Ha Joon Chang The Political Economy of Industrial Policy Palgrave Macmillan 1993
Ha Joon Chang The Political Economy of Industrial Policy Palgrave Macmillan 1993
Ha Joon Chang The Political Economy of Industrial Policy Palgrave Macmillan 1993
of Industrial Policy
Ha-Joon Chang
Faculty o.f Economics and Politics
University of Cambridge
Published in Great Britain by
MACMILLAN PRESS LTD
Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire RG2 l 6XS
and London
Cornpanies and representatives
throughout the world
vii
VIII Contents
Bibliography 157
lndex 173
This page intentionally left blank
Preface to the 1996 Reprint
While one writes a book because one thinks that one has something to
say that will interest more than just a handful of people, for an
unknown first-time author, it was still a wonderful surprise to find out
that The Political Economy of Industrial Policy has been doing suf-
ficiently well to justify a paperback edition. Since the book was
published, 1 have received a surprising number of responses from many
people through various channels. There were sorne predictable
reactions, be they positive or negative, but there were also sorne which
I did not expect when I wrote the book. And for sorne of these reactions
I felt the need to respond in order to clear up the misunderstandings.
Moreover, as sorne of the issues I discussed in the book have seen a
flurry of debate in recent years, 1 felt that I shou]d add a word or two on
the more recent developments.
First of ali, my use of the concept of transaction costs in analysing
the relative costs of different forrns of coordination invited a lot of
justified and unjustified criticism. One criticism was that transaction
costs are perhaps not as important as the costs of coordination failure
themselves, and therefore that my emphasis on transaction costs was
diverting attention from a more important issue. This was a response
that I anticipated at various places in the book, but perhaps I did not do
enough to prevent such misunderstandings. 1 was by no means suggest-
ing that the costs from coordination failures were less important than
the transaction costs involved in correcting them, but simply that
correcting coordination failures is not without cost, as it is assumed in
many economic theories.
Toe other criticism that I faced due to my adoption of the term
'transaction costs' was that I was advocating the purely 'self-seeking'
view of individuals, as many who use the concept tend to be, and that
partly as a consequence of this I failed to see other forrns of
coordination such as 'networks' which are at least partly based on non-
selfish, cooperative behaviours. This was, again, an unfortunate
misunderstanding. While I certainly did not explore the network as an
altemative coordination mechanism to the market or state intervention,
this was not because I believed that human beings are so selfish they
are incapable of spontaneous cooperation. As I keep emphasising at
various places throughout the book, especially in the first two chapters,
xi
12 Preface to the 1996 Reprint
12
12
I do not subscribe to the pure, 'self-seeking' view of individuals. The
reason why I did not deal with mechanisms of coordination based on
horizontal cooperation was partly because I did not have enough
expertise in the area, and partly because the book was on 'policy' by
the state. Indeed, whether the state can make its policy implementation
more effective through promoting cooperation among the relevant
agents is one interesting issue that we should look at in future.
In choosing to use the term 'transaction costs', and also the term
'New lnstitutional Economics', I had sorne misgivings myself. My own
definition of transaction is somewhat broader than that used by many
other authors writing in the tradition of the New lnstitutional
Economics, and refers to the costs of running the economy or, as I also
call in the book, the 'costs of coordination' (see Chapter 2, Section
3.1). And when the term also carried certain ideological baggages to
which I do not fully subscribe, such as its emphasis on opportunistic
individual self-seeking, 1 was not sure whether I should use the term.
On the other hand, 1 did not want to create another term in our jargon-
infested profession when there is an already accepted term which could
convey the meaning sufficiently, if not perfectly, well. Hence my
decision to use the term. Unfortunately, although somewhat predictably,
this brought about unnecessary misunderstandings amongst many readers,
but I still feel that my decision to use the term
'transaction costs' was, on balance, justified.
When one writes on arguably one of the most contentious issues in
modern economic debate, namely, industrial policy, one is bound to
face the problem that by the time the book gets known to people, the
debate has moved on. The book was finalised, except for minor
editorial changes, at the end of 1992, and there has been a good deal of
controversy in the area since then.
The most prominent of the recent debates was due to the World
Bank's East Asían Miracle Report, which was published in late 1993.
The so-called 'Miracle Report' stirred up a good deal of controversy on
industrial policy by arguing that such policy attempted in the East
Asían countries was largely ineffective, perhaps except in Japan, and
that it is not something that other developing countries can try anyway
because they do not have the administrative and other institutional
capabilities to carry out such a demanding policy. While there is no
need to repeat the detailed criticisms by many authors, including
myself, of the methodologies and empírica! validities of the Miracle
Report' s view on industrial policy, 1 feel that I should present a few
salient points in summary form (for details, see the articles published in
Preface to the 1996 Reprint xiii
References
XVI
Acknowledgements xvii
The quarter century after the Second World War was truly the 'golden
age' of capitalism (see Marglin and Schor (eds), 1990, and Armstrong
et al., 1991 ). Ali the major industrial countries in this period experi-
enced unprecedented growth with no serious inflation and near-full
employment, which resulted in a spectacular rise in general living
standards. This achievement was impressive enough to establish
Keynesian economic management, which dominated the economic
policy-making of the major industrial powers in this period, as the
ultimate way to runa viable capitalist system, or the 'mixed economy' .1
However the collapse of rapid growth and full employment in the
mid-1970s in most of the leading industrial economies was a rude
awakening to the fact that certain fundamental structural changes in
national and world economies occurred during the 'golden age'. The
rapid absorption of the agricultura) labour force into industries and
services eliminated surplus labour and created tight labour markets,
often with inflationary consequences. Investments in manufacturing by
multinational corporations emerged as an important form of ínter-
natíonal capital flow, and this, together with the lowering of barriers to
other forms of capital movements, made national economic manage-
ment much less effective, Japan became one of the world's leading
industrial countries and the East Asían newly industrialising countries
(henceforth NICs), that is, Hong Kong, Singapore, Taiwan, and South
Korea (henceforth Korea), becamc major actors in sorne world markets,
such as textiles, electronics, shipbuilding and steel. Together these
changes meant massive dislocations in the old heartlands of world
industrial production, that is, the 'rust belt' of the USA and the old
industrial centres of Western Europe, resulting in a fundamental
transformation in the map of wotld industries.
The rise of new-right ideas and the election of the Reagan and
Thatcher governments in the last years of the l 970s and the early
2 The Political Economy of Industrial Policy
The book is organised into four parts. The first chapter reviews the
Iiterature on state intervention. Without claiming to be exhaustive orto
be doing justice to ali individual theories, four groups of Iiterature are
reviewed, namely market-failure literature, contractarian Iiterature,
political-economy literature and government-failure literature. It is
argued that, even ignoring the moral and political reasons put forward,
respectively, by the contractarian literature and the political-economy
literature, we cannot fully accept the conventional case for state inter-
vention based on the existence of market failures because the very
process of correcting such failures may incur costs greater than the
efficiency gains from it, as the government-failure literature has
correctly pointed out.
In the second chapter we develop a new institutionalist theory of
state intervention. New institutional economics has largely concen-
trated on the theory of firm and contracts, but, as we wish to demon-
strate in this chapter, it can provide sorne interesting insights into the
question of state intervention. In this chapter we interpret the costs of
state intervention as transaction costs incurred ( 1) in policy decision
and implementation, and (2) as a result of the increase in the incentives
for the prívate sector to spend resources to change the property-rights
6 The Political Economy of Industrial Policy
The role of the state in the capitalist econorny has been one of the rnost
controversial issues in econornics since the birth of the discipline (Deane,
1989). Almost everyone agrees that the state has a role to play, but there
is little agreernent as to when and how it should act. Perhaps the reason
why there is such little agreement is that state intervention is a complex
phenomenon involving many contentious issues such as efficiency,
morality, power, liberty and legitimacy, to name justa few.
In this chapter we organise our discussion into four parts to rnake this
complex issue more tractable. In the first section we examine analyses of
market failure which are mainly concemed with the possible failure of the
market mechanism to achieve Pareto efficiency and with the state's role
in overcorning such failure. Then we turn to the politico-philosphical de-
bate on whether the state as a political entity should or should not inter-
vene to correct the market outcome, be such correction efficient or not in
some sense. Thirdly we consider the political econorny - both right-wing
and left-wing - literature, which asks whether it is correct to assurne that
the state serves sorne 'public' or 'social' purpose rather than individual or
group interests. Lastly we examine the govemment-failure literature,
which asks whether the state has the ability to intervene effectively,
whatever its intention is.
7
8 The Political Economy of Industrial Policy
tify state intervention.4 That is, even if there is a public (collective) good,
it is not clear whether the 'collectivity' to provide it should be the state.
As Olson (1965) argues, in a small group, optimal public-good provision
may be achieved without state intervention because in a small group it is
likely that there are individual members who gain so much benefit from
the public good concerned that they are better off providing thc good uni-
laterally (pp. 43-52). And even in a large group where this condition
does not obtain, state intervention is not always necessary. Public goods
may be optimally provided even in a large number setting, if sorne
'selective incentives' (Olson, 1965) in the form ofprivate goods provided
by 'political entrepreneurs' (Popkin, 1979) can overcome the free-rider
problem by bringing individual cost/benefit structures in line with the
social (or group) cost/benefit structure. Of course these arguments do not
allow us to conclude that the public-good problem can always be solved
by prívate initiatives. In many cases, the use of coercion by the state (for
example taxation) may be the only possible way to resolve the problem.t
1.i.3 Extemalities
transactions will be (or should be) adopted and under what conditions
non-market institutions, including state intervention, will be (or should
be) adopted, as new institutional economics has recently tried.
Sorne other anti-interventionists argue that correcting one set of
externalities leads to another. Friedman (1962), for example, has grave
reservations about state intervention based on the externalities argu-
ment - the 'neighbourhood-effects' argument as he calls it - pointing
out that: (a) it will in part introduce an additional set of neighbourhood
effects by failing to charge orto compensate individuals properly; and
(b) it creates externalities in the form of 'threatening freedom' (p. 32).
