Yogachara

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 40

Yogachara

Yogachara (Sanskrit: योगाचार, IAST: Yogācāra) is an influential


Translations of
tradition of Buddhist philosophy and psychology emphasizing the
Yogacāra school
study of cognition, perception, and consciousness through the
interior lens of meditation, as well as philosophical reasoning English Yoga Practice,
Doctrine of
(hetuvidyā).[1][2] Yogachara was one of the two most influential
Consciousness,
traditions of Mahayana Buddhism in India, along with
Consciousness-Only
Madhyamaka.[3]
Doctrine,
The compound Yogācāra literally means "practitioner of yoga", or Cognizance-Only,
"one whose practice is yoga", hence the name of the school is Mind-Only
literally "the school of the yogins".[4][3] Yogācāra was also Sanskrit Yogacāra,
variously termed Vijñānavāda (the doctrine of consciousness), Vijñānavāda,
Vijñaptivāda (the doctrine of ideas or percepts) or Vijñaptimātratā- Vijñaptivāda,
vāda (the doctrine of 'mere representation'), which is also the name Vijñaptimātratā,
given to its major theory of mind which seeks to deconstruct how Cittamātra
we perceive the world. There are several interpretations of this Chinese 唯識瑜伽行派
main theory: various forms of Idealism, as well as a (Pinyin: Wéishí
phenomenology or representationalism. Aside from this, Yogācāra Yúqiexíng Pài)
also developed an elaborate analysis of consciousness (vijñana)
and mental phenomena (dharmas), as well as an extensive system
Japanese 瑜伽行唯識派
(Rōmaji: Yugagyō
of Buddhist spiritual practice, i.e. yoga.[1] Yuishiki Ha)

The movement has been traced to the first centuries of the common Korean 유식유가행파
era and seems to have developed as some yogis of the Sarvāstivāda (RR: Yusik-
and Sautrāntika traditions in north India adopted Mahayana Yugahaeng-pa)
Buddhism. [5][6] The Gandhāran brothers Asaṅga and Vasubandhu Tibetan རྣལ་འབྱོ ར་སྤྱོ ད་པ་
(both c. 4-5th century CE), are considered the classic philosophers (rnal 'byor spyod pa)
and systematizers of this school, along with the figure of Vietnamese Du-già Hành Tông
Maitreya.[7] Yogācāra was later imported to Tibet and East Asia by
Glossary of Buddhism
figures like Shantaraksita (8th century) and Xuanzang (7th-
century). Today, Yogācāra ideas and texts continue to be influential subjects of study for Tibetan Buddhism
and East Asian Buddhism.

Doctrine
Yogācāra philosophy is primarily meant to aid in the practice of yoga and meditation and thus it also sets
forth a systematic analysis of the Mahayana path of mental training (see five paths pañcamārga).[8]
Yogācārins made use of ideas from previous traditions, such as Prajñāpāramitā and the Sarvāstivāda
Abhidharma tradition, to develop a novel analysis of conscious experience and a corresponding schema for
Mahāyāna spiritual practice.[9][10][11] In its analysis, Yogācāra works like the Saṅdhinirmocana Sūtra,
developing various core concepts such as vijñapti-mātra, the ālaya-vijñāna (store consciousness), the
turning of the basis (āśraya-parāvṛtti), the three natures (trisvabhāva), and emptiness.[1] They form a
complex system, and each can be taken as a point of departure for understanding Yogācāra.[12]

The doctrine of vijñapti-mātra


One of the main features of Yogācāra philosophy is the concept of vijñapti-mātra. It is often used
interchangeably with the term citta-mātra in modern and ancient Yogacara sources.[7][13][14] The standard
translation of both terms is "consciousness-only" or "mind-only." Several modern researchers object to this
translation in favor of alternative like representation-only.[10] The meaning of this term is at the heart of the
modern scholarly disagreement about whether Yogacara Buddhism can be said to be a form of idealism (as
supported by Garfield, Hopkins, and others) or whether it is definitely not idealist (Anacker, Lusthaus,
Wayman).[15]

Origins
According to Lambert Schmithausen, the earliest surviving appearance of this term is in chapter 8 of the
Saṅdhinirmocana Sūtra, which has only survived in Tibetan and Chinese translations that differ in syntax
and meaning.[16] The passage is depicted as a response by the Buddha to a question which asks "whether
the images or replicas (*pratibimba) which are the object (*gocara) of meditative concentration
(*samadhi), are different/separate (*bhinna) from the contemplating mind (*citta) or not." The Buddha says
they are not different, "Because these images are vijñapti-mātra." The text goes on to affirm that the same is
true for objects of ordinary perception.[17]

The term is sometimes used as a synonym with citta-mātra (mere citta), which is also used as a name for
the school that suggests Idealism.[7][13] Schmithausen writes that the first appearance of this term is in the
Pratyupanna samadhi sutra, which states "this (or: whatever belongs to this) triple world is nothing but
mind (or thought: *cittamatra). Why? Because however I imagine things, that is how they appear."[18]

Regarding existing Sanskrit sources, the term appears in the first verse of Vasubandhu's Vimśatikā (Twenty
Verses), which states:[19]

This [world] is vijñaptimātra, since it manifests itself as an unreal object (artha), just like the
case of those with cataracts seeing unreal hairs in the moon and the like (vijñaptimātram
evaitad asad arthāvabhāsanāt yathā taimirikasyāsat keśa candrādi darśanam).

According to Mark Siderits, what Vasubandhu means here is that we are only ever aware of mental images
or impressions which manifest themselves as external objects, but "there is actually no such thing outside
the mind."[19]

The term also appears in Asaṅga's classic work, the Mahāyānasaṃgraha (no Sanskrit original, trans. from
Tibetan):

These representations (vijñapti) are mere representations (vijñapti-mātra), because there is no


[corresponding] thing/object (artha)...Just as in a dream there appear, even without a
thing/object (artha), just in the mind alone, forms/images of all kinds of things/objects like
visibles, sounds, smells, tastes, tangibles, houses, forests, land, and mountains, and yet there are
no [such] things/objects at all in that [place]. MSg II.6[20]

Another classic statement of the doctrine appears in Dharmakīrti's Pramānaṿārttika (Commentary on


Epistemology) which states: "cognition experiences itself, and nothing else whatsoever. Even the particular
objects of perception, are by nature just consciousness itself."[21]

Interpretations of vijñapti-mātra

Idealism
According to Bruce Cameron Hall, the interpretation of this doctrine as a form of subjective or absolute
idealism has been "the most common "outside" interpretation of Vijñānavāda, not only by modern writers,
but by its ancient opponents, both Hindu and Buddhist." [22] Scholars such as Jay Garfield, Saam Trivedi,
Nobuyoshi Yamabe, Paul Williams, and Sean Butler argue that Yogācāra is similar to Idealism (and they
compare it to the idealisms of Kant and Berkeley), though they note that it is its own unique form and that it
might be confusing to categorize it as such.[23][24][25][26][27]

The German scholar and philologist Lambert Schmithausen affirms that Yogacara sources teach a type of
idealism which is supposed to be a middle way between Abhidharma realism and what it often considered a
nihilistic position which only affirms emptiness as the ultimate.[28] Schmithausen notes that philological
study of Yogacara texts shows that they clearly reject the independent existence of mind and the external
world.[29] He also notes that the current trend in rejecting the idealistic interpretation might be related to the
unpopularity of idealism among Western academics.[29] Florin Delenau likewise affirms the idealist nature
of Yogācāra texts, while also underscoring how Yogācāra retains a strong orientation to a soteriology which
aims at contemplative realization of an ultimate reality that is an ‘inexpressible essence’
(nirabhilāpyasvabhāva) beyond any subject-object duality.[3]

Similarly, Jonathan Gold writes that the Yogācāra thinker Vasubandhu can be said to be an idealist (similar
to Kant), in the sense that for him, everything in experience as well as its causal support is mental, and thus
he gives causal priority to the mental. At the same time however, this is only in the conventional realm,
since "mind" is just another concept and true reality for Vasubandhu is ineffable, "an inconceivable
'thusness' (tathatā)." Indeed, the Vimśatikā states that the very idea of vijñapti-mātra must also be
understood to be itself a self-less construction and thus vijñapti-mātra is not the ultimate truth (paramārtha-
satya) in Yogācāra.[13] Thus according to Gold, while Vasubandhu's vijñapti-mātra can be said to be a
“conventionalist idealism”, it is to be seen as unique and different from Western forms, especially Hegelian
Absolute Idealism.[13]

Mere representation
The interpretation of Yogācāra as a type of idealism was standard until recently, when it began to be
challenged by scholars such as Kochumuttom, Anacker, Kalupahana,[30] Dunne, Lusthaus,[31] Powers, and
Wayman.[32][a]

Some scholars like David Kalupahana argue that it is a mistake to conflate the terms citta-mātra (which is
sometimes seen as a different, more metaphysical position) with vijñapti-mātra (which need not be
idealist).[10][33] However, Delenau points out that Vasubandhu clearly states in his Twenty Verses and
Abhidharmakosha that vijñapti and citta are synonymous.[34] Nevertheless, different alternative translations
for vijñapti-mātra have been proposed, such as representation-only, ideation-only, impressions-only and
perception-only.[22][35][36][7]

Alex Wayman notes that one's interpretation of Yogācāra will depend on how the qualifier mātra is to be
understood in this context, and he objects to interpretations which claim that Yogācāra rejects the external
world altogether, preferring translations such as "amounting to mind" or "mirroring mind" for citta-
mātra.[36] For Wayman, what this doctrine means is that "the mind has only a report or representation of
what the sense organ had sensed."[36] The representationalist interpretation is also supported by Stefan
Anacker.[37]

According to Thomas Kochumuttom, Yogācāra is a realistic pluralism which does not deny the existence of
individual beings.[10] Kochumuttom argues that Yogācāra is not idealism since it denies that absolute reality
is a consciousness, that individual beings are transformations or illusory appearances of an absolute
consciousness.[38] Thus, for Kochumuttom, vijñapti-mātra means "mere representation of consciousness,"
a view which states "that the world as it appears to the unenlightened ones is mere representation of
consciousness".[35] Furthermore, according to Kochumuttom, in Yogācāra "the absolute state is defined
simply as emptiness, namely the emptiness of subject-object distinction. Once thus defined as emptiness
(sunyata), it receives a number of synonyms, none of which betray idealism."[39]

Soterological phenomenology
According to Dan Lusthaus, the vijñapti-mātra theory is closer in some ways to Western Phenomenological
theories and Epistemological Idealism. However, it is not a form of metaphysical idealism because Yogācāra
rejects the construction of any type of metaphysical or ontological theories.[1] Moreover, Western idealism
lacks any counterpart to karma, samsara or awakening, all of which are central for Yogācāra. Regarding
vijñapti-mātra, Lusthaus translates it as "nothing but conscious construction" and states it is a kind of trick
built into consciousness which "projects and constructs a cognitive object in such a way that it disowns its
own creation - pretending the object is "out there" - in order to render that object capable of being
appropriated." This reification of cognition aids in constructing the notion of a permanent and independent
self, which is believed to appropriate and possess external 'things'. Yogācāra offers an analysis and
meditative means to negate this reification, thereby also negating the notion of a solid self. According to
Lusthaus, this analysis is not a rejection of external phenomena, and it does not grant foundational or
transcendent status to consciousness.[1] In this interpretation, instead of offering an ontological theory,
Yogācāra focuses on understanding and eliminating the underlying tendencies (anuśaya) that lead to
clinging concepts and theories, which are just cognitive projections (pratibimba, parikalpita). Thus, for
Lusthaus, the orientation of the Yogācāra school is largely consistent with the thinking of the Pāli nikāyas
and seeks to realign Mahayana with early Buddhist theory.[40]

Arguments for consciousness-only


According to the contemporary philosopher Jan Westerhoff, Yogācāra philosophers came up with various
arguments in defense of the consciousness-only view. He outlines three main arguments: the explanatory
equivalence argument, the causation-resemblance argument, and the constant co-cognition argument.[41]

Explanatory equivalence argument


This argument is found in Vasubandhu's Vimśatikā (Twenty Verses) and is an inference to the best
explanation. It argues that consciousness-only can provide an account of the various features of experience
which are explained by the existence of mind-independent material objects. This is coupled with a principle
of ontological parsimony to argue in favor of idealism.[41]

Vasubandhu mentions three key features of experience which are supposed to be explained by matter and
refutes them:[42][43][44]

1. According to critics, the problem of spatio-temporal determination (or non-arbitrariness in


regard to place and time) indicates that there must be some external basis for our
experiences, since experiences of any particular object do not occur everywhere and at
every time. Vasubandhu responds with the dream argument, which shows how a world
created by mind can still seem to have spatio-temporal localization.
2. The problem of inter-subjective experience (multiple minds experiencing the same world).
Vasubandhu counters that mass hallucinations (such as those said to occur to hungry
ghosts) caused by the fact they share similar karma (which is here understood as traces or
seeds in the mind-stream), show that inter-subjective agreement is possible without positing
real external objects.
3. Another criticism states that hallucinations have no pragmatic results, efficacy or causal
function and thus can be determined to be unreal, but entities we generally accept as being
"real" have actual causal results (such as the 'resistance' of external objects) that cannot be
of the same class as hallucinations. Against this claim, Vasubandhu argues that waking life
is the same as in a dream, where objects have pragmatic results within the very rules of the
dream. He also uses the example of a wet dream to show that mental content can have
causal efficacy even outside of a dream.
According to Mark Siderits, after disposing of these objections, Vasubandhu believes he has shown that
mere cognizance is just as good at explaining the relevant phenomena of experience as any theory of
realism that posits external objects. Therefore, he then applies the Indian philosophical principle termed the
"Principle of Lightness" (Sanskrit: lāghava, which is similar to Occam's Razor) to rule out realism since
vijñapti-mātra is the simpler and "lighter" theory which "posits the least number of unobservable
entities."[45]

