Sustainable Value Creation
Sustainable Value Creation
The framework presented in this book, Sustainable Value Creation, is the result
of more than twenty years thinking and writing at the intersection of two
subjects, strategy and CSR. I teach strategy and I think about CSR, almost
constantly. Given my academic home in the business school, I appreciate the
importance of markets and the ability of their essential actors (for-profit firms)
to create value. Equally, of course, I see the ability of firms to destroy value,
on an all-too-frequent basis. As such, I have spent a lot of time thinking
about how to promote the beneficial work firms do and eradicate the harm.
The result is this book: a framework through which managers can understand
the essential purpose of the for-profit firm, the most powerful entity we have
devised to drive societal progress.
At its core, this book is structured around the ten principles that define
Sustainable Value Creation. The foundation for these principles is a pragmatic
philosophy, oriented around stakeholder theory and designed to appeal to
managers skeptical of existing definitions of CSR, sustainability, or business
ethics. It is also designed to stimulate thought within the community of aca-
demics committed to these ideas, but who approach them from more tradi-
tional perspectives. Ultimately, therefore, this book aims to reform both
business practice and business education. By building a theory that redefines
CSR as central to everything the firm does (as opposed to peripheral practices
that can be marginalized), these ten principles redefine how firms approach
each of their operational functions, but also how these subjects should be
taught in universities worldwide. As such, this book will hopefully be of value
to instructors as a complement to their teaching, students as a guide in their
education, and managers as a framework to help them respond to the
complex, dynamic context that they are expected to navigate every day.
David Chandler
Second edition published 2021
by Routledge
2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon, OX14 4RN
and by Routledge
52 Vanderbilt Avenue, New York, NY 10017
Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business
© 2021 David Chandler
The right of David Chandler to be identified as author of this work
has been asserted by him in accordance with sections 77 and 78 of the
Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988.
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or
reproduced or utilized in any form or by any electronic, mechanical,
or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including
photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval
system, without permission in writing from the publishers.
Trademark notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or
registered trademarks, and are used only for identification and
explanation without intent to infringe.
[First edition published by Business Expert Press 2015]
British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Names: Chandler, David, 1969– author.
Title: Sustainable value creation / David Chandler.
Description: Abingdon, Oxon ; New York, NY : Routledge, 2020. |
Includes bibliographical references and index. |Identifiers: LCCN
2020003901 (print) | LCCN 2020003902 (ebook) | ISBN
9780367859817 (hardback) | ISBN 9780367859824 (paperback) |
ISBN 9781003016199 (ebook)
Subjects: LCSH: Social responsibility of business. | Value.
Classification: LCC HD60 .C4428 2020 (print) | LCC HD60 (ebook)
| DDC 658.4/08–dc23
LC record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2020003901
LC ebook record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2020003902
Foreword x
Acknowledgments xii
June, 20141
What is the purpose of a business corporation? For much of the past three
decades, observers and even many business leaders embraced the view that
corporations “belong” to their shareholders and that the legal responsibility of
corporate directors and executives is to single-mindedly seek to maximize
shareholder wealth. Today, experts and laypersons alike increasingly recog-
nize this view of business to be both mistaken and harmful.
As a purely factual matter, corporate law does not require directors and
executives to try and maximize profits or share price. Although a business
must be profitable to survive, corporate law grants executives and directors of
business corporations the discretion to pursue any lawful purpose as a business
goal. This “business judgment rule” is something that is consistent across
almost all legal jurisdictions.
Nor do shareholders own corporations. Corporations, as legal entities, own
themselves. Shareholders own shares that are legal contracts with the corpo-
rate entity, just as employees own employment contracts with the entity and
bondholders own debt contracts with the corporate entity. A firm’s share-
holder body is an important partner, but only one of many.
The combined effect of these legal realities, which are the products of
decades of both case and statutory law, is to liberate executives and directors
to pursue a wide range of practices that they believe to be in the best interests
of the organization as a whole. In other words, executives and directors are
not bound by any imperative to maximize profits for shareholders in the short
term, but can seek to sustain the organization over the medium and long
term, ensuring that value is created for a broad range of constituents.
This is important because, from a practical perspective, the dogma of
“maximizing shareholder value” does not seem to be working out particularly
well for the companies that choose to adopt it. In the quest to “unlock share-
holder value,” managers have sold off key assets; fired valuable employees;
leveraged firms to the brink of bankruptcy; and showered CEOs with stock
options in order to “incentivize” them to raise the share price. Some have
even committed fraud. Such strategies have proved harmful not only to
Foreword xi
customers, employees, and taxpayers, but to shareholders themselves. Indeed,
even as the business sector has embraced the ideology of shareholder value,
shareholder returns from holding public equity have declined. Society, as a
whole, is worse off as a result.
This book helps explain why. The framework detailed by David Chandler
offers a roadmap for building companies that can do more not only for share-
holders, but also for customers, suppliers, employees, and society as a whole.
The questions Who owns the firm? and In whose interests should the firm be run?
are central to this quest. Once we successfully challenge the idea that share-
holders own the firm, we remove much of the pressure that drives executives
and directors to always favor shareholders’ interests over the interests of other
stakeholders who are often more invested in the organization and more
central to its sustained success.
Corporate Social Responsibility: A Strategic Perspective offers compelling argu-
ments against shareholder primacy. In its place, it presents an alternative
vision of strategic CSR that builds on a foundation of stakeholder theory and
takes into account core insights from the fields of psychology and economics
to demonstrate that it is in the strategic interests of the firm to respond to the
values, needs, and concerns of all stakeholders. Through this approach, firms
generate the most value for the broadest section of society.
Corporate Social Responsibility: A Strategic Perspective is a manifesto for busi-
ness today. It is essential reading for academics interested in CSR, for students
interested in business, and for executives who seek insight into the complex
web of competing stakeholder interests they must balance every day.
Lynn A. Stout
Distinguished Professor of Corporate and Business Law
Jack G. Clarke Business Law Institute, Cornell Law School
Acknowledgments
The framework presented in this book, Sustainable Value Creation, is the result
of more than 20 years’ thinking and writing at the intersection of two sub-
jects, strategy and CSR. I teach strategy and I think about CSR, almost con-
stantly. Given my academic home in the business school, I appreciate the
importance of markets and the ability of their essential actors (for-profit firms)
to create value. Equally, of course, I see the ability of firms to destroy value,
on an all-too-frequent basis. As such, I have spent a lot of time thinking
about how to promote the beneficial work firms do and eradicate the harm.
The result is this book – a framework through which managers can under-
stand the essential purpose of the for-profit firm, the most powerful entity we
have devised to drive societal progress.
This framework, as far as I can see from the constant stream of CSR-
related articles that cross my desk, is unique. I also believe it is revolutionary.
It challenges much of what is currently taken-for-granted about CSR, both as
it is taught in universities and practiced in corporations. The consequences of
this contrary approach can be seen in answer to the essential question, What
does it mean for a firm to be socially responsible? If you ask that question in most
CSR classes, I believe the answer would be that it looks something like Pat-
agonia or TOMS; with SVC, it is Walmart (or Amazon or Apple). If you ask
that question in most corporations, I believe the answer would be that it
looks something like philanthropy or employee volunteer programs; with
SVC, it is strategy and core operations. Understanding why these differences
are so stark will alter your understanding of business – what the firm is and
what it does.
When I began this journey in the mid-1990s, I held a more traditional
CSR perspective. It has taken me over 20 years of reading, about economics
and social psychology, to reject what I previously accepted. But, although this
perspective is mine and is something for which I am solely accountable, I was
only able to develop it with considerable help along the way. In particular,
when I think about the intersection of strategy and CSR, I think about the
intersection of two Bills: First, Bill Werther, who taught me much of what I
needed to know about strategy and how to be an academic; and second, the
late Bill Frederick, whose intellectual depth and generosity continue to shape
Acknowledgments xiii
the fields of CSR and business ethics and will do so for many generations of
academics to come. I owe a great deal to both Bills.
More specifically, this book benefitted from the insights and constructive
criticism of many friends and colleagues as the core ideas were being
developed. In particular for the first edition, the following people kindly gave
their time and attention to read early drafts and provide feedback: Bart Alex-
ander of Alexander & Associates, LLC; Michael L. Barnett of Rutgers
University; Mark A. Buchanan of Boise State University; William C. Freder-
ick of the University of Pittsburgh (emeritus); R. Edward Freeman of the
University of Virginia; Stuart L. Hart of the University of Vermont; Laura
Pincus Hartman of DePaul University; Joshua D. Margolis of Harvard
University; Miguel Athayde Marques of Católica University; James E. Post of
Boston University (emeritus); Mark P. Sharfman of the University of Okla-
homa; Lynn A. Stout of Cornell University; Roy Suddaby of the University
of Victoria; and William B. Werther of the University of Miami. While all
errors are mine, this book is significantly better due to their expertise.
I am also indebted to a number of colleagues who kindly agreed to review
the proposal (both named and anonymously) for this edition of the book,
including: Robert Arp of Webster University; Kevin Eckerle of New York
University; Scott Freehafer of the University of Findlay; Bruce Kibler of
Gannon University; Seoki Lee of Pennsylvania State University; Karen
Palumbo of the University of Saint Francis; and Andrew Trew of John
Carroll University. The constructive feedback of these experienced teachers,
drawn from many years of experience in the classroom, ensured that this
edition of SVC is considerably better than it otherwise would have been.
Finally, I would like to thank the editorial team at Routledge for their
assistance in preparing this manuscript. In particular, I would like to thank the
senior editor who commissioned this edition of the book, Rebecca Marsh.
Rebecca is a big reason why I decided to revisit this framework, and I am
very happy she persuaded me to do so. More broadly, it is the support of
publishers like Routledge for projects like this that help realize the goal of
building a stronger intellectual framework for more responsible management
education practices in universities around the world.
Introduction
Corporate Social Responsibility
Defining CSR
What is Corporate Social Responsibility (CSR)? What is sustainability? What is
the difference between these two concepts and business ethics? Is CR (Corpo
rate Responsibility) different from CSR? Is a firm’s purpose different from its
responsibility? What does it mean to be a corporate citizen? All of these terms
have become commonplace in recent years, but beyond a general sense that
Corporate Social Responsibility 3
corporations have some form of obligation beyond their organizational
boundaries, what do they actually mean? Are these concepts mutually exclu-
sive or is there significant overlap among them? And, if they are not the same,
why is it that we cannot agree upon universal definitions that convey clearly
to firms the set of behaviors expected of them?7
In other words, in spite of a large and growing amount of work that seeks to
understand a firm’s social responsibility, there remains great confusion and incon-
sistency. Far from the absence of possible definitions, however, as the above
list of terms suggests, “the problem is rather that there is an abundance of defi-
nitions, which are … often biased toward specific interests and thus prevent
the development and implementations of the concept.”9 As a result, while
there is broad agreement about the idea that firms have a social responsibility,
there is little agreement on what that responsibility looks like in practice:
How can we argue that CSR is important if we cannot agree what CSR is,
or at least narrow it down to a reasonable set of definitions?11 If CSR remains
idiosyncratic (different things to different people), then it loses its essential
meaning and ability to influence the way we structure the economic order.
This confusion suggests the need for additional clarification, and hopefully
some agreement, in terms of what we mean when we talk about CSR.
Measuring CSR
Central to the challenge of defining CSR is the ability to measure CSR. You
have to know what something is before you can quantify it; equally, you
have to be able to measure it before it can be widely disseminated. Unfortu-
nately, because we have not been able to define CSR, we have also not done
a very good job of measuring CSR. And, as a direct result, we cannot easily
say which firms are better or worse at CSR (as an objective fact). Even more
problematic, although we have some intuitive sense of which firms are good
4 Corporate Social Responsibility
and which firms are bad (based on our individual assumptions and values), we
are presently unable to compare one firm to another reliably across all aspects
of operations (particularly if the firms operate in different industries). The
reason we are not able to do these things, of course, is because they are
incredibly difficult. It is certainly not for want of trying. But the challenges
involved in defining societal expectations and then quantifying those expecta-
tions holistically in terms of firm performance quickly become apparent with
a simple thought experiment. Consider the complexities inherent in any
attempt to parcel out and quantify the impact an individual firm’s operations
has on the environment:
While we may be able to agree that the aggregate effect of all economic activ-
ity is detrimental and causing climate change,13 the degree to which it is doing
so and what we might do about it remains unclear. In essence, calculating the
present-day value of that future cost and determining what percentage can be
attributed to an individual firm is extremely challenging. Should a firm be
responsible only for the costs incurred during the production of its products,
for example, or also for those incurred during their consumption? Should
automobile companies be held responsible for the pollution caused by people
driving cars or only for the pollution involved in making the cars? What about
smartphone companies, where there is little cost to the environment during
consumption of the product, but the potential for significant damage during
disposal due to e-waste? And, what about a firm’s supply chain – where does
one firm’s responsibility begin and another’s end? Should a sports shoe
company be responsible for the costs incurred during the manufacture of the
shoe (even though that process is completed by an independent contractor)?
What about any work that is further outsourced by that contractor to a sub-
contractor? What about the rubber used to make the soles of the shoes – is
that also the sports shoe company’s responsibility, or the responsibility of the
contractor (or sub-contractor) who purchased the raw material, or of the plan-
tation where the rubber was initially harvested? There are no easy answers to
these questions, which relate only to the costs incurred by a firm. What about
quantifying the benefits the firm and its products provide, which raise a whole
new set of challenges? And, perhaps most importantly, how should these bene-
fits offset the costs – should we sum them to create a net effect or should the
costs be weighted more heavily than the benefits (or vice-versa)?
Corporate Social Responsibility 5
In spite of these complexities (and many more), the idea that firms have a
social responsibility continues to capture our attention.14 We remain convinced
that this special thing we are talking about, CSR, matters. It must matter,
right? After all, being responsible has to be better than being irresponsible. And it
is important for our sense of justice that those firms that are more responsible
should be rewarded in some way, while those firms that are less responsible
should be punished. But, what if the reverse is true and it is those firms that
make the most effort to be socially responsible that are penalized for doing so
by stakeholders who fail to reward the behavior they claim to want from
firms (and fail to punish the behavior they say they do not want)?15 Ulti-
mately, if we cannot develop consistent definitions of good/bad, better/
worse, and then construct a set of measures that capture the extent to which
these ideas are implemented in practice, how can we determine whether
CSR actually matters?