This is unconvincing since: (a) whether the gains from eliminating exist-
ing externalities are smaller than the losses from the newly-created
externalities cannot be determined a priori; and (b) unsolved external-
ities also mean the limiting of someone's freedom - the affecting in the
case of positive externalities, the affected in the case of negative ex-
ternalíties - because one party has the desire to trade but cannot
(recall that externalities are untraded interdependences).1 º
1.2 MORALITY: PATERNALISM AND CONTRACTARIANISM In
The moralistic argument for state intervention usually takes two forms.
Firstly, it is argued that the state may intervene in the provision of 'rnerit
goods', which are 'goods the provision of which society (as distinct
from the preferences of the individual consumer) wishes to encourage
or, in the case of demerit goods, to deter' (Musgrave and Musgrave,
1984, p. 78). Secondly, state intervention may also be justified if society
believes that market-type transactions are not morally acceptable in
sorne areas, for example blood donations or police services. In this case,
the argument goes, the state, as the social guardián, should remove such
activities from the domain of the market and conduct them itself.
13 The Política/
TheoriesEconomy
of State of
lntervention
Industrial Policy 13
13 13
of public goods and services. The third leve) involves changes in the
law itself, namely changes in the rules of the game. Unless there is a
unanimous case for changes in the basic rules of the game of society,
the role of the state should be either the enforcement of the rules of the
game - namely the protection of property (and human?) rights and the
enforcernent of voluntary contracts - and the provision of special goods
and services whose private provision will be suboptimal from the social
point of view - namely the provision of public goods.
Friedman, usually known as the anti-interventionist economist, states
that '[t]he role of government ... is to do something that the market
cannot do for itself, namely, to determine, arbitrate, and enforce the rules
of the game' (Friedman, 1962, p. 27). This view is similar to that of
Buchanan, but in fact Friedman is much more generous, if more vague,
about state intervention than the strict contractarians cited above. His list
of legitimate functions of the state is as follows: maintenance of law and
order, definition of property rights, service as a means whereby people
modify property rights and other rules of the economic game, adjudica-
tion of disputes about the interpretation of the rules, enforcement of con-
tracts, promotion of competition, provision of a monetary framework,
engagement in activities to counter technical monopolies and to over-
come neighbourhood effects widely regarded as sufficiently important to
justify government intervention, supplementation of private charity and
the private family in protecting the irresponsible, whether madman or
child (Friedman, 1962, p. 34).
more importantly, who has the right to decide who is responsible and
who is not, if there should be no supraindividual value? Secondly, there
is 'no intrinsic reason why individuals should always pursue their own
good or why they will always do so better than others can do it for
them' (Freeden, 1991, p. 89). As Goodin (1986) notes, people make
decisions on incomplete information, ignorance of their future prefer-
ences, ignorance of the full consequences of their own actions, deceptive
decision frameworks, the desire to avoid responsibility for risks. The
existence of implicit preferences for preferences (for example reckless
drivers and drug addicts are not to be seen as acting in their best inter-
ests) is another case in point. In such situations it is not clear whether
we should regard individual decisions as the manifestation of their
preferences, and therefore argue against ali intervention.
In contractarian philosophy it is argued that the state cannot be
regarded as being 'above' individuals, since it is a product of free con-
tracts between independent individuals. Contractarians hypothesise a
'state of nature' where ali individuals are free to make contracts but are
involved in a state of war against everybody else, which leads to the
need for the imposition of an extra-individual authority, through volun-
tary contracts, in the form of the state.
This 'state-of-nature' scenario is of course a fiction. During the his-
tory of mankind, the choice has been the one between one form of
authority and another, and not the one between anarchy and authority,
as the contractarians put it (for example Nozick, 1974). Even a cursory
look at the history of the last few centuries reveals that the building of
the modern state was largely initiated by rulers, and not by freely-
contracting indi viduals (Poggi, 1990). Moreover it is in contradiction to
historical truth to argue that market-type transactions brought about the
state - the opposite view is more correct. The market in its present form
is a newer form of social institution compared with other forros, includ-
ing the state. As Polanyi (1957) persuasively puts it, historical
experience shows us that:
[t]he road to the free market was opened and kept open by an
enormous increase in continuous, centrally organised and controlled
interventionism [emphasis added]. To make Adam Smith's 'simple
and natural liberty' compatible with the needs of a human society was
a most complicated affair. Witness the complexity of the provisions in
the innumerable enclosure laws; the amount of bureaucratic control
involved in the administration of the New Poor Laws which for the
17 The Political
TheoriesEconomy
of Stateof Industrial Policy
lntervention 17
17 17
The view that the state should be regarded as 'a dynamic independent
force' (Findlay, 1990, p. 195) with its own objective function that is
distinct from that of the society as a whole is not new. A stream within
the Marxist tradition, originating from Marx's Eighteenth Brumaire of
Louis Bonaparte (Marx, 1934), has recognised that a certain state may
acquire an 'autonomy' from society, if no class is powerful enough to
impose its will on the state (for example, Alavi, 1972).15 One strand in
the recently popular 'neoclassical political economy' goes a step further
and characterises the state as a 'predator', which, acting as a discrimi-
nating monopolist, develops a property-rights structure and a tax
system which maximise its 'profit' or net revenue (tax minus expend-
iture), if necessary at the expense of social productivity.16 Of course
neoclassical political economy recognises that revenue-maximisation
by the state is an exercise in constrained maximisation, since the threat
of takeover by an altemative ruler from within or without the country
imposes a competitive constraint (see North, 1981, ch. 3; Findlay,
1988; Eggertsson, 1990, ch. 10).
The view that the state may actas an entity with its own will (and greed)
is a useful antidote to the naive assumption of welfare economics that it
will correct market failures as soon as it finds them. Moreover, when the
traditional interest-group approach has treated the state as a black box in
19 The Political
TheoriesEconomy
of Stateof Industrial Policy
lntervention 19
19 19
1.3.4 Summary
1.4.2 Rent-Seeking
CONCLUSION
INTRODUCTION
The early debate on the role of the state was conducted in the tenns set
by welfare economics. The degree of market failure may have been
questioned, along with the moral legitimacy and the political intention
of state intervention, but no question was asked as to whether well-
informed (with welfare economics) and well-intentioned state interven-
tion can actually improve the efficiency of the economy by correcting
market failures. With the advent of the govemment-failure school the
terms of debate have considerably changed. Although the possibility of
improvement in efficiency through state intervention is still accepted
(except by sorne staunch free-marketeers who deny the existence of
market failures), now it is being asked whether the net outcome of such
intervention is efficiency-improving when state intervention itself
carries certain costs.
We think that the govemment-failure literature has provided a valu-
able corrective to the naive belief about the state held by sorne welfare
economists that, once we can somehow have a 'benevolent' state, it
will solve ali problems. However, as we pointed out in Chapter 1, we
are still left with one important question: Is there any way to correct
govemment failures, as there are ways to correct market failures'? The
first two sections of this chapter look at the infonnation and the rent-
seeking arguments exarnined earlier and suggest how govemment
failures may be remedied, if not completely eliminated. The last section
moves a step further and develops what we call a 'new institutionalist
theory of state intervention', which incorporares both the market-failure
and the govemment-failure perspectives and suggests sorne roles of the
state that have hitherto been neglected in existing literature.
33
34 Thelnstitutionalist
A New Political Economy of Industrial
Theory Policy
of State lntervention 35
34
able to secure the best decision. Whether this is the case depends upon
the nature of the decision.
People's perceptions of the world, which are bound to be incomplete,
tend to become biased according to their personal experiences. In more
practica) tenns, people tend to develop 'sub-goal identification'
(Simon, 1991). For example Simon (1979) found that '[tjhe business-
men's perceptions oí the principal problems facing the company ...
were mostly determined by their own business experiences - sales and
accounting executives identified a sales problem, manufacturing execu-
tives, a problem of interna) organisation' (p. 501). And when there
exists subgoal identification, it is not necessarily true that leaving the
decision to those al the locality will enhance global efficiency. When
the problem concemed is of a global nature, the top decision-maker, be
he/she the central executive of a firm or a minister of the govemment,
may identify the problem (and hence its solution) more correctly, not
because he is a superior being but simply because he does not have the
subgoal-identiñcation problem. lf the decision is about the global
efficiency of the economy (which is likely to be the case when a state is
contemplating an intervention), a centralised decision-making structure
may be a blessing rather than a curse.
One more point to be made is that the top-decision makers in the
state decision-making hierarchy should be assigned only strategic tasks
- that is, tasks which relate to the long-tenn direction of the economy
as a whole - and be allowed to delegate more routinised day-to-day
tasks to the lower-level decísion-makers.' In the organisational litera-
ture it is found that, when day-to-day tasks and more analytical tasks
were vested in the same decision-making unit, '[t]he pressure of regular
deadlines and the tasks of supervising clerical personnel usually [gives]
the day-to-day activities priority over equally important, but postpon-
able, analytic tasks' (Simon, 1982, p. 81). Given that any individual's
ability to process infonnation is limited, freeing the top-decision
makers from routinised decisions will enhance the overall ability of the
state to process infonnation.
2.1.2.2 Reducing informationa/ asymmetry
lf designing a decision-making structure that can secure rational de-
cisions at the lowest costs can alleviate the infonnation problem that
results from the limited ability of the state to collect and process informa-
tion, how can the infonnation problem due to asymmetric information
be reduced? As we discussed earlier, there are two kinds of infonnational
A New Institutionalist Theory of State lntervention 37
B
Bid Stay Out
payoffs to (A, B)
- 50) + 0.5 x [O - 50] = 0). However, if the two firms can write a
binding contract such that one of them will stay out of the contest, they
can acquire the rent without spending any resource, In this case the
social cost involved may be nil. Of course this simple example ignores
the fact that the possibility of such collusion will depend on the
feasibility of making credible commitments, the possibility of side
payments, and other conditions related to bargaining (for a more
detailed discussion of these conditions, see Schelling, 1960), but it
shows that non-competítive rent-seeking is likely to incur less rent-
seeking costs than a competitive one due to the inherent likelihood of
collusion.