Another objection that Vasubandhu answers is that of how one person can influence another's experiences,
if everything arises from mental karmic seeds in one's mind stream. Vasubandhu argues that "impressions
can also be caused in a mental stream by the occurrence of a distinct impression in another suitably linked
mental stream."[46] As Siderits notes, this account can explain how it is possible to influence or even totally
disrupt (murder) another mind, even if there is no physical medium or object in existence, since a suitably
strong enough intention in one mind stream can have effects on another mind stream.[46] From the mind-
only position, it is easier to posit a mind to mind causation than to have to explain mind to body causation,
which the realist must do. However, Siderits then goes on to question whether Vasubandhu's position is
indeed "lighter" since he must make use of multiple interactions between different minds to take into
account an intentionally created artifact, like a pot. Since we can be aware of a pot even when we are not
"linked" to the potter's intentions (even after the potter is dead), a more complex series of mental
interactions must be posited.[47] Nevertheless, not all interpretations of Yogācāra's view of the external
world rely on multiple relations between individual minds. Some interpretations in Chinese Buddhism
defended the view of a single shared external world (bhājanaloka) which was still made of consciousness,
while some later Indian thinkers like Ratnakīrti (11th century CE) defended a type of non-dual
monism.[48][49]

Causation-resemblance argument
This argument was famously defended in Dignāga's Ālambanaparīkṣā (Examination of the Object of
Consciousness) and its main target is Indian atomism, which was the main theory of matter in the 5th
century.[50] The argument is based on the premise that a perception must resemble the perceived object
(ālambana) and have been caused by the object.[50][41] According to this argument, since atoms are not
extended, they do not resemble the object of perception (which appears as spatially extended). Furthermore,
collections of atoms might resemble the object of perception, but they cannot have caused it. This is because
collections of things are unreal in classic Buddhist thought (thus it is a mereological nihilism), since they are
composites and composites made of parts do not have any causal efficacy (only individual atoms
do).[50][41]

In disproving the possibility of external objects, Vasubandhu's Vimśatikā similarly attacks Indian theories of
atomism and property particulars as incoherent on mereological grounds.[51]

Constant co-cognition argument


This argument was defended by Dharmakīrti in his Ascertainment of Epistemology (Pramāṇaviniścaya),
which calls it "the necessity of things only ever being experienced together with experience" (Sanskrit:
sahopalambhaniyama).[50] According to Dharmakīrti:

Because [something blue] is not apprehended without the additional qualification of


consciousness, [and] because [blue] is apprehended when this [qualification of consciousness]
is apprehended, consciousness [itself] has the appearance of blue. There is no external object
by itself. (PV 3.335)[50]

According this argument, any object of consciousness, like blue, cannot be differentiated from the
conscious awareness of blue since both are always experienced as one thing. Since we never experience
blue without the experience of blue, they cannot be differentiated empirically. Furthermore, we cannot
differentiate them through an inference either, since this would need to be based on a pattern of past
experiences which included the absence or presence of the two elements.[50][41] Thus, this is a type of
epistemological argument for idealism which attempts to show there is no good reason to accept the
existence of mind-independent objects.[50]

Soteriological importance of mind-only


Vasubandhu also explains why it is soteriologically important to get rid of the idea of really existing external
objects. According to Siderits, this is because:

When we wrongly imagine there to be external objects we are led to think in terms of the
duality of 'grasped and grasper', of what is 'out there' and what is ' in here' - in short, of external
world and self. Coming to see that there is no external world is a means, Vasubandhu thinks, of
overcoming a very subtle way of believing in an 'I'... once we see why physical objects can't
exist we will lose all temptation to think there is a true ' me' within. There are really just
impressions, but we superimpose on these the false constructions of object and subject. Seeing
this will free us from the false conception of an 'I'.[52]

Siderits notes how Kant had a similar notion, that is, without the idea of an objective mind independent
world, one cannot derive the concept of a subjective "I". But Kant drew the opposite conclusion to
Vasubandhu, since he held that we must believe in an enduring subject, and thus, also believe in external
objects.[52]

Analysis of Consciousness
Yogācāra gives a detailed explanation of the workings of the mind and the way it constructs the reality we
experience. The central Yogācāra theory of mind is that of the eight consciousnesses.

Eight consciousnesses
A key innovation of the Yogācāra school was the doctrine of eight consciousnesses.[1] These "eight bodies
of consciousnesses" (aṣṭa vijñānakāyāḥ) are: the five sense-consciousnesses (of seeing, hearing, smelling,
tasting and bodily sense), mentation (mano or citta), the defiled self-consciousness (kliṣṭamanovijñāna),[53]
and the storehouse or substratum consciousness (Skt: ālayavijñāna).[54][55] Traditional Buddhist
descriptions of consciousness taught just the first six vijñānas, each corresponding to a sense base (ayatana)
and having their own sense objects (sounds etc). Five are based on the five senses, while the sixth (mano-
vijñāna), was seen as the surveyor of the content of the five senses as well as of mental content like
thoughts and ideas. Standard Buddhist doctrine held that these eighteen "elements" (dhatus), i.e. six external
sense bases (smells, sounds etc.), six internal bases (sense organs like the eye, ear, etc.), and six
consciousnesses "exhaust the full extent of everything in the universe, or more accurately, the
sensorium."[1] The six consciousnesses are also not substantial entities, but a series or stream of events
(dharmas), which arise and vanish very rapidly moment by moment. This is the Abhidharma doctrine of
"momentariness" (kṣaṇavada), which Yogācāra also accepts.[56]

Yogācāra expanded the six vijñāna schema into a new system which with two new categories. The seventh
consciousness developed from the early Buddhist concept of manas, and was seen as the defiled mentation
(kliṣṭa-manas) which is obsessed with notions of "self". According to Paul Williams, this consciousness
"takes the substratum consciousness as its object and mistakenly considers the substratum consciousness to
be a true Self."[55]

Ālaya-vijñāna
The eighth consciousness, ālaya-vijñāna (storehouse or repository consciousness), was defined as the
storehouse of all karmic seeds (bīja), where they gradually matured until ripe, at which point they
manifested as karmic consequences. Because of this, it is also called the "mind which has all the seeds"
(sarvabījakam cittam), as well as the "basis consciousness" (mūla-vijñāna) and the "appropriating
consciousness" (ādānavijñāna). According to the Saṅdhinirmocana Sūtra, this kind of consciousness
underlies and supports the six types of manifest awareness, all of which occur simultaneously with the
ālaya.[57] William S. Waldron sees this "simultaneity of all the modes of cognitive awareness" as the most
significant departure of Yogācāra theory from traditional Buddhist models of vijñāna, which were "thought
to occur solely in conjunction with their respective sense bases and epistemic objects".[58]
As noted by Schmithausen, the ālaya-vijñāna, being a kind of vijñāna, has an object as well (as all vijñāna
has intentionality). That object is the sentient being's surrounding world, that is to say, the "receptable" or
"container" (bhājana) world. This is stated in the 8th chapter of the Saṅdhinirmocana Sūtra, which states
that the ādānavijñāna is characterized by "an unconscious (or not fully conscious?) steady perception (or
"representation") of the Receptacle (*asaṃvidita-sthira-bhājana-vijñapti)."[59]

The ālaya-vijñāna is also what experiences rebirth into future lives and what descents into the womb to
appropriate the fetal material. Therefore, the ālaya-vijñāna's holding on to the body's sense faculties and
"profuse imaginings" (prapañca) are the two appropriations which make up the "kindling" or "fuel" (lit.
upādāna) that samsaric existence depends upon.[57] Yogācāra thought thus holds that being unaware of the
processes going on in the ālaya-vijñāna is an important element of ignorance (avidya). The ālaya is also
individual, so that each person has their own ālaya-vijñāna, which is an ever changing process and
therefore not a permanent self.[1]

According to Williams, this consciousness "seen as a defiled form of consciousness (or perhaps sub- or
unconsciousness), is personal, individual, continually changing and yet serving to give a degree of personal
identity and to explain why it is that certain karmic results pertain to this particular individual. The seeds are
momentary, but they give rise to a perfumed series which eventually culminates in the result including, from
seeds of a particular type, the whole ‘inter-subjective’ phenomenal world."[60] Also, Asanga and
Vasubandhu write that the ālaya-vijñāna ‘ceases’ at awakening, becoming transformed into a pure
consciousness.[61]

According to Waldron, while there were various similar concepts in other Buddhist Abhidharma schools
which sought to explain karmic continuity, the ālaya-vijñāna is the most comprehensive and systematic.[62]
Waldron notes that the ālaya-vijñāna concept was probably influenced by these theories, particularly the
Sautrantika theory of seeds and Vasumitra's theory of a subtle form of mind (suksma-citta).[63]

Transformations of consciousness
Yogācāra sources do not necessarily describe the eight consciousnesses as absolutely separate or substantial
phenomena. For example, Kalupahana notes that the Triṃśika describes the various forms of consciousness
as transformations and functions of a being's stream of consciousness.[64][65][b] These transformations are
threefold according to Kalupahana. The first is the ālaya and its seeds, which is the flow or stream of
consciousness, without any of the usual projections on top of it.[65] The second transformation is manana,
self-consciousness or "Self-view, self-confusion, self-esteem and self-love".[66] It is "thinking" about the
various perceptions occurring in the stream of consciousness".[67] The ālaya is defiled by this self-
interest.[66] The third transformation is visaya-vijñapti, the "concept of the object".[68] In this transformation
the concept of objects is created. By creating these concepts human beings become "susceptible to grasping
after the object" as if it were a real object (sad artha) even though it is just a conception (vijñapti).[68]

A similar perspective which emphasizes Yogācāra's continuity with early Buddhism is given by Walpola
Rahula. According to Rahula, all the elements of this theory of consciousness with its three layers of
vijñāna are already found in the Pāli Canon, corresponding to the terms viññāna (sense cognition), manas
(mental function, thinking, reasoning, conception) and citta (the deepest layer of the aggregate of
consciousness which retains karmic impressions and the defilements).[69][70]

The Three Natures


Yogācāra works often define three basic modes or "natures" (svabhāva) of experience. Jonathan Gold
explains that "the three natures are all one reality viewed from three distinct angles. They are the
appearance, the process, and the emptiness of that same apparent entity."[13] According to Paul Williams,
"all things which can be known can be subsumed under these Three Natures."[71] Since this schema is
Yogācāra's systematic explanation of the Buddhist doctrine of emptiness (śūnyatā), each of the three natures
are also explained as having a lack of own-nature (niḥsvabhāvatā).[72][73] The Trisvabhāva-nirdeśa
(Exposition of the Three Natures) gives a brief definition of these three natures:

What appears is the dependent. How it appears is the fabricated. Because of being dependent
on conditions. Because of being only fabrication. The eternal non-existence of the appearance
as it is appears: That is known to be the perfected nature, because of being always the same.
What appears there? The unreal fabrication. How does it appear? As a dual self. What is its
nonexistence? That by which the nondual reality is there.[13]

In detail, three natures (trisvabhāva) are:[71][74][75][13]

1. Parikalpita-svabhāva (the "fully conceptualized" or "imagined" nature). This is the


"imaginary" or "constructed" nature, wherein things are incorrectly comprehended based on
conceptual construction, through the activity of language and through attachment and
erroneous discrimination which attributes intrinsic existence to things. According to the
Mahāyānasaṃgraha, it also refers to the appearance of things in terms of subject-object
dualism (literally "grasper" and "grasped"). The conceptualized nature is the world of
everyday unenlightened people, i.e. samsara. It is false and empty, and does not really exist
(Triṃśikā v. 20). According to Xuanzang's Cheng Weishi Lun, this nature is an "absence of
an existential nature by its very defining characteristic" (lakṣana-niḥsvabhāvatā). Because
these conceptualized natures and distinct characteristics (lakṣana) are wrongly imputed and
not truly real, "they are like mirages and blossoms in the sky."
2. Paratantra-svabhāva (literally, "other dependent"), which is the dependently originated
nature of dharmas, or the causal flow of phenomena which is erroneously confused into the
conceptualized nature. According to Williams, it is "the basis for the erroneous partition into
supposedly intrinsically existing subjects and objects which marks the conceptualized
nature." Jonathan Gold writes that it is "the causal process of the thing's fabrication, the
causal story that brings about the thing's apparent nature." This basis is considered to be an
ultimately existing (paramārtha) basis in classical Yogācāra (see Mahāyānasaṃgraha,
2:25).[76] However, as Xuanzang notes, this nature is also empty in that there is an "absence
of an existential nature in conditions that arise and perish" (utpatti-niḥsvabhāvatā). That is,
the events in this causal flow, while "seeming to have real existence of their own" are
actually like magical illusions since "they are said to only be hypothetical and not really exist
on their own." As Siderits writes "to the extent that we are thinking of it at all - even if only as
the non-dual flow of impressions-only - we are still conceptualizing it."
3. Pariniṣpanna-svabhāva (literally, "fully accomplished", "perfected", "consummated"): This
is the true nature of things, the experience of Suchness or Thatness (Tathātā) discovered in
meditation unaffected by conceptualization, causality, or duality. It is defined as "the
complete absence, in the dependent nature, of objects – that is, the objects of the
conceptualized nature" (see Mahāyānasaṃgraha, 2:4).[76] What this refers to is that empty
non-dual experience which has been stripped of the duality of the constructed nature through
yogic praxis. According to Williams, this is "what has to be known for enlightenment" and
Siderits defines it as "just pure seeing without any attempt at conceptualization or
interpretation. Now this is also empty, but only of itself as an interpretation. That is, this mode
of cognition is devoid of all concepts, and so is empty of being of the nature of the perfected.
About it nothing can be said or thought, it is just pure immediacy." According to Xuanzang,
this nature has the "absence of any existential nature of ultimate meaning" (paramārtha-
niḥsvabhāvatā) since it is "completely free from any clinging to entirely imagined
speculations about its identity or purpose. Because of this, it is conventionally said that it
does not exist. However, it is also not entirely without a real existence."