The United States income tax laws allow companies to claim they earned
profits in countries where they actually had few, if any, operations, but
where taxes are extremely low. … the U.S. Public Interest Research
Group Education Fund and Citizens for Tax Justice, said that 372 of the
companies in the Fortune 500 … reported a total of 7,827 subsidiaries in
countries that the groups view as tax havens. Some of those subsidiaries
no doubt do real business. … But most … are engaged only in the busi-
ness of tax avoidance.30
In short, society is stronger when capital flows freely and business is incentiv
ized to innovate and compete. This may seem intuitive when we stop and
write it down, but the point is not made often enough. And, in its rush to
improve an economic system that has already delivered phenomenal social
progress, many in the CSR community overlook this fundamental aspect of
capitalism. This does not mean that improvements should not be made and
certainly does not mean that the government does not have a role to play, but
keeping this starting point in mind anchors the framework underpinning Sus
tainable Value Creation (SVC).
For-profit firms
Broadly speaking, there are three types of organizations: for-profit, not-for
profit, and governmental. There are also hybrid mixes of these three forms,
such as social businesses, government-backed enterprises, and benefit corpo
rations.2 Of the basic forms, however, only the for-profit firm is consistently
Business is social progress 13
able to combine scarce and valuable resources efficiently and on the scale
necessary to improve meaningfully our society and standard of living. This
unique position of for-profit firms in our society is enhanced when we con
sider the challenges we face, the timeframe in which substantive action is
required, and the complexity inherent in what the former CEO of Unilever,
Paul Polman, calls today’s “vuca world; volatile, uncertain, complex and
ambiguous.”3
In general, there are two sides to the debate as to how firms should
navigate this dynamic environment. On the one hand, for-profit firms receive
much from society that is essential for them to operate – a stable legal system,
an educated workforce, a modern infrastructure, and so on. As such, many
CSR advocates argue that firms have a broader responsibility to recognize
(and appreciate) that they externalize many of the costs that are associated
with these benefits. Some of these costs are implicit in the social contract and
are a universal good (such as an educated workforce); some of these costs,
however, have harmful societal consequences (such as pollution). Either way,
firms rely on society to thrive – they “receive a social sanction from society
that requires that they, in return, contribute to the growth and development
of that society.”4
On the other hand, however, society receives much from strong, for-profit
firms that operate within a vibrant, market-based economy. Look around
you. Virtually everything you can see was made by a for-profit firm. It is for-
profit firms that are responsible either for much of the innovation that allows
society to progress or for converting the innovations made by others (e.g.,
scientists, artists, and academics) into products that make our lives better.
More important than the value added by for-profit organizations through
innovation, however, is the efficient means by which they are able to convert
valuable and scarce resources into usable products, and distribute those prod
ucts to those who demand them at the price those individuals are willing to
pay. The details of this process (what for-profit firms do and how they do it)
defines our quality of life and our level of social progress. The recognition of
this leads supporters to claim that:
The most important organization in the world is the company: the basis
of the prosperity of the West and the best hope for the future of the rest
of the world.5
In other words, while firms benefit greatly from a stable and enlightened
society, society also benefits greatly from a vigorous, competitive set of for-
profit firms. In considering these tradeoffs and tensions, however, it is
important to remind ourselves that juxtaposing firms and society in this way,
as many in the CSR community continue to do, suggests that firms and
society are independent of each other. In reality, of course, they are insepar
able. Firms exist as part of society in the same way that society is made up of
many functioning parts, an important component of which is for-profit firms.
14 Business is social progress
Equally, managers, board directors, employees, and shareholders each have
additional roles elsewhere in society (as consumers, activists, volunteers, com
munity members, etc.), as well as working together at the same for-
profit firm.
In essence, therefore, business and society are interwoven – their interests
are aligned and business has as much to gain from a strong and healthy society
as society has to lose from a constrained and ineffective business sector. The
question, therefore, is not What do firms owe society? or What does society owe
firms? but, instead, is the more nuanced debate about What role do firms play in
society? While social progress over centuries demonstrates the inescapable
value of for-profit firms within a market-based system, each firm should be
routinely assessed to determine whether their individual contribution is net
positive or net negative. Where it is net positive, we need to ask Is that contri
bution as good as it can be? Alternatively, where it is net negative, we should
inquire How can we introduce incentives to improve performance? But, each firm’s
interest lies not in waiting for this evaluation to be imposed externally, but
initiating it to ensure its operations meet the ever-shifting expectations placed
upon it. Paul Polman understands this iterative dynamic better than most:
Because the relationship between firms and the societies in which they
operate is symbiotic, because firms are able to combine resources on a scale
and with an efficiency that no other human-invented entity can match, and
because there is an ethical and moral component to all aspects of business/
human decisions, it is vital to understand the role of for-profit firms in
society. The behavior of firms (how they do what they do) affects not only
our material wellbeing, but all other aspects of our quality of life and, by a
large margin, they are the dominant predictor of that outcome – from our
experiences at work, to the products we buy, to the air that we breathe; cor
porations define the lives that we live.
As such, the for-profit firm is cause both for celebration and concern. It is
true, for example, that, as a rule, societies that provide more freedom for their
for-profit firms to operate will experience more innovation and progress than
those societies that do not. It is also true that we should expect this relation
ship to hold consistently, all else being equal. Of course, however, all else is
not equal, which is the reason for writing this book, and today many feel
there is more reason than usual for concern:
As with many things in life, the relationship between economic freedom and
societal progress is not linear. While the correlation is undoubtedly positive,
there are limits to the value of untrammeled economic freedom. It does not
necessarily hold, for example, that complete freedom for firms equals
maximum societal progress. If we did not have controls on the use of toxic
16 Business is social progress
chemicals in consumer products, there is plenty of evidence to suggest that
some firms would take advantage of consumer ignorance and use those chem
icals, irrespective of the consequences for public health. Similarly, there is a
reason why we place restrictions on the marketing and sales of products that
are deemed to be socially harmful, such as alcohol and tobacco. There are
good reasons why we allow firms to emit only certain levels of pollutants into
the atmosphere or waste stream; there are also reasons why we pressure firms
to curb their marketing to vulnerable segments of society, such as children,
and so on, and so on.
Rampant, unrestrained capitalism is unlikely to maximize value, broadly
defined. A capitalist system that is constrained through a series of checks and
balances, however, promises outcomes that serve a broad set of interests.
Firms have micro interests and societies have macro interests. A problem
arises, therefore, when the interests of the firm and the interests of society
conflict. When this happens, those societies with fewer controls over firms
will still experience a large degree of innovation, but it will likely result in a
reduction in overall value as firms innovate and bring those innovations to
market in ways that suit their short-term interests, but work against the
longer-term, competing interests of society. The optimal situation is to have
the interests of the firm overlap with the interests of the broader society, with
both parties working to generate constructive, mutually beneficial outcomes.
You can’t just ask customers what they want and then try to give that to
them. By the time you get it built, they’ll want something new.12
Summary
Principle 1 states that Business is social progress. It argues that the for-profit firm
is the most important organizational form because it is best able to convert
valuable and scarce resources into products that we demand that, persistently,
raise the overall standard of living. The incentive to innovate is central to this
process, but innovation occurs elsewhere in society, too. Irrespective of its
origin, for-profit firms excel when they seek to bring such innovation to
market. Integral to this process are the multitude of decisions, laden with
ethical and moral implications, that the firm makes every day. While self-
interest is a powerful motivator, value is optimized in its broadest sense when
the interests of the firm overlap significantly with the interests of its invested
stakeholders. SVC represents the mechanism by which these interests are
aligned.
Principle 2
Shareholders do not own the firm
Key takeaway: Contrary to popular myth, shareholders are not the legal
owners of the firm. Similarly, managers do not have a fiduciary responsibility
to maximize shareholder value. Instead, the firm is an independent legal entity
that should be run in the interests of its broad set of stakeholders.
As argued in Principle 1, for-profit firms are the most effective way we have
devised to advance social wellbeing. Because firms are part of society and
society is constructed of multiple components, including firms, the interests
of the firm and the interests of society are inextricably interwoven. In other
words, business is not a zero-sum exchange, but an ongoing reciprocal rela
tionship between the for-profit firm and its various invested constituents.
Together, all of these stakeholders, plus firms, form the broader group that
we refer to as society. An answer to the fundamental question that we face
(What is the purpose of the for-profit firm in society?), therefore, is best achieved
when the interests of the firm and its stakeholders are aligned.
This iterative relationship stems from the origins of the corporation and
the evolution of this organizational form throughout history. In particular, it
relates directly to the introduction of limited liability in the mid-nineteenth
century.1 Prior to this point, corporate charters were granted by the state as a
privilege (rather than a right) and under strict conditions in terms of the pro
jects that were to be completed (e.g., building a bridge or a railroad) and the
length of time the corporation was allowed to exist. Importantly, these pro
jects were determined on the basis of perceived societal need, rather than the
ability of the firm to make a profit:
In the legal environment of the 1800s, the state in the initial formula
tion of corporate law could revoke the charter of a corporation if it
failed to act in the public good, and routinely did so. For instance,
banks lost their charters in Mississippi, Ohio, and Pennsylvania for
“committing serious violations that were likely to leave them in an
insolvent or financially unsound condition.” In Massachusetts and
Shareholders do not own the firm 21
New York, charters of turnpike corporations were revoked for “not
keeping their roads in repair.”2
And, when the specified project was completed, the corporation ceased to
exist. In short, the corporation existed at the pleasure of the state:3
Understanding the true nature of the relationship between the firm and its
investors is therefore necessary to re-orient firms to act in the interests of
society as a whole. In short, it is essential in order to adopt Sustainable Value
Creation (SVC) as the managing philosophy of a firm.
Limited liability
The great value of limited liability is that it enabled corporations to raise the
capital that was needed to finance the infrastructure that fueled the industrial
revolution. In particular, limited liability allowed firms to build the railways,
canals, and bridges that were central to economic development in the West
22 Shareholders do not own the firm
during the nineteenth century (particularly in the United Kingdom and
United States). As such, at least in its original formulation, the idea of share
holders as a firm’s owners had some validity because, while stocks were still
traded, the primary purpose of shares was to raise capital and provide a return
on that investment from the firm to its investors. Over time, however, the
shareholder’s role and value to the firm has evolved.
Today, on the surface, the relationship between the firm and its share
holders appears unchanged. Many people believe that the primary function of
the stock market is for firms to raise the capital they need to finance their
business and, indeed, when firms initially list their shares, this transfer of funds
from investor to entrepreneur occurs. In reality, however, this initial trans
action is only a minor part of the stock market’s function. Increasingly, it has
evolved into a forum for the subsequent trading of those shares, rather than
for their initial offering. This shift represents the difference between a trade
for which the firm receives money (the initial listing) to one where it receives
no money (a subsequent trade between third parties).
As a firm’s shares continue to trade and a track record of performance is
established, the share price increasingly becomes a vote of confidence in the
firm’s current management team and its future potential. In other words,
when I buy a share in Apple, I almost certainly buy it not from the company,
but from another investor who is seeking to sell that share. The price on
which we agree reflects our respective bets on the future success of the
company. I buy at a price that I believe is lower than it will be in the future,
while the seller sells at a price they believe is higher than it will be in the
future. So, we place our respective bets and the trade is made. In the process,
however, an important shift has occurred in the primary function of the stock
market and of investors who buy and sell shares today, not because they
expect to influence a firm’s strategic direction but because they hope to profit
from the strategic direction that has already been decided by management.
Although activist investors occasionally win seats on a board by amassing
significant share holdings, these investors are a minority. In reality, most
shareholders can only express their opinions about a firm’s management by
holding, buying, or selling shares.
The consequences of this shift in the underlying relationship between the
firm and its shareholders is reflected in the evolving role of stock markets,
which are neither efficient (in terms of complete and freely available informa
tion guiding capital allocation) nor public (in terms of equal and evenly dis
tributed access). Stock markets have benefits (in terms of liquidity and
enabling retirement saving), but it is legitimate to question the overall value
they provide. This is especially true today as the majority of trades on any of
the major exchanges are made by high-frequency algorithms – computers
running programs and holding positions for micro-seconds:
Each day around 7bn shares worth $320bn change hands on America’s
stockmarket. Much of that volume is high-frequency trading, in which
Shareholders do not own the firm 23
stocks are flipped at speed in order to capture fleeting gains. High-
frequency traders, acting as middle-men, are involved in half of the daily
trading volumes. … rules-based investors now make the majority of
trades. … The total value of American public equities is $31tn, as meas
ured by the Russell 3000, an index. The three types of computer-
managed funds – index funds, ETFs and quant funds – run around 35%
of this. Human managers, such as traditional hedge funds and other
mutual funds, manage just 24%.7
[One] group spent $300m to lay a cable in the straightest possible line from
Chicago to New York, cutting through mountains and under car parks,
just so the time taken to send a signal back and forth could be cut from 17
milliseconds to 13. In return, the group could charge traders $14m a year
to use the line. Traders were willing to shell out those fees because those
fractions of a second might generate annual profits of $20 billion.10
Almost all of these stock trades are third-party transactions in which
the firm receives no capital. The overall effect is to drive a wedge
between the interests of the shareholder (return on investment) and the
managers of the firm (sustainable competitive advantage). As pools of
assets are increasingly managed by a concentrated number of massive
investment firms, this wedge grows larger. Take BlackRock, for example,
which, along with Vanguard and State Street (the “Big Three”), are now
“the largest shareholder in just over 40% of listed American firms,”11 and
are predicted to be “less than a decade away” from managing more than
$20 trillion.12 Firms such as BlackRock (the largest asset manager in the
world with “more than $6trn of assets under management”)13 specialize
in what are known as passive investments, such as exchange-traded funds
(ETFs), which attempt to mirror (rather than outperform) the perform
ance of the markets while minimizing fees to their clients.14 The traders
who work for firms like BlackRock therefore have little interest in the
24 Shareholders do not own the firm
day-to-day management of the firms in which they invest. By definition,
traders that seek to mirror market performance invest in proportion to
the size of each firm in the market, rather than caring necessarily whether
Firm A performs better or worse than Firm B.
In response, some concede that, while shareholders may not control the firm,
they still own it. But, does ownership not encompass the ability to control? It
is very difficult to think of a definition of ownership that does not also include
aspects of control or authority over the thing that is owned. The Oxford
English Dictionary, for example, defines ownership as the “act, state, or right of
possessing something,” with possession defined as “the state of having, owning,
or controlling something.”18 Yet clearly, shareholders do not control the firm.