The above discussion shows that when the rent-seeking process is less
competitive, it is more likely that the total costs arising from the
process are lower. This happens basically because there exist entry
barriers into the rent market. Of course, one may argue that resources
will still be wasted even in the case of non-competitive rent-seeking
because people will spend resources to build up entry barriers to the
rent market. We agree that this is sometimes the case - for example I
may spend resources in building personal ties with the industry minister
in order to build barriers against future rent-seeking contests. However,
in a world with imperfect foresight, the scope for such action may be
seriously limited - 1 cannot be sure how helpful the minister will be in
a later, and unforeseen occasion when I want to bid for a rent.I?
Even if the entry barriers to the rent market are sufficiently high that
there are few rent-seeking costs, there may be costs from 'second-tier'
rent-seeking if the state distributes the rent extorted through franchise
bidding or bribery (see Chapter 1.4.2). For example, if the rent extorted
by the state is distributed to bureaucrats in the form of higher salaries,
and if anyone can become a bureaucrat with a certain educational
qualification, people may invest an excessive amount of resources in
education.11 Likewisc, if the state extorts sorne part of the rent in the
form of, say, bribery and distributes it in the form of tax cuts, which are
up for grabs by any interest group, interest groups will spend resources
to secure such rents. These examples of second-tier rent-seeking, how-
ever, still assume that there is unlimited entry al at least one leve) of the
political economy. However, if entry is contained at sorne level and if,
as a result, competition does not overflow into other levels, the rent
extorted by the state may not be tota11y dissipated. And although this
outcome may have undesirable política! and distributional conse-
quences, it may be a less wasteful outcome. For example, if entry into
44 TheInstitutionalist
A New Political Economy of Industrial
Theory Policy
of State Intervention 44
44 44
the bureaucracy is open only to a tiny minority, or if only the most
powerful group is able to secure a new tax cut, there may be no second-
tier rent-seeking and hence no rent-seeking cost to society, although
income distribution may become skewed as a result.
If transaction costs are the costs incurred for the purpose of defining
and redefining the property (and other) rights of economic agents, on
the one hand, and of writing, monitoring and enforcing contracts within
the existing rights structure, on the other hand, the costs of state inter-
vention may also be reinterpreted as transaction costs. Informational
costs, which are costs necessary for the state to decide on a policy and
effectively implement it, are obviously of this kind (analogous to such
costs for private contracts). Costs of rent-seeking, as costs involved in
the process of redefining the property rights structure, can also be class-
ified as transaction costs (see Chapter 1.4.2; see also Varian, 1989;
º
Milgrom and Roberts, 1990).2 Reinterpreting the costs of state ínter-
vention as transaction costs allows us to make sorne important observa-
tions in relation to the theory of state intervention.
B
Left Right
A
Right (0, O) (1, 1)
Payoffs to (A, B)
B
VHS Beta
A
Beta (O, O) (1, 2)
Payoffs to (A, B)
In order to achieve the coordinated outcome, the state need not com-
pletely supersede market transactions, as in our examples above. lndeed
such an exercise may be prohibitively costly, as the examples of central-
planning practice in the socialist countries show (Coase, 1988; for
further references, see Chapter 1.4. l ). There exist ways in which the state
can reduce the transaction costs in the economy without necessarily
superseding all market transactions.
First of all, the state can reduce the transaction costs within the
economy by changing the institutional configuration of society. The
state can provide legal backing to organise agents into large groups and
thus reduce the number of necessary bargainings (and consequently the
transaction costs involved). Social corporatism in Scandinavia or
Austria, whereby the workers and capitalists are respectively organised
into encompassing organisations and conduct nationwide bargaining, is
a good example of this - although the transaction-cost aspect of social
corporatism has been little discussed (see the Introduction to this book
for references).24
Secondly, the state can intervene, through its influence on the educa-
tion system and the mass media, to promote a national 'ideology' or
value system, which will help to reduce the costs involved in the ex-
change of infonnation and bargainíng.P As Arrow (1974) observed, it
is 'easier to communicate with other individuals with whom one has a
common approach ora common language' (p. 42), and therefore con-
tracts between agents sharing the same ideology will reduce the
bargaining, monitoring and enforcement and other transaction costs
required (North, 1981, ch. 3).26 This is obviously what people have in
mind when they say that a homogeneous society like Japan or Korea is
easier to manage than a heterogeneous one like the USA or India.
Although this role of the state may be objected to on the ground that it
can be used to foster 'false consciousness' and other undesirable
qualities among the people, it is undeniable that an ideological
campaign can pJay a tremendously important role, as can be seen in its
A New Institutionalist Theory of State Intervention 53
CONCLUSION
55
56 The Política/ Economy of Industrial Policy
Despite the fact that industrial policy, far from being a novelty of East
Asia, has been an integral part of economic policies of many advanced
capitalist countries during the post-war period, it has become an
important issue only recentiy. In the English-speaking world the OECD
has been the pioneer in this area (see the series of country studies
published by OECD in the early 1970s). In the UK industrial policy
became a controversial issue with the (not hugely successful) intro-
duction of industrial policy programmes by the Labour government in
the late 1970s. l The famous UK deindustrialisation debate also, to a
degree, discussed industrial policy as a possible way to halt deindus-
trialisation and revive the economy.2 During the 1980s, studies of
various European countries' policy responses to the industrial crisis of
the late 1970s also emerged.' The issue of industrial policy, however,
has probably been most hotly debated in the USA, especially in the
early 1980s, with the Harvard Business Review as the major forum.4
The recent rise in strategic-trade-policy literature has also been heavily
influenced by (and has influenced) the industrial-policy debates.5
A major problem with industrial policy issues is that the very concept of
industrial policy is not clearly defined, resulting in heated but often
fruitless debates. A good example of this is the discussion on the postwar
Japanese experience, which inspired many of the industrial-policy
debates. Opponents of industrial policy point out that subsidies and
govemmental loans to industries in Japan are small (in relative terms),
even smaller than in many European countries, and on this ground claim,
as the title of one article goes (Trezise, 1983), that 'industrial policy is
not the major reason for Japan' s success'. Proponents of industrial policy
argue that the non-quantifiability of the famous Japanese 'administrative-
guidance' system makes people underestimate the success of Japanese
industrial policy (Boltho, 1985). Unless we define what we mean by
industrial policy, we cannot judge who is correct and who is not.
'a situation in which ali the facts are supposed to be known' leaves 'no
room whatever for the activity called competition' (p. 182).13 He argues
that '[t]he peculiar nature of the assumptions from which the theory of
competitive equilibrium starts stands out very clearly if we ask which
ofthe activities that are commonly designated by the verb "to compete"
would still be possible if those conditions were ali satisfied ... Advert-
ising, undercutting, and improving ("differentiation") the goods or
services produced are ali excluded by definition - "perfect" competition
means indeed the absence of ali competitive activities' (Hayek, 1949b,
p. 96).
lf the market fails to sol ve the coordination problem and if such failure
can produce waste, there is a case for non-market, or ex ante, coordina-
tion (Pagano, 1985, ch. 8). As new institutional economics demon-
strates, the firm (or the hierarchy, in Williamson's words) is the most
representative form of non-market coordination, but other diverse
forms of non-market coordination mechanisms exist. As Winter (1988)
puts it, '[m]arkets appear and disappear; firms expand in scope and then
turn back toward specialisation; quasi-firms and quasi-markets prolif-
erate' (p. 168).18 Central planning is also an institutional device to
solve the coordination problem (Richardson, 1971), and industrial
policy is another such device.
such contracts, and there is a case for state intervention. Orderly exit or
capacity-scrapping arrangements organised or assistcd by the state can
take the following forros.
First of ali, sorne firms can exit altogether in return for sorne side-
payments. Side-payment may take the form of direct compensation by
the remaining firms, as seen in the Japanese textile industry in the early
1980s (Dore, 1986).21 State subsidies may quicken the process, espe-
cially when negotiations over side-payments prove difficult. Mergers
can also make ít easier to devise side-payment schemes, as seen in the
reorganisation of the French chemical industry (Hall, 1987, pp. 208-9).
Side-payment can also take the form of an increase in a firm's share in
other markets in return for exit from one market. This option may be
feasible if the firms concerned belong to larger entities simultaneously
operating in multiple markets (for example conglomerates) - the 1980
industrial reorganisation programme in Korea is a good example of this
(see Chapter 4.4.2).
Secondly, ali firms can scrap sorne of their capacities according to
sorne norm, for example according to each firm's share in total
industrial capacity or according to its market share. The best examples
are seen in the capacity-scrapping arrangements in the Japanese
aluminium, shipbuilding, textile, petrochemical and steel industries in
the 1970s and the 1980s (Dore, 1986, p. 142; Okimoto, 1989, p. 110).22
The advantage of capacity scrapping over an exit arrangement is that it
can improve the vintage structure of capital, thus raising overall
productivity (on the vintage effect, see Salter, 1960). A capacity-
scrapping arrangement may need state intervention more than an exit
arrangement does because it is more difficult to monitor the compliance
of the parties involved. lt is fairly obvious whether a firm is in
operation or not, but it is difficult to observe whether a firm really has
scrapped its capacity. The presence of government inspectors in
capacity-scrapping processes, as in sorne Japanese capacity-
scrapping arrangements, may help to solve this problem (see Dore,
1986).