Emptiness
The central meaning of emptiness (śūnyatā) in Yogācāra is a twofold "absence of duality." The first element
of this is the unreality of any conceptual duality such as "physical" and "non-physical", "self" and "other".
To define something conceptually is to divide the world into what it is and what it is not, but the world is a
causal flux that does not accord with conceptual constructs.[13] The second element of this is a perceptual
duality between the sensorium and its objects, between what is "external" and "internal", between subject
(grāhaka, literally "grasper") and object (grāhya, "grasped").[77] This is also an unreal superimposition,
since there is really no such separation of inner and outer, but an interconnected causal stream of mentality
which is falsely divided up.[13]

An important difference between the Yogācāra conception of emptiness and the Madhyamaka conception is
that in classical Yogācāra, emptiness does exist (as a real absence) and so does consciousness (which is that
which is empty, the referent of emptiness), while Madhyamaka refuses to endorse such existential
statements. The Madhyāntavibhāga for example, states "the imagination of the nonexistent [abhūta-
parikalpa] exists. In it duality does not exist. Emptiness, however, exists in it," which indicates that even
though that which is dualistically imagined (subjects and objects), is unreal and empty, their basis does exist
(i.e. the dependently arisen conscious manifestation).[78][79]

The Yogācāra school also gave special significance to the Āgama sutra called Lesser Discourse on
Emptiness (parallel to the Pali Cūḷasuññatasutta (https://suttacentral.net/mn121/en/sujato?lang=en), MN
121) and relies on this sutra in its explanations of emptiness. According to Gadjin Nagao, this sutra affirms
that "emptiness includes both being and non-being. both negation and affirmation."[80][c]

Disagreement with Madhyamaka


Indian sources indicate that Yogācāra thinkers sometimes debated with the defenders of the Madhyamaka
tradition.[82] However, there is disagreement among contemporary Western and traditional Buddhist
scholars about the degree to which they were opposed, if at all.[83] The main difference between these
schools was related to issues of existence and the nature of emptiness. The Chinese pilgrim Yijing (635–
713) concisely summarized the differences thus: “For Yogācāra the real exists, but the conventional does not
exist; and [Yogācāra] takes the three natures as foundational. For Madhyamaka the real does not exist, but
the conventional does exist; and actually the two truths are primary".[84] Garfield and Westerhoff write that
"Yogācāra is both ontologically and epistemologically foundationalist; Madhyamaka is antifoundationalist
in both senses."[82] Another way to state this key difference is that Madhyamaka defends a "global
antirealism" while Yogācāra "restrict[s] the scope of their antirealism to the external and the
conventional".[82]

While Madhyamaka generally states that asserting the ultimate existence or non-existence of anything
(including emptiness) was inappropriate, Yogācāra treatises (like the Madhyāntavibhāga) often assert that
the dependent nature (paratantra-svabhāva) really exists and that emptiness is an actual absence that also
exists ultimately.[79] In a similar fashion, Asaṅga states "that of which it is empty does not truly exist; that
which is empty truly exists: emptiness makes sense in this way".[85] He also describes emptiness as "the
non-existence of the self, and the existence of the no-self."[78] Classical Yogācāras like Vasubandhu and
Sthiramati also affirm the reality of conscious appearance, i.e. that truly existent stream of dependent arisen
and constantly changing consciousness which projects false and illusory subjective minds and their
cognitive objects. It is this real flow of conscious transformation (vijñānapariṇāma) which is said to be
empty (of duality and conceptuality).[86] Against the radically anti-foundationalist interpretation of
Madhyamaka, the classic Yogācāra position is that there is something (the dependent nature which is mere-
consciousness) that "exists" (sat) independently of conceptual designation (prajñapti), and that it is this real
thing (vāstu) which is said to be empty of duality and yet is a basis for all dualistic conceptions.[87]

Furthermore, Yogācāra thinkers like Asaṅga and Vasubandhu critiqued those who "adhere to non-
existence" (nāstikas, vaināśkas, likely referring to certain Madhyamikas) because they saw them as straying
into metaphysical nihilism (abhāvānta, see Vimśatikā v. 10).[73][78] They held that there was really
something which could be said to "exist", that is, vijñapti, and that was what is described as being "empty"
in their system.[73] For Yogācāra, all conventional existence must be based on something which is real
(dravya).[88] Sthiramati argues that we cannot say that everything exists conventionally (saṁvṛtisat) or
nominally (prajñaptisat) and that nothing truly exists in an ultimate fashion (which would entail a global
conventionalism and nominalism without any metaphysical ground). For Sthiramati, this view is false
because "what would follow is non-existence even conventionally. That is because conventions are not
possible without something to depend upon (or, “without taking up something”—upādāna)."[89] Thus, for
Sthiramati, consciousness (vijñana) "since it is dependently arisen, exists as dravya (substance)."[89]

The Bodhisattvabhūmi likewise argues that it is only logical to speak of emptiness if there is something (i.e.
dharmatā, an ultimate nature) that is empty. The Bodhisattvabhūmi's Chapter on Reality (Tattvārthapaṭala)
states that emptiness is "wrongly grasped" by those who "do not accept that of which something is empty,
nor do they accept that which is empty".[90] This is because "emptiness holds good only as long as that of
which something is [said to be] empty does not exist, but on the other hand, that which is empty exists. If,
however, all [elements involved in this relation] were non-existent, in what respect, what would be empty,
[and] of what?" For the Bodhisattvabhūmi, the "right" way to understand emptiness is "one regards that
something is empty of that which does not exist in it and correctly comprehends that what remains there
does actually exist here".[90] That which "remains" and "actually exists" is the true reality, the thing itself
(vastumātra), the foundation (āśraya) which remains (avaśiṣṭa) after all conceptual constructs have been
removed.[91]

Yogācārins also criticized certain Madhyamaka accounts of conventional truth, that is, the view which says
that conventional truth is merely erroneous cognitive processes (designations, expressions, and linguistic
conventions) which project an inherent nature.[92] The Yogācārabhūmi's Viniścayasaṃgrahanī states that
either Madhyamakas see conventional reality as produced by linguistic expressions and also by causal
forces, or they see it as produced merely by linguistic expressions and convention. If the former, then
Madhyamikas must accept the reality of causal efficacy, which is a kind of existence (since things which are
causally produced can be said to exist in some way). If the latter, then without any basis for linguistic
expression and convention, it makes no sense to even use these terms (for Yogācāra these conventions must
have some kind of referential basis).[93]
Yogācārins further held that if all phenomena are equally conventional and unreal in the same way this
would lead to laxity in ethics and in following the path, in other words to moral relativism.[94] The basic
idea behind this critique is that if only convention exists (as Madhyamaka claims) and there are no truths
that are independent of convention and linguistic expression, there would be no epistemic foundations for
critiquing worldly (non-buddhist) conventions and affirming other conventions as closer to the truth (like
the conventions used by Buddhists to establish their ethics and their teachings).[94]

Madhyamaka thinkers like Bhaviveka, Candrakirti and Shantideva also critiqued Yogācāra views in their
works for what they saw as an improper reification (samāropa) of mind and for a nihilistic denial of
conventional truth. The work of Xuanzang (7th century) also contains evidence for this Indian debate.[95]

Two interpretations of the three natures


Various Buddhist studies scholars such as Alan Spongberg, Mario D'amato, Daniel McNamara, and
Matthew T. Kapstein have noted that there are two main interpretations of the three natures doctrine among
the various texts of the Yogacara corpus. The two models have been named the "pivot" model and
"progressive" model by these Western scholars.[96][97] The "pivot" model, found in texts like the Triṃśikā
and the Mahāyānasaṃgraha, presents the dependent nature as a kind of "ontological pivot" since it is the
basis for conceptual construction (the imagined nature) and for the perfected nature (which is nothing but
absence of the imagined nature in the dependent nature).[97] As such, the imagined nature is an incorrect
way of experiencing the dependent, while the perfected nature is the correct way.[96]

The "progressive model" meanwhile can be found in the Trisvabhāvanirdeśa and in the
Mahāyānasūtrālaṃkāra and its bhāṣya. In this model, it is the perfected nature which is the primary
element of the three natures schema. Here, the perfected nature is the pure basis of reality, while the other
two natures are both impaired by ignorance.[96][97][98] As the Trisvabhāvanirdeśa states: "The imputed and
the other-dependent are to be known as having defiled characteristics. The perfected is asserted to have the
characteristic of purity."[96] In this text, the dependent nature is seen as something which must be
abandoned since it has the "appearance of duality" (dvayākāra).[96] As such, in this "progressive" model,
the dependent nature is the basis for the imagined nature, but not the basis for the perfected nature.[96][97]
The perfected nature on the other hand is a fundamentally pure true reality (which nevertheless is covered
by adventitious defilements). As the Mahāyānasūtrālaṃkāra states:

Reality - which is always without duality, is the basis of error, and is entirely inexpressible -
does not have the nature of discursivity. It is to be known, abandoned, and purified. It should
properly be thought of as naturally immaculate, since it is purified from defilements, as are
space, gold, and water.[98]

Furthermore, according to the Trisvabhāvanirdeśa (TSN 17-20), the three natures are inseparable (abhinna)
and as such non-dual. This is a key difference between this model and the pivot model, where the
dependent nature is ultimately devoid of the imagined nature.[96][97]

Another difference between these sources is that in the Triṃśikā, the main model of liberation is a radical
transformation of the basis (āśrayaparāvṛtti). The Trisvabhāvanirdeśa meanwhile claims that liberation
occurs through knowledge of the three natures as they are (in their non-duality).[97] Some scholars, like
McNamara, argue that these two models are incompatible, ontologically and soteriologically.[96] Kapstein
thinks that it is possible that the Trisvabhāvanirdeśa is attempting to reconcile them.[97] These differences
have also led some scholars (Kapstein and Thomas Wood) to question the attribution of the
Trisvabhāvanirdeśa to Vasubandhu.[96][97]

Karma
An explanation of the Buddhist doctrine of karma (action) is central to Yogācāra, and the school sought to
explain important questions such as how moral actions can have effects on individuals long after that action
was done, that is, how karmic causality works across temporal distances. Previous Abhidharma schools like
the Sautrantika had developed theories of karma based on the notion of "seeds" (bījā) in the mind stream,
which are unseen karmic habits (good and bad) which remain until they meet with the necessary conditions
to manifest. Yogācāra adopts and expanded this theory.[1] Yogācāra then posited the "storehouse
consciousness" as the container of the seeds, as the storage place for karmic latencies and as a fertile matrix
of predispositions that bring karma to a state of fruition. In the Yogācāra system, all experience without
exception is said to result from karma or mental intention (cetana), either arising from one's own subliminal
seeds or from other minds.[99]

For Yogācāra, the seemingly external or dualistic world is merely a "by-product" (adhipati-phala) of karma.
The term vāsanā ("perfuming") is also used when explaining karma. Yogācārins were divided on the issue
of whether vāsāna and bija were essentially the same, whether the seeds were the effect of the perfuming, or
whether the perfuming simply affected the seeds.[100] The type, quantity, quality and strength of the seeds
determine where and how a sentient being will be reborn: one's race, sex, social status, proclivities, bodily
appearance and so forth. The conditioning of the mind resulting from karma is called saṃskāra.[101]
Vasubandhu's Treatise on Action (Karmasiddhiprakaraṇa), treats the subject of karma in detail from the
Yogācāra perspective.[102]

Meditation and awakening


As the name of the school suggests, meditation practice is central to the Yogācāra tradition. Yogācāra texts
prescribe various yogic practices such as mindfulness and the four investigations, out of which a
revolutionary and radically transformative understanding of the non-duality of self and other is said to arise.
This process is referred to as āśraya-parāvṛtti ("overturning the cognitive basis", or "revolution of the
basis"), which refers to "overturning the conceptual projections and imaginings which act as the base of our
cognitive actions."[1] This event is seen as the transformation of the basic mode of cognition into jñāna
(knowledge, direct knowing), which is seen as a non-dual knowledge that is non-conceptual (nirvikalpa),
i.e., "devoid of interpretive overlay".[1][103] Roger R. Jackson describes this as a "'fundamental
unconstructed awareness' (mūla-nirvikalpa-jñāna)".[104] When this knowledge arises, the eight
consciousnesses come to an end and are replaced by direct knowings. According to Lusthaus:

Overturning the Basis turns the five sense consciousnesses into immediate cognitions that
accomplish what needs to be done (kṛtyānuṣṭhāna-jñāna). The sixth consciousness becomes
immediate cognitive mastery (pratyavekṣaṇa-jñāna), in which the general and particular
characteristics of things are discerned just as they are. This discernment is considered
nonconceptual (nirvikalpa-jñāna). Manas becomes the immediate cognition of equality
(samatā-jñāna), equalizing self and other. When the Warehouse Consciousness finally ceases it
is replaced by the Great Mirror Cognition (Mahādarśa-jñāna) that sees and reflects things just
as they are, impartially, without exclusion, prejudice, anticipation, attachment, or distortion.
The grasper-grasped relation has ceased. ..."purified" cognitions all engage the world in
immediate and effective ways by removing the self-bias, prejudice, and obstructions that had
prevented one previously from perceiving beyond one's own narcissistic consciousness. When
consciousness ends, true knowledge begins. Since enlightened cognition is nonconceptual its
objects cannot be described.[1]

Five Categories of Beings


One of the more controversial Yogācāra teachings was the "five categories of beings", which was an
extension of the teachings on the seeds of the storehouse consciousness. This teacing states that sentient
beings have certain innate seeds that determine their capability of achieving a particular state of
enlightenment and no other. Thus, beings were placed into five categories:[105]

1. Beings whose innate seeds gave them the capacity to practice the bodhisattva path and
achieve full Buddhahood
2. Beings whose innate seeds gave them the capacity to achieve the state of a pratyekabuddha
(private Buddha)
3. Beings whose innate seeds gave them the capacity to achieve the state of an arhat
4. Beings whose innate seeds had an indeterminate nature, and could potentially be any of the
above
5. Beings whose innate seeds were incapable of achieving enlightenment ever because they
lacked any wholesome seeds
The fifth class of beings, the icchantika, were described in various Mahayana sutras as being incapable of
achieving enlightenment, unless in some cases through the aid of a Buddha or Bodhisattva. Nevertheless,
the notion was highly criticized by later Mahayanists who supported the universalist doctrine of ekayana.
This tension is important in East Asian Buddhist history and later East Asian Yogācārins attempted to
resolve the dispute by softening their stance on the five categories.[105][106]

Mental images: true vs false


An important debate about the reality of mental appearances within Yogācāra led to its later subdivision into
two systems of Alikākāravāda (Tib. rnam rdzun pa, False Aspectarians, also known as Nirākāravāda) and
Satyākāravāda (rnam bden pa, True Aspectarians, also known as Sākāravāda). They are also termed
"Aspectarians" (ākāra) and "Non-Aspectarians" (anākāra). The core issue is whether appearances or
“aspects” (rnam pa, ākāra) of objects in the mind are treated as true (bden pa, satya) or false (rdzun pa,
alika).[107] While this division did not exist in the works of the early Yogācāra philosophers, tendencies
similar to these views can be discerned in the works of Yogacara thinkers like Dharmapala (c. 530–561?)
and Sthiramati (c. 510–570?).[108][109][110]