A legal person
Irrespective of dictionary or intuitive definitions of ownership, what does the
law say about the relationship between the firm and its shareholders? Given
the extent to which the idea that shareholders are the “legally defined”
owners of the firm is believed throughout society, it would follow that such a
fact is unambiguously stated in law and demonstrated via legal precedent.19 In
the place of clarity, however, the evidence suggests there is ambiguity:
Essentially, being a shareholder entitles the owner of that share to a few spe
cific and highly limited rights: they are able to vote (although the practical
application of shareholder democracy is weak and narrow); they are able to
receive dividends (only as long as the firm is willing to issue them); and they
are able to offer their share for sale to a third-party at a time of their choos
ing. These rights constitute a contractual relationship between the firm and
the shareholder, but do not constitute ownership. As noted by Eugene Fama,
one of the originators of the agency theory of the firm, “Ownership of capital
should not be confused with ownership of the firm.”23
But, if the shareholders do not own the firm, then who does? One of the
great advantages of the LLC (Limited Liability Company) form is that the
organization is recognized as an independent entity in the eyes of the law (a
legal person). As such, the firm, as an artificial person, has many of the rights
(although, it seems, fewer of the responsibilities) of a human being or natural
person. It can own assets; it can sue and be sued; it can enter into contracts;
and, in the U.S., it has the right to freedom of speech (which it exercises by
spending money). It is these rights (the right to be sued, in particular) that
allow investors to have their legal liability limited to the extent of their
investment. In short, the firm is a legal creation that exists, by design, inde
pendently of all other actors “and it is the corporation not the individual
shareholders, that is liable for its debts.”24
This concept of the firm as a legal person is established in the subconscious
of society in the same way that the idea that firms are owned by their share
holders is also established. The difference between the two is that the idea of
the corporation as a person is legally defined, while the idea of shareholders as
owners is not. In fact, the unique legal status of corporations is constitution
ally protected. Following the Civil War, the Fourteenth Amendment was
26 Shareholders do not own the firm
passed to protect the rights of recently freed African-American slaves. In par
ticular, it stipulates that the states cannot “deprive any person of life, liberty,
or property without due process of law.” It is via the Fourteenth Amendment
that corporations appropriated those rights for themselves.25 In other words,
the U.S. Supreme Court has agreed with the argument that corporations are
legally similar to real people and, as such, enjoy similar constitutionally pro
tected rights. The fact that the root of this legal status lies in the Fourteenth
Amendment, specifically passed to prevent the ownership of individuals by
others, reinforces the idea that the corporation is an independent legal
entity.26
A similar legal foundation for the idea that shareholders own the firm does
not exist, in spite of the popular perception that it is true. In other words, as
even supporters of the notion of shareholder primacy note, “shareholder
wealth maximization is widely accepted at the level of rhetoric but largely
ignored as a matter of policy implementation.”27 The reason for this is that,
even if it was an ideal, “the rule of wealth maximization for shareholders is
virtually impossible to enforce as a practical matter.”28 As a direct result, under
U.S. corporate law, courts are reluctant to intervene in the business decisions
of a firm unless there is evidence of fraud, misappropriation of funds, or some
other illegal activity. The law is clear that corporations are managed by the
board of directors who have “broad latitude to run companies as they see
fit.”29 Although shareholders nominally have the right to vote for directors,
nominating candidates is extremely difficult and, once elected, directors can
ignore shareholder interests. Although shareholders can protest in terms of
resolutions at AGMs, “only certain kinds of shareholder votes – such as for
mergers or dissolutions – are typically binding. Most are purely advisory”:30
This business judgment rule (see below) is similar to common law in the United
Kingdom, which refers to the board and senior managers as the “controlling
mind and will” of the company. This finding can be traced back to a 1957
Court of Appeal decision by Lord Denning, in which the judge made a dis
tinction between the hands and brains of a company:
The legal relationship between the firm and its shareholders is most clearly
defined in the event of a bankruptcy – shareholders’ claims to the firm’s assets
lie behind those of bondholders and all other creditors. In theory, share
holders have a claim to the future earned profits of the firm. In reality, that
claim is weak, with no right to demand the firm issue dividends or buyback
shares if it does not wish to do so. In essence, the reason limited liability is so
important (because it enables investors to limit their risk while allowing firms
to raise capital from multiple sources) also explains why the shareholder is
legally impotent in terms of ownership:33
courts in the United States have on several occasions clearly stated that
directors are not agents of the shareholders but fiduciaries of the corpora
tion. Section 172 of the U.K. Companies Act 2006, moreover, requires
directors to act in the way they consider, in good faith, would be most
likely to promote the long-term success of the company for the benefits
of its members as a whole, heeding the likely consequences of their deci
sions on stakeholders such as customers, suppliers, and community, not
simply shareholders. The Law even allows the board to put the interests
of other stakeholders over and above those of shareholders.41
The legal foundation for the belief in the primacy of shareholder interests
rests largely on a single case decided in 1919 by the Michigan Supreme
Court – Dodge v. Ford Motor Co.42 In the case, two brothers, John Francis
Dodge and Horace Elgin Dodge (who, together, owned 10% of Ford’s
shares), sued Henry Ford because of his decision to distribute surplus profit
to customers in the form of lower prices for his cars, rather than to share
holders in the form of a dividend. As noted above, however, the value of
this case as legal precedent for the idea that the firm must operate in the
interests of its shareholders is disputed. As Lynn Stout explains in her analysis
of this case, contrary to widespread perceptions and norms, there is no
obligation on managers or directors to focus the firm’s efforts primarily on
maximizing shareholder value:
Dodge v. Ford is … bad law, at least when cited for the proposition that
the corporate purpose is, or should be, maximizing shareholder wealth.
Dodge v. Ford is a mistake, … a doctrinal oddity largely irrelevant to cor
porate law and corporate practice. What is more, courts and legislatures
alike treat it as irrelevant. In the past thirty years, the Delaware courts
have cited Dodge v. Ford as authority in only one unpublished case, and
then not on the subject of corporate purpose, but on another legal ques
tion entirely.43
United States corporate law does not, and never has, required directors
of public corporations to maximize either share price or shareholder
wealth. To the contrary, as long as boards do not use their power to
enrich themselves, the law gives them a wide range of discretion to run
public corporations with other goals in mind, including growing the
firm, creating quality products, protecting employees, and serving the
public interest.47
There is even precedent to suggest that courts will favor the firm’s directors
over shareholders when the investors have been deceived, basing investment
decisions on the firm’s publicly stated goals, even if those statements later turn
out to be false.48 A lack of competence or an honest mistake are not sufficient
to override the courts’ reluctance to interfere with the running of the firm.
Unless it can be proved that the directors acted dishonestly or with the inten
tion to deceive, the business will be allowed to rise or fall on the basis of its
operational decisions. Although this issue has been studied and debated by
corporate legal scholars, however, it is less well known in the business school.
This is important and should change:
Key takeaway: Implementing SVC requires the firm to operate in the inter
ests of its stakeholders, broadly defined. While identifying these stakeholders is
easy, however, stakeholder theory will only be of practical value when it helps
managers prioritize among competing stakeholder interests.
A stakeholder
An individual or organization that is affected by the firm (either voluntarily or
involuntarily), and possesses the capacity and intent to affect the firm.
Stakeholder definition and prioritization 35
In identifying and understanding the interests of its core stakeholders, the firm
may find it helpful to divide these constituents into three separate groups:
organizational stakeholders (internal to the firm), and economic and societal stake
holders (external to the firm). Together, these three kinds of stakeholders
form a metaphorical concentric set of circles with the firm and its organiza
tional stakeholders at the center within a larger circle that signifies the firm’s
economic stakeholders. Both of these circles sit within the largest outside
circle, which represents the firm’s operating context and its societal
stakeholders.
Within this overall classification, all possible actors fit primarily into one of
the three stakeholder groups. First, stakeholders exist within the organization
and include the firm’s employees, managers, and directors. Taken together,
these internal stakeholders constitute the operational core of the organization
and, therefore, should be its primary concern. Second are economic stake
holders that include the firm’s shareholders, consumers, creditors, and com
petitors. The interactions these stakeholders have with the firm are driven
primarily by financial concerns. As such, these stakeholders fulfill an important
role as the interface between the organization and its larger social context in
ways that create bonds of accountability. Third are those stakeholders that
constitute the broader political and social environment in which the firm
operates. Examples of these stakeholders include government agencies and
regulators, the media, and the broader communities in which the firm oper
ates (including non-governmental organizations, NGOs, and other activist
groups). These societal stakeholders are essential for the firm in terms of pro
viding the legitimacy necessary for it to survive over the medium to long
term.8
This model of concentric circles indicates the primary association of each
actor, but it is important to recognize that almost all stakeholders exist simul
taneously as multiple stakeholder types with network ties among each of
them, as well as with the firm.9 A company’s employees, for example, are
primarily organizational stakeholders, but are also occasional customers of the
firm, as well as being members of the society in which the firm operates. The
government that regulates the firm’s industry, however, is only a societal
stakeholder and has no direct economic relationship with the company
(beyond the taxes it levies and the subsidies it pays), nor is it a formal part of
the organization. The firm’s economic stakeholders represent the interface
between the organizational and societal stakeholders. A firm’s customers are,
first and foremost, economic stakeholders. They are not organizational stake
holders (unless they are also employees), but they are part of the society in
which the firm operates. They are also one of the primary means by which
the firm delivers its product and interacts with its society. Without the eco
nomic interface, a firm loses its mechanism of accountability, and therefore its
legitimacy, over the long term.
The three layers of a firm’s stakeholders all sit within the larger context of a
business environment that is shaped by macro-level forces such as globalization,
36 Stakeholder definition and prioritization
climate change, and the increasing affluence that is driving development and
raising the expectations different societies place on their for-profit firms,
worldwide.
Prioritizing stakeholders
In spite of its importance to the concept of SVC, stakeholder theory can only
be of value to the firm when it accounts fully for the dynamic environment
in which business is conducted. In particular, while stakeholder theory is con
ceptually useful for managers in terms of defining those groups with an
interest in the firm’s operations, it has been much less instructive in providing
a practical roadmap for implementation. There is a reason for this – while
accounting for a broader range of interests is valuable, it also complicates a
firm’s decisions more often than not:
Customers want lower prices and higher quality; employees want higher
wages and better benefits and better working conditions; suppliers want
to give fewer discounts and want you to pick up more of their products;
communities want more donations; governments want higher taxes;
investors want higher dividends and higher stock prices – every one of
the stakeholders wants more, they always want more.11
Stakeholder definition and prioritization 37
Each stakeholder group “will define the purpose of the business in terms of
its own needs and desires, and each perspective is valid and legitimate.”12 As
such, it is essential for the firm to be able to identify any potential conflict
and, where possible, act to mitigate the potential operational threat. In other
words, the businesses most likely to succeed in today’s rapidly evolving global
marketplace will be those best able to adapt to their dynamic environment by
balancing the conflicting interests of multiple stakeholders. It can even be
argued that, at its core, the fundamental “job of management is to maintain
an equitable and working balance among the claims of the various … interest
groups” that are directly affected by the firm’s operations.13 Just because an
individual or organization merits inclusion in a firm’s list of relevant stake
holders, however, does not compel the firm (either legally or logically) to
comply with every demand that they make. Doing so would be counter
productive as the business would be forced to spend all its time addressing
these different demands and negotiating among stakeholders with diametri
cally opposed requests. A key function of the ability to prioritize stakeholder
interests, therefore, is determining which stakeholders warrant the firm’s
attention and when.
The concentric circles of organizational, economic, and societal stake
holders discussed above provide an initial guide to prioritization. By identify
ing the firm’s key stakeholders within each category, managers can prioritize
the needs and interests of certain groups over others. In addition, among cat
egories, as a general rule, stakeholders decrease in importance to the firm the
further they are removed from core operations. Implicit in this discussion,
therefore, is the idea that organizational stakeholders are a firm’s most
important set of constituents. Organizational stakeholders are followed in
importance by a firm’s economic stakeholders, who provide it with the eco
nomic capital to survive. Finally, a firm’s societal stakeholders deliver it with
the social capital that is central to the firm’s legitimacy and long-term validity,
but are of less immediate importance in terms of day-to-day operations.
In seeking to prioritize its stakeholders, however, a firm needs to keep two
key points in mind: First, no organization can afford to ignore consistently
the interests of an important stakeholder, even if that group is less important
in the relative hierarchy of stakeholders or is removed from day-to-day oper
ations. A good example of this is the government, which is a societal stake
holder and, therefore, is in theory less important than an organizational or
economic stakeholder. It would not be wise, however, for a firm to ignore
the government repeatedly in relation to an important issue that enjoys broad
societal support. Given that the government has the power to constrain or
support industries in ways that affect profit levels dramatically, it is only
rational that firms should be constantly aware of the government’s basic needs
and requests.
Second, it is vital to remember that the relative importance of stakeholders
will differ from firm-to-firm, from issue-to-issue, and from time-to-time.
And, depending on these factors, the change in relative ordering can be
38 Stakeholder definition and prioritization
dramatic. As such, addressing the fluctuating needs of stakeholders and
meeting them wherever possible is essential for firms to survive in today’s
dynamic business environment. In order to do this, it is important that man
agers have a framework that will enable them to prioritize stakeholder inter
ests for a given issue and account for those expectations in formulating a
strategic response.
The key to building such a framework revolves around three moving
parts: the firm, the issue, and the stakeholder. First, the firm. Any for-profit
organization has strategic interests that determine the industries in which it
operates and the products or services that it produces. In addition, the firm
has market goals that outline future levels of performance that it deems both
attainable and desirable (such as percentage market share or a particular level
of sales). Together, these strategic interests and market goals determine the
firm’s operational priorities. With this benchmark in mind, managers are able
to gauge the strategic relevance of any particular issue.
Second, the issue. The key factor with any issue that arises is the extent to
which it is relevant to the firm’s operational priorities. There has been some
useful work in this area by Simon Zadek (founder and CEO of the consul
tancy AccountAbility) that firms can use to evaluate which issues pose the
greatest potential opportunity and danger.14 First, Zadek identifies the five
stages of learning that organizations go through “when it comes to develop
ing a sense of corporate responsibility.”15 Then, he combines these five stages
of learning with four stages of intensity “to measure the maturity of societal
issues and the public’s expectations around the issues.”16 The maximum
danger, Zadek argues, is for companies that are in defensive mode when
facing an institutionalized issue, as they will be ignoring something that
potentially poses a significant threat to their business. A firm that continues
to deny the existence of climate change, for example, falls into this category.
