledgement when-
ever any man of rank performs an important ceremony, and at all
major life crises such as initiation or marriage. Such a present of
food to a chief, known as fakaariki in reference to the chief's title
(ariki), is much larger than the share of an ordinary commoner, and
usually has a supplement of coconuts, both dry and sprouting, and
perhaps some bundles of raw taro as well. That the gift symbolizes a
social and political relationship and is not just a package of food
supplies is shown by the fact that commonly a man from another clan
than that of the chief is selected to bear the food to him, so tacitly
stating the importance of breadth in co-operation (Firth, 1936,
453). Formerly other special food gifts of large size went from each
lineage to their clan chief on the occasion of re-consecration of their
2
FOOD SYMBOLISM 55
clan temple and their sacred canoe. That these symbolized political
and religious ties of major import was illustrated by the manner in
which the baskets from the canoes were topped by bark-cloth
ritual vestments dedicated to the gods concerned; and the baskets of
both types of gift were ritually offered by the chief to the gods when
he received them.* Formal food exchanges between chiefs also
symbolized their political unity, and a special relationship believed to
have been created by an ancestral marriage about eight generations
before was annually celebrated by an enormous food exchange, with
bearers staggering along a path between two temples in conditions
of high ritual tension (1967a, 131-8, 249).
The general symbolic function of raw food contributions has
been mentioned, as representing social co-operation. But special
types of raw food served also as ritual symbols. Freshly plucked
green coconuts were associated with canoe and fishing rites, in one
of which a coconut was smashed by the chief and thrown out to sea
in a symbolic dismissal of the sea deities to their work (1967a,
85-7). In another rather touching piece of ritual symbolism, raw
food from the cultivations of a dead man was stood on his grave,
as a last farewell to him - 'it is announced to the man who is dead;
it is his severance from the middle of the orchard; that is the parting
of his hand from the woods'. This was not just a piece of senti-
mentalism. It was believed that if no such symbolic gesture was made,
the spirit of the dead man would take umbrage and afflict the cultiva-
tions with pests (1970a, 249).
In the Tikopia scheme of presentation of food after it has been
cooked, great attention is paid to the manner in which it is packaged,
and also to the term by which this package is called. The usual
method is to wrap the food in banana or giant taro leaves-the
equivalent of paper in industrial society - and then put the parcels in a
basket. These baskets, made from strong leaf strips, vary in size,
fineness of workmanship and durability, and normally serve dif-
ferent purposes. Tanga, small fine bags, hold betel materials and
* I have observed an apparent contradiction on a small point in my various accounts of this.
In one general passage I state that these gifts were reciprocated by the chief by a basket of
cooked food (1939, 374); in more specific passages I state they were not (1967a, 109, 224,
249). The latter is technically correct. But as I point out in the same context, there tends to be
indirect reciprocation by redistribution of food by the chief, so substantially there is some
basis for the first statement.
256 SYMBOLS
other objects, not usually food. Longi are medium-sized very open
baskets to hold household food; raurau are of the same type but of
finer quality. Kete are rectangular baskets to hold raw fish and other
things when people are at work. Popora are rough open-work
baskets meant to hold already packaged food or coarse food only,
and to last only for a few days. All ordinary gifts of food are taken
in popora, and given a name associated with their particular institu-
tional function or just called 'food'. But some gifts, though carried
in popora, are named tanga, longi, or kete - it is as if bread and meat
carried in sacks were to be labelled 'a handbag', 'a briefcase', etc.
In traditional Tikopia social life there were not many of these sub-
stitute labellings, and I cannot suggest in all cases why they should
have been given. But some seem to refer to rather critical phases of
ritual. The general meaning of the special labels was deprecatory, like
calling 'food' 'water'; in each case a large mass of food was spoken of
as a small mass. The idea of calling a large gift a small one is of
course well known in many societies, and is linked with ideas of
acknowledgement of status. But it is significant that this is really an
acknowledgement of the symbolic value of language. No one
actually believes that the gift is small - the large containers are there
for all to see; but the polite forms are observed. Clearly it is in
the selectivity of such appelations that their value lies. If all large
gifts were termed small, the reduction process would have to be
reconsidered. It is the particular social context that gives the cate-
gorization its meaning.
I give a couple of examples, one from marriage and the other
from initiation (Firth, 1936, 558, 452). In the series of reciprocal
presentations between bride's kin and groom's kin on a Tikopia
marriage, a very large basket of cooked food, prepared by the groom's
kin, is carried by the bride in particular to her kin. The package is so
heavy that it may tax her strength to take it. Early the next day its
reciprocal, also a large mass of cooked food, is sent over to the
bridegroom's kin, some of it being carried by the bride too. Nor-
mally a transaction is ended by the return gift. But on this occasion
when the bride returns again to her husband she takes with her what
is termed a tanga, literally a little bag, of food. Actually it is quite a
big basket, and it is intended to provide a meal for the immediate
household of the newly-married pair. I was at first unable to explain
FOOD SYMBOLISM M7
why such a derogatory name should be given to a substantial
gift, and Tikopia were no help on this specific point. On further
consideration I think two structural elements are involved. By
ordinary social rules the transaction is finished before the tanga is
given, so this is hors de la serie - it can be described appropriately
then as 'just a little something' about the size of a betel bag, and so
not start up another round of exchanges. The second element is that
by intending the food for the household of the newly-weds, the
groom's kin are being a bit more restrictive than usual in such pre-
sentations. This is quite in order since masses of food have gone to a
wide range of other kin. But in calling this gift in effect 'just a little
bag', of the kind to contain betel materials or tobacco, they empha-
size its domestic quality, diminish its social significance and so fend
off possible difficulty in exchange. These are my inferences, but they
fit general Tikopia attitudes.
My second example refers to the longi from which boys are fed on
the morning after their circumcision-type operation. Longi are essen-
tially household food containers, semi-personalized, used normally
for carriage and storage of meals within the domestic sphere. Now
the food on this occasion, though called longi, consists of large
packages in a popora. Significantly, it is brought from the adjacent
oven-house to the more secular 'profane' inland side of the dwelling-
house where normally formal food displays do not go. The reason
for this is that the food is designed not just as a meal for the initiated
boys but also as a gift for their mother's sisters and mother's brothers'
wives, who have spent the night sleeping as a kind of guard of
honour at their feet. The women eat too, but then carry off the
remainder of the food to their own dwellings, while the men at the
ceremonial site are catered for separately. The food of the longi is
brought in to the more secular side of the house because that is
associated with women, and since the formal context is female, the
domestic food basket is an appropriate symbolic title for the food
presentation. Again, this my inference, but it accords closely with
other Tikopia explanations.
As in any Western society, differences in the quality of Tikopia
food can be indices to recognition of social status or attribution of
putative status as a matter of etiquette. There is a vast difference
between offering someone a few green bananas or yams roasted over
258 SYMBOLS
GENERAL CONSIDERATIONS
262
H A I R AS PUBLIC SYMBOL 263
'standing on end' with shock or terror, man's hair is relatively inert.
According to physical anthropologists, hair is apparently a true racial
character in man, hereditary and unaffected by environment. Racial
variables include length of head hair; hairiness of body exclusive of
scalp hair; form, texture and colour of hair. In evolutionary terms,
an important function of hair has been for protection, especially in
serving as an insulator to retain heat, but for human beings this has
long ceased to be of much significance (Hooton, 1946, 41, 192-9,
469-75, 483-8; Howells, 1947, 33, 214; Turney-High, 1949, 22).
Hair is not only perishable, a wasting asset; it can be lost completely
with only social, not physiological disability, or at least minimal
physical discomfort.
It is striking to note how out of this sluggish, physiologically
almost functionless appurtenance of his body, man has imaginatively
created a feature of such socially differentiating and symbolic power.
But in contrast to other bodily appurtenances hair has a number of
qualities which recommend it as an instrument for social action.
Though personal in origin, it is multiple, any single hair of a person
tending to be like any other. It is detachable, renewable, manipulable
in many contexts, so to some degree can be treated as an independent
object. Yet there is some variation in texture and colour, so it offers
scope for social differentiation. And it is associative, tending to call
up important social ideas, especially concerning sex.
Consider first the general association of hair with ideas of multi-
tude and fineness. Before modern technology had developed pro-
cesses of counting and measuring to present refinement, hair re-
presented in Western thought an exemplar of extreme number and
extreme delicacy. The Biblical statement that 'the very hairs of your
head are all numbered' (Matt, x: 30), whether metaphor or not, was
intended to emphasize the interest of the Omniscient in humanity by
his having a knowledge that it was regarded as absurd for any human
being to attempt. (According to the Jewish Encyclopaedia the num-
ber was supposed to be one billion seven hundred thousand, though
actually, authorities report that the human head has about 120,000
hairs). Terms such as hairs-breadth, hair-spring, hair-trigger, hair-
splitting, all indicate extreme fineness and delicacy, whether in
mechanics or in the dialectic of argument. When Samuel Butler
wrote of his Presbyterian Knight:
264 SYMBOLS
* Note that the stress is upon informality, not on the bedroom - in Singapore it was custo-
mary for Chinese prostitutes to let down their hair as a sign that for the time being they were
unable to receive their clients (Ward and Stirling, 1925,1, 26n.).
H A I R AS PUBLIC SYMBOL 269
All such conventions have become much confused and overlaid
by modern developments. Apart from the multiplicity of rapidly
changing women's hair styles in which length becomes subordinate
to fashion, the traditional imagery in which the femininity of a
woman's hair was expressed has lost much of its point through the
rivalry of the advertising profession. If one compares 'a cascade of
lustrous curls' with 'the loose train of your amber-dropping hair',
Milton (Comus, 859) is only marginally ahead of Madison Avenue.
