Kant On Autonomy of The Will
Kant On Autonomy of The Will
Kant On Autonomy of The Will
Draft of a chapter to be included the Routledge Handbook of Autonomy (ed. Ben Colburn)
University of Groningen. He received his PhD from the Universities of St Andrews and Stirling
Abstract: Kant takes the idea of autonomy of the will to be his distinctive contribution to moral
philosophy. However, this idea is more nuanced and complicated than one might think. In this
chapter, I sketch the rough outlines of Kant’s idea of autonomy of the will while also
highlighting contentious exegetical issues that give rise to various possible interpretations. I
tentatively defend four basic claims. First, autonomy primarily features in Kant’s account of
moral agency, as the condition of the possibility of moral obligation. Second, autonomy
capacity. Third, although there is legitimate scholarly disagreement about whether or not
autonomy involves self-legislation of the moral law, there is good reason to believe it
between the will and moral requirements. Fourth, persons have dignity because their
autonomy makes them members in the set of beings over whom the categorical imperative
property.
1
1. Introduction
In the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, Kant boldly asserts that all previous attempts
“to detect the principle of morality […] had to fail” for the same reason (G 4:432) 1:
One saw the human being bound to laws by his duty, but it did not occur to anyone
that he is subject only to his own and yet universal legislation, and that he is only
obligated to act in conformity with his own will which is, however, universally
According to Kant, therefore, the moral philosophers who came before him failed because
they did not consider the possibility that the human being possesses autonomy of the will,
which he defines as “the characteristic of the will by which it is a law to itself (independently
of any characteristic of the objects of willing)”, and that the principle of morality is a “principle
of autonomy” (G 4:440).
Since Kant thus takes the idea of autonomy of the will to be his distinctive contribution to
moral philosophy, we might expect this idea, and the role it plays in his moral theory, to be
clear and straightforward. This expectation might be reinforced by our confidence that we
have a decent intuitive grasp of the concept of autonomy—which, after all, is central to much
of current moral and political philosophy. However, Kant’s idea of autonomy of the will is more
1
I use the following abbreviations for (and translations of) Kant’s works: Col for Collins’s Lecture Notes (Kant
1997); CPR for Critique of Pure Reason (Kant 1999); CPrR for Critique of Practical Reason (Kant 1996); G for
Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (Kant 2011); MM for Metaphysics of Morals (Kant 1996); Vigil for
Vigiliantius’s Lecture notes (Kant 1997). I follow the pagination of the Prussian Academy Edition, except for the
2
In this chapter, I sketch the rough outlines of Kant’s idea of autonomy of the will while also
highlighting contentious exegetical issues that give rise to various possible interpretations. I
will start by considering why Kant attributes such central importance to autonomy of the will
(Section 2). On this basis, I try to gain a better understanding of what Kant means by
‘autonomy of the will’, particularly whether this term denotes a metaphysical property, a
Subsequently, I discuss whether and in what sense Kant’s doctrine of autonomy should be
understood to entail that we self-legislate the moral law (Section 4). Finally, I explore the
relationship between autonomy and the moral standing of persons as ends in themselves
(Section 5).
My focus throughout this chapter is on Kant’s conception of autonomy of the will. I thus
bracket Kant’s remarks about the autonomy of states. Moreover, my goal is to sketch what
autonomy of the will means for Kant and what role it plays in his foundational moral theory,
as laid out, primarily, in the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals and the Critique of
Practical Reason. I do not discuss how Kant argues for the claim that we possess autonomy of
the will, let alone how this claim relates to his overall metaphysical views. Finally, I do not
philosophy. Any serious investigation of these issues would soon reveal that Kant’s idea of
2. Why Autonomy?
Why, according to Kant, does the fact that previous moral philosophers did not consider
autonomy of the will as a possibility mean that their attempts to determine the principle of
morality had to fail? The answer is that Kant holds that a “mere analysis of the concepts of
2
morality” (G 4:440) reveals that we must possess autonomy of the will if morality is to be more
than a “chimerical idea without truth” (G 4:445). That is, the idea of autonomy is already
to make sense of the idea of moral obligation, which is central to this understanding.