In contrast, those businesses that are promoting industry-wide adoption of
standard practices in relation to a newly emerging issue stand to gain the
maximum economic and social value for their effort (notwithstanding
the risks involved). Even more effective, for those firms willing to take a
bold stand on “issues that are contested enough to feel hot, but that have
pretty strong consensus from the tastemakers, mavens and social-media influ
encers of the day,” they both help move the idea to the mainstream, while
positioning themselves to reap the benefits when it arrives.17 Once the firm
has established an issue as operationally relevant and worked out what posi
tion it favors, the next step is to identify those stakeholders that are most
affected.
Third, the stakeholder. In addition to identifying the importance of a par
ticular issue, the firm must account for its various stakeholders. A firm’s stake
holder relations will vary within stakeholders and across issues; they will also
vary within issues and across stakeholders. In other words, each stakeholder
will have a number of issues that it values. The range of issues will not be
valued equally, however, with some prioritized as more important than
Stakeholder definition and prioritization 39
others. Similarly, for each issue the firm faces, its different stakeholders will
have different positions, pushing the firm to respond in one way or another
(or another). The firm’s ability to understand how important an issue is to
any one stakeholder, and how its stakeholders will vary in response to any
one issue, will depend on the depth of the relationship already established. It
is a key aspect of stakeholder theory in implementation that any firm is better
placed to understand its stakeholders if it has already established strong rela
tionships based on trust. If the firm is contacting a stakeholder for the first
time only in response to a crisis, its outreach is likely to be less well received.
If, however, the firm has an established relationship and is already aware of
the needs and positions of the stakeholder, when a crisis arrives, the potential
for a value-added solution is higher.
A decision-making model
Once the three factors (firm, issue, and stakeholder) have been considered
independently, it is necessary for the manager to combine them on an
ongoing basis to determine the appropriate response. This is achieved by con
sidering the three factors in terms of four dimensions: Strategic relevance, Issue
evolution, Stakeholder motivation, and Operational impact. Strategic relevance
captures how important an issue is to the firm – in other words, how proxi
mal it is to the firm’s core competency or source of competitive advantage.
Issue evolution captures the extent to which the issue has become institutional
ized – in other words, the extent to which it has become accepted business
practice. Stakeholder motivation captures how important the issue is to each
stakeholder – in other words, how likely that group is to act in response.
And, Operational impact captures the extent to which a particular stakeholder
group can affect firm operations – in other words, the stakeholder’s ability to
damage reputation, diminish earnings, or demotivate employees.
The extent to which a firm should act in response to a stakeholder concern
about a particular issue, therefore, is determined by the interaction of these
four dimensions.18 The goal is to build a multistep process by which managers
can account for variance in the strategic interests of the firm, the evolution of
each issue, the motivation of the stakeholder(s), and the potential operational
impact of any response. The resulting analysis enables managers to decide
how best to prioritize stakeholder concerns and when to act. Importantly, this
framework should be embedded within a culture of outreach to stakeholders
that allows firms to understand their evolving concerns and assess which issues
are more or less important to which group. It also should be repeated on a
regular basis since any issue will continue to evolve and stakeholders’ interests
will adapt, accordingly. Ultimately, when the firm’s strategic interests are rel
evant, an issue is important, stakeholders are motivated, and there is the
potential for damage due to intransigence, the firm is compelled to act and
act quickly to protect its interests and preserve its relations with stakeholders.
This iterative process can be summarized in a seven-step model of stakeholder
40 Stakeholder definition and prioritization
prioritization that empowers managers to analyze the firm’s operating
environment on an ongoing basis:
Summary
Principle 3 states that, while identifying stakeholders is easy, Prioritizing com
peting stakeholder interests is difficult. It lays out the broad ideas behind stake
holder theory, which is the intellectual backbone of SVC. Importantly,
however, it also extends stakeholder theory by moving beyond merely defin
ing a firm’s stakeholders to developing a seven-step process of prioritization as
a decision-making tool managers can use to extract the maximum value of a
stakeholder perspective. It is the intersection of the firm’s strategic interests,
the evolution of a particular issue, and the stakeholder’s motivations to
respond (and the impact those responses can have) that determine the need
for the firm to act.
Principle 4
CSR is a stakeholder responsibility
Key takeaway: CSR will only work if firms are rewarded for acting and pun
ished for failing to act. As such, while CSR includes a responsibility for a firm to
meet the needs and demands of its stakeholders, the stakeholders themselves
have an equal, if not more important, responsibility to hold the firm to account.
The change in emphasis that forms the core of this definition is subtle, but
the implication for our understanding of what CSR means is radical. To this
end, it is worth keeping two points in mind: First, this reciprocal relationship
does not remove the moral and ethical dimensions of economic exchange.
On the contrary, these factors are embedded in the decisions all stakeholders
take in determining which firms to engage with and which actions to
endorse. As such, this reconceptualization of CSR shifts the role of morals
and ethics in the debate away from absolute standards that are imposed arti
ficially on firms, toward the relative values of each stakeholder that, together,
constitute the convoluted environment to which firms have to operate,
every day.
Second, this division of responsibilities should not be seen as a burden, but
as empowering stakeholders to create the society in which they want to live.
Contrary to how they are often presented, firms are neither inherently evil
nor divinely angelic. As discussed in Principle 3, firms should not be anthro
pomorphized – they cannot be separated from the aggregated interests of their
collective set of stakeholders. Brands and companies are inert – it is the
people inside them that bring them to life. The for-profit firm is a group of
individuals that, collectively, reflects the values of those individuals. In the
same way that we get the politicians we deserve (by electing them), the way
we (as stakeholders) manage our relations with firms generates directly the
companies that dominate our economies. As such, the firm’s stakeholders
need to uphold the values and behavior that they say they want firms to
implement:
One report showed that ensuring good working conditions would add
less than one dollar to the price of a pair of blue jeans. But despite
44 CSR is a stakeholder responsibility
responding to surveys that they care about ethics, shoppers refuse to pay
more. In one study, only half of customers chose a pair of socks marked
“Good Working Conditions” even when they were the same price as an
unmarked pair; only one quarter of customers paid for the socks when
they cost 50 percent more.6
Stakeholder democracy
As these boundaries of acceptable behavior are formed, it is the responsibility
of firms to adhere to them, but it is also the responsibility of the firms’ stake
holders to enforce them. The outcome of this iterative process is akin to a
form of stakeholder democracy:
Summary
Principle 4 states that CSR is a stakeholder responsibility. If we are to achieve
the socially responsible outcomes we say we seek, it is essential that all parties
(the business and each of its stakeholder groups) play their part. While firms
have a responsibility (founded in self-interest) to accommodate, wherever
possible, the needs and concerns of their stakeholders, each stakeholder group
has a responsibility (founded in self-preservation and social progress) to shape
firms’ behavior through the expectations that it conveys via meaningful
engagement. This stakeholder responsibility is equally as important (if not more
so) as the responsibility of the firm.
Principle 5
Market-based solutions are optimal
Imperfect markets
The core idea around which Principle 5 is built is that markets trump all
other known means by which scarce and valuable resources are allocated on a
society-wide basis.2 The beauty of the market, in large part, is its chaotic
complexity, where structure somehow emerges out of a multitude of micro-
level individual decisions that aggregate into a stable macro-economic system.
As Friedrich Hayek noted long ago:
Johnson Controls joined real-estate firm Jones Lang LaSalle to retrofit the
Empire State Building for energy efficiency in 2012. The Clinton
Climate Initiative and Rocky Mountain Institute also collaborated on the
project. The groups estimate the project will cut energy costs by 38%,
saving $4.4m annually and reducing carbon emissions by 105,000 metric
tons over 15 years. Given that the building sector consumes up to 40% of
the world’s energy, energy efficiency is key to reducing our energy use.
Retrofitting for energy efficiency is good for the world, while also gen
erating profit for Johnson Controls. The power of financial motivation
… solved this problem.5
These flaws arise due to the fact that markets (like governments) are enacted
by humans. And, as James Madison astutely noted, “If men were angels, no
government would be necessary.”8 The inescapable presence of human influ
ence means that many of the theoretical assumptions underlying market inter
actions are undermined. Markets work best with complete information, for
example – that is, accurate information that is freely and equally available to
all participants. In the absence of these conditions (i.e., reality), markets
become imperfect. The reason why insider trading in shares is illegal is
because it directly transgresses on the assumption of complete information.9
Unfortunately, incomplete or asymmetric information is the norm. Some
times this is a result of deliberate manipulation (as in the case of insider
trading); more often, however, it is due to human limitations (an inability to
process large amounts of information, act rationally, ignore sunk costs,
evaluate opportunity costs, overcome biases and fears, and so on).10
One market that is often cited by supporters as purer than most is the stock
market. Yet, we know from prior financial crises that the stock market is
inherently challenged when it comes to pricing risk accurately. It is not even
clear that investors are good at assessing overall value. As Warren Buffett has
stated, “I’d be a bum on the street with a tin cup if the markets were always
efficient.”11 The prevalence of bubbles and the tendency toward herd behav
ior demonstrate that psychology and emotion play as large a part in determin
ing stock movements as rigorous analysis. Buffett’s success relies on traders
Market-based solutions are optimal 51
either under- or over-valuing shares as a result of imperfect information and
poor judgment, which allows so-called value traders to take advantage:
Mr. Buffett began an investment partnership in 1956 and, over the next
12 years, achieved a 29.5 percent compound return. … In comparison,
the Dow Jones industrial average rose by 7.4 percent per year during the
same period. Then, in 1965, Mr. Buffett took control of a small Massa
chusetts textile manufacturer and through a combination of buying stocks
and, later, buying entire companies, achieved a 19.7 percent annual
increase in Berkshire Hathaway’s stock price while the average was
increasing by 9.4 percent.12
The bottled water industry is a good example of how, even when faced with
such limitations, the market is able to overcome them – even while the solu
tion provided is replete with additional externalized costs (e.g., increased pro
duction of single-use plastics). Similarly, the example of access to clean water
demonstrates that, because of the flaws inherent in the application of market
ideology, some constraints are often beneficial. As detailed in Principle 4, the
ideal in an effective system of checks and balances is empowered and invested
stakeholders willing to hold the firm to account. This ensures the firm is
incentivized to act in the best interests of its collective set of stakeholders
(which, together, constitute society), rather than the interests of a narrow
select group, such as its shareholders. Although this perspective implies an
equal responsibility across all stakeholders, when CSR advocates envision
what such constraints might look like, they tend to focus disproportionately
on the role of the government. Of course, there is good reason for this as the
government has demonstrated, on many occasions, the value that can be
52 Market-based solutions are optimal
obtained for society by seeking to curb the strongest self-interested impulses
of for-profit firms:
Before the Clean Air Act was passed in 1970 many Americans led
shorter, sicker lives because of pollution. White-collar workers in Gary,
Indiana, a steel town, often went to work with an extra shirt because the
first one looked too dirty by midday. Between 1980 and 2012 total emis
sions of six common air pollutants in America dropped by 67%, accord
ing to the Environmental Protection Agency (EPA). This happened even
as the country’s population grew by 38% and Americans consumed 27%
more energy.15
Unintended consequences
When market forces are subverted with ulterior goals, unintended con
sequences are common. At the extreme, the actual consequences achieve the
opposite of those that were intended. An example of this might be if an
increase in the minimum wage (designed to protect low-wage earners) were
to result in a reduction in overall jobs (reducing the number of low-wage
jobs available). This effect is based on the assumption that:
A related term for this ability to convince ourselves that the best way to solve
our excessive resource depletion of the Earth is through further consumption
is “The Prius Fallacy.”21 By substituting one (possibly) greener product for
another, we kill two birds with one stone – we satisfy both our psychological
and material needs. We also give ourselves the moral license to continue con
suming – a process we are very good at rationalizing after the fact.22 What we
fail to realize is that, even as we innovate and consume, rather than reducing
our environmental impact, the unintended consequence is the opposite.
While generally ignored by environmentalists today, there are important
policy implications to be gleaned from this phenomenon:
During the time of British rule in colonial India, in order to free Delhi
from a plague of snakes, the City’s governor put an incentive scheme in
place for their capture by introducing a bounty on cobra skins. The
bounty was quite high as cobras are tricky to catch. And so, instead of
the snakes being caught in the city, it became a sound business idea to
start farming them. All of a sudden, the number of bounty claims
increased disproportionately. The local authority realised what was going
on and responded by abandoning the incentive scheme. And as they
were no longer profitable, the cobras were released from the farms into
the city, exacerbating the original problem.25
The key to avoiding such unforeseen consequences is, clearly, to ensure the
correct behavior is being incentivized:
In the example from India above, the desired outcome was a reduction of the
number of snakes in Delhi, but the action that was incentivized was an
increase in the number of snakes killed. As demonstrated, these things can
result in opposite outcomes in practice. In the case of calls to raise the
minimum wage, the goal is to reduce poverty and income disparity, but the
action prescribed is to increase the cost of labor. Although economists dis
agree on the effects of a minimum wage (some research indicates that small
increases have little or no effect on job creation), it is possible that in some
cases an increase would result in existing employees being fired (because the
employer can no longer afford to employ them) or a reduction in the number
of new hires (because the cost limits a planned expansion), hence vastly wors
ening the economic situation for these individuals:
The issue of unintended consequences is one of the most important issues for
the CSR community to address, particularly in relation to sustainability.
When we attempt to subvert centuries of economic development, substitut
ing altruistic motivation for economic incentives, we should tread carefully.
Whether it is government subsidies or tax breaks for a particular kind of
alternative energy, or a new technical innovation that interacts with some
other factor (or is applied inappropriately), the result is often an unexpected
outcome that can detract from, rather than promote, overall value. That is
not to say that government intervention is necessarily unwarranted or unhelp
ful. In fact, in terms of shaping the rules of the game to ensure a level playing
field and enforce existing regulations, the government is an essential stake
holder of the firm – what David Sainsbury in his manifesto for progressive capit
alism refers to as an “enabling state,” with responsibilities to support, rather
than direct, markets:
The woollen coat, for example, which covers the day-labourer, as coarse
and rough as it may appear, is the produce of the joint labour of a multi
tude of workmen. The shepherd, the sorter of the wool, the wool-
comber or carder, the dyer, the scribbler, the spinner, the weaver, the
fuller, the dresser, with many others, must all join their different arts in
order to complete even this homely production. … Let us consider only
what a variety of labour is requisite in order to form that very simple
machine, the shears with which the shepherd clips the wool. The miner,
the builder of the furnace for smelting the ore, the feller of the timber,
the burner of the charcoal to be made use of in the smelting-house, the
56 Market-based solutions are optimal
brick-maker, the brick-layer, the workmen who attend the furnace, the
mill-wright, the forger, the smith. … Without the assistance and co
operation of many thousands, the very meanest person in a civilized
country could not be provided, even according to what we very falsely
imagine, the easy and simple manner in which he is commonly
accommodated.29
Behavioral economics
In 2002, the psychologist Daniel Kahneman won the Nobel Prize for Eco
nomics for his work on the cognitive biases of humans. In his 2011 book,
Thinking, Fast and Slow,31 he notes that the human brain works with two
systems – one that helps make decisions rapidly based on emotion (“fast
thinking”), while a second helps make decisions more deliberately (“slow
thinking”), but often rationalizes the choices generated by the first system.