But in the sphere of sex differentiation, hair symbolism is focused
primarily on hair of the head, and nearly all literary statements (until
recent years at least) have concerned this. Hair on other parts of the
body, though also allowing some degree of differential develop-
ment, has in the West been treated with much more reserve. Hair on
the chest, normally an attribute of men, may be held to connote
strength and sexual vigour, but also tends to have an association of
lack of refinement. Men who devote time and money to careful
dressing of hair on scalp and face may make no attempt to barber
their hair on the chest - though I have been told by a colleague that
'chest toupees' have appeared on the Costa Brava! Axillary hair,
common to both sexes, is commonly regarded as neutral on a man,
but unfashionable on a woman, as also with hair on legs. Both can be
in the category of 'superfluous hair' recognized by purveyors of
depilatories. This 'superfluous' is a complex social category. It can
include hair of legs and armpits, conventionally unaesthetic, to be
concealed or removed. But what about pubic hair? In the West and
fairly generally elsewhere this should be concealed from public view
- except in vulgar nudity shows, of which it is a high point, or in
some modern ballet or other stage presentations in which the
aesthetic focus is on the nude body as a whole and not specifically on
the sex organs. But the pubic hair is not normally removed by either
sex, presumably because of its private erotic interest - leaving aside
the fullsome descriptions of pornographic literature. But this con-
cealment, yet preservation, of pubic hair is a Western custom. Other
societies vary, from taking nakedness and open display of pubic
hair completely for granted, to complete depilation of the genital
area. So, in Western society, hair on the upper part of the body,
especially the face for men and the scalp for women, has been
traditionally an object of admiration and solicitous care, whereas
270 SYMBOLS
M O D E R N S I G N I F I C A N C E OF M E N ' S L O N G HAIR
In the West until recently, norms of hair style were based on the
convention that while curls or ringlets might be permissible to
children of both sexes, in adolescence and maturity the hair of
females was worn long and that of males was short. Style might
indicate social progression, as when a girl symbolized her maturity by
'putting up' her hair into a roll or 'bun' on the nape of the neck or
top of the head, equated with 'growing up'; or in parallel, a boy
began to shave. For men, short scalp hair had been the custom for
more than a century. With men's facial hair more variation was
H A I R AS PUBLIC SYMBOL 275
allowable, and fashion saw changing styles, from clean-shaven to
combinations of beard, whiskers and moustache. But less than
twenty years ago the view could be expressed that shaving of the
beard continued in all ranks of life in England, though the mous-
tache, in vogue for many years, had become less common {Pears
Cyclopaedia, 1958-9). As for scalp hair, Hoebel in the third edition of
his Anthropology (1966, 282) could remark that 'in America, the
culture pattern with its attendant symbolic quality is still so strong
that short-haired women are considered mannish and long-haired
men effeminate5, though he added cautiously - ' a t least by most
individuals over 30'.
But such opinions have been overtaken by events. In recent years,
much more tolerance has been extended to male facial hair. What in
England we thought were the occupational beards of submariners
during the war turned out to be merely the advance guard of an
army. Beards are now so common among men of all ages as to attract
little attention, and indeed have become almost standardized pattern
in some circles.* Many men well over the age of 30 can be seen with
long-haired coiffure, from shaggy strands to duckstail or other neck
fringe. Seasonal factors may enter-as a Prime Minister known
socially as rather a trend-setter was reported to be having his hair
shortened for the summer after having it long during the winter.
Essentially, many men have been using their hair for aesthetic experi-
ment with their personalities.
But as well as personal aesthetic and conformity to fashion, it
seems clear that deliberate statements are often being made by such
practices. Quite generally, in line with modern values of self-
expression, the wearing of long hair by men, from hippy to univer-
sity student, can express an attitude of laissez-faire - avoidance of
the trouble and expense of hair-cut, letting nature take its course,
and so on. There may be also an attitude of sexual awareness,
though in a contrary direction to that put forward by Darwin in his
theory of the value of hair in sexual selection. When I once asked a
graduate student why he wore his hair long, he replied, laughing,
because his wife considered it more sexy;f she, listening, only
* There is some point to a New Yorker cartoon (23 May 1970) of two clean-shaven business
men standing on a commuter platform filled with an array of wearers of beards and whiskers;
one saying to the other: *I feel like a damn fool\
t For an elaborate examination of the sexual significance of head hair see E. R. Leach, 1958.
276 SYMBOLS
barred from school till he had his hair cut, an Education Department
spokesman said there was a school rule which stated that hair must
be of 'reasonable' length - which obviously leaves room for a great
deal of interpretation {Evening Standard, 12 May 1972).
The complications of the male long-hair issue emerge still more
when questions of employment arise. The managing owner of a
Chicago taxicab company posted a notice warning his drivers that
those who did not soon get their hair cut would not be allowed to
drive. He argued that passengers had complained about their long
hair, and unless he conformed he would lose business and money.
'We gave them [the drivers] a choice/ he said, 'either get haircuts or
don't drive. It's their choice.' The retort of the drivers was to collect
signed statements from passengers who had no objection to long
hair. Another manager, in Honolulu, defended his long-haired
drivers against criticism on the grounds that if he did not hire such
men they would be standing in the compensation lines for unem-
ployment benefit {New York Times, 29 December 1970; Chicago
Tribune, 17 November 1970). But the benefit issue itself was not
clear, since if prospective employers were known not to be interested
in long-haired men, these might be thought to be unwilling to take
work if they refused to cut their hair. So on several occasions in
California unemployment benefit has been refused on this score. The
manager of the state unemployment office for the Monterey penin-
sula was reported in May 1970 to have said that men whose hair,
beards or sideburns were long and scraggly could not collect un-
employment insurance on the peninsula. He said that after a survey
of 900 employers it was clear that the overwhelming majority of
them would not accept long hair on male employees - hence 'we
feel that those who persist in wearing it are voluntarily restricting
their availability'. Such men had only to shave or trim their hair and
they would receive insurance payments. At the beginning of 1972
the California Unemployment Insurance Appeals Board ruled that
jobless men with long hair were not eligible for unemployment
compensation benefits in towns where most of the employers rejected
long-haired applicants {The Province, B.C., 29 May 1970; New York
Times, 9 January 1972). Note that in this type of case, as with the
taxi-drivers, the operative factor was public opinion, real or alleged.
In some employment fields orders to employees to cut their hair
HAIR AS PUBLIC SYMBOL 28l
have been successfully challenged. The policy of the New York
City Housing Authority for some time had been against the wearing
of beards by their patrolmen, and a patrolman who insisted on
wearing a beard had been discharged for insubordination. But pre-
sumably it was later thought that public sentiment did not provide
sufficient sanction for such action, and the Authority rescinded its
'no-beard' rule, on the ground that 'where it is not clear that the rule
has anything to do with the proper performance of duty' it was 'un-
wise' and 'an unwarranted infringement on personal freedom' to
enforce it (New York Times, 23 April 1970; 16 May 1970). It may be
that legal sanctions also were not thought strong enough. For
instance, a volunteer fireman of Long Island was suspended for a
year for not conforming to the rules about hair; he brought a case
against the Board of Fire Commissioners of his district, and the state
Supreme Court upheld the constitutional right of a public employee
to determine the length of his hair, sideburns, moustache and beard.
When the fireman promised to obey the department rules, the judge
said, he did so not in waiver or violation of his constitutional rights
(New York Times, 3 December 1971).
But with more direct organized sanctions, the reaction against
long hair has tended to be firmer. On various occasions the United
States Army and Navy have issued directives about grooming of
hair and beards, and made it plain that they do not condone long
unkempt hair. In December 1969 it was reported that a black airman
was convicted of refusing to obey an order to trim his Afro-style
haircut, and was sentenced by special court-martial to three months'
confinement, demotion, and $60 a month fine for three months. The
offence was not wearing his hair long but refusing to obey a military
order, but the issue was clear (Life, 8 May 1970; cf. Newsweek, 23
November 1970; 29 May 1971; Chicago Daily News, 3 December
1970; New York Times, 28 November 1971).
The most extreme forms of reaction against male long hair in the
name of discipline have occurred in prisons, where haircuts have
been imposed by force. Two kinds of rationalization have been
invoked in such cases-that the shearing has been for 'sanitary
reasons', or to destroy a possible hiding-place for forbidden goods.
Both the United States and Britain have had recent instances of this,
with offenders who have been involved with the law primarily on
K
282 SYMBOLS
When the symbolism of scalp and facial hair is not simply part of a
diffuse set of social norms, but is integrated with an organized set of
religious norms, the issues take a different form.
Many religious communities have incorporated regulations about
hair into their body of rules for the faithful, involving both cutting
or shaving of hair and growth of hair, according to circumstance.
Judaism, which tends to equate male hair with strength and vitality,
has rules for Nazarite-vows, focusing upon a man's growing his hair
for thirty-day periods (or multiples thereof), ritual cutting and
burning of it, and presentation of animal offerings in celebration.
Detailed specification of such vows includes a distinction between
one kind of lifelong Nazarite, who may lighten his hair with a razor
if it becomes too heavy; and another kind 'the like of Samson', who
may not so lighten his hair (Mishnah, Nazir - Danby, 1933, 281). In
orthodox Hinduism a shaving of a child's head leaves only a tuft of
hair, a topknot, 'universally' recognized as the distinctive mark of a
* But note that in other cultures the symbolism may take a contrary form. Before a Toda
man entered the dairy, a sacred place, for ritual performance, he tied up the straggling hair at
the back of his head (Rivers, 1906, 92, 221).
284 SYMBOLS
others doing penance, letting their hair grow long (George Ferguson,
1961, 47, 135, 137). Interpretation varied according to context.