According to Yaroslav Komarovski the distinction is as follows:

Although Yogācāras in general do not accept the existence of an external material world,
according to Satyākāravāda its appearances or “aspects” (rnam pa, ākāra) reflected in
consciousness have a real existence, because they are of one nature with the really existent
consciousness, their creator. According to Alikākāravāda, neither external phenomena nor their
appearances and/in the minds that reflect them really exist. What exists in reality is only
primordial mind (ye shes, jñāna), described as self-cognition (rang rig, svasamvedana/
svasamvitti) or individually self-cognizing primordial mind (so so(r) rang gis rig pa’i ye
shes).[111]

Davey K. Tomlinson describes the difference (with reference to later Yogacara scholars from Vikramashila)
as follows:

On one hand is the Nirākāravāda, typified by Ratnākaraśānti (ca. 970–1045); on the other, the
Sākāravāda, articulated by his colleague and critic Jñānaśrīmitra (ca. 980–1040). The
Nirākāravādin argues that all appearances do not really exist. They are ersatz or false (alīka).
Ephemeral forms appear to us but are the erroneous construction of ignorance, which
fundamentally characterizes our existence as suffering beings in saṃsāra. In the ultimately real
experience of an awakened buddha, no appearances show up at all. Pure experience, unstained
by false appearance (which is nirākāra, “without appearance”), is possible. The Sākāravādin,
on the other hand, defends the view that all conscious experience is necessarily the experience
of a manifest appearance (consciousness is sākāra, or constitutively “has appearance”).
Manifest appearances, properly understood, are really real. A buddha's experience has
appearances, and there is nothing about this fact that makes a buddha's experience
mistaken.[112]

Practice
A key early source for the yogic practices of Indian Yogācāra is the
encyclopedic Yogācārabhūmi-Śāstra (YBh, Treatise on the
Foundation for Yoga Practitioners). The YBh presents a structured
exposition of the Mahāyāna Buddhist path of yoga (here referring
to spiritual practice in general) from a Yogācāra perspective and
relies in both Āgama/Nikāya texts and Mahāyāna sūtras while also
being influenced by Vaibhāṣika Abhidharma.[113] According to
some scholars, this text can be traced to communities of yogācāras,
which initially referred not to a philosophical school, but to groups
of meditation specialists whose main focus was Buddhist yoga.[114]
Other Yogācāra texts which also discuss meditation and spiritual
practice (and show some relationship with the YBh) include the
Saṃdhinirmocanasūtra, the Madhyāntavibhāga,
Mahāyānasūtrālaṃkāra, Dharmadharmatāvibhāga and Asanga's
Mahāyānasaṃgraha.[115]

The YBh discusses various topics relevant to the bodhisattva Maitreya meditating, 2nd century CE,
practice, including: the eight different forms of dhyāna (meditative Loriyan Tangai, Indian Museum,
absorptions), the three samādhis, different types of liberation Kolkata
(vimokṣa), meditative attainments (samāpatti) such as
nirodhasamāpatti, the five hindrances (nivaraṇa), the various types
of foci (ālambana) or 'images' (nimitta) used in meditation, the various types contemplative antidotes
(pratipakṣa) against the afflictions (like contemplating death, unattractiveness, impermanence, and
suffering), the practice of śamatha through "the nine aspects of resting the mind" (navākārā cittasthitiḥ),
the practice of insight (vipaśyanā), mindfulness of breathing (ānāpānasmṛti), how to understand the four
noble truths, the thirty-seven factors of Awakening (saptatriṃśad bodhipakṣyā dharmāḥ), the four
immeasurables (apramāṇa), and how to practice the six perfections (pāramitā).[116]

Bodhisattva path
Yogācāra sources like the Abhidharmasamuccaya, the Chéng Wéishì Lùn and the commentaries to the
Mahāyānasaṃgraha and the Mahāyānasūtrālamkāra also contain various descriptions of the main stages
of the bodhisattva path.[117][118] These Yogācāra sources integrate the Mahayana teaching of the ten
bodhisattva stages (bhūmis) with the earlier Abhidharma outline of the path called the "five paths"
(pañcamārga), to produce a Mahayanist version of "five stages" (pañcāvasthā).[118][119] In classic
Yogācāra, this bodhisattva path is said to last for three incaculable eons (asaṃkhyeya kalpas), i.e. millions
upon millions of years.[120][119]

The five paths or stages are outlined in Yogācāra sources as follows:[118][117][119][121]

1. Path of accumulation (sambhāra-mārga, 資糧位 ), in which a bodhisattva gives rise to


bodhicitta, and works on the two accumulations of merit (puṇya) and wisdom (jñana). These
are linked with the practice of the six perfections. In this first stage of the path, one attains
merit by doing good deeds like giving (dana) and one also accumulates wisdom by listening
to the Mahayana teachings many times, contemplating them and meditating on them. One
also associates with good spiritual friends. According to the Mahāyānasaṃgraha, at this
stage the bodhisattva focuses on accumulating wholesome roots (kuśalamūla) and on
permeating one's mind with learning (bahuśrutaprabhāvita).[122] This leads to the
accumulation of great faith and conviction in the Mahayana and in the principle of
consciousness-only.[123]
2. Path of engagement (prayoga-mārga, 加行位 ), also termed "the stage of the practice of faith
and convinction" (adhimukticaryābhūmi). Here, a bodhisattva practices morality, meditation,
and wisdom in order to quell the manifest activities of the two types of obscurations:
emotionally afflictive and cognitive. While their active elements are quelled, they remain as
seeds in the foundation consciousness. Furthermore, one also cultivates the "factors
conducive to penetration", which consists of the "four investigations" and the "four correct
cognitions". These are ways of contemplating the truth of mind-only and lead to the
"entrance into the principle of cognizance-only" (vijñaptimātrapraveśa) as well as to "the
certainty as to the non-existence of the object" (arthābhāvaniścaya).[124] At this stage one
relies on the fourth dhyana and also attains various samadhis (meditative concentrations).
The final stage of this path which is just before the path of seeing is called "the elimination of
the ideation of cognizance-only" (vijñaptimātrasaṃjñāvibhāvana). As the
Mahāyānasaṃgraha states, at this point, the realization of the absolute nature
(pariniṣpannasvabhāvabuddhi) eliminates the very "perception of mind-only"
(vijñaptimātratābuddhi).[125] The resulting wisdom is described by Asanga as "the non-
conceptual cognition (nirvikalpakajñāna) in which the object (ālambana) and the subject
(ālambaka) are completely identical (samasama)."[126]
3. Path of seeing (darśana-mārga, 見道位), at this stage (which lasts for only a few moments), a
bodhisattva attains an untainted knowledge (Skt. anāsrava-jñāna, 無漏智) into emptiness,
the non-duality of self and other, and consciousness-only. The Cheng wei shi lun describes
this knowledge which realises Suchness (tathatā) as being "entirely undifferentiated
(samasama) from Suchness since both are free from the characteristics (lakṣaṇa) of subject
(grāhaka) and object (grāhya)."[127] This stage is equated with the first bodhisattva stage, the
stage of joy. At this point, one is a proper noble (arya) bodhisattva instead of just a beginner.
4. Path of cultivation (bhāvanā-mārga, 修道位 ), at this stage, a bodhisattva continues to train
themselves in two main cognitions in order to fully eliminate all the seeds of the two types of
obscurations. They train in the non-conceptual gnosis (nirvikalpakajñāna) of ultimate reality,
and the wordly or subsequent knowledge (pṛṣṭhtalabdhajñāna) which knows conventional
reality as illusory, and is yet able to conceptually understand it and use it for guiding sentient
beings according to their needs. Part of this path requires effort, as the bodhisattva is said to
"repeatedly (abhīkṣṇam) cultivate the non-conceptual cognition" (Cheng wei shi lun).
However, after a certain point one advances effortlessly. This path corresponds to the
second to ninth stages of the bodhisattva path. The Mahāyānasaṃgraha states that at this
stage the yogin "dwells in intense cultivation for hundreds of thousands of koṭis of niyutas
[an astronomical number] of aeons and consequently attains the transformation of the basis
(āśrayaparavṛtti)".[128]
5. Path of fulfillment (niṣṭhā-mārga), also known as the path of no more learning (aśaikṣa-
mārga, 無學位 ) in other sources. This is equivalent to complete Buddhahood. It also entails
attaining the three bodies (trikāya) of the Buddha (a doctrine which was also invented by the
Yogācāra school).

Bodhisattva practice
The Bodhisattvabhūmi discusses the Yogācāra school's specifically Mahāyāna forms of practice which are
tailored to bodhisattvas.[129] The aim of the bodhisattva's practice in the Bodhisattvabhūmi is the wisdom
(prajñā) which realizes of the inexpressible Ultimate Reality (tathata) or the 'thing-in-itself (vastumatra),
which is essenceless and beyond the duality (advaya) of existence (bhāva) and non-existence
(abhāva).[130][131]

The Bodhisattvabhūmi outlines several practices of bodhisattvas, including the six perfections (pāramitā),
the thirty-seven factors of Awakening, and the four immeasurables. Two key practices which are unique to
bodhisattvas in this text are the four investigations and the four correct cognitions or "the four kinds of
understanding in accordance with true reality".[132][133] These two sets of four practices and cognitions are
also taught in the Abhidharmasamuccaya and its commentaries.[133]

The four investigations and four correct cognitions


The four investigations (catasraḥ paryeṣaṇāḥ) and the corresponding four correct cognitions (catvāri
yathābhūtaparijñānāni) are a set of original contemplations found in Yogācāra works. These were seen as
very important contemplative methods by the authors of the Bodhisattvabhūmi. They were considered to
lead to awakening, and were linked with the thirty-seven factors leading to Awakening.[134]

The four investigations and the corresponding four correct cognitions (which are said to arise out of the
investiations) are:[135][136]

1. The investigation of the names [of things] (nāmaparyeṣaṇā), leads to correct cognition
resulting from the investigation of names just for what they are, which is "just names"
(nāmamātra), i.e. arbitrary linguistic signs.
2. The investigation of things (vastuparyeṣaṇā), leads to correct cognition resulting from the
investigation of things. One sees things just for what they are, namely a mere presence or a
thing-in-itself (vastumātra). One understands that this is apart from all labels and is
inexpressible (nirabhilāpya).
3. The investigation of verbal designations suggesting and portraying an intrinsic nature
(svabhāva-prajñapti-paryeṣaṇā), leads to correct cognition resulting from the investigation of
such designations. One sees the designations just for what they are, namely as mere
designations (prajñaptimātratā). Thus, one sees the idea of intrinsic nature to be illusory like
a hallucination or a dream.
4. The investigation of verbal designations expressing individuation and differences
(viśeṣaprajñaptiparyeṣaṇā), leads to correct cognition resulting from the investigation of
such designations. One sees the designations just for what they are, namely as mere
designations. For example, a thing may be designated as existing or non-existing, but such
designations do not apply to true reality or the thing-in-itself.
The practice which leads to the realization of the true nature of things is based on the elimination of all
conceptual proliferations (prapañca) and ideations (saṃjñā) that one superimposes on true reality.[137] The
YBh states that the yogin must "repeatedly remove any ideation conducive to the proliferation directed at all
phenomena and should consistently dwell on the thing-in-itself by a non-conceptualizing mental state which
is focused on grasping only the object perceived without any characteristics".[138]

Four prayogas
Various Yogācāra sources provide a four step process of realization leading to the path of seeing, these four
are the four yogic practices (prayogas):[139]

Yogic practice of observation (upalambha-prayoga) - Outer objects are observed to be


nothing but mind.
Yogic practice of non-observation (anupalambha-prayoga) - Outer objects are not observed
as such
Yogic practice of observation and non-observation (upalambhānupalambha-prayoga) - Outer
objects being unobservable, a mind cognizing them is not observed either
Yogic practice of double non-observation (nopalambhopalambha-prayoga) - Not observing
both, nonduality is observed
This process is conceisely explained in the Trisvabhāvanirdeśa which says "through the observation of it
being merely mind, a knowable object is not observed. Through not observing a knowable object, mind is
not observed [either]. Through not observing both, the dharmadhātu is observed."[140] Thus, the goal of
meditation is a totally unified mind that goes beyond all concepts and language to directly know the
undifferentiated "uniformity of phenomena" (dharmasamatāḥ) and the thing-in-itself, the supreme
reality.[141] The elimination of all concepts applies even to the very idea of mind only or "mere-cognizance"
itself.[142] As the Dharmadharmatāvibhāga states: "through [referents] being observed in this way, they are
observed as mere cognizance. By virtue of observing them as mere cognizance, Referents are not observed,
and through not observing referents, mere cognizance is not observed [either]."[143] This elimination of
concepts and ideas is the basic framework applied by the bodhisattva to all meditative practices, including
the different mindfulness meditations.[137] The three samādhis (meditative absorptions) are likewise
adapted into this new framework. These three are the emptiness (śūnyatā), wishlessness (apraṇihita), and
imagelessness (ānimitta) samādhis.[144]

Meditation
As the "school of yoga practitioners", meditative practice is discussed in various Yogācāra sources. The
sixth chapter (the Maitreya Chapter) of the Saṃdhinirmocanasūtra focuses entirely on meditation. It
extensively discusses the meditative aspects of ‘calm’ (śamatha) and ‘insight’ (vipaśyanā) from unique
perspectives.[145] Success in both of these is based on pure ethics and on pure views based on listening and
reflecting (viśuddhaṃ śrutamayacintāmayadarśanam).[145] Insight is paired with "objects consisting in
images accompanied by reflection" (savikalpaṃ pratibimbaṃ) while tranquility is seen as based on objects
consisting in images unaccompanied by reflection (nirvikalpaṃ pratibimbaṃ).[145] Thus, insight
meditation is based on the uninterrupted contemplation of mental images, while calming meditation is
simply focusing on "the continuous flow of mind with uninterrupted attention".[146] The
Saṃdhinirmocana also states that the teachings themselves are an important object of meditative
contemplation. This includes the Yogācāra teaching of consciousness-only, the teachings on the twofold
emptiness (of self and phenomena), and the schematic analysis of the subject and its objects of
consciousness.[147]