Market-based solutions are optimal 57
The combination creates a contrast between the rational, agentic decision-
makers that we think we are and the emotional, impulsive decision-makers
that the evidence suggests we are more often:
Although humans are not irrational, they often need help to make more
accurate judgments and better decisions, and in some cases policies and
institutions can provide that help. … The assumption that agents are
rational provides the intellectual foundation for the libertarian approach
to public policy: do not interfere with the individual’s right to choose,
unless the choices harm others. … For behavioral economists, however,
freedom has a cost, which is borne by individuals who make bad choices,
and by a society that feels obligated to help them.32
Many of these ideas, which integrate insights from economics and psychology
(social and cognitive), form the foundation of what today is known as behavi
oral (or nudge)33 economics. The advantage of behavioral economics is that it
works with what we know of the imperfections in human nature to curb the
raw excesses of market forces, yet preserves the illusion of choice that markets
enable and is an essential component of an open society:
In one trial, a letter sent to non-payers of vehicle taxes was changed to use
plainer English, along the line of “pay your tax or lose your car”. In some
cases the letter was further personalised by including a photo of the car in
question. The rewritten letter alone doubled the number of people paying
the tax; the rewrite with the photo tripled it. … A study into the teaching
of technical drawing in French schools found that if the subject was called
“geometry” boys did better, but if it was called “drawing” girls did equally
well or better. Teachers are now being trained to use the appropriate term.35
My first instinct was to agree with this quote. After all, government has con
sistently demonstrated an inability to shape outcomes as effectively as markets.
On second thoughts, however, it is clear we are often incapable of making
ideal (or even beneficial) decisions when left to our own intuition. Because
humans are driven by our inherent and persistent fallibilities (bounded ration
ality, innate biases, emotional impulses, and cognitive constraints), we often
Market-based solutions are optimal 59
make short-term decisions that do not serve our long-term interests. This
happens even when we are trying to be rational – there are good reasons, for
example, why many people fail to save enough money for their retirement,
even when they have the capacity (sufficient earnings) and tools (corporate
pension plans) to do so.
Given that we are living in a system designed for and operated by humans,
where is the balance between government oversight and individual enter
prise? As an integral component of SVC, behavioral economics helps push
the debate in a helpful direction. Cass Sunstein, who wrote Nudge with
Richard Thaler,39 for example, draws on human frailties, such as “‘framing
effects’ (our interpretation of facts is affected by how they are presented to us)
and ‘status-quo bias’ (we prefer the status quo, simply because it is the status
quo, over potential alternatives) to promote what he calls ‘libertarian
paternalism’ ”:40
what we are today is, to a very large extent, a function of what we were
yesterday. … this means [for business practitioners] that there is not likely
to be any escape from the very powerful motive of private gain and
profit, which is often at variance with social interest.42
Nudge economics incorporates the biases and prejudices that inform our
decisions into policies that encourage optimal social outcomes, while still
retaining the illusion of choice. As such, it is a valuable consideration in the
debate between government oversight and unrestricted market forces and,
therefore, is an important part of SVC.
Summary
Principle 5 states that Market-based solutions are optimal. It argues that, while
markets are far from perfect, they are the most efficient means we have of
allocating scarce and valuable resources via the for-profit firms that populate
them. More importantly, the evidence suggests that, when we seek to subvert
these highly developed forces, however well-intentioned, the result is often
an unintended consequence that destroys (rather than creates) value. One way
to curb the raw excesses of market forces, yet preserve the illusion of choice
that markets enable, is the wider use of behavioral economics to help nudge
individuals to make decisions that better serve their own (and society’s)
interests.
Principle 6
Profit = total value
Key takeaway: In essence, a firm’s profit represents the ability to sell a good
or service at a higher price than what it costs to produce. Production and con
sumption, however, are more than merely technical decisions. They encap
sulate the total value (to all stakeholders) that is added by the firm.
The existence of a profit is an indication prima facie that the business has
succeeded in producing something which consumers want and value. …
a business that fails to make an adequate profit is a house of cards. It
cannot grow or provide more jobs or pay higher wages. In the long run,
it cannot even survive. It offers no stability or security or opportunity for
its workers and investors. It cannot meet its broader obligations to
society. It is a failure from all points of view.1
I would amend this quote only to replace the narrow stakeholder group, con
sumers, with the much broader concept of society. If a society (the collective
set of all stakeholders) permits a firm to continue operations, then it is
acknowledging that it adds value – that society is better off than if the firm
did not exist. At present, the best method we have of measuring that value is
the profit the firm generates. This statement is core to the idea of Sustainable
Value Creation (SVC), but exists in contrast to the way profit is often dis
cussed within the CSR community – as a narrow measure of economic value
and something that can detract from social, moral, and ethical value. This
representation of economic value as an independent construct, separate from
other kinds of value, demonstrates a misunderstanding of what profit is and
how it is generated. In reality, a firm’s profit represents the total value added,
to all stakeholders, as a result of ongoing operations.
62 Profit = total value
Economic value + social value
The profit motive is closely linked in business to the price mechanism, which
is an assessment of the cost of bringing a product or service to market, plus a
margin that provides sufficient incentive for the business to operate. In the
marketplace, price is the best way we have developed to measure the value-
added in an exchange. In terms of firm performance, a profit or loss is the
aggregated outcome of multiple production and consumption decisions.
These decisions are arrived at through individual evaluations of cost and
benefit along many, many dimensions, at each stage of development, and ulti
mately expressed in the consumer’s willingness to pay the price that is being
charged. If the value I obtain from a product exceeds the costs involved in
earning sufficient money to pay the price, then I should be willing to buy it.
In other words, when I buy a product, I am signaling to the firm that I value
what it does. When this transaction is repeated by all stakeholders in each of
the ways they interact with the firm, this signal amounts to a societal-wide
sanction of the underlying business. As Howard Bowen noted back in 1953:
when businessmen follow the profit motive they are merely following
social valuations as expressed in the prices at which they can sell their
products and the prices at which they can buy productive services, mater
ials, supplies, and their other requirements. … When the businessman
follows this signal, he is following not only his own interest but that of
society as well. … The practical and the democratic thing for him to do
is to rely primarily on profit as his guide in deciding his business actions.2
The profit motive can be objected to legitimately when the quest for
profits results in restrictive monopoly, exploitation, fraud, misrepresenta
tion, political bribery, waste of nature resources, economic insecurity,
etc. It is the abuse of the profit motive, not the motive itself, that comes
under criticism.6
Nevertheless, given what we know, monetary value is the best way we have of
capturing overall value creation. The price of a product and the profit of a firm
incorporate a significant amount of all aspects of value (economic, social, moral,
and ethical) that is encapsulated in market transactions. While the correlation
among these different measures of value is high, however, it is not perfect. As
such, SVC exists to redefine our understanding of economic exchange in order
to minimize the gap among different measures of value. One example of this is
to ensure that firms internalize the complete costs of production and consump
tion in the price that is charged for the finished good (detailed in Principle 7).
Before we turn to that discussion, however, it is necessary to complete our
consideration of the role played by profit in terms of total value creation.
Profit optimization
In the process of delivering value to its broad range of stakeholders, it is
essential that the firm generates a profit. Profit generation is, therefore, also
Profit = total value 65
central to the concept of SVC. Rather than challenge what the firm does
(make money), SVC is focused more specifically on how the firm does it (the
hundreds and thousands of operational decisions made every day). In the
process, one of the goals of SVC is to shift the debate around the purpose of
the for-profit firm in society. By challenging taken-for-granted assumptions
about business and the value it delivers, the potential for reform to help build
a more sustainable economic system becomes possible. One of the taken-for
granted assumptions that must be challenged is the idea that firms pursue pol
icies and practices that result in profit maximization. First, this concept is not
provable; second, it is unhelpful.
First, the idea of profit maximization is something that is impossible to
prove as a firm can never know whether the profit generated was in fact
maximized or what effect making an alternative decision would have had
instead:
Our standard of living … consists of two parts: that which derives from
the conditions under which production is carried on and that which
derives from the goods and services resulting from that production. An
improvement in the conditions of production – resulting in a better
working environment of better functioning of the economy – may fre
quently be entirely justified even if achieved at a sacrifice in output of
final goods and services.10
In other words, profit is the outcome of a highly complex process that, more
accurately, determines whether the firm is being socially responsible. As such, it
is the detail of that complex process that matters. Understanding how firms
can balance the pursuit of profit and the need to satisfy a broad range of
stakeholder interests (how they should achieve their profit) is essential.
68 Profit = total value
Recognizing that this realization of empowered stakeholders is achieved
largely through the value creation process, and that a necessary element of
this is understanding what value (all kinds of value) looks like for each of these
stakeholders, is central to understanding the different approach to business
that is demanded by SVC.
Summary
Principle 6 states that Profit = total value. It argues that conceptualizing eco
nomic value as an independent construct, separate from other kinds of value
(such as social, ethical, and moral), demonstrates a fundamental misunder
standing of what profit represents. Although imperfect, profit is the best
measure we have of capturing the total value added by a specific company
and product/service during production and consumption. Rather than asking
firms to focus on profit maximization (both impossible to prove and unhelpful
because it distorts decision-making), the goal of profit optimization better
reflects the value judgments made every day as firms balance competing
stakeholder interests. Even better, understanding the total value added in
terms of the separate processes associated with production and consumption
provides a mechanism by which society can more easily identify those behav
iors that create (and destroy) total value.
Principle 7
The free market is not free
Politicians on both the left and the right tend to favor government inter
vention when it is in support of a cause in which they believe (e.g., sub
sidies for solar power on the left; tax breaks for oil firms on the right), but
at least the left admits that it favors government intervention. Right-wing
ideology, in contrast, preaches free market ideas, but then implements
heavily subsidized intervention in contravention of that ideology. Although
shocking in itself, the above quote about the extent of corporate welfare
only hints at the inefficient system of corporate support we have created in
the West. A good example of these distortions can be found in the energy
market:
So it’s worth pointing out that special treatment for fracking makes a
mockery of free-market principles. Pro-fracking politicians claim to be
against subsidies, yet letting an industry impose costs without paying
compensation is in effect a huge subsidy. They say they oppose having
the government “pick winners,” yet they demand special treatment for
this industry precisely because they claim it will be a winner.11
markets are truly free only when everyone pays the full price for his or
her actions. Anything else is socialism. … Our future will largely be
determined by our ability to admit the need to end planetary socialism.
That’s the most fundamental of economics lessons and one any serious
environmentalist ought to heed.12
Externalities
A core tenet of economic theory is that, over the long run, prices are formed
by the market in response to demand and supply and, as such, are essentially
outside the control of individual firms. In other words, in the long run, firms
can only charge what market forces will allow them to charge. Any higher
and the firm will lose business to its competitors; any lower and the firm will,
at a minimum, leave money on the table and, more likely, will operate at
a loss.
The problem with this theory is twofold: first, many of the assumptions
that accompany it (free and open competition, complete information, equal
access among buyers and sellers, etc.) are rarely, if ever, present; and second,
most business occurs in the short run – as Keynes noted, “In the long run we
are all dead.”13 As a result, markets are imperfect and prices fail to capture all
costs associated with production and consumption. Given the opportunity,
firms will externalize these costs, allowing others (society, broadly speaking)
to incur them. Thus, firms are not directly responsible for building roads,
72 The free market is not free
although they benefit greatly from using them to transport goods; they also
do not pay for the education system, legal infrastructure, or national defense,
even though they value access to an educated workforce, enforceable prop
erty rights, and stable borders. All of these costs are what economists refer to
as an externality – a cost (or benefit) that is incurred, but not paid for, either
by the firm (during production) or the purchaser (during consumption):
Over the past century, companies have been rewarded financially for
maximizing externalities in order to minimize costs. … Not until we
more broadly “price in” the external costs of investment decision across
all sectors will we have a sustainable economy and society.14
While it takes 500–2,000 liters of water to produce the 4oz. of ginned cotton
necessary to make a cotton T-shirt, for example, the farmer who produced
that 4oz. of cotton receives only approximately U.S.$0.20.15 This is because,
in many countries, water is provided free or heavily subsidized by the state in
ways that fail to reflect either the true value of water in the production process
or the cost of replenishing stocks so others may have a guaranteed supply in
the future. Clearly this is less than optimal because it distorts the normal inter
action of demand and supply to create an artificially low price (and distorted
market) for, in this case, T-shirts. If we are to fundamentally reform our eco
nomic model, therefore, a vital step is to account adequately for such external
ities. In other words, the price of a product should not only include the cost of
production, but also the cost of replenishing the raw material and disposing/
recycling the waste post-consumption. If all firms are forced to incorporate
externalities into the price of the finished product or service, many of the
cheap items in our disposable economy will become significantly more expen
sive and firms will be incentivized to produce sustainable alternatives.
Lifecycle pricing
A major flaw in economic theory will remain if we continue to allow
resources to be treated as though they are infinite. Until Elon Musk works
out a way to get us to Mars,16 there is only one planet and, as much research
has demonstrated, we are already placing significant constraints on the
resources at our disposal:
Some seven billion people are alive today; the United Nations estimates
that by the end of the century we could number as many as 15.8 billion.
Biologists have calculated that an ideal population – the number at which
everyone could live at a first-world level of consumption, without
ruining the planet irretrievably – would be 1.5 billion. … Each year the
world adds the equivalent of another Germany or Egypt; by 2040, China
will have more than 100 million 80-year-olds. We add another million
people every four and a half days.17
The free market is not free 73
Population level, in itself, however, is not necessarily a problem. It is a large
population combined with a materialistic lifestyle that places such a strain on
resource levels:
Without doubt, the single most damaging aspect of the present economic
system is that the expense of destroying the earth is largely absent from
the prices set in the marketplace.21
One idea that has been proposed to solve the problem of externalities by
accounting for (internalizing) these true costs is lifecycle pricing22 (related to the
idea of Pigovian taxes).23 In other words, the price of a product should not
only include the cost of production, but also include the costs associated with
replenishing the raw materials used and disposing/recycling of the waste after
consumption.24 Attempts to price carbon reflect this process (either through a
carbon tax or some form of cap-and-trade), while firms’ efforts to measure
the carbon footprints of their products (such as a carton of Tropicana orange
juice)25 provide a possible means of implementation.