L O S S OF H A I R
from the head has often been prized and used as a symbol for
manipulation, especially for memorial purposes. In the eighteenth
and nineteenth centuries aristocratic and middle-class circles in
Europe and America made great play with lock, tuft, curl, tress or
ringlet of hair-as reminiscence of her child's babyhood for a
mother, token of affection for a lover, or sign of mourning in a close
relative. An exotic example of this kind of interest is the recent sale of
a lock of George Washington's reddish-brown hair, which his wife
Martha had given to a New York society belle, for $550 {Chicago
Tribune, 2 November 1970; Chicago Daily News, 22 November
1970). Analogous customs have existed in many other cultures - as
my example from Tikopia has indicated (p. 272).
In many societies, however, it is the act of severing a person's hair
rather than the fate of the hair which attracts prime attention. In
ordinary modern Western conditions the focus is upon the skill of
the operator and the result, for which he is highly rewarded, but in
some other cultures the relationship between the parties may be the
main object of concern. A striking instance of how cutting a per-
son's hair may imply a special relationship is given in traditional
Dobu society. Care of hair is a reciprocal service between husband
and wife, and is interpreted as associated with sexual intercourse. So
an adulterer will openly cut the hair of a woman with whom he has
committed adultery if he wishes to make the matter public and defy
the woman's husband (Fortune, 1932, 50).
In other conditions it is the shorn state of the person that is the
most significant element. Simulated baldness, as by shaving the pate,
has been used to give relief from heat or to cope with scalp infection
or - formerly - as part of treatment in some fevers. Socially, head
shaving has been used for dramatic effect, as by the 'soul' singer
Isaac Hayes {Ebony, 1970, 86; New York Times, 18 April 1971); or as
a demarcation sign, by British 'skinheads', teenagers opposed to
long-haired 'hippies' and bearded 'Pakistanis' {New York Times,
29 March 1970).
But on the whole, deliberate shaving of the head, or close cutting
of the hair, has taken on a ritual quality, intended to mark a transi-
tion from one social state to another, and in particular to imply a
modification in the status or social condition of the person whose
hair is so treated. At many periods women have cut their hair short
H A I R AS P U B L I C SYMBOL 289
* An alternative to a wig for men has been a hair transplant of scalp grafts from sides to top
of the head {Chicago Daily News, 20 April 1970). Analogous to wigs as enhancement of
personality have been false beards for men and false eyelashes for women.
HAIR AS PUBLIC SYMBOL 293
and the Fathers condemned disguises, but wigs disguised the clerics
who wore them Thiers proposed various measures, including
a papal bull, to stop such abuse. That his arguments had some effect
is seen by the publication of his work in Italian nearly a century
later, with episcopal authority from Benevento.
An interesting question about the concept of personality is raised
by the wearing of wigs. Ordinarily, contact with another person's
discarded hair is apt to be repulsive, if there is no positive affective
tie, as with a lock of hair from a relative or lover. Yet human hair in
a wig is acceptable, even preferred to artificial hair. How can this be
so? It is clear that many external elements from living or dead
things can be associated with the human personality without strain -
leather, wool and meat from animal tissue for shoes, clothing and
food. Even elements from another person's body may be incor-
porated nowadays by blood transfusion, corneal grafts and organ
transplants. But it is a delicate issue. Apart from susceptibilities
about food taboos on pork, or beef, or meat generally, there may be
religious objections to some surgical transfers, as in Muslim debates
about the propriety of eye grafts.
What is interesting about wigs made from human hair is that they
seem to arouse no serious objection. A few people seem relieved to
know they are wearing man-made plastic, but most seem happy to
sport 'real first-grade human hair'. This is so even when ethnic
boundaries are crossed - for much hair made up into Western wigs
comes from Oriental heads. Two conditions here are relevant. The
first is that people incorporate other people's hair into their own
personality on their own responsibility - they are not just con-
fronted with it at random; it is under their own control. The second
condition is that it is de-personalized. Once on the commercial
market, human hair is treated and sold just as if it were a fibre of
animal or vegetable origin. This point can be emphasized in another
way, by contrast of custom. I mentioned that Tikopia women with
close-cropped heads have customarily worn, not a wig, but a ring of
their menfolk's hair as a kind of everyday obligatory ornament. In
the West, however, whether women cut their hair or not, men until
recently have done so. Yet I have never heard of a woman's tresses
being made into a wig for her father or brother, or a man's locks for
his sister or wife; this would probably be regarded as eccentric if not
294 SYMBOLS
The intimate relation of the hair of the head with its owner's bodily
appearance and movement, and his personality, makes it an obvious
object of emotional association and stimulus, so that it may be said
to have force or power as a symbol for the personality, as in poetry
or sentimental conservation. But ethnographic literature gives a
wide range of examples where the power of hair is regarded as not
simply emotional but magical. The hair is believed to have in itself
some quality of affecting either the person from whom it has been
obtained, or the person with whom it is newly put in contact. It is
not uncommon in traditional sorcery for hair of an intended victim
to be secured as an object for spells, a vehicle to convey the mystical
power. On the other hand, hair is sometimes used as if it had thera-
peutic or prophylactic qualities, such as a cure for snakebite, an aid
to recovery after circumcision, or a reinforcement of a warrior's
virtue.*
In cases of negative magic or sorcery using hair of a projected
victim, what seems to be dangerous to the owner is not the involun-
* For data of classical type see for example Seligman (Veddas), 1911, 197; Rivers (Todas)
1906, 257, 267; Tylor, 1878, 127-30; Crawley, 1902, 107-8, 202. For ideas of sacredness of
organic tissues see Durkheim, 1926, 137-8.
H A I R AS PUBLIC SYMBOL 295
tary detachment of the hair - loss of 'soul-stuff' in the older anthro-
pological terminology - but loss of control over it. Hair detached
but under owner's control cannot be used against him. So until
recently old Maori men who might go to a barber to have their hair
cut often made a contract with him to have all the hair ends gathered
up; the owner would then go and hide them away to avoid the
possibility of having them used for sorcery against him. Conversely,
a controlled hair of one's own could be launched against someone
else. There is a story of a Maori in quite recent times who had begun
to drink a glass of beer in a public house when he noticed a hair in
the liquid. He reacted swiftly, not aesthetically in disgust but ritually
in fear. Supposedly plucked from a sorcerer's head, the hair was a
sign of evil power against him; he vomited, ejected the hair and so,
he thought, escaped death. What such a sorcery interpretation does
is to translate a kind of careless aggression on the physical plane -
leaving one's hair lying around - into intentional aggression on the
conceptual (putatively spiritual) plane.
But as Leach has pointed out in his subtle analysis of 'magical
hair' (1958) such symbolic conceptions are not simply an outgrowth
of individual theories about personality; they are highly patterned
social responses, elaborately integrated into a system of beliefs about
protection and pollution, sacred and profane. As he indicates, too,
there are many types of situation where it is not just individually
identified and associated hair that is the object of magical interest,
but any hair as an object in its own right, infused with attributes of a
mystical kind. I can illustrate this from a Malay example.
At the end of 1939 a woman in the village where my wife and I
were living fell ill, in her delirium trying to distribute the rice from
her household and making sexual advances to men. One of our
neighbours, who had been an object of such advances, said that
earlier she had learned magic and had a tiny familiar spirit (pelesit)
which attacked people. Now it had turned on her. She was given
relief by spirit medium performances. Subsequently I found out that
one of the most respected and feared spirit medium performers (who
had not on this occasion been called in to the woman) had a lock of
female hair attached to his rebab, the fiddle of Arab type which is a
prime instrument of the master of spirits. He said the fiddle was 'a bit
potent' because the lock of hair was the repository of a pelesit, and
296 SYMBOLS
given may even have been false. But what matters is that some name
has been given, and some personal manual contact made. The
accidental travel neighbour has been socially pin-pointed, and the
handshake is the formal symbol of a social relationship established,
of the reduction of an unknown to a (putatively) known social
position. The handshake has been interpreted as equivalent to a
disclaimer of aggression, as a residual pledge against resort to force
of arms. But in such modern conditions the risk of physical assault
is minimal (these words were first drafted before air hijacking had
been invented). If a threat is conceived it is of interference with the
personality, not with the person, and the handshake has a much more
subtle function of serving to reduce social uncertainty.
In such a situation the social identification has been provided
by the two parties immediately concerned. The relationship is
casual, the identification nominal. But it is not automatic; if neither
party takes the initiative no formal greeting takes place. Moreover,
it is status-regulated. Handshake in such travel conditions is pri-
marily behaviour between male equals or those making a show of
equality. My guess is that it occurs much less frequently between
men and women; and between women no handshake at all may be
exchanged - though other identificatory signs may be. Between
adults and children the handshake of casual acquaintance is nearly
always lacking. When children shake hands, it is commonly a con-
cession to adult, usually parental, direction, and is primarily a symbol
of relations between the adults involved - the child is a kind of
instrumental extension of adult greeting.
Modern anthropological idiom stresses both the communicative
and the expressive functions of ritual. In rituals of greeting and part-
ing the inter-relation of these elements is quite complex. There is
conveying of information - of social recognition and acceptance,
of status and general quality of the relationship. But there is also
an implication, in popular estimation in Western society, of emo-
tional involvement, if even low-keyed. Greeting behaviour is
expected to express approval of the encounter, even pleasure;
parting behaviour is expected to express the opposite, or at least a
recognition that the severance of the encounter is necessary. Yet
it is a matter of common knowledge that the reverse may be the
case, or that the parties may be indifferent. Popular jokes make play
3°4 SYMBOLS
S Y M B O L I C USE OF THE W H O L E B O D Y I N
GREETING AND PARTING
may be cited: a woman kneeling to be ordained as deacon by a Bishop of New York Diocese;
the Duchess of Windsor curtseying to Queen Elizabeth who was taking leave after a visit;
200 candidates for the priesthood in the Philippines lying prostrate in front of the altar as
part of their ordination ritual by the Pope (New York Times, 14 November 1971; 4 January
1972; The Times, 19 May 1972). An elaboration of a greeting gesture took place when Queen
Elizabeth visited France. Having been told that the Queen liked horses the French introduced
a white horse which had been trained to kneel, and which at the appropriate moment went
down on its knees 'in a dutiful manner' on a pile of sand provided for the purpose. In contrast
to such proceedings was the attitude of Mrs Martha Mitchell, wife of a high United States
official, who remained upright when presented to Queen Elizabeth at a garden party. 'I feel
that an American citizen should not bow to foreign monarchs', Mrs Mitchell wrote in explana-
tion - curtseying apparently being optional for guests who are not British subjects (Time
Magazine, 29 November 1971).