While insight meditation is initially based on conceptual reflection, these are gradually abandoned at later
stages until the yogin lets go of all concepts, teachings, and mental images.[147] Furthermore, at the higher
stages of meditation, the calm and insight meditations must ultimately be blended or yoked together
(yuganaddha) in a single state of one-pointedness of mind (cittaikāgratā).[146] This unified state is described
as that state in which the yogin: "realises that these images (pratibimba) which are the domain of
concentration (samādhigocara) are nothing but representation (vijñaptimātra), and having realised this, he
contemplates (manasikaroti) Suchness (tathatā)."[146]

History
Yogācāra, along with Madhyamaka (Middle Way), is one of the two principal philosophical schools of
Indian Mahāyāna Buddhism,[148] though the related movement of Tathāgatagarbha-thought was also
influential.[149][note 1]

Origin and early Yogācāra


The term "yogācāra" (yoga practitioner) was originally used to refer to the Buddhist meditation adepts of
the first centuries of the common era which were associated with the Sarvāstivāda and Sautrāntika traditions
in north India (some of their key centers included Gandhara, Kashmir and Mathura). Modern scholars like
Florin Delenau have suggested that some yogis in this north Indian Buddhist milieu gradually adopted
Mahāyāna ideas, eventually developing into a separate movement (a process which was complete by the
5th century).[150][5][6] According to Delenau, the Chinese Dhyana Sutras indicate just such a gradual
adoption of Mahāyāna elements.[5]

One of the earliest texts of the Mahāyāna Yogācāra tradition proper is the Saṃdhinirmocana Sūtra
(Unraveling the Profound Intent) which might be as early as the first or second century CE.[151] It includes
new theories such as the basis-consciousness (ālaya-vijñāna), the doctrine of vijñapti-mātra and the "three
natures" (trisvabhāva). However, these theories were not completely new, as they have predecessors in
older theories held by previous Buddhist schools, such as the Sautrāntika theory of seeds (bīja) and the
Sthavira theory of the bhavanga.[152] Philosophically speaking, Richard King notes that Sautrāntikas
defended a kind of representationalism, in which the mind only perceives an image (akara) or representation
(vijñapti) of an external object (never the object itself). Mahayana Yogācāras adopted a similar model but
removed the need for any external object which acts as a cause for the image.[153] As the doctrinal
trailblazer of the Yogācāra, the Saṃdhinirmocana also introduced
the paradigm of the Three Turnings of the Wheel of Dharma, with
its own teachings being placed into the final and definitive teaching
(which supersedes those of the Prajñaparamita sutras).[148]

The early layers of the massive Yogācārabhūmi-śāstra (Treatise on


the Stages of the Yogācāras) also contains very ancient Yogācāra
material which is earlier than the Saṃdhinirmocana.[154] However,
in its current form it is a "conglomeration of heterogenous
materials" (Schmithausen) which was finally compiled (perhaps by
Asanga) after the Saṃdhinirmocana (hence, later layers quote the
sutra directly). Modern scholars consider the Yogācārabhūmi to
contain the work of several authors (mainly of a Mūlasarvāstivāda
milieu), though it has traditionally been attributed in full to the
bodhisattva Maitreya or to Asanga.[155][156] It is influenced by The Kushan Empire ruled much of
Sarvāstivāda Abhidharma and Sautrāntika traditions, who also had north India during the early period of
similar texts called by the name "Yogācārabhūmi", such as the the Yogācāra school.
Yogācārabhūmi of Saṅgharakṣa.[157]

Classical Yogācāra - Asaṅga and Vasubandhu


Yogācāra's systematic exposition owes much to the Gandharan
Buddhist brothers Asaṅga (4th c. CE) and Vasubandhu (c. 4th - 5th
CE). Little is known of these figures, but traditional accounts (in
The bodhisattva Maitreya and
authors like Xuanzang) state that Asaṅga received Yogācāra disciples, a central figure in
teachings from the bodhisattva and future Buddha, Yogacara origin myth. Gandhara, 3rd
Maitreya.[158][159] However, there are various discrepancies century CE.
between the Chinese and Tibetan traditions concerning these so
called "five works of Maitreya".[160]

Modern scholars argue that the various works


traditionally attributed to Maitreya are actually by
other authors. According to Mario D'amato, the
Mahāyānasūtrālamkāra and the
Madhyāntavibhāga are part of a second phase of
Yogācāra scholarship which took place after the
completion of the Bodhisattvabhumi, but before
the composition of Asanga's Mahāyānasaṃgraha
(which quotes the Mahāyānasūtrālamkāra as an
authoritative text).[161] Regarding the
Abhisamayalankara and the Ratnagotravibhaga,
modern scholars generally see these as the works Asaṅga (left) and Vasubandhu statues at Kofuku-ji
of different authors.[162][163]

Asaṅga went on to write many of the key Yogācāra treatises such as the Mahāyānasaṃgraha and the
Abhidharma-samuccaya.[160] Asaṅga also went on to convert his brother Vasubandhu to Yogācāra.
Vasubandhu was a top scholar of Vaibhāṣika and Sautrāntika Abhidharma thought, and the
Abhidharmakośakārikā is his main work which discusses the doctrines of these traditions.[164] Vasubandhu
also went on to write important Yogācāra works like the Twenty Verses and the Thirty Verses on
Consciousness-Only.

The middle period and the epistemological turn


The Yogācāra school held a prominent position in Indian Buddhism for centuries after the time of the two
brothers. According to Lusthaus and Delenau, after Asaṅga and Vasubandhu, two distinct "wings" of the
school developed during the "Middle Period" of Yogācāra, the epistemological school and the scholastic
school. Another important third movement developed a synthesis of Yogācāra with buddha-nature
thought.[1][165]

Thus, the three main branches of the Yogācāra movement which developed during the so called middle
period are:[1][165]

1. A logico-epistemic tradition (pramāṇavāda) focusing on issues of epistemology (Sanskrit:


pramāṇa) and logic (hetuvidyā), exemplified by such thinkers as Dignāga, Dharmakīrti,
Dharmottara, Devendrabuddhi, Prajñakaragupta, Jinendrabuddhi, Śākyabuddhi
2. A scholastic and exegetical tradition which refined and elaborated Yogācāra Abhidharma
and wrote various commentaries, exemplified by such thinkers as Gunamati, Asvabhāva,
Sthiramati, Jinaputra, Dharmapāla, Śīlabhadra, Xuanzang, and Vinītadeva (710-770).
3. The Yogācāra-tathāgatagarbha synthesis, found in the Laṅkāvatāra Sūtra, and Ghanavyūha
sūtra, two treatises attributed to an author named Sāramati: the Ratnagotravibhāga, and
Dharmadhātvaviśeṣaśāstra (Dasheng fajie wuchabie lun 大乘法界無差別論 ), as well as in
the works of Paramārtha (499-569 CE), including his translations: Buddhagotraśāstra (Fó
xìng lùn, 佛性論 ), and Anuttarâśrayasūtra.[166]
These branches of Yogācāra thought were not mutually exclusive however, for example, Vinītadeva wrote
pramāṇa works as well as commentaries on the works of Vasubandhu. Aside from these, there were also
Yogācāra authors writing commentaries on the Prajñaparamita sutras, including the unknown author of the
Abhisamayālaṅkāra (AA), Arya Vimuktisena (6th century) who commented on the AA, and Daṃṣṭrāsena
(author of the Bṛhaṭṭīkā).

The doctrines of the exegetical tradition sometimes came under attack by other Buddhists, especially the
notion of ālaya-vijñāna, which was seen as close to the Hindu ideas of ātman and prakṛti. It was perhaps
due to this that the logical tradition shifted over time to using the term citta-santāna instead, since it was
easier to defend a "stream" (santāna) of thoughts as a doctrine that did not contradict not-self. By the end of
the eighth century, the scholastic tradition had mostly become eclipsed by the pramāṇa tradition as well as
by a new hybrid school that "combined basic Yogācāra doctrines with Tathāgatagarbha thought."[1]

The influential Pramāṇavāda tradition led by Dignāga and Dharmakīrti defined the main epistemological
method for Indian Buddhism. Modern scholars see this school as having ushered in an "epistemological
turn" for all Indian philosophy.[167] The pramāṇa tradition continued to thrive in Magadha (especially at
Nalanda) as well as in Kashmir well into the 11th century. One of the most important late figures of this
tradition was Śaṅkaranandana (fl. c. 9th or 10th century), "the second Dharmakīrti".[168]

Yogācāra-tathāgatagarbha synthesis
According to Lusthaus, the synthetic Yogācāra-tathāgatagarbha
school accepted the definition of tathāgatagarbha (the buddha-
womb, buddha-source, or "buddha-within") as "permanent,
pleasurable, self, and pure" (nitya, sukha, ātman, śuddha) which is
found in various tathāgatagarbha sutras.[1] This hybrid school
eventually went on to link the tathāgatagarbha with the ālaya-
vijñāna doctrine. Some key sources of this tendency are the Panorama of the site of Vikramaśīla
Laṅkāvatāra Sūtra, Ratnagotravibhāga (Uttaratantra), and in university (Bhagalpur district, Bihar).
China the Awakening of Faith.[1] Vikramaśīla was an important center
for late Indian Yogacara scholars,
The synthesis of Yogācāra and Tathāgatagarbha thought became including the great panditas like
extremely influential in both East Asia and Tibet. During the sixth Jñānaśrīmitra and Ratnākaraśānti.
and seventh centuries, various forms of competing Yogācāra
systems were popular in Chinese Buddhism. The translator
Bodhiruci (6th century CE) for example, took a more "classical" approach while Ratnamati was attracted to
Tathāgatagarbha thought and sought to translate texts like the Dasabhumika commentary accordingly. Their
disagreement on this issue led to the end of their collaboration as co-translators.[169] The translator
Paramārtha is another example of a hybrid thinker. He promoted the theory of a "stainless consciousness"
(amala-vijñāna, a pure wisdom within all beings, i.e. the tathāgatagarbha), which is revealed once the
ālaya-vijñāna is purified.[170]

According to Lusthaus, Xuanzang's travels to India and his translation work was an attempt to return to a
more "orthodox" and "authentic" Indian Yogācāra, and thus put to rest the debates and confusions in the
Chinese Yogācāra of his time. The Cheng Weishi Lun returns to the use of the theory of seeds instead of the
tathāgatagarbha to explain how some beings can reach Buddhahood.[171] However, by the eighth century,
the Yogācāra-tathāgatagarbha synthesis became the dominant interpretation of Yogācāra in East Asian
Buddhism.[1] Later Chinese thinkers like Fa-Tsang would thus criticize Xuanzang for failing to teach the
tathāgatagarbha.[171]

Karl Brunnhölzl notes that this syncretic tendency also existed in Indian Yogācāra scholasticism, but that it
only became widespread during the later tantric era (when Vajrayana became prominent) with the work of
thinkers like Jñānaśrīmitra, Ratnākaraśānti, and Maitripa.[172] Kashmir also became an important center for
this tradition, as can be seen in the works of Kashmiri Yogacarins Sajjana and Mahājana.[173]

Yogācāra and Madhyamaka


Yogācāra and Madhyamaka philosophers demonstrated two opposing tendencies throughout the history of
Buddhist philosophy in India, an antagonistic stance which saw both systems as rival and incompatible
views and another inclusive tendency which worked towards harmonizing their views.[174] Some authors
like the Madhyamikas Bhaviveka, Candrakīrti, and Śāntideva, and the Yogācāras Asanga, Dharmapala,
Sthiramati criticized the philosophical theories of the other tradition. While Indian Yogācāras criticized
certain interpretations of Madhyamaka (which they term “those who misunderstand emptiness”), they never
criticize the founders of Madhyamaka themselves (Nāgārjuna and Āryadeva), and saw their work as
implicitly in agreement with Yogācāra. This inclusivism saw Nāgārjuna's teachings as needing further
expansion and explication (since it was part of the "second turning" of the wheel of Dharma). Thus,
Yogācāra thinkers affirmed the importance Nāgārjuna's work and some even wrote commentaries on
Nāgārjuna's Mūlamadhyamakakārika as a way to draw out the implicit meaning of Madhyamaka and show
it was compatible with Yogācāra. These include Asanga's Treatise on Comforming to the Middle Way (Shun
順中論
zhonglun ) and Sthiramati's Mahayana Middle Way Commentary (Dasheng zhongguanshi lun 大乘
中觀釋論 T.30.1567).[175] Similarly, Vasubandhu and Dharmapāla both wrote commentaries on
Āryadeva's Catuḥśātaka (Four Hundred Verses).[176]

The harmonizing tendency can be seen in the work of philosophers like Kambala (5-6th century, author of
the Ālokamālā), Jñānagarbha (8th century), his student Śāntarakṣita (8th century) and Ratnākaraśānti (c.
1000).[174] Śāntarakṣita (8th century), whose view was later called "Yogācāra-Svatantrika-Madhyamaka"
by the Tibetan tradition, saw the Mādhyamika position as ultimately true and at the same time saw the
Yogācāra view as a useful way to relate to conventional truth (which leads one to the ultimate).[177]
Ratnākaraśānti on the other hand saw Nagarjuna as agreeing with the intent of Yogācāra texts, while
criticizing the interpretations of later Madhyamikas like Bhaviveka. Later Tibetan Buddhist thinkers like
Shakya Chokden would also work to show the compatibility of the alikākāravāda sub-school with
Madhyamaka, arguing that it is in fact a form of Madhyamaka.[178] Likewise, the Seventh Karmapa
Chödrak Gyamtso has a similar view which holds that the "profound important points and intents" of the
two systems are one.[179] Ju Mipham is also another Tibetan philosopher whose project is aimed as
showing the harmony between Yogacara and Madhyamaka, arguing that there is only a very subtle
difference between them, being a subtle clinging by Yogacaras to the existence of an "inexpressible,
naturally luminous cognition" (rig pa rang bzhin gyis ’od gsal ba).[180]

Yogācāra in East Asia


Translations of Indian Yogācāra texts were first introduced to China
in the early 5th century CE.[181] Among these was Guṇabhadra's
translation of the Laṅkāvatāra Sūtra in four fascicles, which would
also become important in the early history of Chan Buddhism.
Influential 5th century figures include the translators Bodhiruci,
Ratnamati, and Paramārtha.[182] Their followers founded the Dilun
(Daśabhūmikā Commentary) and Shelun (Mahāyānasaṃgraha)
schools, both of which included Yogācāra and tathāgatagarbha
elements.[183] Modern scholars also hold that the Awakening of
Faith, a very influential work in East Asian Buddhism, was written
by a member of the Dilun tradition.[184]