The core idea behind lifecycle pricing is to capture all of the impacts at
each step of the production process and assign a quantitative value to that
step. At the risk of over-simplifying a highly complex calculation (managing
to avoid double-counting is, in itself, extremely challenging); in essence, life-
cycle pricing requires a firm to add up all the positive and negative costs in
the value chain to arrive at a net impact score for each product. This is
important because, “If prices reflected all the costs, including ecological costs
spread across generations, the world would not face sustainability challenges;
at least in theory.”26 The debate surrounding the pricing of “natural capital”
(the resources that exist naturally and are exploited by business, often for
free – a form of “environmental profit and loss accounting”)27 is central to
this task:
74 The free market is not free
Natural capital is simple. The value of well-functioning natural systems is
clearly manifest to all people and companies – in the form of clean air,
reliable availability of freshwater and productive topsoil in which to grow
food, among other benefits. Yet, the way that finance works – from
GDP calculations through corporate to accounting – it is as if reliable
flows from well-functioning natural systems have no value.28
One of the earliest adopters of the concept of “environmental profit and loss”
(EP&L) accounting was Puma. The firm developed and first published an
EP&L statement in 2011, in which it concluded its operations had an “impact
of €51 million resulting from land use, air pollution and waste along the value
chain added to previously announced €94 million for GHG emissions and
water consumption.”29 It is an idea that is making progress, with a number of
firms already incorporating carbon pricing into their planning and budgeting
models. Sometimes this is driven by a genuine desire to account for all costs
incurred; other times it is to prepare for anticipated legislation that must come
at some point. Exxon, for example, applies a cost of “$80 a tonne … when
making investment decisions for 10 years,”30 while Microsoft “charges all
departments for every kilowatt-hour of dirty energy they contract or air mile
flown by executives, to help meet firm-wide climate targets.”31 According to
CDP, “a British watchdog, 607 [firms] now claim to use ‘internal carbon
prices.’ … Another 782 companies say they will introduce similar measures
within two years.”32
If firms can account for all costs incurred at all stages of the value chain
(extraction, processing, manufacture, wholesale/retail, purchase/consump
tion, disposal/recycling), including transportation and storage, as well as all
resource inputs (e.g., energy and materials) and outputs (e.g., waste and other
pollutants), they would have an accurate snapshot of the true costs involved
in producing a product. More important, they would be able to include those
costs in the price they charge to customers, which would then allow the
market to determine the true demand for that product. Perhaps the best
example of a firm that has comprehensively attempted to integrate this life-
cycle approach throughout all aspects of operations is Interface carpets, whose
inspirational founder and CEO, the late Ray Anderson, explained his journey
in terms of the seven (+1) faces of Mount Sustainability: 1. Waste. 2. Emis
sions. 3. Energy. 4. Materials. 5. Transportation. 6. Culture. 7. Market. 8.
Social equity.33 In Anderson’s vision, the peak of the mountain represents
sustainability, which he defines as “take nothing, do no harm.” The natural
conclusion of such a closed-loop system is zero waste and, to Anderson, this
makes perfect business sense:
More happiness with less stuff. You know, that would reframe civiliza
tion itself and our whole system of economics – if not for our species,
then perhaps for the one that succeeds us – the sustainable species, living
on a finite earth, ethically, happily, and ecologically in balance with
The free market is not free 75
nature and all her natural systems for a thousand generations or ten thou
sand generations. … But, does the Earth have to wait for our extinction
as a species … I don’t think so. At Interface, we really intend to bring
this prototypical, sustainable, zero-footprint industrial company fully into
existence by 2020. We can see our way now clear to the top of that
mountain and now the challenge is in execution.34
Summary
Principle 7 states that The free market is not free. It argues that, at present, our
economic system allows firms to externalize costs (to society) that are then
not included in the prices that are charged (to customers). The problem,
therefore, is not that the price mechanism does not work, but that all relevant
costs are not currently included in the prices that are charged. And if prices
are distorted, the resulting economic exchange will be distorted – producers
benefit from lower costs, while consumers benefit from lower prices, and the
rest of us pick up the tab. Not only does this create an artificial market for
existing products and services; it creates artificial barriers to entry for more
competitive alternatives. The solution lies in lifecycle pricing, where all related
costs of production and consumption are incorporated into the final prices
charged.
Principle 8
Only business can save the planet
Key takeaway: The environmental crisis has reached the point where
individual-driven change is insufficient. While for-profit firms were the main
cause of the problem, they are also the main hope for a solution. Scale is vital
and large firms must do much more if we are to build a sustainable economy.
Second, it is not about the actions of the individual, however worthy, but the
actions of the for-profit firm. And, in particular, it is the actions of large cor-
porations that will matter most. Scale is central to any meaningful solution.
While much of the focus remains on reusing shopping bags and banning
drinking straws, the planet is deteriorating before our eyes. In spite of all the
attention to this issue and all the micro actions taken, greenhouse gas emis-
sions continue to rise:3
The problem we face is far greater than anything portrayed by the media.
… recycling aluminum cans in the company cafeteria and ceremonial
tree plantings are about as effective as bailing out the Titanic with
teaspoons.4
Only business can save the planet 77
Only for-profit firms are able to deliver the necessary reforms on the scale
and at the speed at which they must occur to avert widespread ecological
devastation.
Sustainability
In 1987, The Brundtland Report was published. The report, which was named
after its lead author, Gro Harlem Brundtland (Norwegian Prime Minister and
chair of the United Nation’s World Commission on Environment and Devel-
opment), was established to investigate the sustainability of our economic
development. As well as concluding that our current system is unsustainable,
the committee provided a definition of what a sustainable system would
look like:
The discussion fostered by the report essentially defined the field of sustain-
ability as concerned primarily with resource use (in particular, the rapid rate
of depletion and accompanying waste).6 As such, most people today under-
stand sustainability to represent issues related to the natural environment.7
Importantly, however, the report was also prescient in framing the central
role of business as both the cause of the problem and also the best hope for a
solution:
The Brundtland Report, which inspired the 1992 Earth Summit in Rio
de Janeiro that resulted in the Climate Change Convention and in turn
the Kyoto Protocol, acknowledged that many “of the development paths
of the industrialized nations are clearly unsustainable.” However, it held
fast to its embrace of development toward industrialized nation living
standards as part of the solution, not part of the problem. “If large parts
of countries of the global South are to avert economic, social, and
environmental catastrophes, it is essential that global economic growth be
revitalized,” the report stated.8
In the debate over whether we should pursue sustainability via material sacri-
fice (produce and consume less) or technological innovation (produce and
consume more effectively), The Brundtland Report, with the supporting legiti-
macy of the UN, came down firmly in favor of progress. This presents a clear
paradox between the damage to the environment done so far by the industrial
revolution and subsequent economic development, and the future potential
contributions firms can make to create a more sustainable economic system.
The key is to move quickly:
78 Only business can save the planet
The world has warmed more than one degree Celsius since the Industrial
Revolution. The Paris climate agreement … hoped to restrict warming
to two degrees. The odds of succeeding, according to a recent study
based on current emissions trends, are one in 20. … Keeping the planet
to two degrees of warming, let alone 1.5 degrees, would require trans-
formative action. It will take more than good works and voluntary com-
mitments; it will take a revolution.9
Given the scale of the problem, large-scale business is central to any potential
solution. While greenhouse gas emissions from energy use are an important
source of global emissions, for example, they form only 35% of the total, with
industry (21%), forestry and agriculture (24%), transportation (14%), and
buildings (6%) contributing the remainder.10 There is much work to do, espe-
cially given the inherent flaws in our economic system built on waste and
materialism.
Waste
Waste is a central component of the economic model that drives the global
economy. For the majority of for-profit firms, the more you buy of their
products, the better they perform and the faster the economy grows. In other
words, excessive consumption and quick turnover are essential. Whether we
need a product is less important than whether we want it. And, if we buy
something, the quicker we throw it away and buy another one, the better for
all concerned. Restraint and conservation are not encouraged. When you
realize that Starbucks goes through 4 billion disposable cups a year at its
30,000 locations worldwide,11 you understand that refusing a straw or bring-
ing your own reusable cup (even if you get all of your friends to do the same)
pales in comparison to the scale of the action required to make a difference.
An important assumption of this economic model is that the world’s
resources are unlimited. When a company extracts a raw material and converts
it into something consumers want to buy, the price covers only the costs the
firm incurred during the extraction and conversion. For the most part, there is
no charge associated with the replenishment of the resource (e.g., the cost of
losing forever the precious metals used in smartphones not recycled) or the
pollution emitted during consumption (e.g., when driving a car). In short, our
economy is based on waste – the more the firm uses and customers discard,
the higher a country’s GDP, and the stronger its economy. A question worth
asking is “Are we sinking under the weight of our disposable society?”12
Though often laced with lead, mercury or other toxic substances, laptops
and phones also contain valuable elements like gold, silver and copper.
Yet barely 20 percent of the world’s e-waste is collected and [recycled].
… the raw materials contained in e-waste were worth roughly $61
billion in 2016. … the gold in the world’s e-waste equaled more than a
tenth of the gold mined globally that year. … Based on e-waste disposal
rates, Americans alone throw out phones worth $60 million in gold and
silver every year.15
There is a similar story with the amount of plastic that we use and discard
every day. Plastic, which was invented in the early twentieth century and
commercialized in the 1950s, has become one of our most versatile materials
– “Some 322m tons of plastic were produced in 2015, and that number is
expected to double by 2025.”16 It is particularly useful in single-use applica-
tions, which are convenient in households (e.g., bottled water) and critical in
hospitals (e.g., syringes and packaging), where hygiene is life and death. In
addition to being so useful, of course, plastic is highly durable, which unfor-
tunately makes it difficult to dispose of. In fact, since the 1950s, while “8.3bn
tonnes [of plastic] has been created. … just 9% has been recycled, 12% incin-
erated and 79% has accumulated in landfills or the wider environment.”17 At
the rate we are going, by 2050, it is estimated there will be “12 billion metric
tons of plastic waste … in landfills or the natural environment”18 and “more
plastic than fish by weight in the oceans.”19
Together, e-waste and plastic are poster children for the ecological con-
sequences of our consumption-based economic model, which treats all
resources as infinite and fails to fully account for the externalities created
during the production process. Yet waste reduction, when approached with a
more enlightened attitude, can be a potential source of differentiation.
Walmart, for example, whose ex-CEO (Lee Scott) committed the firm to the
goal of “zero waste” in 2005,20 presents an excellent case-study of what this
can look like in practice. Ever since, Walmart has been committed to mini-
mizing the waste packaging that is processed through its stores:
Our packaging team, for example, worked with our packaging supplier to
reduce excessive packaging on some of our private-label Kid Connection
80 Only business can save the planet
toy products. By making the packaging just a little bit smaller on one
private brand of toys, we will use 497 fewer containers and generate
freight savings of more than $2.4 million per year. Additionally, we’ll
save more than 38-hundred trees and more than a thousand barrels
of oil.21
When a large corporation such as Walmart alters its business practices, it has
immediate ramifications for its tens of thousands of suppliers that have to
adapt to the firm’s new demands. And, given that Walmart has over 11,000
stores worldwide, in 27 countries, it only has to make a minor change to
produce a dramatic effect.22 The reason we have concentrated laundry deter-
gent, for example, is because Walmart (which is responsible for “approxi-
mately 25 percent of the liquid laundry detergent sold in the United States”)
told its suppliers it wanted to reduce packaging waste and transportation costs.
Every three years, the firm estimates its decision saves “more than 400 million
gallons of water; more than 95 million pounds of plastic resin; and more than
125 million pounds of cardboard.”23 For Walmart, the connection between
waste reduction and its overarching strategy is clear. Driving waste out of its
supply chain creates savings, which the firm passes on to its customers in the
form of lower prices. The extension of this philosophy to its support of the
Sustainable Product Index,24 ultimately, is designed to enhance consumer
awareness by allowing like-for-like comparison across all products in its
stores. Equally important for Walmart, however, it will provide more data
about its supply chain that the firm can use to drive costs even lower.
Examples such as these exist in many industries. Unfortunately, there are
many more examples of waste and inefficiency. We use and dispose of far
more resources than we conserve or recycle. A direct driver of this waste is
the materialism that motivates our desire to consume.
Materialism
A characteristic of the developed world is that, as a general rule, our posses-
sions vastly exceed our needs on a day-to-day basis. Perhaps it is part of our
genetic inheritance from our hunter-gatherer days but, for some reason, we
seem incapable of living within our means.25 It is not clear that we are more
prosperous as a result. It is a pity that, given our obvious capability for inge-
nuity, we have created an economic system that impoverishes as much as it
enables:
A quote from the former Vogue editor Diana Vreeland comes to mind:
“Give ’em what they never knew they wanted.” Fast-fashion retailers
like H&M, Topshop and Forever 21 are great at hawking what we never
knew we wanted. Not only that, they offer it at steadily reduced prices.