It is sometimes stated that the reason why Kant deems autonomy necessary for moral
the claim that moral obligations are unconditionally binding could be understood as the mere
claim that they bind us regardless of our antecedent desires. But intuitionists like W.D. Ross,
for example, agree with this claim and nevertheless deny that our will is a law to itself (Ross
2002: 157-160; see also Stratton-Lake 2013: 254-55). Ross holds that some acts are required
or prohibited as a matter of “the fundamental nature of the universe” (ibid: 29). Thus, to
understand why Kant attaches such great importance to autonomy, we need to determine in
what sense he takes moral obligations to be unconditionally binding. And to determine this,
we need to look at the entire bundle of moral concepts that he analyses in the Groundwork.
Kant’s analysis starts with the concept of the good will. He asserts that “[i]t is impossible to
think of anything at all in the world, or indeed even beyond it, that could be taken to be good
without limitation, except a GOOD WILL” (G 4:393). Kant grants that there are many other
things that can be taken to be good, such as wit, confidence, and happiness. Yet, Kant argues,
none of these things are good unconditionally. More specifically, they are not good unless they
According to Kant, to unpack the concept of a good will, we should “inspect the concept of
DUTY, which contains that of a good will, though under certain subjective limitations and
3
hindrances” (G 4:397). To imperfect rational beings like us, who are not solely determined by
reason but also possess a sensuous nature, the actions that a good will would perform are
represented as duties. More specifically, since our sensuous nature makes us susceptible to
Kant argues that the limitations of imperfectly rational beings implicit in the concept of duty
allow us to bring the concept of a good will into especially sharp relief (G 4:397). Imperfectly
rational beings can act either from duty or from inclination. Thus, by contrasting the two
sources of motivation available to them, we can get a better grasp of what it would mean to
Kant argues that action “from duty” is to be distinguished, not only from action “contrary to
duty”, but also from action that is merely “in conformity with duty” (G 4:397-98). One of the
examples that Kant uses to illustrate the latter distinction is that of an agent who helps others
from sympathy, i.e. because their suffering pains him and its relief gratifies him. Kant asserts
that, while this agent’s action “conforms with duty”, is even “amiable”, it “has no true moral
worth” (G 4:397). While the agent acts as duty requires, he does so only because, and insofar
as, duty aligns with his inclinations. By contrast, the beneficent action of an agent who,
through grief or by nature, is not inclined to act beneficently at all, has “far higher worth”
(ibid.).
Kant takes this to show that, in imperfectly rational beings like us, a good will corresponds to
the will of an agent who does his duty from duty alone, and thus regardless of inclination. He
also takes it to show that “an action from duty has its moral worth not in the purpose that is
4
to be attained by it, but in the maxim according to which it is resolved upon, and thus […] the
Kant’s reasoning seems to run as follows. The difference in moral worth between an action
from duty and an action from inclination cannot be due to their respective purposes because
they can have the same purpose (see Korsgaard 2008: 178; Timmermann 2007: 38). For
example, both the sympathetic benefactor and the agent who acts beneficently from duty
desiderative faculty” cannot determine the will immediately (G 4:400). If it determines the will
at all, it does so via an inclination of the agent’s. And we have already seen that, for Kant,
Note that the properties of the particular act-type that the agent performs are external to his
deliberation in the same way as his purpose. Thus, they cannot be what determines the choice
of a good-willed agent either. Accordingly, Kant remarks that moral worth does not reside in
For Kant, then, actions from duty are guided, not by some external object or feature, but by
something internal to the agent’s deliberation. More specifically, they are guided by the
quality of the agent’s maxim. He states that “[a] maxim is the subjective principle of willing”
(G 4:400, footnote). He later adds that a maxim is the principle an agent actually acts on, and
thus to be distinguished from the law, which is the principle that the agent ought to conform
question (see Gressis 2010a; Gressis 2010b). What is important for our purposes is that Kant
5
thinks that the moral worth of an action depends on which maxim governs the agent’s choice
of the action.