Xuanzang (fl. c. 602 – 664) is famous for having made a dangerous


journey to India in order to study Buddhism, obtain more indic
Yogācāra sources.[185][95] Xuanzang spent over ten years in India Statue of a traveling Xuanzang at
traveling and studying under various Buddhist masters and drew on Longmen Grottoes, Luoyang
a variety of Indian sources in his studies. [185][95] [186] Upon his
return to China, Xuanzang brought with him 657 Buddhist texts,
including the Yogācārabhūmi and began the work of translating them.[185][187] Xuanzang composed the
Cheng Weishi Lun (Discourse on the Establishment of Consciousness Only) which drew on many Indian
sources and commentaries and became a central work of East Asian Yogācāra.[188]

Xuanzang's student Kuiji continued this tradition, writing several important commentaries. However,
another student of Xuanzang, the Korean monk Wŏnch’ŭk, defended some of the doctrines of the Shelun
school of Paramārtha, for which he was criticized by the followers of Kuiji. Wŏnch’ŭk's teachings were
influential on the Yogācāra (Beopsang) of Silla Korea. Both of
these competing Yogācāra sub-sects were then imported to Japan
where they became the two sub-sects (the northern and southern
temple lineages) of the Hossō school.[189] Xuanzang's school later
came under criticism from later Chinese masters like Fazang and it
became less influential as the fortunes of other native Chinese
schools rose. Nevertheless, Yogācāra studies continued to be
important at different times throughout Chinese history, including
during the modern revival of Yogācāra in the 20th century.[190]

Yogācāra in Tibet
Yogācāra is studied in all schools of Tibetan Buddhism, though it
receives different emphasis in each of these. Yogācāra thought is an
Kuījī (632–682), a student of
integral part of the history of Tibetan Buddhism. It was first
Xuanzang
transmitted to Tibet by figures like Śāntarakṣita, Kamalaśīla and
Atiśa.[191]

The Tibetan Nyingma school and its Dzogchen teachings draw on


both Madhyamaka and Yogācāra-Tathāgatagarbha thought.[1][192]
Similarly, Kagyu school figures like the Third Karmapa also rely on
the Madhyamaka and Yogācāra-Tathāgatagarbha systems in their
presentation of the ultimate view (termed Mahamudra in
Kagyu).[193] The Jonang school also developed its own synthetic
philosophy which they termed shentong ("other-emptiness" Wylie:
gzhan-stong), which also included elements from Yogācāra,
Madhyamaka and Tathāgatagarbha.[194] In contrast, the Gelug and
Sakya schools generally see Yogācāra as a lesser view than the
Madhyamaka philosophy of Candrakirti, which is seen as the
definitive view in these traditions.[195]

Today, Yogācāra topics remain important in Tibetan Buddhism and


Yogācāra texts are widely studied. There are various debates and Rangjung Dorje, 3rd Karmapa Lama
discussions among the Tibetan Buddhist schools regarding key (1284–1339)
Yogācāra ideas, like svasaṃvedana (reflexive awareness) and the
foundational consciousness. Furthermore, the debates between the
other-emptiness and self-emptiness views are also similar in some ways to the historical debates between
Yogācāra-Tathāgatagarbha and Madhyamaka, though the specific viewpoints have evolved further and
changed in complex ways.[196] Modern thinkers continue to discuss Yogācāra issues, and attempt to
synthesize it with Madhyamaka. For example, Ju Mipham, the 19th-century Rimé commentator, wrote a
commentary on Śāntarakṣita's synthesis arguing that the ultimate intent of Madhyamaka and Yogācāra is the
same.[177]

Influence
Virtually all contemporary schools of Mahāyāna Buddhism are influenced by Yogācāra to some extent. This
includes modern East Asian Buddhist traditions (like Zen and Pure Land) and Tibetan Buddhism.[197] Zen
was heavily influenced by Yogācāra sources, especially the Laṅkāvatāra Sūtra.[197] In Tibetan Buddhism,
Yogācāra sources are still widely studied and several are part of the monastic education curriculum in
various traditions.[198] Some influential Yogācāra texts in Tibetan Buddhism include: Asanga's
Abhidharma-samuccaya, and the "Five Treatises of Maitreya" including the Mahayanasutralankara, and
the Ratnagotravibhāga.[198]

Hindu philosophers such as Vācaspati Miśra, Utpaladeva, Abhinavagupta, and Śrīharṣa were also
influenced by Yogacara ideas and responded to their theories in their own works.[199][200]

Textual corpus

Sūtras
The Saṃdhinirmocana Sūtra (Sūtra of the Explanation of the
Profound Secrets; 2nd century CE), is a key early Yogācāra sutra
which is considered to be the foundational sutra for the Yogācāra
tradition.[201] There are two Indian commentaries to this, one by
Asanga and one by Jñanagarbha.[202] The Avataṃsaka Sūtra
(which includes the Daśabhūmikasūtra) also contains numerous A wall painting depicting Xuanzang's
teachings on mind-only and is very influential for East Asian travels and his translation work,
Xuanzang Memorial Hall, modern
Buddhism.[203] Vasubandhu's Commentary on the
[204][205] Nalanda
Daśabhūmikasūtra is an important commentary to this.
Another text, the Mahāyānābhidharmasūtra is often quoted in
Yogācāra works and is assumed to also be an early Yogācāra sutra.[206]

The Laṅkāvatāra Sūtra also later assumed considerable importance in East Asia, and portions of this text
were considered by Étienne Lamotte as being contemporaneous with the Saṃdhinirmocana.[207][208] This
text equates the Yogācāra theory of ālayavijñāna with the tathāgatagarbha (buddha-nature) and thus seems
to be part of the tradition which sought to merge Yogācāra with tathāgatagarbha thought.[209] Another
sutra which contains similar themes to the Laṅkāvatāra is the Ghanavyūha Sūtra.[210][211]

All these five sutras are listed by Kuiji as key sutras for the Yogācāra school in his Commentary on the
Cheng weishi lun ( 成唯識 論述記 ; Taishō no. 1830).[212][213] Another lesser known sutra which was
important in East Asian Yogācāra is the Buddha Land Sutra (Buddhabhūmi-sūtra; Taishō vol. 16, no. 680)
which along with its commentary (Buddhabhūmyupadeśa), teaches that the pure land is not a physical
place, but a symbol for wisdom.[214]

There are also various Indian, Chinese and Tibetan commentaries to these various Mahayana sutras.
Furthermore, the Prajñaparamita sutras are also important sources in Yogācāra, even though most do not
cover specifically "Yogācāra" doctrines. This is shown by the fact that various Yogācāra commentaries were
written on Prajñaparamita sutras, including commentaries by Asanga (Vajracchedikākāvyākhyā),
Vasubandhu, Dignāga, Daṃṣṭrasena (Bṛhaṭṭīkā), Ratnākaraśānti (various), and the
Abhisamayālaṅkāra.[215][216]

Treatises
Yogācāra authors wrote numerous scholastic and philosophical treatises
(śāstra) and commentaries (ṭīkā, bhāṣya, vyākhyāna, etc). The following is
a list in historical order and only includes specifically Yogācāra-
Vijñānavāda figures and works:[217][218]

Yogācārabhūmi-śāstra, the earliest Yogācāra treatise, a


massive encyclopedic work on Yogācāra theory and praxis
which is a composite work reflecting various stages of historical
development (compiled 3rd to 5th century CE).[154][1]
Mahāyānasūtrālamkāra and its bhāṣya, traditionally attributed to
the bodhisattva Maitreya or Asanga, modern scholars like
D'amato place this text (together with the commentary) after the
Bodhisattvabhumi, but before Asanga.[219] Tibetan depiction of Asaṅga
Madhyāntavibhāga (Distinguishing the Middle and the receiving teachings from the
Extremes), another work of the "second phase" of post- bodhisattva Maitreya. This
Yogācārabhūmi Yogācāra thought, traditionally attributed to the is one of the founding
bodhisattva Maitreya who is said to have revealed it to religious myth of Yogācāra
Asanga.[220] scholasticism.
Dharmadharmatāvibhāga (Distinguishing Dharmas and
Dharmata), another work of the so called "Maitreya corpus"
Nāgamitra's (3rd-4th century?) Kāyatrayāvatāramukha (a treatise on the trikaya and the three
natures)
The works of Asaṅga (4th-5th century CE): the Mahāyānasaṃgraha and the Abhidharma-
samuccaya.[221]
Vasubandhu's (4th-5th century CE) Viṃśaṭikā-kārikā (Treatise in Twenty Stanzas), Triṃśikā-
kārikā (Treatise in Thirty Stanzas), Vyākhyāyukti ("Proper Mode of Exposition"),
Karmasiddhiprakarana ("A Treatise on Karma"), and Pañcaskandhaprakaraṇa (Explanation
of the Five Aggregates).[206][222]
Ālokamālāprakaraṇanāma (An Explanation named 'Garland of Light') by Kambala (c. fifth to
sixth century) which attempts to harmonize Madhyamaka and Yogācāra, mostly by
assimilating Madhyamaka under Yogācāra.[217][223]
The Saṃdhinirmocanasūtravyākhyāna is a commentary to the Saṃdhinirmocanasūtra
attributed to Asanga, but this has been questioned by modern scholars.[224]
Abhisamayālaṅkāra (Ornament of Realization), a commentary on the Prajñaparamita sutras.
It is attributed to Maitreya-Asanga by Tibetan tradition, but it is unknown in Chinese sources.
Modern scholars see this as a post-Asanga text. Makransky attributes it to Ārya Vimuktisena,
the first commentator on this text.[225][226]
Dignāga's Ālambanaparīkṣā and its vrtti (commentary) defend the view of consciousness-
only using epistemological arguments
The Indian Paramārtha (499–569) translated many works to Chinese, and also wrote some
original treatises and commentaries, possibly including the Buddhagotraśāstra (Fo Xing
Lun)
Sthiramati (6th century), wrote numerous commentaries like Pañcaskandhakavibhāṣā and
Triṃśikāvijñaptibhāṣya
Mahayana Awakening of Faith (author unknown)
Dharmapala of Nalanda (6th century), wrote commentaries to the Ālambanaparīkṣā and
Āryadeva's Catuḥśataka
Asvabhāva, wrote Mahāyānasūtrālaṃkāra-ṭīkā, Mahāyānasaṃgrahopanibandhana and a
commentary on Ālokamālā
Dharmakīrti's (6th or 7th century) Pramānaṿārttika (Commentary on Epistemology), is mostly
a work on pramana, but it also argues for consciousness-only
Śīlabhadra (529–645) - Buddhabhūmivyākhyāna
Xuanzang's (602-664) Cheng Wei Shi Lun is a large Chinese commentary on the Triṃśikā
which draws on numerous Indian sources
Kuiji (632–682) - Various commentaries on texts like Cheng weishi lun, Heart-sutra,
Madhyāntavibhāga etc.
Wŏnch'ŭk (613–696) - Commentaries on the Samdhinirmocanasutra, Heart-sutra, and
Benevolent King Sutra
Wŏnhyo (617–686) - wrote commentaries on various works such as the Madhyāntavibhāga
Guṇaprabha - Bodhisattvabhūmiśīlaparivarta-bhāṣya
Jinaputra, wrote a commentary to the Abhidharmasamucchaya
Candragomī (sixth/seventh century) - Śiṣyalekha, Bodhisattvasaṃvaraviṃsaka
Vinītadeva (c. 645–715) - wrote commentaries on Viṃśatikā, Triṃśika and Ālambanaparīkśā
Jñānacandra (eighth century) - Yogacaryābhāvanātātparyārthanirdeśa, a meditation manual
Sāgaramegha (eighth century) - Yogācārabhūmaubodhisattvabhūmivyākhyā, a large
Yogācārabhūmi commentary
Sumatiśīla (late eighth century) wrote a commentary on Vasubandhu's
Karmasiddhiprakaraṇa
Prajñakaragupta (8th-9th century) - Pramāṇavārttikālaṃkāra and
Sahāvalambanirṇayasiddhi, a proof of idealism
Śaṅkaranandana (fl. c. 9th or 10th century) - Prajñālaṅkāra (Ornament of Wisdom), an
exposition of vijñaptimātratā [227]
Dharmakīrti of Sumatra - Durbodhālokā (Light on the Hard-to-Illuminate), a sub-commentary
to the Abhisamayālaṃkāra-śāstra-vṛtti of Haribhadra.[228]
Jñānaśrīmitra (fl. 975-1025 C.E.) - Sākarasiddhi, Sākarasaṃgraha, and Sarvajñāsiddhi
Ratnakīrti (11th century CE) - Ratnakīrtinibandhāvalī and Sarvajñāsiddhi
Ratnākāraśānti (10-11th century) - Prajñāpāramitopadeśa, Madhyamakālaṃkāropadeśa,
Vijñaptimātratāsiddhi, Triyānavyavasthāna, Madhyamakālaṃkāravṛtti-
Madhyamapratipadāsiddhi
Jñānaśrībhadra - commentaries on Laṅkāvatārasūtra, Mahāyānasūtrālaṃkāra, and
Pramāṇavārttika
Sajjana (11th century) - Putralekha, Mahāyānottaratantraśāstropadeśa and
Sūtrālaṃkārapiṇḍārtha[173]
Jōkei (1155–1213) - Gumei hosshin shū (Anthology of Awakenings from Delusion)
Ryōhen (1194–1252) - Kanjin kakumushō (Précis on Contemplating the Mind and
Awakening from the Dream)
See also
Madhyamaka
Mahayana
Idealism
Vedanta
Kashmir Shaivism
School of the Heart-Mind

Notes
a. Alex Wayman, A Defense of Yogacara Buddhism. Philosophy East and West, Volume 46,
Number 4, October 1996, pages 447-476: "Of course, the Yogacara put its trust in the
subjective search for truth by way of a samadhi. This rendered the external world not less
real, but less valuable as the way of finding truth. The tide of misinformation on this, or on
any other topic of Indian lore comes about because authors frequently read just a few verses
or paragraphs of a text, then go to secondary sources, or to treatises by rivals, and presume
to speak authoritatively. Only after doing genuine research on such a topic can one begin to
answer the question: why were those texts and why do the moderns write the way they do?"
b. Kalupahana: "The above explanation of alaya-vijnana makes it very different from that found
in the Lankavatara. The latter assumes alaya to be the eight consciousness, giving the
impression that it represents a totally distinct category. Vasubandhu does not refer to it as the
eight, even though his later disciples like Sthiramati and Hsuan Tsang constantly refer to it
as such".[65]
c. Majhima Nikaya 121: Cula-suññata Sutta [81]

1. Frauwallner, Die Philosophie des Buddhismus,treats Tathāgatagarbha-thought as a


separate school of Mahayana, providing an excerpt from the Uttaratantra, written by a certain
Sāramati (娑囉末底 ), c.q. Maitreya-nātha.