… Quality is no longer an issue, because you need clothes to last just
“until the next trend comes along.”26
Only business can save the planet 81
It is equally distressing that we are willing to place our superficial concern for
material objects above the wellbeing of other humans. In addition to wasted
resources, there are social and human costs to the mass-production of cheap
T-shirts. We may believe that it improves our lives to have someone else do
our hard work for us (“Today, the United States makes only 2 percent of the
clothing its consumers purchase, compared with roughly 50 percent in
1990”),27 but there is nothing sustainable (in a holistic sense) in manufacturing
clothes thousands of miles away, shipping them to the West, all for under
$10. Ultimately, we are all worse off as a result:
On the surface, there has seemingly never been a better time to launch a
sustainable offering. Consumers – particularly Millennials – increasingly
say they want brands that embrace purpose and sustainability. … Yet a
frustrating paradox remains at the heart of green business: Few consumers
who report positive attitudes toward eco-friendly products and services
follow through with their wallets. In one recent survey 65% said they
want to buy purpose-driven brands that advocate sustainability, yet only
about 26% actually do so.30
No doubt some wear the bands in solidarity, or for inspiration – but, that
said, the wristband conceit was simply ingenious. It allowed people to
make a show of their virtue. They could give to a good cause, and they
could advertise their caring to everyone else.35
Scale
In order to quantify the scale of the challenge humanity faces in creating a
more sustainable economic system, it is instructive to understand not only the
extent of the damage done to date but, perhaps more importantly, the pace at
which we continue to do harm:
Everyone knows what must be done about climate change, but no one is
doing anything about it. More than two decades of speeches and sum-
mitry have failed to thin out emissions of greenhouse gases. In fact, emis-
sions are accelerating: a quarter of all the carbon dioxide pumped into the
air by humans was put there in the decade between 2000 and 2010. It
will hang around for centuries, meaning that the future is sure to be
hotter, even if all greenhouse-gas emissions cease overnight. The official
ambition of limiting the global temperature rise to 2ºC looks increasingly
like a bad joke.39
The issues discussed in Principle 8 (and indirectly throughout the book) rely
on the assumption that society today owes an obligation to future generations
to leave them a planet that is functional. If we accept this broad, inter-
generational obligation, the question then becomes: How much should we be
willing to pay today to minimize the future costs of our current actions? Long ago,
Howard Bowen was thinking about “the responsibilities of a business toward
future generations as distinct from the present generation” and the difficult
tradeoffs involved:
This issue is particularly relevant in terms of issues such as climate change, but
relates also to the broader issue of how to value future benefit against present-
day cost. One attempt to do that was the influential Stern report on climate
change,43 which argued that society must “value the welfare of all present and
future citizens equally and give no special preference to current voters.”44 The
difficulty is, of course, how to account for the possibility of unknowns such
as technical innovation and the greater wealth of future generations and, as a
result, avoid exaggerating the immediate cost implications of climate change
(and causing unnecessary present-day suffering). Getting this balance between
current and future obligations correct is crucial if we are to ensure an effective
and realizable response to this hugely important issue:
The problem of weighting the present and the future equally is that there
is a lot of future. The number of future generations is potentially so large
that small but permanent benefit to them would justify great sacrifice
now. If we were to use this criterion to appraise all long-term invest-
ment, the volume of such investment would impoverish the current
population. … The burden of caring for all humanity, present and future,
is greater than even the best-intentioned of us can bear.45
While it appears that our capacity for altruism toward future generations is
limited, perhaps we can act to save ourselves. The speed at which climate
change is occurring suggests we will see dramatic consequences in our
Only business can save the planet 85
lifetime. If so, sustainability increasingly represents a present-day imperative.
Although all the warnings may motivate us to act, however, human nature
suggests that meaningful change will most likely occur only in the face of
impending doom. At that time, it will require more dramatic change in a
shorter timeframe at a much higher cost (if it is possible at all). Given the
radical changes in behavior that will be required of people in both developed
and developing countries, even if we start seriously today, it is therefore pre-
ferable that buy-in is secured as quickly as possible and large corporations are
recruited to help us respond:
Here’s a question. Which trio of companies has done more for the
environment … Patagonia, Starbucks and Chipotle? Or Walmart, Coca-
Cola and McDonald’s? … Patagonia, Starbucks and Chipotle have been
path-breaking companies when it comes to sustainability, but Walmart,
Coca-Cola and McDonald’s are so much bigger that, despite their glaring
flaws, and the fundamental problems with their business models, they will
have a greater impact as they get serious about curbing their environ-
mental footprint, and that of their suppliers.46
While provocative, the answer to the question is intuitive. That is not to say
that the question isn’t an important one to ask. Perhaps, for the CSR/sustain-
ability community, it is the only one worth asking. Ultimately, the core ques-
tion is: Are we interested in ideal possibilities or meaningful change? If change is
what we want, then Walmart, Coca-Cola, and McDonald’s need to be the
source. That is not to diminish the wonderful business models of other
smaller companies, especially Patagonia and Starbucks. If anything, they are
the roadmap for what larger firms also need to accomplish. But, unless the
largest firms are fully invested in Sustainable Value Creation (SVC), we will
only be working at the periphery of the progress that needs to be made.
This conundrum plays out at a micro level whenever we make the effort
to recycle a plastic bottle or aluminum can – it is still the environmentally
responsible thing to do, even though we know the effect on the planet’s
future is limited, especially in light of the huge amount of resources that are
wasted elsewhere in our economic system every day. It is not even clear that
the item will be recycled47 and, if it is, it is not clear that recycling results in
less environmental impact. Just as building more roads encourages more
people to drive and we know that “recycling programs do increase recycling
rates, studies have shown that they also increase total consumption.”48
For-profit firms are the most valuable organizational form because it is
only these organizations that can act with the efficiency required on the scale
necessary to implement meaningful reform in the timeframe within which
change is needed. Yet, in order for this to occur, we need to ask firms to take
on this task. The for-profit firm is simply a tool we have devised to solve a
specific problem – how to allocate scarce and valuable resources to achieve
optimal outcomes (a problem that has challenged humanity throughout our
86 Only business can save the planet
existence). The best solution we have found to date is for-profit firms operat-
ing within a market-based, democratic form of capitalism. Once you under-
stand firms are merely a tool, however, you understand that they will do what
we ask of them. If we ask them to pollute the planet (as we are, at present),
they will do that, very efficiently. Equally, if we ask them to preserve the
planet, they will find the most efficient means of achieving that goal. They
will do what we want them to do – they reflect our collective set of values.
Yet, within the vast group of organizations labeled for-profit firms, there are
clearly some that contain vastly more potential for significant impact. Massive
firms have a disproportionate impact on our daily lives. The market capitali-
zation of the Top 10 global firms alone is $6.5 trillion.49 What these large
firms do in the near future, therefore, will do more to influence our lifestyles,
standard of living, and future security than all of the smaller firms combined.
As Jason Clay states in his TED talk on how big brands can save biodiversity:
100 companies control 25% of the trade of all 15 of the most significant
commodities on the planet. … Why is 25% important? Because if these
companies demand sustainable products they will pull 40–50% of
production.50
According to Clay, it is all about the B2B supply chain. Suppliers are as
important a stakeholder to the firm as the customer. Large companies pushing
other large companies will achieve change much faster and on a scale that
actually matters than waiting for consumers, one-by-one, to wake up to the
global consequences of their consumption decisions.
Summary
Principle 8 states that Only business can save the planet. The core argument rests
on the idea that, in order to solve the climate crisis, scale and speed are essen-
tial – that the problem has reached a point where only radical and rapid
change will produce meaningful effects and help avert the catastrophic
outcome we are hurtling toward. In this light, while for-profit firms are the
main cause of the environmental mess we face, they are also the main hope
for a solution, as long as we ask them to tackle the task. There is much work
to do, both in terms of production and consumption, in order to create a
truly sustainable economic system.
Principle 9
Value creation is not a choice
What if corporate America was willing to take the more than $18bn it
donates annually4 and, instead, invest it in what it does best – operating its
business? For-profit firms should focus on identifying those problems for
which there is a clear market-based solution and then deliver that solution in
an efficient and socially responsible manner. The idea of SVC as a managing
philosophy focuses on firms’ areas of expertise throughout all aspects of oper
ations and de-emphasizes actions that stray outside that expertise for which
there either is not a market solution, or the firm is not well-equipped to
deliver that solution. That is how value is optimized over the medium to
long term – by operating in a way that seeks to meet the needs and demands
of the firm’s stakeholders, broadly defined. In other words, the focus of busi
ness remains the same; it is the way the organization goes about it that is
different with an SVC perspective.
While appealing at first glance, it is not clear what Gates actually means by
“creative capitalism” and how it is to be realized in practice. For example, it
is easy to say that:
But, in reality, how is a firm to decide which issue it should prioritize and
devote its most valuable resources? How much value is compromised because
these “top innovators” are working on a philanthropic problem (that may or
may not be suited to their particular skillset) instead of one based on market
demand? How are firms to determine exactly which projects are appropriate
and which are not? Do firms need to calculate a certain level of potential
social welfare in advance? If so, how would they do that? What if it is not
realized? None of these questions are addressed sufficiently, with Gates
weaving back-and-forth between an argument based on market forces and
one based on an appeal to firms’ altruism without any clear guidance as to
how priorities among competing claims should be set. As one supportive
commentator noted:
Put more bluntly, SVC, implemented throughout the firm via a stakeholder
perspective and a focus on medium- to long-term value creation, optimizes
performance:
Sure, let those who have become rich under capitalism try to do good
things for those who are still poor, as Mr. Gates has admirably chosen to
do. But a New-Age blend of market incentives and feel-good recogni
tion will not end poverty. History has shown that profit-motivated capit
alism is still the best hope for the poor.12
Similar criticisms can be leveled against Muhammad Yunus, the 2006 winner
of the Nobel Peace Prize, whose concept of “social business” touches on
ideas similar to those expressed by Gates.13 In reality, what both men are
expressing is a form of social entrepreneurship, which demands that firms
replace profit-seeking with something that amounts to altruism:
Such business models have limited market appeal – while some consumers are
willing to pay the associated price premiums, the evidence suggests that such
charitable motivations cannot be assumed market-wide. In advocating such a
philosophy, Yunus is turning his back on the sound business model for which
he won his Nobel Prize. Microfinance (and Grameen Bank, the organization
founded by Yunus to deliver microloans to individuals who cannot secure
Value creation is not a choice 91
them from mainstream financial institutions) was effective because it extended
the market to consumers whose demand was thought to be insufficient for
traditional finance models. All it took was a product tailored to the specific
needs of a specific segment of the market. While microfinance is an industry
that is grounded in business fundamentals, however, it is not clear how Yunus
expects altruism to constitute sufficient incentive to mobilize the private
sector as a whole:
The genius of microfinance was in getting the profit motive to work for
the very poorest. The drawback of social business is that it depends on
the kindness of strangers.15
On the surface, Porter’s shared value (or caring capitalism) and SVC can
appear to produce similar behavior. The motivating force is different,
however, and this is important because it will lead to different outcomes in
terms of the venture’s ultimate success or failure. The difference comes down
to the focus of the firm and the relevance to core operations of the issue at
hand. Starbucks, for example, should not form partnerships with shade-grown
coffee farmers in Guatemala because it recognizes those farmers face an uncer
tain future with an insufficient welfare net to support them if their businesses
fail (a non-operational goal), but because Starbucks needs to secure a stable
supply of high-quality coffee beans and supporting these farmers in a sustain
able manner is the best way to guarantee that supply (an operational goal). In
other words, Starbucks should form stable and lasting partnerships with these
key suppliers not because it is seeking to fill a charitable social need; the firm
should do it because these farmers produce a raw material that is essential to
its business. Starbucks is incentivized to protect the raw material in a sustain
able way, rather than ruthlessly exploit it. If those Guatemalan farmers are not
producing a product that is in demand (i.e., if the business logic for a rela
tionship is not there), the argument that Starbucks should get involved is dif
ficult to make.
Ultimately, although for-profit firms can help with the first perspective
(caring capitalism), they are much better suited to the second perspective
(market capitalism). Ideally, it is the role of governmental and nonprofit
92 Value creation is not a choice
sectors to focus on those problems that the market ignores or cannot solve. In
contrast, Porter and Kramer argue that charitable goals should be considered
equally with operational goals and firms should then utilize their market-
based skills and expertise to solve both kinds of problem – in other words,
that they should become less like for-profit firms and more like nonprofit
organizations or government agencies. But, the challenges with this notion
again quickly become apparent when a firm tries to implement these ideas in
practice. To turn back to the Starbucks example, above – because Starbucks
is forming ties with Guatemalan coffee growers due to their value to the
firm’s core business, the way they structure their proposed solution is different
than if they were forming the ties for other, more altruistic reasons. As it is,
Starbucks provides the farmers with financial security (by providing long-
term contracts and guaranteeing an above-market price for their beans) but,
in return, secures guarantees of quality and the right (and incentive) to be
directly involved in training the farmers to ensure the coffee is prepared in
exactly the way the firm needs it to be. In other words, the motivation for
the engagement is central to the value of the solution provided. Encouraging
firms to adopt altruistic motivations is not an effective plan for “how to fix
capitalism” but, instead, represents a misunderstanding of what profit is and
how it is generated. As suggested by other critics of these attempts to reinvent
capitalism:17
Rosabeth Moss Kanter warned of the pitfalls for companies that make
“social commitments that do not have an economic logic that sustains the
enterprise by attracting resources.” More companies are learning to reap
commercial benefits from strategies that have a wider social value. That’s
great. But the basic job of coaxing capitalism in the right direction is the
same as it always has been: find ways to harness society’s needs to com
panies’ self-interest and hope the two stay together.18
Summary
Principle 9 states that Value creation is not a choice. SVC is a management philo
sophy that is intricately woven into every decision the firm makes. It is not
about peripheral activities, such as philanthropy, but about how the firm
treats its employees and suppliers and customers, and all of its stakeholders. It
is not about being compassionate or sharing value; it is about a firm doing
what it does best – applying its technical expertise to build a competitive
advantage to solve a market-based problem (from which society benefits). As
such, SVC is not a choice; it is integral to all aspects of operations. There is
simply no choice to be made. All firms create value (like all firms do strategy,
marketing, and so on) – it is just that some do it better than others.
Principle 10
The business of business is business
Key takeaway: Milton Friedman believed that firms should prioritize eco-
nomic success. Similarly, SVC is all about strategy, day-to-day decisions, and
core operations. The pursuit of profit and value creation are synonymous. Busi-
ness serves society best when it focuses primarily on business.
Milton Friedman
Milton Friedman was right – the social responsibility of business is business. In
Friedman’s own words, what he meant by this is that:
I share Adam Smith’s skepticism about the benefits that can be expected
from “those who affected to trade for the public good.” … in a free
society, … “there is one and only one social responsibility of business – to
use its resources and engage in activities designed to increase its profits.”4
It is salutary to ask about any organization, “If it did not exist, would we
invent it? Only if it could do something better or more useful than
anyone else” would have to be the answer, and profit would be the
means to that larger end.6
On the surface, the positions taken by Friedman and Handy appear irrecon-
cilable, and that is how they are often treated by the CSR community.
Indeed, Friedman seems to go out of his way to antagonize CSR advocates
by arguing that socially responsible behavior is a waste of the firm’s resources,
which legally (in his view, cf. Principle 2) belong to the firm’s shareholders
and not the firm’s managers:
The business of business is business 97
That is why, in my book Capitalism and Freedom, I have called [social
responsibility] a “fundamentally subversive doctrine” in a free society.7
But, on closer analysis, their arguments are not nearly as far apart as they ini-
tially appear. Incorporating the ideas underpinning SVC narrows the gap
between the two positions considerably. First, it is necessary to ask: If the
purpose of the firm is to meet a need that society values as a whole (as Handy
argues), what is the best means we have of quantifying that value? As discussed
in Principle 6, profit is by far the most accurate method we have of capturing
total value – not perfect, but it is difficult to imagine a more complete (or
more elegant) measure. If true, then surely the most profitable firms are adding
the most value (as Friedman argues). Again, the correlation is imperfect but, as
a general rule, the relationship between profit and value holds.