But what characterises the maxim underlying a morally good action? Kant writes that “as every
material principle has been taken away from it […] nothing remains for the will that could
determine it except, objectively, the law and, subjectively, pure respect for this practical law”
(G 4:400). Kant’s reasoning is that, since a morally worthy action is done from duty, and duty
presupposes a law,2 the maxim underlying such an action must be lawful. Therefore, an action
However, the law in question cannot be a particular, substantive law. This is what Kant’s
statement that “every material principle has been taken away from [the will]” highlights
(ibid.). It means that, in choosing how to act, a good will is not guided by the satisfaction of
purpose. Instead, the maxims underlying morally worthy actions are distinguished by their
“mere conformity with law as such”, i.e. their conformity to the very idea of law (G 4:402). In
other words, what distinguishes these maxims is that they could serve or function as laws. We
might say that they possess the form of laws (see G 4:436).
According to Kant, then, the lawful form of its maxims “alone is to serve the will as its principle,
i.e. I ought never to proceed except in such a way that I could also will that my maxim should
become a universal law” (G 4:402).3 Kant thus identifies the merely formal requirement only
2
“The concept of duty stands in immediate relation to a law (even if I abstract from all ends, as the matter of the
3
Why does Kant suddenly speak of universal law here? The reason seems to be that the law in question must be
6
to act on maxims that one could also will to become universal laws as the supreme principle
of morality. For imperfectly rational beings, who are necessitated by the law, this principle
takes the form of an imperative. Kant later identifies it as the only imperative that necessitates
according to that maxim through which you can at the same time will that it become a
The categorical imperative leads us straight to the idea of autonomy of the will. Recall that
Kant defines autonomy as “the characteristic of the will by which it is a law to itself
(independently of any characteristic of the objects of willing)” (G 4:440). This is exactly the
characteristic that the will must have if it is to be able to act from duty: it must select its
maxims by a law, and yet independently of any particular, substantive law. To do so, it must
select its maxims in light of whether they could be willed to be universal laws. Accordingly,
Kant also refers to the categorical imperative as “the principle of every human will as a will
universally legislating through all its maxims” (G 4:432) or simply as “the principle of
autonomy” (G 4:440).
We can now see why it is so important to Kant that the will is regarded as autonomous.
According to Kant, the concepts of duty and the good will, which are central to ordinary
people’s understanding of morality, entail the concept of a law that binds unconditionally.
Such a law is not merely independent of our antecedent desires (pace Ross), but necessitates
us through pure respect for lawfulness as such. But this means that, if the concepts of duty
and a good will are instantiated in the real world, we must possess autonomy of the will.
Therefore, Kant’s charge that previous thinkers foreclosed the possibility of autonomy
7
amounts to the charge that they rendered morality itself, as understood by ordinary people,
a mere fiction.
Kant’s idea of autonomy primarily characterises the way we, as agents, must relate to moral
requirements if such requirements are to be possible. This, then, is the primary function that
autonomy serves within Kant’s framework. But what exactly does autonomy of the will
Kant argues that autonomy is both necessary and sufficient for freedom of the will. The will is
free if it “can be efficient independently of alien causes determining it” (G 4:446). Thus, if the
will can determine itself by its own lawful form, and thus independently of sensibility, it is free.
To show that autonomy is also necessary for freedom of the will, Kant argues that freedom
has not only a “negative” but also a “positive” aspect (ibid.). According to Kant, “the will is a
kind of causality” (ibid.). Now, “[s]ince the concept of causality carries with it that of laws”
connecting causes with effects, this means that a free will cannot be “lawless” (ibid.).