References
1. Lusthaus, Dan (2018). What is and isn't Yogacara (http://www.acmuller.net/yogacara/articles/
intro.html), Yogācāra Buddhism Research Association.
2. Makransky, John (1997). Buddhahood Embodied: Sources of Controversy in India and Tibet
(https://books.google.com/books?id=I4qmkptncxQC&pg=PA211). SUNY Press. p. 211.
ISBN 978-0-7914-3431-4.
3. Delenau, Florin. Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation (https://www.acade
mia.edu/106604621/_Mind_Only_and_Beyond_History_of_Yogacara_Meditation_Oxford_le
ctures_2010_), 2010, Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies).
4. Jones, Lindsay (Ed. in Chief) (2005). Encyclopedia of Religion. (2nd Ed.) Volume 14:
p.9897. USA: Macmillan Reference. ISBN 0-02-865983-X (v.14)
5. Deleanu, F. (Ed.). (2006). The Chapter on the Mundane Path (Laukikamārga): A Trilingual
Edition(Sanskrit, Tibetan, Chinese), Annotated Translation and Introductory Study (2 vol), p.
162. Tokyo:International Institute for Buddhist Studies.
6. Kragh, U.T. (editor), The Foundation for Yoga Practitioners: The Buddhist Yogācārabhūmi
Treatise and Its Adaptation in India, East Asia, and Tibet, Volume 1, pp. 30-31. Harvard
University, Department of South Asian studies, 2013.
7. Siderits, Mark, Buddhism as philosophy, 2017, p. 146.
8. Jones, Lindsay (Ed. in Chief)(2005). Encyclopedia of Religion. (2nd Ed.) Volume 14;
Masaaki, Hattori (Ed.)(1987 & 2005)"Yogācāra": p.9897. USA: Macmillan Reference.
ISBN 0-02-865983-X (v.14)
9. Keenan, John P. (tr). The Scripture on the Explication of the Underlying Meaning. 2000. p. 1
10. Kochumuttom 1999, p. 1.
11. Peter Harvey, "An Introduction to Buddhism." Cambridge University Press, 1993, page 106.
12. Muller, A. Charles (2005; 2007). Wonhyo's Reliance on Huiyuan in his Exposition of the Two
Hindrances. (Published in Reflecting Mirrors: Perspectives on Huayan Buddhism. Imre
Hamar, ed., Harrassowitz Verlag, 2007, p. 281-295.) Source: [1] (http://www.acmuller.net/artic
les/wonhyo-huiyuan-2006.html) (accessed: April 7, 2010)
13. Gold, Jonathan C., "Vasubandhu", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2018
Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.),
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/vasubandhu/
14. Schmithausen, Lambert, The Genesis of Yogācāra-Vijñānavāda: Responses and
Reflections, Tokyo, The International Institute for Buddhist Studies, 2014, p. 597.
15. Trivedi, Saam (November 2005). "Idealism and Yogacara Buddhism". Asian Philosophy. 15
(3): 231–246. doi:10.1080/09552360500285219 (https://doi.org/10.1080%2F095523605002
85219). S2CID 144090250 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:144090250).
16. Schmithausen, Lambert, The Genesis of Yogācāra-Vijñānavāda: Responses and
Reflections, Tokyo, The International Institute for Buddhist Studies, 2014, p. 387.
17. Schmithausen, Lambert, The Genesis of Yogācāra-Vijñānavāda: Responses and
Reflections, Tokyo, The International Institute for Buddhist Studies, 2014, p. 391.
18. Schmithausen, Lambert, The Genesis of Yogācāra-Vijñānavāda: Responses and
Reflections, Tokyo, The International Institute for Buddhist Studies, 2014, p. 598.
19. Siderits, Mark, Buddhism as philosophy, 2017, p. 149.
20. Schmithausen, Lambert, The Genesis of Yogācāra-Vijñānavāda: Responses and
Reflections, Tokyo, The International Institute for Buddhist Studies, 2014, p. 389.
21. Kapstein, Matthew T. (July 2014). "Buddhist Idealists and Their Jain Critics On Our
Knowledge of External Objects". Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement. 74: 123–147.
doi:10.1017/S1358246114000083 (https://doi.org/10.1017%2FS1358246114000083).
S2CID 170689422 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:170689422).
22. Cameron Hall, Bruce, The Meaning of Vijnapti in Vasubandhu's Concept of Mind, JIABS Vol
9, 1986, Number 1, p. 7.
23. Saam Trivedi, Idealism and Yogacara Buddhism, Asian Philosophy Volume 15, 2005 - Issue
3 Pages 231-246.
24. Butler, Sean, Idealism in Yogācāra Buddhism, The Hilltop Review Volume 4 Issue 1 Spring
2010,
25. Garfield, Jay L. Vasubandhu's treatise on the three natures translated from the Tibetan
edition with a commentary, Asian Philosophy, Volume 7, 1997, Issue 2, pp. 133-154.
26. Williams 2008, p. 94.
27. Yamabe, Nobuyoshi (2004), "Consciousness, Theories of", in Buswell, Jr., Robert E.,
Macmillan Encyclopedia of Buddhism, USA: Macmillan Reference USA, pp. 177, ISBN 0-
02-865910-4
28. Schmithausen, Lambert, The Genesis of Yogācāra-Vijñānavāda: Responses and
Reflections, Tokyo, The International Institute for Buddhist Studies, 2014, p. 625.
29. Schmithausen, Lambert (2005). On the Problem of the External World in the Ch’eng wei shih
lun. Tōkyō: The International Institute for Buddhist Studies. The International Institute for
Buddhist Studies.
30. Kalupahana 1992.
31. Dan Lusthaus, What is and isn't Yogacara. [2] (http://www.acmuller.net/yogacara/articles/intro
-uni.htm). Archived (https://web.archive.org/web/20080612084656/http://www.acmuller.net/yo
gacara/articles/intro-uni.htm) June 12, 2008, at the Wayback Machine
32. Garfield, Jay L. (2002). Empty words : Buddhist philosophy and cross-cultural interpretation
([Online-Ausg.]. ed.). New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780195145519.
33. Kalupahana 1992, pp. 122-126, 135-136.
34. Delenau, Florin. Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation (https://www.acade
mia.edu/106604621/_Mind_Only_and_Beyond_History_of_Yogacara_Meditation_Oxford_le
ctures_2010_), p. 162. 2010, Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies).
Vasubandhu: cittaṃ mano vijñānaṃ vijñaptiś ceti paryāyaḥ (Viṃś 3.3); ‘mind, thinking,
consciousness, and representation are synonymous terms’. Cf. AKBh II.34 (p. 61, l. 20):
cittaṃ mano ʼtha vijñānam ekārthaṃ; ‘now, the mind, thinking, and consciousness have the
same meaning’.
35. Kochumuttom 1999, p. 5.
36. Wayman, Alex, A Defense of Yogācāra Buddhism, Philosophy East and West, Vol. 46, No. 4
(Oct., 1996), pp. 447-476.
37. Vasubandhu (author), Stefan Anacker (translator, annotator) (1984). Seven works of
Vasubandhu, the Buddhist psychological doctor. Issue 4 of Religions of Asia series. Motilal
Banarsidass Publ. ISBN 978-81-208-0203-2. Source: [1] (accessed: Wednesday April 21,
2010), p.159
38. Kochumuttom 1999, p. 1-2.
39. Kochumuttom 1999, p. 6.
40. Dan Lusthaus (4 February 2014). Buddhist Phenomenology: A Philosophical Investigation of
Yogacara Buddhism and the Ch'eng Wei-shih Lun (https://books.google.com/books?id=j0TK
AgAAQBAJ). Taylor & Francis. p. 43. ISBN 978-1-317-97342-3.
41. Westerhoff, Jan (November 2020), "For your eyes only: the Problem on Solipsism in Ancient
Indian Philosophy", BSHP Annual Lecture 2020 (https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=oBVXC
c8N5zE), British Society for the History of Philosophy, retrieved 2024-02-21
42. Williams, 2008, pp. 94-95.
43. Fernando Tola, Carmen Dragonetti, Being as Consciousness: Yogācāra Philosophy of
Buddhism, Motilal Banarsidass Publ., 2004, p xxiv.
44. Siderits, Mark, Buddhism as philosophy, 2017, pp. 150-151.
45. Siderits, Mark, Buddhism as philosophy, 2017, p. 157.
46. Siderits, Mark, Buddhism as philosophy, 2017, p. 170.
47. Siderits, Mark, Buddhism as philosophy, 2017, p. 173.
48. Brewster, Ernest Billings. "What is Our Shared Sensory World?: Ming Dynasty Debates on
Yogacara versus Huayan Doctrines." (http://buddhism.lib.ntu.edu.tw/FULLTEXT/JR-BJ001/bj
001577597.pdf) Journal of Chinese Buddhist Studies (2018, 31: 117–170) New Taipei:
Chung-Hwa Institute of Buddhist Studies. ISSN: 2313-2000 e-ISSN: 2313-2019
49. Wood, Thomas E. Mind Only: A Philosophical and Doctrinal Analysis of the Vijñānavāda, p.
205. University of Hawaii Press, 1991
50. Finnigan, Bronwyn (2017). "Buddhist Idealism." In Tyron Goldschmidt & Kenneth Pearce
(eds.), Idealism: New Essays in Metaphysics. Oxford University Press. pp. 178-199.
51. Gold, Jonathan C., "Vasubandhu", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2018
Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.),
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/vasubandhu/
52. Siderits, Mark, Buddhism as philosophy, 2017, p. 175.
53. Kalupahana 1992, p. 138-140.
54. Kalupahana 1992, p. 137-139.
55. Williams, Paul (2008). Mahayana Buddhism: The Doctrinal Foundations, Routledge, p. 97.
56. Fernando Tola, Carmen Dragonetti, Being as Consciousness: Yogācāra Philosophy of
Buddhism, Motilal Banarsidass Publ., 2004, p xxv.
57. Waldron, William S. The Buddhist Unconscious: The Alaya-vijñana in the context of Indian
Buddhist Thought. Routledge Critical Studies in Buddhism, 2003, pp 94-95.
58. Waldron, William S. The Buddhist Unconscious: The Alaya-vijñana in the context of Indian
Buddhist Thought. Routledge Critical Studies in Buddhism, 2003, p 97.
59. Schmithausen, Lambert (1987). Ālayavijñāna: on the origin and the early development of a
central concept of Yogācāra philosophy, Part I: Text, page 89. Tokyo, International Institute
for Buddhist Studies, Studia Philologica Buddhica Monograph Series IVa.
60. Williams, 2008, pp. 97-98.
61. Williams, 2008, pp. 98-99.
62. Waldron, William S. The Buddhist Unconscious: The Alaya-vijñana in the context of Indian
Buddhist Thought. Routledge Critical Studies in Buddhism, 2003, page 131.
63. Waldron, William S. The Buddhist Unconscious: The Alaya-vijñana in the context of Indian
Buddhist Thought. Routledge Critical Studies in Buddhism, 2003, page 93.
64. Kalupahana 1992, p. 137.
65. Kalupahana 1992, p. 139.
66. Kalupahana 1992, p. 138.
67. Kalupahana 1992, p. 140.
68. Kalupahana 1992, p. 141.
69. Padmasiri De Silva, Robert Henry Thouless, Buddhist and Freudian Psychology. Third
revised edition published by NUS Press, 1992 page 66.
70. Walpola Rahula, quoted in Padmasiri De Silva, Robert Henry Thouless, Buddhist and
Freudian Psychology. Third revised edition published by NUS Press, 1992 page 66, [3] (http
s://books.google.com/books?id=4Fb0q9bKJjIC&pg=PA65&dq=development+of+the+theory+
of+karma+buddhism&lr=#PPA66,M1).
71. Williams (2008), p. 90.
72. Siderits, Mark, Buddhism as philosophy, 2017, p. 176.
73. King, Richard, Early Yogācāra and its Relationship with the Madhyamaka School,
Philosophy East & West Volume 44, Number 4 October 1994 PP.659-683.
74. Peter Lunde Johnson, Xuanzang, On There Only Being the Virtual Nature of
Consciousness, 2019, p. 470.
75. Siderits, Mark, Buddhism as philosophy, 2017, pp. 177-178.
76. Williams (2008), pp. 90-91.
77. Skilton, Andrew (1994). A Concise History of Buddhism. Windhorse Publications, London:.
pg 124
78. King, Richard, Early Yogācāra and its Relationship with the Madhyamaka School,
Philosophy East & West Volume 44, Number 4 October 1994 pp. 659-683.
79. Williams (2008), p. 93.
80. Gadjin M. Nagao, Madhyamika and Yogachara. Leslie S. Kawamura, translator, SUNY
Press, Albany 1991, pp. 53-57, 200.
81. Cula-suññata Sutta: The Lesser Discourse on Emptiness (http://www.accesstoinsight.org/tipi
taka/mn/mn.121.than.html)
82. Garfield, Jay L.; Westerhoff, Jan (2015). Madhyamaka and Yogacara: Allies Or Rivals? p. 3.
Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-023129-3
83. Conze, Edward (1993). A Short History of Buddhism (2nd ed.). Oneworld. ISBN 1-85168-
066-7.:50f.
84. Garfield, Jay L.; Westerhoff, Jan (2015). Madhyamaka and Yogacara: Allies Or Rivals? p.
133. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-023129-3
85. Garfield, Jay L.; Westerhoff, Jan (2015). Madhyamaka and Yogacara: Allies Or Rivals? p. 68.
Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-023129-3.
86. Garfield, Jay L.; Westerhoff, Jan (2015). Madhyamaka and Yogacara: Allies Or Rivals? pp.
41-52. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-023129-3
87. Garfield, Jay L.; Westerhoff, Jan (2015). Madhyamaka and Yogacara: Allies Or Rivals? p. 59.
Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-023129-3
88. Garfield, Jay L.; Westerhoff, Jan (2015). Madhyamaka and Yogacara: Allies Or Rivals? p. 50.
Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-023129-3
89. Garfield, Jay L.; Westerhoff, Jan (2015). Madhyamaka and Yogacara: Allies Or Rivals? p. 46.
Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-023129-3
90. Delenau, Florin. Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation (https://www.acade