S Y M B O L S OF G R E E T I N G A N D P A R T I N G 311
KISS OF GREETING
H A N D A N D ARM I N G R E E T I N G A N D P A R T I N G SYMBOLISM
GENERAL OBSERVATIONS
do this is one of the few reasons for which I have seen a child beaten'
(1934, 65).
Yet despite the moral sanctions in vogue for carrying out the
'correct' behaviour it is remarkable how easily such patterns have
altered. The more elaborate formal procedures of many African
and Asian societies - including the Ganda-have tended to be
abandoned in modern times as familiarity with Western patterns has
spread and as Western economic, educational and religious institu-
tions have affected traditional status alignments. I would put status
considerations at the core of the symbolism of greeting and parting
rituals.
Chapter 10
SYMBOLISM OF FLAGS
Like the symbolism in the manner of wearing the hair, and in be-
haviour at greeting and parting, the symbolism offlagslies primarily
in their display. But whereas hair is basically a personal symbol, a
flag is basically a social symbol. Not an attached, growing, shearable
part of a human personality, it is a manufactured object, often made
to a formula, detachable from maker or user and meant to show to
others rather than to be an ornament to oneself. And yet a flag may
be an object of strong sentiment, its symbolism may be deeply felt,
and as such it may serve as a symbol for the unity of a large body of
people. Now when it is said in Durkheimian fashion that a flag is a
symbol to which sentiments spontaneously attach themselves, and
that this intensifies social solidarity, what is meant by such state-
ments?
I begin with a piece of personal observation. A couple of years
ago, from my room overlooking the quadrangle of an eastern
university in the United States, I heard one day the sound of a
kettledrum in even taps, at the same time as I saw the statue of one
of the founding fathers of the university, a seated bronze figure,
being draped in a plastic robe. Then a procession came into view,
headed by a single male figure with head-band and long hair, slowly
carrying an uplifted American flag on a pole. He was followed by
about twenty young men, some carrying a large chair. To the sound
of the drum the procession advanced to the plinth of the statue, the
chair was set down, and a black student was seated temporarily in it.
Then the student was 'rescued' and the chair was set on fire. A
speech was given, inaudible to me and apparently to other people at
a distance - some lying on the grass reading, some talking with backs
turned. From later report the speech gave some explanation of these
events.
328
SYMBOLISM OF FLAGS 329
ETHNOGRAPHY OF FLAGS
flag defeats the bride's flag and is crossed over it. Then the two
flags are hoisted above the house, the groom's again on top. The
symbolism here is obvious in one sense, but whether it represents
male dominance in actuality or only in wish-fulfilment is not clear.
The flags bear various devices, such as the Union Jack, and em-
broidered mottoes such as 'Long Life', 'Prosperity' or (a rather
depressing comment on the future of marriage) 'In God We Trust'
(Smith, 1962, 127-8).
F L A G S AS SIGNALS
be found at the bottom of the page, but also more elaborate objects
and devices, such as the flags and signal lights, which are not ordin-
arily regarded as important in themselves but which point to ideas
and actions of great consequence to societies— .In the case of a
national flag or a beautiful poem, a symbolic expression which is
apparently one of mere reference is associated with repressed emo-
tional material of great importance to the ego' (1934). The interest of
this statement does not lie so much in the hint of latent wonder that
such mediocre objects should arouse such strong sentiments - which
one would expect to be a lay reaction rather than a professional one in
such a sensitive sociologist. It lies rather in the notion of the symbol
evoking emotional responses of a repressed kind. It is not clear just
what Sapir thought this repressed material to be in the case of flags.
But the statement is an echo of Sapir's psychoanalytical interests, and
a pointer to some later anthropological ideas about symbolism.
The Durkheimian sociological viewpoint about flags has been
repeated by many writers, including Boas, Linton and Levi-Strauss.
It is epitomized in the kind of statement made by J. J. Honigman
about the rituals of the United States Memorial Day - that the
emotions canalized towards flags, images or dead heroes intensify
solidarity (1959, 515).
But what I have not found in sociological writings about the use of
flags as symbols is any systematic examination of why flags should
have attained such prominence. It is true that other national symbols
have been of great importance, especially national anthems and
national emblems. Indeed the government of India has been so
aware of this that a few years ago they issued a series of brochures
explaining the origin, meaning and use of these symbols of the Indian
nation. 'The National Flag, the National Anthem and the National
Emblem are the three symbols through which an independent
country proclaims its identity and sovereignty and, as such, they
command instantaneous respect and loyalty. In themselves, they
reflect the entire background, thought and culture of a nation/
This might be called an exercise in practical Durkheimianism.
342 SYMBOLS
C R E A T I O N OF NEW N A T I O N A L FLAGS
the girls, who had also knelt with lotus flowers. The rite was said to
have been improvised for the occasion (so much for the 'tradition'!).
But clearly it involved Buddhist elements of chant, lotus symbolism
and offering, with concepts of purity and more general symbolic
behaviour of kneeling and other signs of respect. It was both a
dedication of the new national flag to public state uses, and also a
respectful recognition of its importance as a sacred symbol (New
York Times, 9 October 1970).
The creation of a national flag is so much part of modern political
symbolism of nation-making that a people may even proceed to the
recognition of a flag before they attain nationhood. So in the move-
ment of East Pakistan towards autonomy as Bangladesh, the Bengal
Nation, when militant students and workers began to demand com-
plete independence, the green, red and gold flag of Bangladesh was
unveiled in anticipation (New York Times, 29 March 1971). Many
Blacks in the United States have adopted their own liberation flag -
black, with three horizontal bars of red, black and green. (These
were colours popularized by the late Marcus Garvey.) According to
the chairman of the Pan-African Congress, U.S.A., the red bar
stands for the blood shed by black people to achieve the Black
Nation. The black bar represents the 'black race' which, though
fallen on evil days, will rise again to take its rightful place in the
world. The green bar is symbolic of land and nationhood, for land is
the basis of power and freedom. The creation of this flag is regarded
as based on the black American's 'passionate belief that the true
meanings of the nation's patriotic symbols and ceremonies have
never been extended to include him'. The broad truth of this state-
ment can hardly be questioned. But one may surmise that the crea-
tion of this flag, and the recognition of a 'black national anthem' as
well, are perhaps symbols of compensation, substitutes for more
tangible independence in terms of political and economic power
(L. F. Palmer, Jr, 1970).*
An interesting light is thrown on the relation between symbolic
* This black-green-red flag of 'Negro nationalism' was raised over the coffin of one of the
convicts killed in retaking the Attica prison in September, 1971. It was also waved in an
African-American Parade in Harlem in the same month. In Vietnam a 'Black Powerflag*dis-
played 'Black Unity' in black letters at the top, and a black fist in the middle, on a red ground.
In August 1971, the Black-owned and Black-operated Amsterdam News of New York
adopted a combination of red and green ink with its black print. As the editor stated: 'This
was our symbolic way of expressing typographically and in our format our commitment to
S Y M B O L I S M OF F L A G S 349
creation and considerations of expediency by the history of the
wheel symbol in the national flag of India. It has been said that the
chakra-dhvaja or the Wheel Flag of India is the symbol of her
civilization as evolved through the ages. When the national leaders
of India were fired with the spirit of asserting the country's indepen-
dence they naturally felt the need of a national flag. Various designs
were used from 1906 onwards, commonly with red, yellow and
green. The Home Rule movement of 1917 devised a flag which
incorporated the Union Jack, since they were aiming at local
autonomy, not complete independence. 'The people, however, did
not take kindly to it'! Finally, partly on Mahatma Gandhi's sugges-
tion, a tricolour was accepted, of saffron above, green below, with
white in the middle, in which was set a spinning-wheel sign of navy-
blue. With the coming of Independence in 1947 it was felt necessary
to modify the spinning wheel for the sake of simplicity, to avoid
directional confusion; if the symbol appeared identically on both
sides of the flag it would be pointing different ways. So, on a resolu-
tion moved by Pandit Sri Jawaharlal Nehru, a simple wheel was
substituted. He described the flag as 'a flag of freedom and symbol of
freedom'. He pointed out that in the white previously there was the
chakra which symbolized the common man in India, which sym-
bolized the masses of people, which symbolized their industry. But
in considering a simplified revision, minds went to the wheel of the
Asokan column. 'That wheel is a symbol of India's ancient culture;
it is a symbol of the many things that India had stood for throughout
the ages....' The theme of the symbolic significance of the wheel in
Indian history was elaborated by others also, and the wheel was
described as the Wheel of the Law of Dharma, denoting motion,
representing life, symbolizing righteousness, etc. (Vasudeva, 1964;
Y. G. Naik, 1957). So here a contemporary symbol, the spinning
wheel, associated with the mass of the peasantry, and with Gandhi's
simplicist but powerfully appealing mode of life, was converted to
the historic symbol, the wheel of Asoka, associated with much more
complex religious sentiment, at a deeper level. Though motivated by
expediency, the translation gave an increment of symbolic power.
The circumstances of the decision on the symbolism of the Indian
what it means to be black in this country today*. (See for example New York Times, 13-19
September 1971; 17 November 1971.) For action in schools see later.