Second, for additional consideration that Friedman and Handy are not as
far apart as many believe, consider the following two questions:
• Does it make sense for a large financial firm to donate money to a group
researching the effects of climate change because the CEO believes this is
an important issue?
• Does it make sense for an oil firm to donate money to the same group
because it perceives climate change to be a threat to its business model
and wants to mitigate that threat by investigating possible alternatives?
Economist Milton Friedman … has argued that social matters are not the
concern of business people and that these problems should be resolved by
the unfettered workings of the free market system. Friedman’s argument
loses some of its punch, however, when you consider his assertion in its
totality. … Most people focus on the first part of Friedman’s quote but
not the second part. It seems clear from this statement that profits, con-
formity to the law, and ethical custom embrace three components of the
CSR pyramid – economic, legal, and ethical. That only leaves the phil-
anthropic component for Friedman to reject. Although it may be appro-
priate for an economist to take this view, one would not encounter many
business executives today who exclude philanthropic programs from their
firms’ range of activities.9
Rather than the result of this softening being presented as a reason for Fried-
man’s argument to lose “some of its punch,” however, I would argue that it
reinforces the importance of incorporating Friedman’s ideas within the intel-
lectual framework underpinning SVC. As long as an argument can be made
that any particular decision is in the best business interests of the firm, then I
believe that is something that Milton Freidman would agree lies within the
definition of business. In other words, while this book does not represent any
kind of endorsement of Friedman’s complete economic perspective (at a bare
minimum, he mischaracterized the legal relationship between a firm and its
shareholders), it does argue that SVC is compatible with the economic
rationale that all of a firm’s actions should reinforce its economic interests. As
such, SVC, built on a foundation of iterative, long-term ties to all of the
firm’s stakeholders, offers managers a roadmap to survive and thrive in today’s
complex, dynamic business environment.
To be sure, the philosophy of SVC is demanding. It requires engagement
– the idea that stakeholders must act in order to shape society in their col-
lective interests. It also requires firms to respond to these demands and, where
The business of business is business 99
possible, to anticipate them. But, again, as long as stakeholders are willing to
enforce their values and beliefs, conforming to those expectations is in the
firm’s economic interest. SVC is not a passive philosophy; it is proactive, but
the result is a society that is shaped, rather than one that forms. If stakeholders
are motivated to change the rules in a way that promotes value, broadly
defined, then for-profit firms are the best means we have of interpreting those
new standards and responding more rapidly and efficiently than any other
organizational form in any other economic system.
Summary
Principle 10 states that The business of business is business. It argues that SVC is
not about issues peripheral to the firm, but instead focuses on day-to-day
decisions, strategic planning, and core operations. Equally important, it does
so in a way that accounts for the complex, dynamic business environment in
which firms must operate. As such, SVC is a philosophy of management
designed to generate business success. And, because this success (i.e., profit)
optimizes value when the firm meets the needs and demands of its broad
range of stakeholders, it is compatible with Milton Friedman’s arguments that
firms benefit society the most when they focus on business.
Conclusion
Sustainable Value Creation
The ideas detailed in this book revolve around the ten principles that define
Sustainable Value Creation (SVC). That is, in a dynamic environment defined
by the actions and decisions of a firm’s broad set of stakeholders, value is
optimized when the firm’s stakeholders are willing to convey and enforce
their needs, while the firm is willing to respond and, where possible, antici
pate those changing needs. Thus, these economic and social exchanges, at
their most fundamental, are interactions formed around the collective set of
values prevalent in society at any given point and are best measured by the
profit the firm is able to generate.
Defining SVC
The goal of this book has been to frame SVC (CSR, redefined) in terms of a
set of principles that differentiate it from existing definitions of CSR, and
from related concepts such as sustainability and business ethics. While sustain-
ability relates to issues of ecological preservation and business ethics seeks to
construct normative prescriptions of right and wrong, SVC is a pragmatic
philosophy grounded in the strategic planning and day-to-day operations of
the firm. As such, SVC is central to the firm’s value creating activities and,
ultimately, its business success.
In constructing a working definition of SVC that draws upon the ten
underlying principles, five components are essential: First, that a firm incorp
orates a CSR perspective within its culture and strategic planning process;
second, that any actions it takes are directly related to core operations; third,
102 Sustainable Value Creation
that it seeks to understand and respond to the needs of all of its stakeholders;
fourth, that it aims to optimize value created; and fifth, that it shifts from a
short-term perspective to managing its resources and relations with key stake
holders over the medium to long term.1
Essential to any definition of SVC is the idea that a firm should incorporate a
CSR perspective, as redefined in this framework, within its culture and stra
tegic planning process. This CSR perspective presupposes an iterative rela
tionship between the firm and all of its stakeholders, with equal responsibilities
to convey needs and respond to those needs whenever possible (Principle 4).
An important tool that helps the firm do this is a stakeholder filter integrated
into the firm’s operational decision-making processes. This filter is defined as
a conceptual screen through which strategic and tactical decisions are evalu
ated for their impact on the firm’s various stakeholders.2 Embedding the
profit incentive within a framework of guiding values further enables man
agers to implement SVC throughout all aspects of operations (Principle 10).
The second component of SVC is that any action a firm takes should be
directly related to core operations. In short, the same action will differ from
firm-to-firm in terms of whether it can be classified as value creation,
depending on the firm’s expertise and the relevance of the issue to the organ
ization’s vision and mission (and, therefore, to its stakeholders). SVC is not
about activities peripheral to the firm, such as philanthropy; it is also not
about redefining or reinventing capitalism; it is about the operational deci
sions the firm makes day-in and day-out (Principle 9). All aspects of business
involve economic, social, moral, and ethical considerations and the primary
role of the manager is to balance these considerations in prioritizing the
diverse set of interests that have a stake in the firm’s operations (Principle 1
and Principle 3).
The third component of SVC is that firms incorporate a stakeholder per
spective throughout the firm. A barrier to the implementation of a stake
holder perspective, however, is the primary emphasis currently given by
many corporations to the interests of its shareholders. Firms need to expand
their view of stakeholders beyond shareholders (who neither own the firm,
nor deserve any special attention from management and the Board), to
include all of the firm’s stakeholders who, collectively, define the firm’s
operating environment (Principle 2). In so doing, however, the firm has
a responsibility not only to respond to stakeholder concerns, but also to
anticipate these concerns whenever possible (Principle 3). For their part,
Sustainable Value Creation 103
stakeholders should be willing to enforce their needs onto firms by actively
discriminating in favor of those firms that best meet expectations (Principle 4).
By managing the firm in the interests of its broad range of stakeholders, the
firm increases its chances of building a sustainable competitive advantage.
The fourth component of SVC relates to the drive to optimize (as opposed
to maximize) value, broadly defined (Principle 6). In essence, the goal is to
balance the production and consumption activities in society in order to build
a standard of living that meets the needs of the collective (Principle 5). The
production component includes incorporating costs that firms currently seek
to externalize, while the consumption component includes incorporating costs
that society currently seeks to avoid (Principle 7). If we can achieve this
balance and spread both the benefits and the costs over a wide range of stake
holders, we will be significantly closer to optimizing value throughout society.
The final, and perhaps most important, component of SVC is the shift
from a short-term perspective when managing the firm’s resources and stake
holder relations to a medium- or long-term perspective. If managers alter
their horizons from the next quarter or next season to the next decade or
beyond, they immediately alter the priorities by which they manage and, as a
result, automatically change the nature of the decisions they make today
(Principle 2 and Principle 8). If a CEO is only interested in the next quarter,
it is difficult to make the case for SVC. But, if the CEO is concerned with
the continued existence of the firm 5, 10, or 20 years from now, the value of
building lasting, trust-based relationships with key stakeholders increases
exponentially.
These five components combine the ideas contained in the ten principles
and define SVC. In short: Principle 1 identifies the for-profit firm as the most
important organizational form in driving societal progress; Principle 2 locates
stakeholder theory as central to operations; Principle 3 recognizes the prac
tical importance for managers of being able to prioritize stakeholder interests;
Principle 4 establishes the importance of stakeholders holding the firm to
account; Principle 5 reminds us of the preeminent role of the market in pro
ducing optimal outcomes; Principle 6 notes that economic value and other
kinds of value are not independent of each other; Principle 7 argues that,
while the market is imperfect, it is more effective than all other organizing
systems; Principle 8 highlights the importance of scale to achieving sustain-
ability; Principle 9 states that all firms already create value, to varying degrees;
and Principle 10 reaffirms the idea that business best serves society when it
focuses on business, as illustrated by the previous nine principles.
Combining these ten principles, the five components of SVC are realized
through a series of three conscious shifts that the firm’s management team
must make:
Enlightened management
SVC delivers an operational and strategic advantage to the firm. As such, it is
central to the goal of value creation, which is the primary purpose of the
firm. In some ways, SVC is a subtle tweak of our economic model; in other
ways, it is a radical transformation. It will increasingly become the most
effective way for firms to create value in the business environment.
In essence, SVC represents an enlightened approach to management that
retains the focus on adding value that is emphasized by a traditional bottom-
line business model. Importantly, however, SVC incorporates a commitment
to meet the needs and demands of the firm’s broad range of stakeholder
groups; it also recognizes the essential role stakeholders play in holding the
firm to account for its actions. Equally important, in order to implement SVC
comprehensively, the focus of the firm has to be on optimizing value over
the long term by acting in areas in which it has expertise (related to core
operations).
This focus on long-term added value is the principal difference between a
traditional shareholder-focused business model and one based on SVC integ
rated throughout operations. This shift in perspective (from short to long
term) is relatively easy to envision, but much more difficult to implement
firm-wide. Nevertheless, this shift alone brings a firm significantly closer to
building a competitive advantage that is truly sustainable. SVC, therefore, is
as simple (and as complex) as conducting all aspects of business operations in a
responsible manner – responding to those needs that stakeholders are willing to
convey and enforce, with an emphasis on the medium to long term.
Sustainable Value Creation 105
SVC focuses on evolution, not revolution, working within what we know
about human psychology and economic exchange. As such, SVC encapsulates
the way humans behave and business is conducted. It does not alter the goals of
the firm (profit, except to say that a short-term focus is counter-productive)
and it does not alter our understanding of fundamental economic theory (actors
pursuing their self-interest can optimize value, broadly defined). What it does
do, is alter the perspective from which operational and strategic decisions are
made. For example, do the managers of the firm believe they can optimize per
formance by paying the firm’s employees a minimum wage (because there is suf
ficient unemployment that, if one employee leaves, they can hire another one),
or do the managers believe that they can optimize performance by paying the
firm’s employees a living wage (because it raises morale and productivity, while
decreasing turnover rate and the hiring costs associated with replacing workers)?
These two positions are substantively different approaches to business. Good
arguments can be made in defense of both positions, but they are fundamentally
different. This is the arena in which SVC operates. It is a progressive, enlight
ened approach to management that places the interests of a wide range of stake
holders within the decision matrix of the firm.4
The essential difference between those firms that do SVC well and those
that do it badly, therefore, is a greater sensitivity to the needs and concerns of
the firm’s broad range of stakeholders. This provides the firm with an acute
ability to understand when the (stakeholder-defined) rules that define the
firm’s operational context have changed, and a framework within which to
apply that knowledge to the firm’s strategic advantage. Those firms that can
respond to (and, ideally, anticipate) those changes are better placed to survive
and thrive in a dynamic business environment. Also, in striving to meet the
needs and concerns of their stakeholders, those firms that engage in these
activities in a more genuine, authentic way will find that the associated bene
fits are sustained because the effort is more effective and valued.
A short-term focus, driven by quarterly earnings guidance to investors
with little long-term interest in the organization’s survival, is of little concern
(and is most likely detrimental) to firms committed to implementing SVC.
Similarly, while economic value and other kinds of value (social, moral,
ethical) cover similar ground, the overlap is not perfect. Externalities and
transgressions are the result. Values help fill the gap and aid the SVC decision-
making process.5 To this end, a stakeholder filter is the tool the firm can use
to apply its values to identify both potential opportunities and potential prob
lems. The firm retains the societal legitimacy to remain an ongoing entity by
seeking to implement its strategic plan and conduct operations while con
sidering the needs and concerns of a broad array of stakeholders. The result is
that, rather than profit maximization through a short-term focus, profit optimi
zation emphasizes the importance of meeting the needs of these stakeholders
over the medium to long term.
SVC, therefore, refines the economic system in which capitalism drives
social and economic progress. The effects enhance the magnificent potential
106 Sustainable Value Creation
of business to alter our lives that has been summarized by some of the greatest
business minds of our time:
Profit for a company is like oxygen for a person. If you don’t have
enough of it, you’re out of the game. But if you think your life is about
breathing, you’re really missing something.
Peter Drucker6
Being the richest man in the cemetery doesn’t matter to me. … Going to
bed at night saying we’ve done something wonderful … that’s what
matters to me.
Steve Jobs7
In short, SVC equals value creation in today’s complex and dynamic business
environment – sustainable value creation. What does this mean in practice?
Primarily, it means that those firms that “get” SVC will be able to create
more value over a longer period of time than those firms that either do not
understand the strategic value of this perspective, or ignore it altogether.
Final thoughts
As noted many years ago by Howard Bowen, the process of re-orienting
capitalism to better suit the interests of society, broadly defined, is a complex
process “which goes to the very root of our basic social and economic philo
sophy.”8 As a result, this task will not be achieved overnight. Given that we
are working to reform a system that is already well-equipped to generate
phenomenal economic and social progress, however, the task is also not
unimaginable:
The development of a moral code for business that can win wide accept
ance and social sanction necessarily involves somewhat the same
evolutionary process as characterizes the development of the law. … We
should not assume, however, that we are starting in this process from zero.
Even under laissez faire, there was a system of moral rules for business.9
–––––––––– « » ––––––––––
About the author
Epigraph
1 Milton Friedman, Capitalism and Freedom, University of Chicago Press, 1962,
Chapter VIII, p. 133.
Foreword
1 This Foreword appeared in the first edition of this book: David Chandler, Corporate
Social Responsibility: A Strategic Perspective, Business Expert Press, 2015. Lynn Stout
passed away in April 2018.