Accordingly, a free will is not merely independent of alien causes (and thus of the laws of
nature) but proceeds in accordance with its own law. That is, it is autonomous.
As Karl Ameriks points out, Kant’s notion of freedom of the will is “transcendental” rather than
“empirical” (Ameriks 2013: 54-58). For the will to be independent from ‘alien causes’—and
thus to exhibit the negative aspect of freedom—it is not sufficient that it be independent from
empirical causes outside ourselves, such as manipulation or external compulsion. Instead, the
8
will must not be determined by any empirical causes, including aspects of our empirical nature
Thus, the association between autonomy and freedom of the will clearly shows that autonomy
has a metaphysical dimension. But the association between autonomy and transcendental
freedom also highlights another, normative dimension of autonomy (see, e.g., Reath 2013: 36;
Sensen 2013b: 263). We can see this by shifting our attention to the side of autonomy that
mirrors the positive aspect of freedom. Since autonomy is the characteristic of the will to be
a law to itself, independently of the objects of volition, autonomy is not only necessary but
sufficient for the authority of the moral law. Thus, Kant writes: “a free will and a will under
moral laws are one and the same” (G 4:447). Henry Allison has labelled this the “reciprocity
It follows that imperfect rational beings like us (who do not necessarily conform to the moral
law), insofar as they are autonomous, are bound by the law, in the form of the categorical
imperative. Thus, our will’s being a law to itself—its ability to be efficacious independently of
empirical causes—has implications for what we ought to do. As Jens Timmermann puts it,
“[o]ddly enough, ‘can’ implies ‘ought’” (2007: 121). We might even say that, for beings like us,
autonomy itself is a normative principle. Indeed, Kant explicitly identifies “[t]he autonomy of
the will as the supreme principle of morality” (G 4:440). For Kant, to say that the will is
autonomous just is to say that it is subject to the “principle of autonomy”, i.e., “not to choose
in any other way than that the maxims of one’s choice are also comprised as universal law in
This highlights that autonomy is not only the condition of the possibility of moral obligation
but also furnishes the content of moral commands. Since the moral law’s only prescription is
9
that our maxims be willable as universal laws, we might say that the moral law commands
that we “realise” or “express” our autonomy (Sensen 2011: 169 and Hill 1992: 85,
respectively). In Kant’s words, the law “commands neither more nor less than just this
autonomy” (G 4:440).
But the positive aspect of freedom not only reveals the normative dimension of autonomy; it
also implies that beings with autonomy must have certain psychological capacities. In
particular, if a rational will is not only (negatively) independent of the laws of empirical nature
but also (positively) a law to itself, rational agents must be capable of recognising and being
motivated by that law. It thus seems that autonomy is not only a metaphysical property and a
normative principle, but also “a recognitional cum motivational capacity” (Reath 2013: 33).
Note, however, that the precise psychological implications of autonomy can vary between
different kinds of rational beings. For imperfect rational beings like us, who are sensuously
affected, the capacity to be motivated by the law requires the existence of an incentive to
comply with it (CPrR 5:72). Since this incentive must be able to counteract impulse and
inclination, which are “based on feeling”, the incentive must itself be (based on) a feeling
(ibid.). Yet, since this feeling could not enable autonomy if it was empirically conditioned, it
must instead be “solely produced by reason” (CPrR 5:76). Kant identifies that feeling as
By contrast, perfect rational beings (such as “the divine will”) do not require any incentive to
be motivated by the moral law (CPrR 5:72). Since they are not sensuously affected, their
actions necessarily conform to the moral law. Consequently, autonomy should not be
identified with the capacity to act from respect for the law, although it requires that capacity
in human beings.