35° SYMBOLS
flag appear quite clear. But as with the national flag of the United
States, establishing the origin of some other national flags has been
a subject of some controversy, often of political significance. This
seems to have been the case in Argentina, where the history of the
precise colours of the national flag has been open to debate, and
where a military circular was issued on the antecedents of the
'national symbols' (no. 635/41; cf. Luis Canepa, 1943, 1953).
MORAL S I G N I F I C A N C E O F F L A G COLOURS
N A T I O N A L F L A G S AS SYMBOLS OF S T A T U S A N D POWER
the owner of the vessels. Countries such as Liberia and Panama, who
are prepared to register vessels under their jurisdiction but who are
less concerned than many other countries about regulation of crew
wages and employment conditions, standards of seaworthiness and
taxation levels, present operating advantage to shipping companies
which some regard as more than offsetting protection from their
own national flag. The system has been shown to have advantages
too at a national level for a country such as the United States, which
wishes for strategic reasons to keep in being a considerable merchant
fleet but finds difficulty in manning it on American standards.*
Such a device of transfer of status involves much more than
merely flying an appropriate national flag; complex legal instruments
are necessary to secure and implement the status which the flag
symbol indicates. In other conditions the use of a national flag may
be a more formal device to indicate not so much temporary transfer
of sovereignty as a claim to privilege or an avoidance of responsi-
bility, with the implied consent of the countries concerned. In the
field of international relations some national vessels engaged on
United Nations business, as F.A.O. fishing research vessels, may fly
a United Nations flag in addition to or as substitute for their own
flag. A practice, which has as much an element of disclaimer as of
claim in it, is that reported of submarines in the Adriatic manned by
Chinese crews but flying the Albanian flag - though Albania was not
known to possess submarines.
In these examples the national flag is a symbol of the political
entity, and it is displayed officially as a symbol of the status, often
also of the power, of the nation concerned. By implication too it is
expected that the symbol will receive the respect ordinarily paid to
more substantial tokens of the nation's strength. So, the expression
'showing the flag', even if metaphorical, means staking a claim to
national interest. So when a Soviet ship opened a passenger run
between South-East Asia and Australia, this new development was
interpreted by foreign diplomats as a matter of Russian policy -
'another Russian step to show her flag in a new area'. When the
United States acquired a naval base on Bahrain this was treated as
* For brief discussion of economic and political questions raised by 'flags of convenience',
see Roger Eglin, Observer, 7 March 1971; Michael Baily, Times, 3 June 1972. Official dis-
regard of a 'flag of convenience' by Cuba was reported in tension with the United States
(New York Times, 19 December 1971).
S Y M B O L I S M OF F L A G S 355
'a flag-showing operation to manifest United States interests in the
area'. That a physical flag was flown in such circumstances was
almost irrelevant; in each case the political implications of the
physical operations were indicated by the verbal use of the symbol of
the flag. So when the President or Prime Minister of a country makes
an official visit abroad he may be said to be 'showing the flag' merely
by advancing his country's interests.
S T A T U S SYMBOLS I N R E V E R S E
Peking to the United Nations. (For some details see: Times, 24 July
1970; New York Times, 25 May 1970; 15 September 1971; Time
Maga^ne, 18 May 1970; Chicago Tribune, 16 October 1970.) The
major point about such demonstrations is that while they show
resentment against a national power, they substitute action against
the symbol for action against more integral constituents of the
nation such as the person of its citizens. So, an American report on
the Filipino incident of burning the Stars and Stripes described the
demonstration as 'noisy but peaceful' since no one was assaulted. It
is noteworthy that such incidents have now come to be accepted as
part of the modern way of life by the powers whose flag symbols are
maltreated. Assuming that formal diplomatic protest is lodged, there
nevertheless seems to be tacit recognition that in the prevailing
climate of criticism of economic and political power as exercised by
the larger nations, these had better tolerate abuse of their symbols
than threaten reprisals. In this sense the symbol is treated as a surro-
gate, on which moral and physical force can be allowed to spend itself
with minimal harm.*
because some young men, charged in court with having had a picnic
on the American flag, defended themselves by producing a photo-
graph of the actress clad rather scantily in some arrangement of the
Stars and Stripes. The judge, inquiring rhetorically: 'Is she glamour-
izing the flag or desecrating it?', dismissed the case. A New York
City Transit Authority patrolman, who had been charged with
wearing an unauthorized emblem on his uniform, was found not
guilty on the grounds that this was done out of patriotism, and that
President Nixon himself had supported similar action in another
case, writing: 'We need to encourage Americans in pride of country'.
From such incidents it may be inferred that associating the national
flag with the person in unorthodox ways may be interpreted as
decoration or desecration depending on what may be thought as to
be the wearer's motivation.* In this context it is significant that the
action under scrutiny had a public character - wearing or using the
symbol so that it could be seen generally. Whether for patriotic
decoration or for protest, the symbol is expressly utilized as a
medium of communication of an attitude towards the society it
represents.
Other protest methods of handling national flags may be even
more open to ambiguity in that it may be hard to say whether they
are acts of desecration or respectful usage to express personal views.
In the 'hard hat backlash' of May 1970 in New York, when massed
building-construction workers demonstrated with Stars and Stripes
against the frequent anti-war demonstrations, there was no doubt:
they were carrying the national flag in defence of what they regarded
as the national interest. The national flag painted on their construc-
tion helmets was taken as positive criticism and fully permissible
(New York Times, 16, 21 and 25 May 1970; Time Maga^ne, 25 May
1970; 1 June 1970). But how about the man who flew the American
flag upside down and at half-staff in front of his house, with the
flagpole draped in black, in protest against the conviction of an Army
lieutenant for murder of civilians in Vietnam? The protester's argu-
ment was that such a conviction was not in the best national interest;
it was 'killing our flag'. The local police did not accept this attitude,
* For detail, see Honolulu Star-Bulletin, 2 September 1968; New York Times, 1 February
1970; 24 and 25 February 1970; 16 April 1970; Chicago Tribune, 3 December 1970; Ithaca
Journal, 14 May 1970; Time Magazine, 2 November 1970; The Times, 25 March 1971.
S Y M B O L I S M OF F L A G S 361
saying: 'You can't put the flag that way; you're not in distress/
There is also the case of an American housewife who flew the
national flag upside down to protest against the involvement of the
country in the Vietnam war, and who was arrested and charged with
violating a state law which prohibited showing 'contempt, either by
word or act, upon the flag'. The judge held that an act of turning a
flag upside down did not indicate a dishonourment or defilement of
the flag, and that what was being expressed as a personal opinion of
distress was a legitimate use of the flag. Yet when a group of high
school students petitioned their authorities to allow the school
American flag to be lowered to half-staff as a token of mourning for
the notorious shooting of Kent State University students, the judge
in this case refused the request. His judgement was that to fly the
national flag at half-staff was to commemorate the death of a per-
sonage of national or state standing or of a contributor to the local
community service. It should not be so flown to involve 'an expres-
sion of a political concept' (see New York Times^ 18 March 1970;
2 June 1970; Chicago Tribune^ 31 March 1971). On the other hand,
a group of demonstrators who flew the United States flag upside
down from the head of the Statue of Liberty for two days, as a
distress signal against the Vietnam war, were allowed to leave with
impunity in compliance with a court order for their eviction {Time
Maga{iney 4 January 1972).
Why these differences of treatment? To some extent they were due
to differences in state law, and in judicial interpretation. But broadly
they indicate that a symbol is essentially not an object but a relation-
ship; that with acceptance of the object goes also acceptance of
notions of its 'normal' or 'proper' use. Hanging out or waving -
even wearing - of a national flag symbol in normal 'correct' position
is a socially acceptable act, irrespective of whether the motivation
that inspires it is loyalty and respect or a scornful concession to
popular opinion. But to put the symbol in an unusual context causes
confusion, and focuses attention on motivation. Yet the situation is
ambiguous because most of the evidence about motivation often comes
only from the act of flag display itself. Hence the variation in judicial
and other public interpretations of 'contempt' towards the symbol -
leaving aside the debatable issue of the right of 'free speech' which
may be involved in personal use of a national flag. The 'distress
362 SYMBOLS
F L A G AS SYMBOL OF D I S S E N T
other partisan activity. The sponsor of the resolution argued that it would stimulate Black
consciousness and pride without lessening allegiance to the American flag; but critics held
that it was an unwarranted introduction of political symbolism into the educational system.
(New York Times, 2,3 and 5 December 1971; Time Magazine, 13 December 1971). The issue
was high-lighted by an earlier attempt in a Florida school to use a Confederate battle flag
pattern as a school banner (New York Times, 14 October 1971) which outside observers saw
as equally subversive.
S Y M B O L I S M OF F L A G S 365
the United States flag as a prime example because superficially in the
overt sacralization of its national symbol that country has gone
further than many others, and so invited more direct challenge by
those of its citizens who wished to protest. The United States posi-
tion in this respect may be a reflection of several circumstances: the
initial revolutionary character of the society; its development by
federation of a large number of discrete units; and its rapid absorp-
tion of many immigrants from diverse linguistic, cultural and
national sources. All this would make sense of concentration on some
easily identifiable symbols of national unity, and protection of them
from abuse. The United States flag has been described as 'a protec-
tive symbol' but it has also needed protection.
The Durkheimian type of proposition about national flag as focus
for sentiment about society, with sacred character, is valid to only a
limited degree. The 'sentiment5 has usually been interpreted as
positive, involving consensus. But in writing about Australian
aboriginal society, with totem as 'flag of the clan', Durkheim omitted
the political dimension. For totemic belief and behaviour the assump-
tion of positive sentiment and consensus was reasonable, though not
unchallengeable. But to cite as a parallel the national flag, or flag of
a military unit, was to ignore the significance of the power com-
ponent. A national flag of a modern state is an officially defined
symbol, not simply a symbol of informal public choice or traditional
development. As such, its 'sacredness' is an officially imputed quality.
Hence 'desecration' becomes a legal matter, to be judged in the light
of official pronouncements, either codified or expressed in the com-
mon law.