Thirdly, there is the interesting practice of 'mothballing', defined as
stripping equipment down and concreting in the mountings so that it
requires a good deal of time and effort to rehabilitate it, as practiced in
Japan (Dore, 1986, p. 142). This mitigates the problem of credibility
that is inherent in recession cartels by making cheating costly. However
it keeps open the option of returning to the former levels of production
if necessary (although ata cost) and therefore avoids the risk of scrap-
70 The
The Political
Political Economy
Economy of
ofIndustrial
Industrial Policy
Policy 70
70 70
In the first part of this section we discussed why the market mechanism
may fail to solve the coordination problem, and why coordination fail-
ures can be costly. In the second part we discussed how state ínter-
vention can prevent and/or redress coordination failures. lnvestment
coordination, recession cartels and negotiated exit/capacity scrapping
were examined.
Common to all these forms of industrial policy is the problem of
strategic uncertainty. Of course the existence of strategic uncertainty does
not necessarily mean that state intervention is the optima! solution. After
ali many non-market institutions enable long-range planning by reducing
strategic uncertainty (Schumpeter, 1987, pp. 102-3; Eatwell, 1982,
p. 210).24 Long-term supply contracts, technological cooperation and
vertical integration between firms all fall into this category (Richardson,
1972). In a situation of strategic uncertainty, making one's commitment
credible is vital in working out a coordinated outcomc. And, as we
argued, state intervention can help overcome the problem of credibility in
such situations. Investment coordination by the state is a way of avoiding
overinvestment and underinvestment due to the difficulty of making
71 The
The Political
Political Economy
Economy of
ofIndustrial
Industrial Policy
Policy 71
71 71
may cut sharply the transaction costs involved in such contracts. Such
intervention need not involve financia! resources such as subsidies. As
we discussed earlier, govemmental announcements (for example the
French and East Asian 'indicative-planning' exercise) may suffice if
they can provide obvious focal points for coordination between com-
plementary investments (see Chapter 2.3.2).36 Financia! incentives
provided by the state, say, for cooperative research in new industries,
although not necessary, may make the state's commitment to its
announcement more credible by serving as a signalling device (Porter,
1990, ch. 12). Thus seen, industrial policy that coordinates comple-
mentary investment decisions may be essential for economic change in
a world of interdependence, rather than be an obstacle to it.37
In the first half of this section we discussed the nature of change in the
capitalist economy. We argued that the process of change in the capital-
ist economy is best characterised as a quasi-biological evolutionary
process whereby the agents can and do change both their own 'genes'
(behavioural characteristics) and the selection mechanism (or environ-
79 The Political Economy of Industrial Policy 79
79 79
two major elements in this argument (also see Chapters 1.4.1 and 2.1 ).
First of ali, it is argued that the state does not possess enough informa-
tion to decide correctly on the future industrial structure of the econo-
my. This is, according to our earlier classification, the problem of
'insufficient information'. Secondly, it is argued that the state is at an
informational disadvantage vis-a-vis the firms that are subject to indus-
trial policy. The firms, the argument goes, may use their informational
advantage to extract more than they deserve on social grounds (a moral
hazard problem). This is the problem of 'asymmetric infonnation'.
With the exception of sorne staunch free-marketeers (for example,
Burton, 1983), those who employ informational arguments (for exam-
ple, Caimcross et al., 1983; Grossman, 1988; OECD, 1989) support a
generalised industrial policy targeted at certain types of activities rather
than at particular industries (for example, investment, R&D), against
selective industrial policy - the type of policy we defined as industrial
policy proper at the beginning of the chapter. If the state has ali the
relevant information, the argument goes, particularistic interventíons
may work, but since this is unlikely to be the case, the state should
support productive behaviour in general rather than pick the winners on
the basis of incomplete information (Price, 1980; Líndbeck, 1981 ).
can be justified. After ali, large modem corporations carne into being
despite the dangers of the principal-agent problem, because there are
ways of controlling managerial excesses (see Chandler, 1962). And
likewise there are ways and means to reduce informational asymmetry
between the state and firms (see Chapter 2.1.2).
Secondly, the problem of asymmetric information is not unique to
industrial policy as defined by us, but it applies to other policies too.
Moreover, general industrial policy, which its supporters assume to
have no moral-hazard problem due to asymmetric information (for
example Corden, 1980, pp. 182-3; Balassa, 1985, p. 319), may suffer
even more acutely from such a problem. As contracts become more and
more general, the contingencies to be considered become more and
more numerous, resulting in prohibitive transaction costs in drawing up
effective contracts. This means that general industrial policy can be
compromised by unforeseen contingencies. An interesting example is
the US 1981 tax-code provisions, which were originally intended to
boost industrial R&D but ended up subsidising advertising firms
(Lawrence, 1984, p. 140, n. 45). Industrial policy, as defined by us,
being particularistic in its nature, tends to involve contracts that are
more custom-designed and hence allow fewer unforeseen contingencies
and less moral hazard. The use of plan contracts with specified targets
between the state and individual firms in France is the best example of
preventing moral hazard through the use of custom-designed policy
(see Hall, 1987, p. 207).
Thirdly, the asymmetric-information argument assumes that local
information is always better than global information because it is more
finely-meshed.O However, as we pointed out earlier, people with
localised information may make a substantively less rational decision
due to the subgoal-identification problem (see Chapter 2.1.2). lf the aim
of industrial policy is to improve the efficiency of the economy as a
whole, it may actually be better, under certain circumstances, not to be
affected by the localised information possessed by the firm. Especially
when the decision involves extemalities that are not borne out by the
firm, the state can make a better decision solely due to the more global
nature of its information, and not because it is a superior being.
3.4.3.1 Legitimacy
Sorne may argue that industrial policy should not be used because it
undennines the legitimacy of the state. First of all, by opening the door
for special interests, industrial-policy practice can erode the image of
the state as a social guardian and therefore make people question its
intentions.47 Secondly, industrial policy gives bureaucrats the power to
allocate property rights and hence creates scope for bureaucratic
corruption. In addition to its efficiency consequences (for example an
industrial license may go to an inefficient producer), corruption may
have consequences for the legitimacy of the political system (Krueger,
1990, p. 18). lf industrial policy may endanger the legitimacy of the
political system, should we not refrain from it, whatever its efficiency
gains may be?
Against this view, it should firstly be pointed out that sorne degree of
bureaucratic control is necessary for any society of reasonable sophis-
tication, because 'many decisions have to be taken in response to rapid-
ly changing situations and cannot, except at the cost of total stasis and
chaos, be "left" until a highly democratic decision-rnaking process has
been completed. Almost immediately then, in any real situation it
becomes necessary to delegate powers from larger, more democratic
bodies ... to smaller, more "efficient" bodies. However, once such
delegation has occurred, a great deal of the real day-to-day decision-
making power is taken out of democratic channels and placed in the
hands of small minorities which may then be beyond the effective
control ofthe larger bodies' (Kitching, 1983, p. 39). That is, there may
be a certain trade-off between democratic control and efficiency in
decision-making. However no a priori criterion can tell us which mix
of democratic control and efficiency - including the one existing in an
industrial-policy régime - is the most desirable.
87 The Political Economy of Industrial Policy 87
87 87
its interventionist and 'modemising' attitude, was famous for its laissez-
faire and 'anti-modern' attitude before the Second World War (Cohen,
1977; Kuisel, 1981). Toe well-known Swedish labour-capital consensus
emerged in a relatively short period of time out of one of the most
contested industrial relations in Europe of the 1920s (Korpi, 1983).
Moreover learning from other countries with different institutions
does not necessarily mean that a country has to exactly copy their
institutions. lt is often possible to create functional equivalents of
foreign institutions. For example the Swedish 'active labour-market
policy' and Japanese lifetime employment are very different institu-
tional arrangements, but they are functionally equivalent in creating a
positive attitude among workers toward technological change by
guaranteeing them jobs. In this regard, the following quotation from
Dore ( 1986) is well worth consideration:
[Learning from the Japanese experience] need not mean that we [the
British] have to become Japanese, absorb the Confucian ethic, or
raise our sense of national identity to the Japanese levels. What it
does mean is that we should ask ourselves whether there are not
other ways in which sorne of the things which Japanese institutions
and traditions achieve for the Japanese might be obtained by other
methods, other institutional arrangements, more consonant with our
own tradition. If close co-operation and consultation between mana-
gers and workers seems to be a precondition for rapid innovation in
manufacturing firrns, and if it is difficult to achieve this, given our
adversaria! traditions, what forrns of industrial democracy or work-
place decision-sharing might substitute for the easy acceptance of
bureaucratic hierarchy which facilitates co-operation in Japanese
firrns? If we cannot have, and do not want, lifetime employment to
be the norrn, if we want to preserve a more mobile system with the
greater personal freedom which that provides, can we at the same
time devise schemes which would give British employers the same
incentive to invest in training their employees as the lifetime
employment expectation gives Japanese employers? If the crucial
aspect of the Japanese system of financing industry seems to be the
way in which it facilitates long-term planning and investment, and
reduces preoccupations with next year's bottom line, is there any
way in which our own financia! institutions could be mended to
achieve the same effect, without necessarily modeliing our stock
exchange on Japan's? If inflation control in Japan crucially depends
89 The Political
The Política/ Economy
Economy of
ofIndustrial
Industrial Policy
Polícy 89
89 89
CONCLUSION
The common reaction to the argument for industrial policy has been
one of suspicion and incredulity. The opponents of it regard industrial
policy either as a bureaucratic meddling that is at best irrelevant - for
example, 'Industrial policy is not the major reason for Japan's success'
(Trezise, 1983, tille) - or as a peculiar form of state intervention that
works only in countries with a particular culture - for example, 'Indus-
trial policy: It can 't happen here' (Badaracco and Yoffie, 1983, title).
Such reactions are more than understandable when thinking that
orthodox economic theory hardly recognises any form of coordination
other than the idealised perfect market and ignores the role of
endogenous technical change and learning.