10
4. Autonomy as Self-Legislation of the Moral Law?
So far, my focus has been on the autonomous will’s ability to be determined by a law that is
not empirically conditioned. But ‘autonomy’ literally means self-legislation. As Kant himself
states, “the will is not just subject to the law, but subject in such a way that it must also be
viewed as self-legislating, and just on account of this as subject to the law” (G 4:431). Hence,
autonomy of the will seems to imply that the will in some sense gives law to itself.
suggests that autonomy underwrites “a normative standing of the rational will” (2013: 33).
The autonomous will seems to be “normatively self-governing” in that “it need not answer to
any outside authority, but only to itself” (ibid.) In short, autonomy underwrites a kind of
However, the idea that the will self-legislates the moral law, i.e. the law expressed by the
categorical imperative, can seem puzzling. The puzzle is how to square this idea with the
unconditional authority of the moral law. For talk of ‘self-legislation’ may seem to suggest that
the law’s authority is conditional on an act of legislation (Kleingeld and Willaschek 2019: 3;
This raises the question of how the ‘legislation’ part of ‘self-legislation’ is to be understood.
Kant distinguishes two roles in legislative processes. He calls the one who commands a law its
“lawgiver” (MM 6:227). Since the lawgiver makes the law binding, he is the “author of the
obligation” (ibid.). But the lawgiver need not also be the “author of the law”, i.e. the one who
determines its content (ibid.) And, indeed, Kant seems to suggest that the moral law has no
author (Col 27: 282–83; Vigil 27:544; see also, e.g., Kain 2004; Stern 2010; Timmermann 2007:
11
107; Wood 2008: 113). It is thus not up to us, nor anyone else, what the law commands.
However, this qualification may not dispel the air of paradox surrounding the notion of
autonomy completely. After all, it leaves open the possibility that it is up to us—the very
agents who are subject to the law—to make the law binding. This leads us to a second
One option is that it refers to our self as concrete, empirical human beings. This interpretation
might be congenial to theorists who associate autonomy with the expression of one’s personal
values or identity (e.g. Bratman 1979; Frankfurt 1988). And, indeed, some contemporary
Kantians are sometimes read as endorsing it (e.g. Korsgaard 2009). But this interpretation also
makes it harder to see how the moral law can possess unconditional authority. For it suggests
that the self that is subject to the moral law is indeed identical to the self that legislates it.
Kant seems to rule out this interpretation for this very reason (MM 6:417).
It seems more likely that, instead, the ‘self’ refers to our noumenal self (Sensen 2013b: 268;
Timmerman 2007: 115). While our phenomenal self corresponds to our nature as a concrete
human being, our noumenal self corresponds to our nature as a being with pure practical
reason, an immutable nature that we share with all other rational beings (MM 6:418). A
related (though not identical) distinction in Kant’s works is between our faculty of “choice”
(Willkür) and our “will” (Wille): while the former enables us to act and realise the objects of
our desires in general, the latter enables us to be guided by pure reason alone (MM 6:213;
also see Sensen 2013b: 269; Timmermann 2007: 115, 173-75). Thus, if our noumenal self or
will—as opposed to our phenomenal self or faculty of choice—gives the law to us, this might
12
explain how we can be both self-legislating and subject to the unconditional authority of the
law.4
A third option is that the ‘self’ in ‘self-legislation’ does not refer to one of the agent’s selves
at all. Instead, it indicates that the law is authoritative of itself, i.e. without presupposing
anything else (Sensen 2013b: 269; also see O’Neill 2003: 15-19). The idea is that the moral law
states the conditions of the possibility of lawgiving, and therefore does not depend on the
This interpretation suggests that the moral law is not ‘legislated’ in any literal or
straightforward sense. But it does not abandon the assumption that the moral law is legislated
in some sense, which is shared by a wide range of scholars (e.g. Engstrom 2009: 149; Reath
2006; Reath 2013; Schneewind 1998: 6; Wood 2008: 106). An outright rejection of this
assumption has been suggested more recently, by Pauline Kleingeld and Marcus Willaschek
(2019).