What is at stake in most of these cases of unorthodox use of a
national flag is the issue of legitimacy. The national symbol is mal-
treated as an instrument of protest against authority, to deny the
legitimacy of what that authority has done. It may express dissent
from a single type of action - such as involvement in overseas con-
flict - or it may represent basic disagreement with the structure and
ideology of the society as at present constituted. But in essence the
national symbol is manipulated to assert moral value over existing
power value. (That some of the issues may have been misconceived
is beside the point.)
Such critical use of national flags as symbols bears also upon the
366 SYMBOLS
SYMBOLISM IN GIVING
AND GETTING
* See for example the account by T. F. Mitchell (1957) of the language of buying and selling
in Cyrenaican shops and markets.
t For a recent study of ceremonial exchange among New Guinea 'big-men* see A. Strathern,
1971.
370 SYMBOLS
most men wish what is noble but choose what is profitable; and
while it is noble to render a service not with an eye to receiving one
in return, it is profitable to receive one (Blau, 1964, 88). It was sug-
gested by Mauss but demonstrated by M. I. Finley (1962, passim)
that antiquity indeed knew a period when gift-exchange was the
dominant mode of transaction. In modern times it has often been
pointed out that the tradition of 'one good turn deserves another'
underlies many of our social institutions, from sending of Christmas
cards to wedding invitations. Manning Nash has even gone so far as
to say that middle-class social life in the United States approximates
to the reciprocal-exchange systems of the Melanesian archipelago;
that among families of equal status, dinner invitations in number and
quality have all the essentials of exchange equivalents; and that if the
balance gets too badly disturbed there may be some show of aggres-
sion or the invitations may cease (Nash, 1966, 31).
In an even broader approach George Homans and Peter Blau
have sought to show, not just that giving is a part of exchange but
that the structure of social relations in areas right outside the market
field is an exchange structure. Homans has seen social behaviour as
an economy, with interaction between persons as an exchange of
non-material as well as material goods, and a pay-off in terms of cost
and reward. Blau is much more concerned with the polity of social
life, the status and power differentials which are the object of recipro-
cal social behaviour. (Cf. Ehrmann, 1970, for a striking analysis in
this field.)
In all this the theory of the gift has been brought into line with the
theory of market exchange. The gift relationship appears as a kind of
market relationship, in that a kind of cost-benefit analysis applies but
in different operational channels - less open to alternative offering,
a minimum of haggling, and an almost explicit admission of in-
tangible, non-material elements into the exchange situation. From
different angles, both Mauss and Homans have indicated this. Mauss
has stated (1925, 34) that the market is a human phenomenon
familiar to every known society. Primitive societies do not lack the
'economic market' - though their exchange patterns are different
from ours. And Homans has argued that his theory of social inter-
action as exchange is quite compatible with 'the special conditions of
exchange that economics chooses to confine itself to' (1961, 79). He
SYMBOLISM IN GIVING AND GETTING 37I
has said in his charmingly blunt style that he is out to rehabilitate the
'economic man', and that by broadening the range of values of
'economic man' he gets a greater realism into his propositions; that
the new economic man is just 'plain man'.
In the terms of such a theoretical approach the gift of flowers to
my wife, which I mentioned earlier, can be regarded as not just a
simple expression of goodwill to a stranger, but as an item in an
on-going series of social exchanges. My wife and I made the effort to
initiate a social contact. We used the occasion for a mild exercise in
Italian; and we diverted ourselves during the wait for a train - in
a very minor way we obtained social benefit from the encounter. But
so also did the station master's wife - she had momentary relief from
the fatigue of gardening; a fleeting acquaintance with the world out-
side to give food for gossip; and praise of her flowers to support her
self-esteem. Her present of a bunch of flowers could be seen then as
not just a courtesy but also as an acknowledgement of social service.
One can even introduce a principle of balanced opposition into the
analysis - her gift of garden flowers was the response of culture
and nurture to nature and casual exploitation.
Yet while one may have much sympathy with this type of inter-
pretation the monolithic exchange theory seems inadequate. One
need not accept the postulate of Karl Polanyi and George Dalton,
that the distinction between market behaviour and gift or gift-
exchange behaviour is so radical that ordinary concepts of economics
are useless in interpretation of 'primitive' economic systems (cf.
Firth, 1972). But the patterned differences between market process
and the passage of gifts are considerable. Among the criteria generally
involved are: a wider field of alternatives in choice in market rela-
tions; much less personalized ties as a rule in buying and selling
than in gift; a different range of sanctions for reciprocity, with much
more specific legal sanctions in the market;* and much more closely
specified equivalents in market exchange.
* Legal sanctions have not necessarily been absent from the field of the gift. In Britain
formerly it was an implied condition that the gift of an engagement ring was returnable in the
event of the marriage not taking place, unless it was the man himself, the giver, who refused
to marry. By an Act of January 1971, however, gifts made to each other by engaged persons
will normally be returnable only if they were made on the specific assumption that there would
be a marriage. A purely personal present such as an engagement ring is therefore not recover-
able - though conventional wedding presents are, since they are thought of as made on the
condition that the wedding takes place (see The Times, 6 June 1970).
372 SYMBOLS
C O N C E P T OF THE G I F T
The notion of the gift is complex, in several ways. The basic element
of a gift is an outgoing from the self, but this implies an input to
another. In judging the implications of a gift then, the effect upon
the other has to be taken in conjunction with the effect upon the self.
So, as F. G. Bailey and others have emphasized (Bailey, 1971,
23-4) all gifts, like all exchanges, have both competitive and co-
operative elements. A gift commonly involves the transfer of a
material object, or the performance of a service over time which
involves the displacement of material objects. But it is also com-
monly regarded as implying some immaterial quality, of positive
sentiment, of goodwill. In many conditions the material good or
service is regarded as not only the token but as even the measure of
the sentiment. Gifts are often judged not primarily as a contribution
to resources, but as an index to the attitude of the giver. In this
sense that which is seen, the gift, is a symbol of what is unseen, the
concepts and emotions of the giver. But it may not be a reflection of
a simple state: the giver may feel he is acting under pressure and
react later accordingly; he may be using the gift as a 'sprat to catch a
mackerel', to benefit by a larger counter-gift; he may be focusing on
the social rather than on the material aspects of the transfer and
looking to intangible benefits; he may be concerned with his own
reputation and only marginally with the recipient; he may envisage
his gift primarily as a statement of a moral position. The donor may
even see the gift as just an expression of himself in a general bene-
factor role. Max Beerbohm's remark that mankind is divisible into
two great classes, hosts and guests, might be translated into terms of
donors and recipients, and be regarded as valid in some people's
conceptualization.
By definition a gift is freely made. Any notion of duress is alien
to the concept. As Blackstone put it in his Commentaries 200 years
ago: 'gifts are always gratuitous; grants are upon some considera-
tion or equivalent'. A gift is a voluntary, non-contractual transfer of
property without any valuable consideration - in particular, without
any material equivalent being stipulated.
Each of these criteria, however, is capable of further interpreta-
tion. The notion of gratuitous transfer may be used as a disguise for
SYMBOLISM IN GIVING AND GETTING 373
all thou canst; High Heaven rejects the lore, of nicely calculated
less or more'-in the Ecclesiastical Sonnets -'Tax Not the Royal
Saint5. But perhaps the best example of poetic expression in this
line comes from a confessed pagan, Walt Whitman: 'Behold I do
not give lectures or a little charity - When I give, I give myself
(Song of Myself).
But commitment of the self is not necessarily without thought.
A text in the Douai Bible (Ecclesiasticus, 11) is cautious: 'Do good
to the just, and thou shalt find great recompense, and if not by him,
assuredly of the Lord.' Even in the New Testament there are dif-
ferences of emphasis. According to St Luke: 'Give and it shall be
given unto you; good measure, pressed down and shaken together
and running over shall men give into your bosom' (6: 38). So one
should give not because one has received, as St Matthew says, but
in order to receive - with forethought of the advantage to be gained,
which sounds just like the 'nice calculation' which Wordsworth so
scorned! Coleridge put it more coolly: 'We receive but what we give'
- from a poem perhaps appropriately named Dejection. And in his
Complaints Edmund Spenser listed the results of lack of calculation
more sadly - 'to spend, to give, to want, to be undone'.
There is clearly a paradox in this traditional literary field - giving
is good, but getting is not to be ignored. I am not concerned to
explain discrepancies in Biblical and other standard texts, but
literary wisdom, and presumably popular wisdom too, bear out the an-
thropological conception of reciprocity attaching to a gift. I examine
this aspect in more detail later. But if one distinguishes the symbolic
quality of a gift from its pragmatic quality, it is evident that insistence
on a pragmatic return may detract from the symbolic value of the
transfer. Underneath the paradox about giving and receiving, then,
may be a dilemma as to how far pragmatic components may be
supported, in the light of symbolic aims. This is where the formalism
of the gift has an important function.
F O R M A L I T Y OF GIFT-MAKING
what may further come if certain conditions are met by the recipient.
A Trobriand example of this is what Malinowski has described as a
'solicitary gift' (1922, 354), by which a man who hopes to secure a
valuable shell ornament in the kula distribution tries to make an
initial present of some smaller item to the immediate owner, with
the implication that he is ready to make the appropriate large gift
if he is successful. Interpretation of the donor's attitude may be
difficult - he may be supplicating from an inferior position for the
grant of the valuable, or he may be virtually issuing a command that
he expects it to be given to him. But in terms of socio-economic
relationship, the offer of the earnest has set up a bond of obligation
which the recipient must take into account even if he does not
accede to the donor's request. In Western society a small gift is
sometimes made as an earnest because a larger gift which is intended
or promised is not yet ready for presentation. Here the accent of the
earnest is on maintaining the character of the social relationship,
lest the recipient may think the donor promises but does not perform,
and modify his attitude accordingly.