However, as we have tried to show, industrial policy is a policy
practice that can be firmly anchored in economic theory if we incor-
porate recent developments in economic theory that take seriously the
issues of institutional diversity and technical change. As a coordination
mechanism, industrial policy can be most efficient in a context where
interdependence and asset specificity are important. In this context,
coordination through the market would incur high bargaining costs and
coordination through central planning high information costs, while
industrial policy is likely to incur little of both types of cost. When we
take the issue of technical change into account, industrial policy also
emerges as a superior way to promote it. Industrial policy does not kili
off the profit motive - which is the most irnportant, if not the only,
driving force behind technical progress - as central planning would,
and, through the socialisation of risk, it can promote changes that are
additional to what the market can produce on its own.
Industrial policy, needless to say, is no panacea. Like any other
policy, or any other form of economic coordination, it has its own costs
and benefits. Its benefits seem to have more than offset its costs in
success stories like thosc of Japan and Korea, but we have plenty of
other examples that show that its costs may overwhelm its benefits. The
90 The Political
The Política/ Economy
Economy of
ofIndustrial
Industrial Policy
Polícy 90
90 90
real question is not whether industrial policy can work or not (because
it does), but how it can be made to work. In this chapter we have tried
to provide sorne theoretical grounds for identifying the economic,
political and institutional conditions under which industrial policy
would work and have suggested sorne ways and meaos to achieve
them. The next chapter, which looks at the Korean experience,
demonstrates how they have been achieved in practice.
4 Industrial Policy in
Action - The Case of
Korea
INTRODUCTION
91
92 The Industrial Policy in of
Political Economy Action - Korea
Industrial Policy 92
92 92
Since the early 1960s Korea has shown a truly remarkable economic
performance in terms of growth and structural change. Between 1965 and
1986 Korea's annual per capita real GNP growth was 6.7 per cent
compared with that of 2.9 per cent for the developing world as a whole
(World Bank, 1988, Table 1 ). Table 4.1 compares the growth perform-
ance of Korea since i 950 with that of other leading developing countries
- Taiwan, China, India, Argentina, Brazil, Chile and Mexico - and of
three OECD countries that were at relatively low levels of development
in the immediate post-war years - Japan, Italy and Austria. Although the
Korean growth performance was respectable before 1964, it was not
particularly outstanding. However from 1964 its growth accelerated and,
especially in the inter-oil-shock period (1973-9), its growth performance
exceeded that of all other countries in our sample, including Taiwan, the
world's best growth performer in the post-war period.
Mexico (8.7 per cent), India (4.5 per cent), Greece (9.7 per cent) and
Spain (10.8 per cent). Thanks to the country's ambitious heavy and
chemical industrialisation (HCI) programme launched in 1973 (see 4.4.1
below for details), the growth of the Korean manufacturing sector
accelerated even further between the two oil shocks (1973-8), a period
when most other major NICs experienced a substantial slowdown in
their manufacturing growth. In the ten-year period following the second
oil shock (1979-88), Korea's manufacturing growth slowed down to
11.7 per cent, due to reasons such as the slowdown in world-demand
expansion after the end of the 'golden age', the growing maturity of the
economy (reduced catching-up effect), and the substantial restructuring
of the economy in the ear!y half of the l 980s. However this was still an
Table 4.2 Manufacturing growth in sorne selected developing countries
(average annual growth rates)
1 . For 1 963-69
2. For 1 965-80
3. For 1980-87
4. For 1966-72
Sources: UN, The Growtb of World lndustry, 1973; UN, Yearbook of
Industrial Statistics, 1979, 1988; World Bank, World
Development Report, 1988 (for China).
Source: UN, The Growth of World lndustry, 1969, 1973; UN, Industrial
Statistics Yearbook, 1975, 1978, 1979, 1987, 1988.
97 The Industrial Policy in of
Political Economy Action - Korea
Industrial Policy 97
97 97
within the manufacturing sector. As we can see in Table 4.4, the heavy
industries - International Standard Industrial Classification (ISIC)
numbers 37 and 38 - which grew much more slowly than the manu-
facturing sector as a whole between 1963 and 1972 (13.9 per cent per
annum as opposed to 17.0 per cent per annum), started to grow rapidly
with the launch of the HCI programme and showed an incredible growth
performance of 39.5 per cent per annum between 1973 and 1978 - as
opposed to around 18 per cent per annum for other industries. Even after
the slow down caused by the advent of the 1979-80 recession (for
details, see Chang, 1987), heavy industry continued to grow at a much
faster pace than the chemical and the light industries (17.4 per cent per
annum as opposed to 8.1 per cent per annum and 7 .6 per cent per annum
respectively between 1979 and 1988). As a result the share of heavy
industry in total manufacturing output (in current prices) rose from 16.4
per cent in 1963 to 42.0 per cent in 1987 (calculated from UN Yearbook
of Industrial Statistics, 1969, and Industrial Statistics Yearbook, 1988).
Since the launch of the HCI programme, chemical industry has also
shown slightly faster growth rates than that of light industry, increasing
its share in total manufacturing output from 17.l per cent to 20.l per
cent during the same period.
Toe magnitude of Korea's intramanufacturing structural change can
be put into perspective by comparing it with that of Taiwan. Despite the
fact that the Korean economy grew more slowly than that of Taiwan
(see Table 4.1), Korea experienced an intramanufacturing structural
change of a greater magnitude than that of Taiwan. Table 4.5 compares
Korea's intramanufacturing structural change with that of Taiwan
between 1965 and 1984. In this period, the share of heavy and chemical
industry in total manufacturing output rose by 48.7 per cent in Korea
(from 38.2 per cent to 56.8 per cent), whereas that in Taiwan rose by
only 17.5 per cent (from 49.8 per cent to 58.5 per cent). Even when
Table 4.5 Intramanufacturing structural change in Korea and Taiwan,
1965-84 (percentages)
With the accumulation of studies that revea) the important role of the
state in Korea, the fonnerly common interpretation of the Korean
developmental experience as a free-market and free-trade economy is
rapidly losing its popularity.1 However it is useful to discuss briefly the
argument because the more recent mainstream interpretations examined
below (4.2.2) can be seen as atternpts to rescue the conclusions of the
carly interpretation.
According to the free-market view, the Korean economy stagnated in
the late I 950s after it had depleted the possibility of 'easy irnport-
substitution' in non-durable consumer goods. This inward-looking
strategy was trammelled with inefficiencies due to distortions generated
by excessive state intervention in various markets. Such chaotic import
substitution with multiple exchange rates and across-the-
board protection, largely by the use of discretionary quantitative
restrictions rather than universal tariffs, allowed inefficient firms to
survive and discouraged export activities. This in tum added to the
foreign-exchange shortage and hence to pressure for more import
res trictions.
99 The Industrial Policy in of
Political Economy Action - Korea
Industrial Policy 99
99 99
Fourthly, there were many state supports for import substitution, for
example subsidised credits to import-substitutors and the purchasers of
sorne domestic products (especially machinery), which in effect acted
as import restrictions. Lastly, and most importantly, there was
widespread foreign-exchange rationing, which often meant that
importation of a certain ítem was impossible not because it was illegal
to do so, but because it was impossible to obtain the foreign exchange
to pay for it.
Table 4.6 Real interest rates in Korea, 1960-84 (percentages)
Period Unregulatedfinancial market! Deposits? Export loans
Note: Toe series between 1953 and 1970 and the series between 1970 and
1986 are not fully compatible due to changes in the accounting method.
Source: BOK, National Accounts, 1987.
Jrulustrial Policy in Action - Korea 101
Evidence shows that state intervention was pervasive in Korea during its
rapid industrialisation period. As Bhagwati (1987) correctly argues, '[t]he
key question then is not whether there is govemmental action in the Far
Eastern economies, but rather how have these successful economies
managed their intervention and strategic decision making in ways that
domínate those of the unsuccessful ones' (p. 285). And, naturally, sorne
neoclassical economists, including Bhagwati hirnself, have put forward
explanations of the Korean experience that try to reconcile the existence
of an interventionist state with the rapid growth of the economy.
One such argument is the theory of virtual free trade régime, which
suggcsts that various measures of statc intervention in Korea cancelled
out each other to produce a neutral incentive structure (Little, 1982;
Lal, 1983; World Bank, 1987). Another is the theory of prescriptive
state intervention, which argues that state intervcntion in Korea does
not hinder growth because it leaves room for prívate initiatives
(Bhagwati, 1985, 1987, 1988). In effect these theories argue that,
whatever state intervention there may have been in Korea, it did not
affect the workings of the market mechanism because it was either self-
cancelling (virtual free trade) or porous (prescriptive state intervention).
Below, we will examine these arguments in turn, and argue that they
are neither theoretically convincing nor empirically correct.
South
/SIC lndustry Brazil Chile Greece Korea Mexico Africa Spain
[:: l [ :::i
Light lndustry* 1.5 2.6 0.3 7.8 2.7
31 1/2 Food products 2.2 3.83 0.5 8.6 2.9
313 Beverages 1.8 1.5 4.0 6.0 6.4
314 Tobacco 3.0 -1.1 0.2 3.4 4.2
321 Textiles o.o 2.1 o.o 7.2 --0.16 1.2 --0.3
322 Apparel --0.41 2.1 -2.5 9.0 _6 0.1 -3.61
323 Leather and n.a. -5.4 -3.3 10.7 n.a. ....:1.3 0.4
leather products
324
331 Footwear
Wood products _1 -1.44
-3.7 -4.7 6.6
--0.4 n.a. --0.5
332 Fumiture and
n.a.
n.a. 12.1
-5.5
-8.4 13.9 [1.1 J 0.4
-1.0 n.a.
fixtures 0.3
341 Paper and paper 4.2 2.3 5.6 11.5 2.7 5.1 3.29
r, [�¡]
products
publishing
369
Glass and glass
products
Non-metal
products
0.4
2.2
4.7
--0.4
1.5s
10.5
8.5
t0.6
7.2
1.3
390 Other industries n.a. -4.8 0.6 9.8 1.7 6.9 n.a.
Chemical industry* 2.6 0.6 2.2 7.5 3.41 1.3 0.8
35! Industrial 3.62 1.9 1.4 7.9 3.41 0.8 1.12
chemical
352 Other chemicals _2 1.0 3.9 11.8 _7 2.2 _2
353 Petroleum 1.6 0.3 2.0 4.2 _7 n.a. 0.3
refineries
354 Pctroleum and n.a. n.a. --0.2 8.1 _7 n.a. n.a.
coal products
355
356
Rubber products
Plastic products
2.7
n.a.