Kleingeld and Willaschek raise a third question about talk of ‘self-legislation’: what, if anything,
is being legislated? They argue that Kant does not regard the moral law, as expressed by the
legislation only in the context of substantive moral laws, i.e. imperatives that express the
specific duties that result from applying the categorical imperative to our maxims. According
to Kleingeld and Willaschek, Kant calls the categorical imperative “the principle of autonomy”
because it commands that we select our maxims as if we were thereby also giving law to all
rational beings (2019: 6-7). They conclude that Kant’s notion of autonomy does not imply that
4
For a qualified criticism of this idea, see Reath (2013: 45-47).
13
the authority of the moral law is grounded in any kind of legislation. Instead, this authority is
The latter three interpretations of the notion of self-legislation—that the noumenal self or
Wille legislates the law, that the law is authoritative of itself, and that only particular moral
laws are to be regarded as self-legislated—all seem like promising candidates when it comes
to salvaging the unconditional authority of the moral law. However, these interpretations may
not seem congenial to the idea with which this section started: that autonomy underwrites a
Yet, one idea, which is popular among Kantian ethicists and seems largely compatible with
these three interpretations, might help to alleviate this concern. The idea is that the moral law
is the constitutive principle of willing or, equivalently, of the activity of practical reason.
Different versions of this idea have been proposed in the literature (see, e.g., Engstrom 2009;
Hill 1992: 87-88; Korsgaard 2009; Reath 2013; Sensen 2019).5 Here, I merely try to sketch what
As Christine Korsgaard notes, to say that a principle is constitutive of an activity is to say that
“unless you are guided by the principle in question, you are not performing that activity at all”
(2009: 29). For example, the constitutive principle of building a house requires that you erect
a physical structure that provides shelter from the weather (ibid.). If you do not at least aspire
or strive to conform to this principle, you are not engaged in house-building at all.
5
One question that divides theorists is whether the law is constitutive of Wille (Sensen 2019), Wille and Willkür
14
The constitutive principle of an activity is a normative standard for that activity (Korsgaard
2009: 29-32). For example, building a physical structure that has random holes in the walls
and ceiling will at best count as building a house badly because it at most imperfectly conforms
to the constitutive principle of that activity. However, whereas normative standards that are
certain external factors (e.g. whether the house-builder cares about beauty), the constitutive
principle of an activity seems to provide a normative standard which is internal to that activity.
Thus, the claim that the moral law is the constitutive principle of willing amounts to the claim
that, unless we acknowledge the categorical imperative as binding, we are not engaged in the
activity of willing at all. What is more, it implies that the categorical imperative provides a
normative standard for our actions which is internal to our will. Far from imposing an external
constraint on us, it expresses our own will’s in-built ambition to be a law to itself.6
It is not implausible to attribute this view to Kant. As we saw above, Kant thinks that if our will
psychological capacity), we are bound by the normative requirement to make our maxims
willable as universal laws. The idea that the categorical imperative is constitutive of the activity
If this is Kant’s view, then perhaps the idea that autonomy accords the will a kind of
sovereignty can be salvaged after all. Even if we do not legislate the moral law to ourselves, it
is in a sense our own law. We strive to comply with this law by virtue of being the kind of
6
This need not make immoral willing impossible. Agents who don’t comply with the moral law might still be said
to acknowledge its bindingness. Kant writes: “even the most hardened scoundrel [...] is conscious of [...] the law,
15
creatures who engage in willing (see Reath 2013). Indeed, since it is an internal standard of
willing, the law would not bind anyone if there were no creatures like us (see Sensen 2013c;
Sensen 2019).