Of the same general order as an earnest is a token gift. The two
terms are often merged, but as I indicate later, the concept of token
can also carry a more critical negative connotation. In common
usage one function of a token gift is to serve symbolically in overt
fashion. A small presentation is made, commensurate neither with
the resources of the donor nor with the needs of the recipient, but as
index of commitment. In itself this may be encouraging, as support
for the recipient's interests or conception of his own personality.
But in public affairs in Western society a token gift is often designed
as a means to stimulate other gifts, more substantial, or other com-
mitments which can lead to effective action. In a recent election
campaign in the state of Michigan, the chairman of a noted auto-
mobile firm sent $900 to aid the cause of a Democratic candidate. The
amount was small by comparison with other contributions, but it
was noted in a New York newspaper with the comment that 'in his
case, the symbolism was the main thing' {New York Times, 8
November 1970). Looked at as a serious campaign contribution
from such a multimillionaire source, the gift was ludicrous; but the
knowledge that this particular donor had engaged himself on the
candidate's side was presumably of great value to the campaign
S Y M B O L I S M IN G I V I N G A N D G E T T I N G 383
* Michel Panoff(i970,60-1) concedes that Mauss may have misread ethnographic accounts
at some points, but holds that this does not impair the theoretical results of his study of gift-
giving. But while it is true that Mauss's most general results are unaffected, his theory of the
relation of the gift to the personality of the giver is certainly distorted by his ethnographic
errors. Sahlins (1970) traverses Mauss's Maori ethnography and commentaries upon it, and
comes up with an ingenious (though I think misconceived) suggestion of his own about the
concept of hau which is central to this part of Mauss's work. Sahlins's rendering of the hau of
the forest as its fecundity, in my view, mistakes an indirect expression of a relationship for a
direct expression. It reminds me of my own concrete interpretation of the Tikopia concept of
manuy but the evidence is of a different order (cf. Firth, 1929, 412-15; 1967b, 174-94).
386 SYMBOLS
THE O B L I G A T I O N TO G I V E
fact, if there be any good deed, He will repay it doubly, says the
Koran, provided that it should not be given in order to be seen of
men. (Here is one form of reciprocity for an anonymous giver!) Yet
while approving gifts in general, Muslim law lays down quite
stringent conditions about them, particularly where they affect the
family (see Seymour Vesey-Fitzgerald, 1931, 201-2, 206-23).
Although a gift is gratuitous, the Muslim law regards it as always
made with an object in view - it is not a simple discard of property.
Gifts made to acquire merit in the sight of God have as object a
recompense in the next world. Worldly gifts are made to ingratiate
oneself with other human beings. A leading Muslim legal treatise
says of these that the object of a gift to a stranger is to get a return.
(It is lack of specification of return, and lack of contract for return
that makes the transfer a gift.) It is the custom to send presents to a
person of high rank that he may protect the donor; to a person of
inferior rank that the donor may obtain his services; and to a person
of equal rank that the donor may obtain an equivalent. All these
gifts are legitimate.
Gifts to acquire merit, if made without thought of worldly recom-
pense, may be given to people of one's own surroundings, even to
one's own kin. In fact, it is held that charity literally begins at home,
and properly so; gifts to members of one's own family are highly
approved by Islam. But here the interest of the law begins to emerge.
A gift to acquire merit cannot be used as a cloak for an act unpleasing
to God and the Muslim courts will reject it.
Moreover, to support the interests of the family, Muslim law
severely restricts freedom of testation. A person can leave by will
only one-third of his property, and legacies to heirs are severely
restricted in the interests of the equitable division of the property,
which is a cardinal principle of Muslim law. On the other hand,
Muslim law makes allowance for a special type of religious gift known
as waqf. In theory, this means putting an object in the category of
divine property so that the donor's right in it is extinguished and it
becomes the property of God to be used for the advantage of His
creatures. Such would be a piece of land donated for a religious
foundation. But since marriage and family life are the religious
obligation of every adult Muslim, a man's duty to his family takes
precedence over all other objects of his generosity. He can then make
SYMBOLISM IN GIVING AND GETTING 389
The symbolic qualities of the gift come out especially in the obliga-
tion to receive it. Even if on the material side a person may not need
* For further details see J. N. D. Anderson, 1959, 78-9; Snouck Hurgronje, 1906, II, 321;
J. Schacht, 1955, 82-3; Gibb and Bowen, I, pt 2,165-78; E. C. C. Howard, Minhaj et Talibin,
230-3.
39° SYMBOLS
others who might like to be their friends. Hence the various strata-
gems to evade gifts from people with whom one does not want to
intensify social relations. The obligation to receive is inhibited then
in the light of the further obligation - the need to repay, it being
understood that repayment may involve intangible as well as tangible
considerations.
From this point of view quite stringent limitations may arise on
the obligation to receive gifts, when differential status of the parties
involves the higher status person as recipient. There are two possible
interpretations of gift in such circumstances: that it is complimentary,
an acknowledgement of status as a kind of return for the general
symbolic role of the recipient; or that it is establishing a platform for
future benefit in goods, services or reputation from having social
contact with the person of high status. When gifts to modern
Western heads of state are in question, both interpretations may
apply, but it would seem that the danger of the second has led to
restriction. It is understood, for example, that presents sent to
members of the British Royal Family by private citizens not known
to them are normally returned, though presents from other heads of
state, public bodies, and their personal friends are not. While no
implication of reciprocity may be involved with the act of the private
citizen, the acceptance of the gift might be treated as the creation of a
personal link which might be invidious as regards other citizens.
The obligation to receive is not acknowledged because it runs coun-
ter to another type of obligation - not to discriminate among citizens
in what should be equality of general relationship to the Sovereign
and Royal Family.
With a head of state the status factor is of prime importance, since
in modern times no one is likely to think of any service that can be
secured by a gift to a member of the Royal Family. But in the broader
sphere of public role the obligation not to receive a gift may be much
more pointed. By the Civil Service regulations of most advanced
countries a civil servant is required not to accept gifts from people
with whom he may have technical relationships in the course of his
duty. Acceptance of a gift, or even of lavish hospitality, has at
times imperilled a politician's or a civil servant's reputation, led to
his resignation or dismissal from public office, or possibly brought
him to the brink of criminal prosecution.
392 SYMBOLS
and other themes, and I think came to respect each other - partly
perhaps because being more detached I could question his views
more stoutly than could his clergy. At last the time came for him to
land me on the beach of Tikopia and leave me to my fate. He had
shown me many kindnesses, which I could not repay. This was his
last trip on the Southern Cross; he was retiring from the Mission after
many years and we both knew it was unlikely we should ever meet
again - and we never did. As he said goodbye, leaving me alone in
this remote community he shook me firmly by the hand, said
gruffly 'No reciprocity!', turned his back and walked off down the
beach to the boat. This was his way of hiding his emotions with a
joke - but his words were also a reaffirmation of a moral viewpoint.
The Christian ethic in its basic postulates stresses the significance
of vicarious giving, of lack of thought for the interest of the self.
All major religions indeed include in their precepts some positive
approval of giving without thought of return. Of course this may be
wishful thinking. Notions of merit so acquired may be built into
the ideology. Ideas of reaping after sowing, and casting one's bread
upon the waters (or in a new version, shipping one's grain across the
sea) suggest fairly direct interest in output-input analysis on a
spiritual plane. As I have argued, one counterpart to giving in this
sphere is the maintenance of the dignity and integrity of the self.
While such compensatory theory may find little backing in modern
theology, it is clear that empirically, consistent selfless gift-making
is no more of an operative principle than is reciprocity. Moreover,
pragmatically, we tend to oppose any attempt to translate the
philosophy of complete self-sacrifice into ordinary social terms.
Anyone who might try to put into practice the principles of the
Sermon on the Mount would be regarded as eccentric; 'sell all you
have and give to the poor' is regarded as metaphor, not an injunction
to be taken literally. But such principles are not to be completely
dismissed from a sociological analysis.
Each society defines differently what acts should conventionally
be followed by a 'return'. In the West we have isolated par excellence
the economic, commercial field of buying and selling, and applied
it to most transfers of goods and services. From this range of
transactions is normally excluded, and termed gift, those which
operate especially in the domestic field, in kinship and friendship
402 SYMBOLS
SYMBOL AND
SUBSTANCE
In this book I have been examining some of the general ideas about
symbols held by anthropologists, or held by others and of possible
use to anthropologists. I have exemplified this examination by a
series of illustrations from some fields where public and private
symbolism seems to be closely inter-related: food; hair; flags; giving
and getting; greeting and parting. Each of these objects and actions
is meaningful symbolically to individuals personally as well as
collectively and socially. Unlike some of my colleagues, I argue that
important problems of interpretation and clues to understanding lie
in analysis of such intricate conjunction between the individual and
the collective symbolization.
The kind of illustrations I have taken bear for the most part on
issues of status. This was deliberate because I am convinced that
what I have called status-involvement is basic in a large number of
social arrangements, and comes to expression in highly sensitive,
elaborately patterned symbolic forms which are both individually
meaningful and socially validated. It has been said often enough that
the nature of life in society can be grasped only in symbolic forms,
and that people must use symbols to handle their problems of rela-
tionship with one another. For their actions to be effective, that is for
them to lead a viable social existence, the symbols they use must be
individually meaningful as well as collectively recognized. But
differences of interest lead to lack of agreement on symbolic mean-
ings as well as to manipulation of symbols in partisan fashion.