1.8
n.a.
1.6
2.3
11.6
7.5
_7
_7
1.6
4.8 [ 1.7 J
n.e.c.
371
372
381
Iron and steel
Non-ferrous me
Metal products
[ l 3.6 --0.4 10.5 0.3 J
104 The Political
IndustrialEconomy
Policy inofAction
Industrial Policy
- Korea 104
104 104
South
Brazil Chile Greece Korea Mexico A/rica Spain
!SIC Industry
* Weighted averages: the weights are 1980 (except for South Africa, which is
for July 1980-June 1981) output at producers' prices (including indirect
taxes and excluding subsidies), except for Greece, South Africa and Spain,
which are at factor values (excluding indirect taxes and including subsidies).
1. Major group 324 is included in 322.
2. Major group 352 is included in 351.
3. Excluding slaughtering.
4. Excluding sawmills.
5. Magnesite roasting is included in mining.
6. Major group 322 is included in 321.
7. Major groups 352 to 356 are included in 351.
8. Major groups 383 to 385 are included in 381 and 382.
9. Major group 342 is included in 341.
Source: UN, Industrial Statistics Yearbook, 1983, 1984, 1990.
The basic theme of state intervention in Korea has been the making of an
'independent economy' (Jarip Gyongjé) (see various Five-Year-Plan
[FYP] documents and EPB, 1982).11 Until recently the balance-of-
payments constraint has been the main concem of Korean policymakers,
and, as Michell (1982) points out, even exports were regarded more as a
means to reduce the unfavourable externa! balance than as the engine of
growth (p. 196). Policymakers have regarded the ultimate solution to the
problem of dependence on foreign savings for financing of investments
(Table 4.7) to be the construction of an economy with the degree of
technological capability that would permit a reasonable living standard
without a chronic balance-of-payments deficit. It was believed that the
cause of the balance-of-payments problem lay in the underdevelopment
of the capital and intermediate goods industries, and therefore that 'a shift
towards heavy and chemical industries is imperative in order to increase
the independence of the Korean economy' (WP, 1970, p. 340) - a
principie known in Korea (and Japan) as 'upgrading' the industrial
structure (also see, Second FYP, pp. 9-10; Third FYP, p. 1).
To Korean policymakers, industrial upgrading required giving priority
to investment, which was essential for growth (WP, 1968, p. 48).
Therefore, macroeconomic policy was geared towards the need to
create an expansionary environment - if necessary through inflationary
measures - which was seen as vital for a sustained high leve] of invest-
ment through its effect on investors' confidence.
Until the late 1980s, of course, there existed a persistent savings gap,
which had to be filled by foreign savings (see Table 4.7). Although the
filling of the savings gap was believed to depend ultimately on the rise in
income leve! (a Keynesian savings assumption), serious attempts were
also made to repress consumption demand through policy measures,
expressed in unashamedly patemalistic terms like 'the need to establish a
sound consumption pattem' [emphasis added] (Fourth FYP, p. 27). The
banks, which are mostly owned by the state, were instructed not to make
consumer loans. The heavy reliance on indirect taxes was also justified -
112 The Political
IndustrialEconomy
Policy inofAction
Industrial Policy
- Korea 112
112 112
110 The Political Economy of Industrial Policy
against the accusation that they are less equitable than income taxes - in
tenns of their discouraging effect on consumption (Third FYP, p. 16).
Toe control was even stricter when it carne to consumption that involved
foreign-exchange expenditure. For example, foreign holidays were
banned until the late 1980s when the country finally became a net
exporter of capital, and imported luxury goods were either banned or
were subject to high tariffs and inland taxes (see 4.2.1 above). One
outcome of such anti-consumption policies was low passenger-car
ownership, which was discouraged by high taxation and restrictions on
consumer loans until very recently. Despite Korea being a major exporter
of passenger cars, Koreans have owned far fewer passenger cars than
people in other developing countries with a comparable income level, In
1985 there were 73.5 people per passenger car in Korea, whereas the
corresponding figures in 1983 were 27.0 in Taiwan, 21.8 in Chile, 16.3 in
Malaysia and 15.2 in Brazil (NRl, 1988, p. 190, table 9-8). Given such a
clear (stated and revealed) anti-consumption bias, Korean macroecono-
mic policy may be more appropriately understood as 'investment
management' rather than as 'aggregate-demand management'.
Throughout the last three decades the Korean state has chosen severa)
industries at a time as priority sectors and has provided massive support
to them. Most of Korea's major industries have been designated as
priority sectors at sorne stage and were developed through a com-
bination of massive support from and heavy control by the state. The
designated industries had priority in acquiring rationed (and often
subsidised) credits and foreign exchange, state investment funds,
preferential tax treatments (for cxample tax holidays, accelerated de-
preciation allowances) and other supportive measures, including import
protection and entry restrictions.17 In return for this support, they
became subject to state controls on technology (for example production
methods, products), entry, capacity expansion and prices.
Non-
Major Content Mach- Ship- Electr- Petro- lron & ferrous
(year of inery building onics chemical steel metals Textiles
enactment} ( 1967) ( /967) (1969) (1970) (1970) (1971) (1979)
REGULATIONS
Entry Restriction X X X X X X X
Capacity Regulations
Setting up Facility X X
Standard
Capacity Expansion X X X
Approval
Incentives to use X X
Domestically
Produced Facilities
Production
Regulation
Regulation of X X
Material Imports
Production X X X X X
Standard and
its Inspection
Restrictions on X X
Technology lmports
Price Control X X
Reporting and X X X X X X X
Inspection
RATIONALIS-
ATION
Rationalisation X X X X X
Programmes
R&DSUPPORT
Subsidies to R&D X X X X
Joint R&D Projects X
FINANCIAL
SUPPORT
Special Purpose X X X X X X
Fund
Financia) X X X X X X
Assistance
Subsidies
Direct Subsidy X X
Reduced Public X X
Utility Rates
116 IndustrialEconomy
The Political Policy inof
Action - Korea
Industrial Policy 116
116 116
116
Non-
Major Content Machin- Ship- Electro- Petro- /ron & ferrous
(yearof ery building nics chemical Steel metals Textiles
enactment} (1967) (1967) (1969) (1970) (/970) (1971) (1979)
Tax Preferences
Special Deprecia- x X
tion
Tax Reduction/ x X X X X X
Exemption
SPECIAL x X X X
INDUSTRIAL
COMPLEX
ADMINISTRAT-
IVE
ASSISTANCE
Facilitating O X X
verseas Activities
Purchase of
Raw Materials X X
PRODUCERS' x
ASSOCIATION
X X X
Sources: Kim (1989), p. 34, table 3.1.; S. H. Lee et al. (1989), pp. 52-9.
The measures employed by the IDL can be divided into three groups.20
First, there are protective measures to ease the adjustment process, which
inc1ude import restrictions on competing products, rcductions in tariffs
on raw materials, priee controls, and outright subsidies. Secondly, there
are measures related to the attainment of an optimal production scale and
the prevention of excessive competition. These include restrictions on
entry and capacity expansión, state-initiated mergers, coordinated
capacity scrapping and/or exit, rnarket-sharing arrangements (that is
subdividing markets into non-overlapping segments). Thirdly, there are
measures aimed at raising productivity: These inc1ude the provision of
subsidised credits for such activities as capacity upgrading (or capacity
scrapping for declining industries), import substitution of inputs (for
117 IndustrialEconomy
The Political Policy inof
Action - Korea
Industrial Policy 117
117 117
117
example machine parts), subsidies for expenditure on R&D and training
programmes, and joint research programmes between the prívate firms
and government-funded research institutes.
118 IndustrialEconomy
The Political Policy inof
Action - Korea
Industrial Policy 118
118 118
118
In our opinion the most serious problem with industrial policy is that,
once implemented, state-created rents may be difficult to withdraw
due to political pressure from the recipients of such rents. The
existence of infant industries that refuse to 'grow up' in many
developing countries is a testimony to such a danger (see Bell et al.,
1984). As emphasised by economists such as Marx, Schumpeter and
Richardson, the beneficia! role of rents as a mcans to Jure (positive
rents) and force (negativc rents) firms into more productive activities,
hinges on the fact that no rent accruing to the innovator is permanent.
In a situation where rents are created by the state, these rents may
cease to be transitory if the state is unable to withdraw them when
necessary. 24
The Korean state has played a central role in the country's economic
development through its cunning use of state-created rents as an
instrument for industrial development. Of course such a result has been
possible only because the Korean state has been a strong state, able to
discipline firms whenever necessary. The power of the Korean state has
frequently been underrated, especially by sorne neoclassical eco-
124 TheIndustrial Policy in of
Political Economy Action - Korea
Industrial Policy 124
124 124
124 124
nomists, on the ground that the 'size' of the Korean state (defined in
tenns of public-sector expenditure) is relatively small (for example
Balassa, 1988, but see Sachs, 1987, for sorne evidence to the contrary).
However, what matters for the effectiveness or ineffectiveness of state
intervention is not where the boundary of thc state as a legal entity Jies,
but how far it can exercise its influence. Public-sector expenditure as it
is usually defined is a very poor measure of this. What, then, was the
basis of the power of the Korean state?