This suggests that Kant’s idea of autonomy of the will parallels his so-called Copernican
Revolution in theoretical philosophy (see CPR BXvi). As Oliver Sensen puts it, just as Kant’s
theoretical philosophy proposes that “we are not merely passive observers in cognizing
nature, but that our mind (partly) constitutes how reality appears to us”, his practical
philosophy proposes that “it is an activity of reason, something reason does spontaneously
and out of itself (not something that it discovers) that grounds morality” (2019: 199 and 217,
respectively). We might say that Kant’s idea of autonomy portrays the relationship between
I have argued that autonomy primarily features in Kant’s theory of moral agency. But Kant
famously claims that rational beings are “persons” rather than “things”, “because their nature
already marks them out as ends in themselves, i.e. as something that may not be used merely
as a means” (G 4:428). And he writes that “[a]utonomy is […] the ground of the dignity of a
human and of every rational nature” (G 4:436). This suggests that autonomy also plays an
Furthermore, since Kant describes “dignity” as “an inner worth”, contrasting it with “a price”,
which is merely “a relative worth” (G 4:435), it might seem as if the property of autonomy has
value or some other kind of moral importance, independently of the moral law. And this might
in turn seem to explain the special moral standing of persons. Some Kant scholars seem to
come close to endorsing this interpretation (e.g. Caranti 2017; Guyer 1998). It might appeal
16
to theorists who want to derive human dignity or human rights from autonomy directly,
without taking a detour through the categorical imperative (e.g. Griffin 2008). But this
interpretation seems to contradict my claim that Kant proposes an ‘inside-out’ rather than an
However, there is good reason to doubt that Kant conceives of autonomy as an independently
important property. As we saw in Section 2, Kant thinks that a morally worthy action cannot
be one that is done for the sake of some “object of the desiderative faculty”, i.e. some object
that lies outside the will and that the will is aimed at, because such an object can only
determine the will via the agent’s inclinations (G 4:400; also see CPrR 5:62-64). Connectedly,
actions done for the sake of such an object would not realise our autonomy. After all, when
property (Sensen 2013b: 276-79).7 Any action for the sake of such a property would be from
inclination, and hence not realise autonomy. Kant holds that autonomy, and the ordinary
conception of morality that relies on it, are possible only if the will has its own, a priori law.
All objects of the will—even the property of autonomy itself—are to be assessed by that law.
independently important property? Recall that the moral law requires that we act on maxims
that we could will to be universal laws, i.e. laws that determine the will of every rational being.
Hence, our will “must always take its maxims from the point of view of itself, but also at the
same time of every other rational being as legislating (which are therefore also called
7
Also see Chapter 3 in this volume.
17
persons)” (G 4:438). In other words, the will’s maxims must be such that they could be willed
as universal laws by—and thus realise the autonomy of—every rational being. And this,
arguably, just is the requirement not to use others as mere means and instead to regard them
as ends-in-themselves. The following passage seems to confirm this reading (CPrR 5:87, italics
altered):
[E]very will […] is restricted to the condition of agreement with the autonomy of the
rational being, that is to say, such a being is not to be subjected to any purpose that is
not possible in accordance with a law that could arise from the will of the affected
subject himself; hence this subject is to be used never merely as a means but as at the
The idea seems to be roughly that, in order to avoid using someone as a mere means, we have
to act on a maxim that they could also rationally will (O’Neill 1989: 141-44; Reath 2013: 51-
52; Sensen 2011: 109).8 And this is just what it takes for our maxim to be compatible with the
categorical imperative.
independently valuable or otherwise important property, but because the law commands that
our maxims be such that we could will them to become universal law, which is the case if and
only if they could be willed by any rational being as such. The dignity of persons is therefore
grounded in their autonomy in the sense that their autonomy makes them members in the
set of beings over whom our maxims must be universalisable (see Bader forthcoming). In
8
For a different reading, see Kleingeld (2020). For discussion, see Chapter 3 in this volume.
9
I bracket the question of whether the moral standing of persons should be framed in terms of value at all (see
Bader forthcoming).