Broadly speaking, all the symbols of the kinds I have considered
may be said to represent the social order and the individual's place
in it. Food exchanges symbolize basic social relationships; mode of
wearing the hair makes a statement about the wearer's personality
and his attitude to established authority; hanging out a national flag
403
404 SYMBOLS
ETHNICITY OF JESUS
O
4io SYMBOLS
THE S A C R E D HEART
C O N C E P T OF S A C R A M E N T A L SUBSTANCE
bread and wine into the Body and Blood of Christ, in such a com-
plete manner that none of the substance of the bread or wine remains,
but only the species thereof... It implies t h a t . . . Our Lord's
Sacred Body comes, and is truly and really t h e r e . . . ' (compare
O'Neill, 39-40). The concept means basically that the accidents or
qualities of the bread and wine, which are perceptible to the senses,
continue to exist apart from, and without the support of, the sub-
stance of the bread and wine, which ceases and is replaced by the
substance (but not the sensory qualities) of Christ's body and
blood.
Various anthropological issues of interest arise from this concept.
It has certain parallels over a wide ethnographic field. Pagan Tikopia,
for instance, believed that every religious offering had in addition to
its material stuff, visible and palpable, an immaterial counterpart,
invisible and impalpable. They regarded this as in part a matter of
demonstration, as when fresh taro plants set out as offering on a
grave wilted; they argued that the immaterial counterpart of the
plants had been taken away by the spirits, leaving the solid part of
the offering behind. In ordinary terminology one might speak, as
I have been accustomed to do, of the visible part of the offering as
the substance, and the invisible counterpart as the essence. But in
Catholic terminology one might speak of the visible part as the
appearances (or accidents or species) and the invisible part as the
substance. Now both the pagan Tikopia and the Catholic theologians
have been faced by the same problem: how if the substance (essence)
be withdrawn can the appearance sustain itself? The Tikopia view
was less abstract - the material stuff suffers - but they bothered little
about the problem, attributing the whole phenomenon to the work
of spirits. The Catholic view has been to regard the persistence of
the bread and wine when deprived of their essential substance as a
matter altogether above the order of nature - 'part of the mystery
of the Real Presence which we do not pretend to fathom', as our
popular account puts it. The explanations are very similar.
In keeping with the sacred character of the Eucharistic rite, a
number of ritual precautions have been traditionally observed in
regard to it. The fitness of the priest to consecrate the Host, and the
fitness of the celebrant to receive it have been naturally the subject of
considerable regulation. And since partaking of the Eucharist means
SYMBOL A N D SUBSTANCE 423
communing not only with Christ but also with fellow Christians in
a common body, views have been expressed on who should be
allowed to share in the celebration. More specific ritual procedures
have also been closely specified. Traditionally, the wafer of un-
leavened bread has been placed by the priest on the tongue of the
celebrant; it has been taboo for the celebrant to touch it with his
hand. In some modern Catholic churches it has now been allowed for
a celebrant to take the host in his hand and place it in his mouth, and
an apostolic constitution issued by the Pope in 1953 relaxed some of
the rules for fasting before Communion. But while the sacred
proprieties seem capable of modification, an attempt is made to
preserve the sensory message of the Eucharist. Some modern
Catholic circles find it very important that celebrants shall still feel,
taste and smell bread and wine; that no violence be done to the
senses. A recommendation in a new Roman Catholic missal was that
the Host received by laymen during Holy Communion should
'really appear to be food'. In the New York metropolitan area in
1970 a new order of the Mass tried to bring the sacred rite closer to
the people inter alia by using real unleavened bread instead of the
former round small communion wafers that quickly dissolved on the
tongue without chewing. The idea of the real bread was to emphasize
that the rite was not only a memorial to the sacrifice of Christ but
also a communal meal. But there were technical difficulties. The
church requires the bread to be unleavened, and without yeast it is
hard to get the bread to rise. A suggestion to use Jewish matzoth as
in Passover, understandably, met with little favour. For some time
convents which made communion host experimented. Wafers made
from whole-wheat flour were found to be more tasty, but to
crumble easily; and the production change-over required to make
them needed new equipment that could be expensive for convents on
tight budgets. A large commercial concern in this field began
marketing 'unleavened altar bread', tiny baked cubes that could be
chewed; but some priests complained that these 'looked like break-
fast food' (patent commercial cereal). (See New York Times, 23
March 1970; Chicago Daily News, 16 November 1970.) So the search
for new recipes may still proceed. In parallel style, outside the
Catholic range, another concession to sensory elements occurred in
some Nonconformist circles which stressed teetotalism. Spurred on
424 SYMBOLS
CONCLUSION
429
43° REFERENCES
457
458 INDEX
Smith, Margaret 28911. 25-30, 5i-3, T7> 58, 62-3, 71, 74,
Smith, W. Robertson 59,107,115-16, 75, 83, 86, 90-1, 92, 124, 146, 161,
124, 132, 179, 394 170, 426-8; classification, 50, 174,
Social, context, see Contextualization; 212-16; definition, 15, 25, 34, 46,
drama, 194-5; structure, 25, 112, <>i, 75> 9°> 9 8 , " 5 , 137-8, 163,
163, 170, 184, 191-3, 197, 200, 187,192; dominant (master), 8 6 - 9 1 ,
207, 214, 240, 252, 254, 258, 260, 191, 211, 245-6; history of term,
390, 400, 426 47, 54; 'natural* symbolsl, 25, 49,
Somerville, J. 49m 58-60, 63, 98, n 5 , 169, 413-14;
Sorensen, B. A. 94n. logic* of symbols, 243, 252, 324,
Speech 143, 378; see also Language 419, 420-4; meaning for social
Speke, J. H. 319, 373m relations, 81, 82, 133-4, 163, 173-6,
Spencer, B. 125 190, 402, 427; systems, 67, 70, 146,
Spencer, H. 112 164, 202, 246, 252, 290, 298, 414;
Spencer, R. F. 54m validation, 237-40, 424; variation,
Spicker, S. F. 307m 214, 246, 323, 325
Spillius, J. 253 Symbolist movement 3 0 - 2 , 83, 105,
Spirit 26, 47, 58, 65, 79, 82, 114, 159, 126, 127, 131
171, 216, 217, 223, 250, 405, 422; Synaesthesis 72n.
medium cult 199, 210, 225, 295
Spiro, M. E. 54n. Taboo 136, 137, 138, 253, 272, 293,
Stanner, W. E. H. 132-3, 134, 201-2, 320, 329, 413, 423
366 Tarn, N . 125m
Status 88, 138, 152, 167, 169, 179, Tedlock, D . i25n.
185, 199, 200, 206, 210, 214, 248, Tennyson, A. 27on.
250-9, 261, 403; see also Flag, Theomyth 100
Gift, Greeting, Hair Thiers, J-B. 292
Stebbing, Susan 63, 64n., 66, 81 Thoene, P. 42
Stirling, W. G. ii9n. Thompson, M. 397
Structure see Social Structure; Symbol Thouless, R. K. 212
systems Thurnwald, R. 368
Structuralism 46,70,85,121,171,196, Tikopia 26, 34, 65, 79, 82, 115, 121,
198, 199, 243; see also Levi-Strauss i5on., 168, 173, 175, 185, 218, 228,
Stout, D. B. 386 306, 329, 342, 379, 3 8 5 ^ , 390,
Strathern, A. 294, 369m 414-16, 420, 422; food symbolism,
Strathern, Marilyn 294 244-61; hair, 272-3, 288, 293, 297
Suger, Abbot 40 Titmuss, R. 400
Sundkler, B. 220-1 Todas i5on., 2 8 3 ^ , 294m
Surrealism 44 Totemism 59, 131-4, 137, 152-3,
Swastika 120, 129, 152 168, 202, 209, 217, 252, 260, 330,
Symbol, anthropological approach 339, 421
INDEX 469
Trance 224, 238; see also Spirit Wannijn, R. 4o8n.
medium cult Ward, J. S. M. ii9n., 268n.
Trevor, E. 3i2n. Warner, W. L. 204, 416, 418
Trobriands 140, 144, I45n., 151-3, Wasche, E. io3n.
220, 221, 369; kula, 382, 397 Weber, M. 86
Tropology 49, 51 Weitman, S. 336m, 35on.
Trotter, W. 132 Werbner, R. 199
Trumbull, H. C. iion. 117-18, 179, Westermarck, E. 59, non., 122, 128
Weston, Jessie L. 125
Turel, A. 106 Westropp, H. M. 123
Turner, T. S. 166, 203-4, 272 Whatmough, J. 64n., 72m
Turner, V. W. 25, 27, 33n., 67, 68, White, T. H. 38, 173m, 286n.
8in., 82, 86, i25n., 155, 166, 170, Whitehead, A. N. 138
186, 189-95, 196, 199, 205, 209, Whitehorn, Katharine 266n.
214-15? 2 34, 244, 246, 405 Whitman, W. 33, 375
Turney-High, H. H. 263 Whittier, J. G. 343
Tylor,E. B. 27,102,108, n o , 111-15, Whorf, B. 172
131, 217, 294^, 309^ Wig 291-4
Wilde, O. 32
Unconscious 40, 60, 101-3, 149, 151- Wilder, A. 123
3, 170, 212, 217, 2i9n., 222, 225, Wilson, Edmund 35, 36
237; collective, 157 Wilson, Monica 27, 186-9, I 9 I > I92
Urban, W. M. 50-3, 190 Wilson, T. 120
Winter, E. K. io6n.
Valerian, J. 266, 285 Wissler, C. 129
Values 20, 28, 51, 56, 77, 79, 84, 89, Witchcraft 35, 68, 121, 161, 199, 207,
136, 145, 163, 164, 172, 184, 185, 218
196, 246, 371 Wolf, A. 69-70
Van Gennep, A. see Gennep Wordsworth, W. 71,375
Verlaine, P. 31, 32 Wundt, W. 153
Vesey-Fitzgerald, S. 388
Villon, F. 30 Yalman, N. 166
Virgil, 71, 27on. Yang, M. C. 69
Vivaldi, A. 75 Yonge, Charlotte 268, 271
Volkelt, J. I03n., 147, I48n. Young, Michael 89
Voss, J. V. 101 Young, Michael D. 244