It has often been suggested that the Korean state is strong because the
country's historical development left a social structure with no power-
ful social classes to contest state power (Hamilton, 1983; Lim, 1985;
Cumings, 1987; Evans, 1987; Amsden, 1989, ch. 2). The landed class
was eliminated through land refonns around about the Korean War, and
the incipient (largely socialist) political organisations of the working
class and fanners were also crushed during the war and the subsequent
era of Cold War politics. Moreover it is argued that the country's
history of Confucian tradition produced a society where the state
commands the moral high ground and draws in the best talent (for
example Luedde-Neurath, 1988).28 Toe long tradition of centralisation
in Korean history seems to have been another factor serving to
Jegitimatise the power of the central bureaucracy.29
We think these historical factors are extremely important, and perhaps
are what differentiates the Korean developmental experience most from
that of, say, India or Latin America.P The weakness of the social
classes was certainly important in deciding the balance of power
between the state and socicty in Korea. The Confucian belief in the
state as a Jegitimate social institution (if not necessarily in particular
governments and individual political leaders), often lacking in other
developing countries, also seems to have been an important factor in
rnaking state intervention effective in Korea. Moreover there are
reasons to believe that the relatively high cultural and ideological
homogeneity of Korean society - although it is not as absolute as is
often argued (there have been rather intense regional conflicts) - has
also helped in the effective implementation of government policies, as
we have discussed earlier.
However we think that such historical factors are, in themselves, not
enough to bring about a strong state and effective state intervention. If
such conditions have been present since the end of the Korean War,
why was the Korean state so weak and incompetent in the l 950s? And,
125 TheIndustrial Policy in of
Political Economy Action - Korea
Industrial Policy 125
125 125
125 125
if Confucianism is conducive to a strong and competent state, why was
the Kuomintang government before their defeat to the Chinese
Communist Party so weak and incompetent? Although a full discussion
of the subject is beyond the scope of this chapter, we suggest that the
emergence of a strong state in Korea should be understood in relation
to the political agenda of the military régime of General Park Chung
Hee, which fundamentally shaped the political economy of the country
for decades to come. The strong state was as rnuch, if not more, an
outcome of calculated political moves and institutional innovations as
that of historical conditions and culture.
resulting in full state control over investment loans.T' At the same time,
the Park régime imprisoned many prominent businessmen on the
charge of having accumulated wealth through illicit means (for
example by using political connections), but they were later released in
retum for their promise to 'serve the nation through enterprise', which
basically meant building new plants in state-designated industries (on
the so-called 'Illicit Wealth Accumulation' episode; see Jones and
Sakong, 1980, pp. 69-70, 281-2). With these two major political
blows, the business community suddenly became, morally, a criminal
on parole and subject to 'serving the nation through enterprise', and,
economically, a paper tiger with little power to rnake investment
decisions - the ultimate capitalist prerogative.
Another important institutional innovation made by the Park
régime was the centralisation of economic policy-making power in
the hands of a super-ministry, the Economic Planning Board (EPB),
headed by the deputy prime minister (see Whang, 1991, pp. 86-7).
The integration of both planning and budgeting authorities within the
EPB eliminated the conflict of interests between the planning and
industrial ministries (which are usually more interested in long-term
investments) and the finance ministry . (which is usually more
interested in short-term stability), if at the cost of concentrating
power within the govcrnment (which may be objected to 011 other
grounds). Elimination of such conflict made the implementation of
industrial policy in Korea more effective than in other industrial
policy-states such as Japan and France, where such conflict has been a
problem.J"
Even the much-vaunted cultural and ideological homogeneity of
Korean society was not purely historical bounty that the nation
accidentally stumbled on. The Park régime mobilised the nation with
the ideology of 'Renaissance of the Nation' through the building of
Jarip Gyongjé (independent economy). 35 Workers were described by
the state-controlled media and state-issued school textbooks as 'indus-
trial soldiers' fighting a patriotic war against poverty (although the
labour movement was brutally suppressed) and businessmen were
given medals for achieving export targets as if they were generals who
had won major battles. Farmers were mobilised into semi-compulsory
(unpaid) labour for rural infrastructural development a la Mao Tse
Tung, through the Sémaul (new village) movement (Michell, 1982,
pp. 205-8). Although not ali such ideological mobilisations were
successful (for example, the Sémaul movement was much resented) and
127 TheIndustrial Policy in of
Political Economy Action - Korea
Industrial Policy 127
127 127
127 127
sorne rightly criticised them as 'militarising' the society (for example
Halliday, 1980), it is undeniable that they were important in promoting
ideological homogeneity.
The Korean state has continued to dominate economic and moral issues
throughout the country's developmental period. State control over
credit, which has been the most effective means of controlling private
firms, given their high leverage, has continued throughout.36 Although
sorne of the state-owned banks (the so-called 'city banks') were partially
privatised in 1982, the independence of these banks is almost nil
because of their lending to high-borrowing finns and their consequent
dependence on the central bank, which is under the full control of the
state. 37 In fact, following their privatisation, the share of policy loans -
loans with subsidised interest rates and/or priorities in credit rationing -
actually increased, from 56.0 pcr cent (1962-81) to 67.6 per cent
(1982-5), making it very difficult to argue that state control over the
banking sector has loosened (also see Cole and Park, 1983, p. 173). In
addition to their freedom to make loan decisions, the banks' freedom to
set interest rates has also been severely limited. Despite the legal
deregulation of interest rates on loans and long-term deposits in
December 1988, it was reported in 1991 that '[i]nterest rates are still
strictly controlled by guidance from the Bank of Korea and the Ministry
ofFinance, despite the legal deregulation' (FEER, 30 May, 1991, p. 52).
In addition to its control over bank loans, the Korean state has
maintained tight foreign-exchange controls. The buying and selling of
foreign exchange has been tightly regulated, and up until a few years
ago it was illegal (subject to prison sentence) to possess foreign
cxchange except for state-approved business purposes. The state's
control over foreign loans and foreign direct investrnent has been near-
absolute. Although foreign borrowing and, to a lesser degree, foreign
dircct investment have not been discouraged, the state has had the final
say in deciding whether a certain loan or foreign direct investrnent is
permitted, and on what terms.
Although far less important than its control over financia] resources,
the state's control over material resources through public enterprises
should not be ignored. The Korean state has owned various strategic
industries, including oil, coa) (partly), gas, fertilíser, steel and electri-
city. The fact that such crucial intermediate inputs as oil, coal, gas,
electricity, steel and fertiliser are supplied by public enterprises is
anothcr important factor contributing to the power of the state in Korea.
128 TheIndustrial Policy in of
Political Economy Action - Korea
Industrial Policy 128
128 128
128 128
Of course the regular threat by the Korean state that it is going to use its
power to discipline those firms which do not comply with its policies
does not always materialise, partly because large business firms have a
strong influence on policy formation and implementation. Nevertheless
the threat is not an idle one and it is often realised, as exemplified by
the freezing of bank credit (on 8 May 1991) to 14 subsidiaries of eight
conglomerates that had not complied with state pressure to sell non-
business land (EIU, 1991, p. 20). A still more dramatic example of how
far the Korean state can go, if it chooses, was the Kukje-group incident
in 1985, when the state deliberately bankrupted the inefficiently-run
Kukje group, the then seventh largest conglomerate in the country, by
ordering its major lending bank not to honour its cheques, although it is
believed that the decision to Jet Kukje go under was in part motivated
by its lukewarm attitude to meeting the ruling party's financia)
demands (for details, see FEER, 21 April 1988, pp. 58-60).
CONCLUSION
131
132 Conclusion
The Political Economy of Industrial Policy 132
132 132
132 132
non-market coordination within and between enterprises, and also at
the deterrninants of the scope of individual enterprises. The govern-
ment-failure literature discusses the problems of the centralised forrn of
coordination between enterprises through state intervention. What is
becoming increasingly clear from these writings is that effective
coordination both within economic units and between such units can
only be achieved at a cost, and that different forrns of coordination have
different costs under different conditions.
By introducing the costs of achieving coordination, or transaction
costs in more popular terms, into the picture, we effectively break away
from the neoclassical tradition in which perfect coordination is
achieved without any cost, either by the Walrasian auctioneer (as in the
general-equilibrium version) or by the benevolent, omniscient and
omnipotent state (as in the welfare-economics version). In this new
frarnework, the market is but one of many possible economic institu-
tions, or coordination mechanisms, each of which incurs certain trans-
action costs of different types and magnitudes in resol ving the
coordination problem (Pagano, 1985, ch. 8). By adopting a theoretical
framework that recognises that all institutions are costly to run, we
implicitly reject the common view which assigns theoretical primacy to
the market and views other institutions as merely surrogates, which are
simply 'rneans of achieving the benefits of collective action in situ-
ations in which the price system fails' (Arrow, 1974, p. 33).
By regarding the market as just one of many alternative economic
institutions, we also come to realise that the efficient operation of the
market depends on many more institutional arrangements than those
which are usually recognised in the conventional literature.1 To begin
with, we need at least a mínimum degree of morality to have any
exchange which is intertemporal, as otherwise the costs of policing and
contract-enforcement will be prohibitive (McPherson, 1984). Also,
existing exchange relationships are definable only in relation to the
existing system of property and other rights (for example social-security
entitlements, working conditions, rights for clean air), and the en-
forcement of such rights necessarily requires certain institutions - the
police, the courts, and the prison system. And in this process the state
not only plays the role of the ultimate guarantor of property rights and
other legal forms but also extensively intervenes in order to establish
the market itself asan institution (Polanyi, 1957; Coase, 1988; see also
Chapter 1.2.3). Thus seen, the seemingly 'instítuüon-free' market
mechanism is sustainable only as a part of the intricate fabric of various
133 Conclusion
The Political Economy of Industrial Policy 133
133 133
133 133
The conclusion that emerges from our discussíon is that neither the
market, nor the state, nor any other economic institution is perfect as a
coordination mechanism. Each institution has its costs and benefits, and
is therefore bctter than others under certain conditions and worse under
other conditions. This means that different countries facing different
conditions can, and should, have different mixes of the rnarket, the state
and other institutions. And in fact, as we observed in the Introduction,
even economies that are usually Jumped together as 'capitalist' or
'market' economies have been based on substantially different institu-
tional mixes. In other words, there are many feasible ways of managing
a capitalist economy.