18
Kant’s words, autonomy makes each person a “legislating member of the universal kingdom
of ends” (G 4:438).
This corroborates my claim that autonomy primarily characterises the way persons,
rather than as mere subjects. The moral standing of persons, considered as moral patients,
merely reflects this relation. Hence, Kant writes, “morality and humanity, in so far as it is
capable of morality, is that which alone has dignity” (G 4:435, italics added).
6. Conclusion
I have argued that autonomy primarily features in Kant’s account of moral agency, as the
of the will, a normative principle (for imperfectly rational beings) and a psychological capacity.
While there is reasonable disagreement about whether autonomy implies that the moral law
is self-legislated, there is good reason to think that it underwrites an ‘inside-out’ picture of the
relation between moral agents and moral requirements. These claims are not undermined by
autonomy’s relation to dignity. Persons have dignity because their autonomy makes them
members in the set of beings over whom the law requires us to universalise, not because
Further Reading
Oliver Sensen (ed.), Kant on Moral Autonomy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013)
significance, and its relevance today. Stefano Bacin and Oliver Sensen (eds.), The Emergence
19
collection of cutting-edge essays on the development of the idea of autonomy across the
References
Allison, Henry. 1990. Kant’s Theory of Freedom, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bader, Ralf. Forthcoming. “The Dignity of Humanity,” in Sarah Buss and Nandi Theunissen
Bratman, Michael. 1979. “Practical Reasoning and Weakness of the Will.” Noûs, 13: 131–51.
Caranti, Luigi. 2017. Kant’s Political Legacy: Human Rights, Peace and Progress, Cardiff:
Engstrom, Stephen. 2009. The Form of Practical Knowledge, Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Frankfurt, Harry. 1988. The Importance of What We Care About, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
— 2010b. “Recent Work on Kantian Maxims II.” Philosophy Compass 5(3): 228–239.
Guyer, Paul. 1998. “The Value of Reason and the Value of Freedom.” Ethics 109: 22–35.
Hill, Thomas Jr. 1992. “The Kantian Conception of Autonomy,” in Dignity and Practical Reason
in Kant’s Moral Theory, Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press: 76-96.
Kain, Patrick. 2004. “Self-Legislation in Kant’s Moral Philosophy.” Archiv für Geschichte der
Kant, Immanuel. 1996. Practical Philosophy, Mary Gregor (ed. and trans.), Cambridge:
20
Cambridge University Press.
— 1997. Lectures on Ethics, Peter Heath (ed. and trans.) and Jerome B. Schneewind (ed.),
— 1999. Critique of Pure Reason, Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood (eds. and trans.),
Gregor and Jens Timmermann (eds. and trans.), Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Kleingeld, Pauline. 2020. “How to Use Someone ‘Merely as a Means’.” Kantian Review 25(3):
389-414.
Kleingeld, Pauline and Willaschek, Marcus. 2019. “Autonomy Without Paradox: Kant, Self-
Korsgaard, Christine. 2008. The Constitution of Agency: Essays on Practical Reason and Moral
Press.
Pinkard, Terry. 2002. German Philosophy 1760–1860: The Legacy of Idealism, Cambridge:
Reath, Andrews. 2006. Agency & Autonomy in Kant’s Moral Theory, Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
21
— 2013. “Kant’s Conception of Autonomy of the Will,” in Sensen 2013a: 32-52.
Ross, William D. 2002. The Right and the Good, Philip Stratton-Lake (ed.), Oxford: Clarendon
Press.
— 2019. “Kant’s Constitutivism,” in Robinson dos Santos and Elke Elisabeth Schmidt
(eds.), Realism and Antirealism in Kant’s Moral Philosophy: New Essays, Berlin/Boson:
De Gruyter, 197-220.
Stern, Robert. 2010. “Moral Scepticism and Agency: Kant and Korsgaard.” Ratio 23(4): 453-
474.
Wood, Allen W. 2008. Kantian Ethics, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
22