This point, which may seem obvious to the rcader by now, however
does not seem to be widely recognised by policy-makers in many refonn-
ing cconomies of the ex-socialist world and the developing world. Toe
reform packages applicd in these countries are modeled on Anglo-Saxon
capitalism, and they are often a crude caricature of it al that. The possibil-
ity that this may not be the only, or the most efficient, way of managing a
capitalist economy seems to be largely ignored. This is a disturbing state
of affairs, especially when within the Anglo-Saxon economies them-
selves there is growing disillusionment with their own models of econo-
mic management. Now their policy-makers are thinking seriously about
policy changes which recognise the positive role that the state and other
non-market institutions can play in the economy, as exemplified in the
renewed interest in industrial policy in these countries.
Of course this does not mean that the refonning countries would
necessarily succeed if they were to follow sorne other model, say that of
Scandinavia or East Asia. lf there are many different ways of combining
different economic institutions, this means that each country has to decide
on the exact mix between the market, the state and other institutions on
136 Conclusion
The Political Economy of Industrial Policy 136
136 136
136 136
the basis of a careful consideration of its economic, political and social
conditions, rather than blindly follow one model or another. Needless to say,
finding an appropriate mix of the market, the state and other non- market
institutions is not easy. Such a task, especially in a world of ever- changing
technology, is formidable, as the sceptics point out. However, as we have
repeatedly pointed out with reference to countries such Japan, Korea and
France, it can in principie be met through a process of institutional
leaming and innovation.
Notes and References
Introduction
137
138 Notes and
Notes and References
References to
to pp. 8-9
pp. 9-17 138
138 138
138
15. For Marxist theories of the state, see Milíband, 1969, and Jessop,1982.
16. According to neoclassical política) economy, what differentiates the
market from the polity is not the different behavioural principie of the
participants (always self-interested) but the different constraints that
they face (the individual bearing or otherwise of the whole effects of
one' s decision) (McCormick and Tollison, 1981, p. 5). Still emergent,
this school has many different names, such as economics of politics
(Buchanan et al., 1978), neoclassical política) economy (Colander [ed.],
1984), public-choice school (Mueller, 1979), new political economy
(Findlay, 1990), or positive política) economy (Alt and Shepsle [eds],
1990).
17. In sorne models of interest-group theory, interest groups - acting as
maximisers of utility (or wealth) - make demands to claim the largest
possible amount of state largesse, which the politicians who make up
the state distribute with a view to maximising their votes, and not to
maximising social welfare. The result often is the generation of policies
that are 'irrational' from the social point of view, for example 'political
business cycles'.
18. From the viewpoint of extreme methodological individualism this
argument is a non sequitur, because if these norms restrict the formation
of a certain interest group, the individuals who belong to that potential
interest group can organise themselvcs first to remove such restrictions.
However, in the real world, as Eggertsson (1990) argues, 'various
factors work against special interest groups and limit their effectiveness,
including laws against bribery, rules regulating the behaviour of lobbyists,
and public-spiritedness of civil servants and legislators' (pp. 66-7).
Moreover norms may have arisen due to the utility-maximising
behaviour of individuals but they acquire an autonomous Iife once they
come into being, because individuals who join the society by birth or
immigration after these norms have been established will internalisc
them through the socialisation processes.
19. Moreover, even when assuming that there are no unnecessary activities
initiated by the budget-maximising attempts of the bureaucrats, the state
activities may not be fully cost-efficient, Toe fact that the state bureau-
cracy is in a monopolistic position may mean that there is x-inefficiency
in their activities (see Peacock, 1979b, pp. 123-4). x-inefficiency, as
defined by Leibenstein (l 966), is generated when production units use
inputs in the right proportion, but on an unnecessarily large scale. Thus,
even when strict marginal pricing is conducted within the state
bureaucracy, it may operate with considerable slack due to the lack of
competitive pressures.
20. Marxists emphasise this problem when they discuss the nced for the
state in a class society to ensure the Iegitimacy of the system (see
Gramsci, 1988; O'Connor, 1973; Gough, 1979).
21. Even from a purely selfish point of view, there is far more scope for
cooperation in a stable organisation like the bureaucracy than in a
strictly atomised world. Firstly, since an organisation by definition
implies a long-lasting relationship between a given set of people, there is
141 Notes and
Notes andReferences
Referencestotopp. 24-9
pp. 17-24 141
141 141
141 141
12. Moreover, as Williamson (1988) states, 'it does not suffice to demon-
strate that a condition of large numbers competition obtains at the outset.
Jt is also necessary to examine whether this continues or if, by reason of
transaction specific investments and incomplete contracting, a condition
of bilateral trading evo/ves thereafter' (p. 71 ).
13. What Hayek calls the 'competition as a state of affairs' view is still
dominant in the field of industrial economics (on different notions of
competition, sec Hayek, 1949b, 1978; McNulty, 1968; O'Driscoll, 1986).
For example, even a most updated industrial economics textbook, Tirole
( 1988), argues that replacement of one monopolist by another through a
patent race 'does not mean competition, as one monopolist replaces
another' (p. 396, n. 12). However Hayek would have argued that the
replacement was a result of 'the activity called competition',
14. Dobb (1925, ch. 23) expresses a similar concem. He describes the
capitalist economy as an 'economic anarchy' that gives fluidity to the
economy but at the cost of instability due to coordination failure. In
particular, he points out that miscalculations by competing firms might
not cancel out because expectations tend to move in the same direction.
15. lt should, however, be noted that Marx had another vision of socialist
society organised on the basis of a more democratic and less specialised
division of labour, which Pagano (1985) aptly calls 'anti-firm
communism' (p. 60).
16. Amadeo and Banuri (1991) argue that there is a correlation between the
liquidity of the assets owned by different groups (for example financiers,
industrialists, workers) and their degrees of support for unregulated
competition in the market.
17. Sorne recent developments in mainstream theory attempt lo incorporate
these observations through modelling 'wasteful R&D' and the like.
However this type of model is not generally extended to the theory of
competition in general.
18. The very diversity of coordination devices in a capitalisl economy is a
testimony to the diversity of coordination problems to be sol ved. And this
is one reason why we emphasise the particularistic nature of industrial
policy, since, to be successful, it has to be custorn-designed to fit the
nature of the coordination problem in volved in a particular instance.
19. Marx's concept of 'constant capital' (which was absent in the Ricardian
systern) and the Austrian concept of 'roundabout methods of production'
are two importan! ways of theorising such a characteristic.
20. Of course there are other options open to firms. One is to find a hitherto
unexploited market, say, through exporting. Another is to diversify into
other related industries, as shown in the examples of sorne Japanese firrns
in declining industries like textiles, brewing and food-processing that have
successfully diversified into biotechnology (see Okimoto, 1989, p. l 28).
21. However, devising a side-payrnents scheme is not easy because the
estímate of future costs and benefits from exit may differ among the
agents concemed. For example, in the branches of the Japanese textile
industry that are dominated by many small-scale firrns, who were hard-
pressed by imports from the NICs in the early 1980s, the govemment
149 Notes and
Notes and References
References to
to pp. ó2-9
pp. 69-73 149
149 149
149 149
took the view that exit compensation should be financed by the remaining
firms who would benefit from such exit, while the remaining firms argued
that the exiters' share of the total market was minute (and hence benefit
negligible) and that any room left in the market by the exit of home
producers was likely to be taken up by imports (see Dore, 1986, p. 236).
22. In this case, side-payments will mainly involve compensation for
workers who are laid off. For example, in the case of the Japanese
shipbuilding industry, additional unemployment benefits and special
placement services for workers, provided by the state, were important in
arranging a speedy capacity-scrapping arrangement (see Renshaw, 1986,
p. 145; Dore, 1986, p. 143).
23. In the case of the Japanese textile industry, sorne equipment was
mothballed in 1978, but it was eventually scrapped in 1981 as the
demand downtum proved to be permanent (Dore, 1986, pp. 235-6).
24. More generally, given the limited human capacity to process
information, the introduction of rigidity in behaviour through such long-
term binding contracts may well be essential to achieve rational
decisions (Simon, 1983; Heiner, 1983).
25. In this particular case, no exit was negotiated, and the cut was graduated
to the size of the firm, ranging from 40 per cent for the seven biggest
firms to 15 per cent for the 21 smallest (Dore, 1986, p. 145).
26. And this is why '[c]onsumers do not wish to contract for their future
purchases because they cannot foretell what their future needs and
opportunities will be; and produccrs do not generally wish to commit
themselves to forward purchases of inputs because they cannot predict
the productive possibilities that will be open to them' (Richardson, 1971,
p. 437).
27. In the case of the Japanese aluminium-smelting industry, one reason pul
forward for not cutting capacity to the leve) dictated by current relative
prices (mainly due to the oil price hike and the conscquent rise in
electricity prices) was the need to maintain a sizeable industry to support
an R&D capacity, which is an important precondition for regaining
intemational competitiveness if the cost situation improves in the future
(Dore, 1986, p. 143).
28. While arguing that the coordination failures of the market entails enorm-
ous waste and therefore needs to be replaced by less wasteful ex ante
coordination through central planning, Marx was also a precursor of the
Schumpeterian, and to sorne extent the Austrian, 'process' view of com-
petition, which emphasises the role of market competition in developing
the 'forces of production' (see, for example, Marx, 1981, pp. 373-4).
29. In contrast, in the ncoclassical frarnework every piece of information (or
knowledge) is seen as obtainable, albeit ata cost (for example search cost)
(for similar views, see Heiner, 1988, p. 148, and Pelikan, 1988, p. 385).
30. The importance, in the nineteenth century, of the migration of skilled
technicians in transmitting technical knowledge from one to another part
of the then industrialised world (that is, Europe and the USA)
documented by Rosenberg (1976, pp. 154-5) shows the difficulty of
codifying technical knowledge.
150 Notes
Notes and
and References
Referencestotopp.
pp. 77-86
73-6 150
150 150
150 150