mia.edu/106604621/_Mind_Only_and_Beyond_History_of_Yogacara_Meditation_Oxford_le
ctures_2010_), 2010, p. 76. Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies).
91. Delenau, Florin. Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation (https://www.acade
mia.edu/106604621/_Mind_Only_and_Beyond_History_of_Yogacara_Meditation_Oxford_le
ctures_2010_), 2010, p. 77. Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies).
92. Garfield, Jay L.; Westerhoff, Jan (2015). Madhyamaka and Yogacara: Allies Or Rivals? p. 86.
Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-023129-3
93. Garfield, Jay L.; Westerhoff, Jan (2015). Madhyamaka and Yogacara: Allies Or Rivals? pp.
86-87. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-023129-3
94. Garfield, Jay L.; Westerhoff, Jan (2015). Madhyamaka and Yogacara: Allies Or Rivals? p.
116. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-023129-3
95. Lusthaus, Dan (undated). Xuanzang (Hsüan-tsang). Source: "Archived copy" (https://web.arc
hive.org/web/20131208153924/http://www.acmuller.net/yogacara/thinkers/xuanzang-bio-uni.
htm). Archived from the original (http://www.acmuller.net/yogacara/thinkers/xuanzang-bio-uni.
htm) on December 8, 2013. Retrieved December 8, 2013. (accessed: December 12, 2007)
96. McNamara, Daniel (2011). “On the Status of the Trisvabhāvanirdeśa in Contemporary
Conceptions of Yogācāra Thought.” (http://www.academia.edu/8365343/.)
97. Matthew Kapstein. Who Wrote the Trisvabhāvanirdeśa? Reflections on an Enigmatic Text
and Its Place in the History of Buddhist Philosophy. (https://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/
s10781-017-9334-2) Journal of Indian Philosophy, 2017. ⟨halshs-02503277⟩
98. D’AMATO, M. “THREE NATURES, THREE STAGES: AN INTERPRETATION OF THE
YOGĀCĀRA ‘TRISVABHĀVA’-THEORY.” Journal of Indian Philosophy, vol. 33, no. 2, 2005,
pp. 185–207. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/23497001. Accessed 16 Feb. 2024.
99. Harvey, Brian Peter (2000). An Introduction to Buddhist ethics: Foundations, Values, and
Issues (https://books.google.com/books?id=URZNk9noWJEC&q=%22due+to+karma%22+y
ogacara&pg=PA297). Cambridge University Press. p. 297. ISBN 0-521-55640-6.
100. Lusthaus, Dan (2002). Buddhist Phenomenology: A philosophical Investigation of Yogācāra
Buddhism and the Ch'eng Wei-shih lun (https://books.google.com/books?id=IeiwsT-XqwQC
&q=conditioning&pg=PA60). RoutledgeCurzon. p. 194. ISBN 0-415-40610-2.
101. Lusthaus, Dan (2002). Buddhist Phenomenology: A philosophical Investigation of Yogācāra
Buddhism and the Ch'eng Wei-shih lun. RoutledgeCurzon. p. 48. ISBN 0-415-40610-2.
102. Karmasiddhiprakarana: The Treatise on Action by Vasubandhu. translated by Etienne
Lamotte and Leo M. Pruden. Asian Humanities Press: 2001 ISBN 0-89581-908-2. pg 13, 35
103. Williams, 2008, p. 95.
104. "How Mystical is Buddhism?" by Roger R. Jackson Asian Philosophy, Vol. 6, No.2, 1996 pg
150
105. Groner, Paul (2000). The Establishment of the Tendai School. University of Hawaii Press.
pp. 97–100. ISBN 0824823710.
106. Ford, James L. (2006). Jokei and Buddhist Devotion in Early Medieval Japan. Oxford
University Press, USA. pp. 35-68. ISBN 978-0-19-518814-1
107. Komarovski, Yaroslav, Visions of Unity: The Golden Paṇḍita Shakya Chokden's New
Interpretation of Yogācāra and Madhyamaka. Albany, New York: State University of New
York Press, 2011, p. 8.
108. Komarovski, Yaroslav, Visions of Unity: The Golden Paṇḍita Shakya Chokden's New
Interpretation of Yogācāra and Madhyamaka. Albany, New York: State University of New
York Press, 2011, p. 73.
109. Zhihua Yao. The Buddhist Theory of Self-Cognition, pp. 149-150. Routledge, 2012.
110. Kajiyama, Yuichi. “Controversy between the sakara- and nirakara-vadins of the Yogacara
school-some materials.” Journal of Indian and Buddhist Studies 14 (1965): n. pag.
https://www.semanticscholar.org/paper/Controversy-between-the-sakara-and-nirakara-
vadins-Kajiyama/655a1f561c18725188c0916ca05ec334b5f9f7cd
111. Komarovski, Yaroslav, Visions of Unity: The Golden Paṇḍita Shakya Chokden's New
Interpretation of Yogācāra and Madhyamaka. Albany, New York: State University of New
York Press, 2011, p. 73-74.
112. Tomlinson, Davey (2022). "Limiting the Scope of the Neither-One-Nor-Many Argument: The
Nirākāravādin's Defense of Consciousness and Pleasure" (https://muse.jhu.edu/pub/5/articl
e/854947). Philosophy East and West. 73 (2): 392–419. doi:10.1353/pew.0.0235 (https://doi.
org/10.1353%2Fpew.0.0235). ISSN 1529-1898 (https://www.worldcat.org/issn/1529-1898).
113. Timme Kragh 2013, pp. 16, 25-26, 30, 46.
114. Timme Kragh 2013, p. 31.
115. Timme Kragh 2013, p. 34.
116. Timme Kragh 2013 pp. 51, 60–230
117. Brunnholzl, Karl (trans.), Asanga. (2019) A Compendium of the Mahayana: Asanga's
Mahayanasamgraha and Its Indian and Tibetan Commentaries, Appendix 10. Shambhala
Publications.
118. Watanabe, Chikafumi, A Study of Mahayanasamgraha III: The Relation of Practical Theories
and Philosophical Theories, pp. 40-65. University of Calgary, 2000.
唯識修道五位
119. Muller, Charles. Five stages of cultivating the Yogâcāra path (http://www.budd
hism-dict.net/cgi-bin/xpr-ddb.pl?55.xml+id(%27b552f-8b58-4fee-9053-4e94-4f4d%27)),
Digital Dictionary of Buddhism, 2006
120. Watanabe, Chikafumi, A Study of Mahayanasamgraha III: The Relation of Practical Theories
and Philosophical Theories, p. 66. University of Calgary, 2000.
121. Delenau, Florin. Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation (https://www.acade
mia.edu/106604621/_Mind_Only_and_Beyond_History_of_Yogacara_Meditation_Oxford_le
ctures_2010_), 2010, pp. 97-107, 119-125. Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist
Studies).
122. Delenau, Florin. Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation (https://www.acade
mia.edu/106604621/_Mind_Only_and_Beyond_History_of_Yogacara_Meditation_Oxford_le
ctures_2010_), 2010, pp. 107. Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies).
123. Delenau, Florin. Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation (https://www.acade
mia.edu/106604621/_Mind_Only_and_Beyond_History_of_Yogacara_Meditation_Oxford_le
ctures_2010_), 2010, pp. 119. Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies).
124. Delenau, Florin. Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation (https://www.acade
mia.edu/106604621/_Mind_Only_and_Beyond_History_of_Yogacara_Meditation_Oxford_le
ctures_2010_), 2010, p. 109. Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies).
125. Delenau, Florin. Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation (https://www.acade
mia.edu/106604621/_Mind_Only_and_Beyond_History_of_Yogacara_Meditation_Oxford_le
ctures_2010_), 2010, p. 111. Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies).
126. Delenau, Florin. Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation (https://www.acade
mia.edu/106604621/_Mind_Only_and_Beyond_History_of_Yogacara_Meditation_Oxford_le
ctures_2010_), 2010, p. 111. Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies).
127. Delenau, Florin. Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation (https://www.acade
mia.edu/106604621/_Mind_Only_and_Beyond_History_of_Yogacara_Meditation_Oxford_le
ctures_2010_), 2010, p. 122. Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies).
128. Delenau, Florin. Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation (https://www.acade
mia.edu/106604621/_Mind_Only_and_Beyond_History_of_Yogacara_Meditation_Oxford_le
ctures_2010_), 2010, p. 114. Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies).
129. Deleanu, Florin. "Meditative Practices in the Bodhisattvabhūmi: Quest for and Liberation
through the Thing-In-Itself," in Kragh 2013 pp. 884-885.
130. Kragh 2013, p. 157.
131. Deleanu, Florin. "Meditative Practices in the Bodhisattvabhūmi: Quest for and Liberation
through the Thing-In-Itself," in Kragh 2013 pp. 889-891.
132. Deleanu, Florin. "Meditative Practices in the Bodhisattvabhūmi: Quest for and Liberation
through the Thing-In-Itself," in Kragh 2013 pp. 893-894.
133. Brunnholzl, Karl (trans.), Asanga. (2019) A Compendium of the Mahayana: Asanga's
Mahayanasamgraha and Its Indian and Tibetan Commentaries, Appendix 8. Shambhala
Publications.
134. Delenau, Florin. Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation (https://www.acade
mia.edu/106604621/_Mind_Only_and_Beyond_History_of_Yogacara_Meditation_Oxford_le
ctures_2010_), 2010, p. 78. Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies).
135. Kragh 2013, p. 160.
136. Deleanu, Florin. "Meditative Practices in the Bodhisattvabhūmi: Quest for and Liberation
through the Thing-In-Itself," in Kragh 2013 pp. 894-896.
137. Deleanu, Florin. "Meditative Practices in the Bodhisattvabhūmi: Quest for and Liberation
through the Thing-In-Itself," in Kragh 2013 pp. 896-897.
138. Deleanu, Florin. "Meditative Practices in the Bodhisattvabhūmi: Quest for and Liberation
through the Thing-In-Itself," in Kragh 2013 pp. 897-898.
139. Brunnholzl, Karl (2009). Luminous Heart: The Third Karmapa on Consciousness, Wisdom,
and Buddha Nature, pp. 21-22. Snow Lion Publications.
140. Brunnholzl, Karl (2009). Luminous Heart: The Third Karmapa on Consciousness, Wisdom,
and Buddha Nature, p. 24. Snow Lion Publications.
141. Delenau, Florin. Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation (https://www.acade
mia.edu/106604621/_Mind_Only_and_Beyond_History_of_Yogacara_Meditation_Oxford_le
ctures_2010_), 2010, p. 87. Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies).
142. Brunnholzl, Karl (2009). Luminous Heart: The Third Karmapa on Consciousness, Wisdom,
and Buddha Nature, p. 25. Snow Lion Publications.
143. Brunnholzl, Karl (2009). Luminous Heart: The Third Karmapa on Consciousness, Wisdom,
and Buddha Nature, pp. 23-24. Snow Lion Publications.
144. Deleanu, Florin. "Meditative Practices in the Bodhisattvabhūmi: Quest for and Liberation
through the Thing-In-Itself," in Kragh 2013 pp. 898-899.
145. Delenau, Florin. Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation (https://www.acade
mia.edu/106604621/_Mind_Only_and_Beyond_History_of_Yogacara_Meditation_Oxford_le
ctures_2010_), 2010, p. 90. Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies).
146. Delenau, Florin. Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation (https://www.acade
mia.edu/106604621/_Mind_Only_and_Beyond_History_of_Yogacara_Meditation_Oxford_le
ctures_2010_), 2010, p. 92. Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies).
147. Delenau, Florin. Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation (https://www.acade
mia.edu/106604621/_Mind_Only_and_Beyond_History_of_Yogacara_Meditation_Oxford_le
ctures_2010_), 2010, pp. 94-95. Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies).
148. Jones, Lindsay (Ed. in Chief)(2005). Encyclopedia of Religion. (2nd Ed.) Volume 14;
Masaaki, Hattori (Ed.)(1987 & 2005)"Yogācāra": p.9897. USA: Macmillan Reference.
ISBN 0-02-865983-X (v.14)
149. E. Frauwallner (2010 (1956)), Die Philosophie des Buddhismus (http://indologica.de/drupa
l/?q=node/561), p.166
150. O’Brien-Kop, K. Dharmamegha in yoga and yogācāra: the revision of a superlative
metaphor. (https://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s10781-020-09432-3) J Indian Philos 48,
605–635 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10781-020-09432-3
151. Powers, John (2004). Hermeneutics and Tradition in the Saṃdhinirmocana-sūtra (https://boo
ks.google.com/books?id=T3jIh-xPVhIC). Motilal Banarsidass. pp. 4–11. ISBN 978-81-208-
1926-9.
152. Waldron, William S (2003). The Buddhist Unconscious: The Alaya-vijñana in the Context of
Indian Buddhist Thought (https://books.google.com/books?id=x9iCAgAAQBAJ). Routledge.
ISBN 978-1-134-42886-1.
153. King, Richard; Vijnaptimatrata and the Abhidharma context of early Yogacara
154. Kritzer (2005), p. xvii, xix.
155. M. Delhey, ‘The Yogācārabhūmi Corpus: Sources, Editions, Translations, and Reference
Works’. (https://www.academia.edu/3358152/The_Yog%C4%81c%C4%81rabh%C5%ABmi
_Corpus_Sources_Editions_Translations_and_Reference_Works) 2013.
156. Kragh, U.T. (editor), The Foundation for Yoga Practitioners: The Buddhist Yogācārabhūmi
Treatise and Its Adaptation in India, East Asia, and Tibet, Volume 1, p. 312. Harvard
University, Department of South Asian studies, 2013.
157. Deleanu, F. (Ed.). (2006). The Chapter on the Mundane Path (Laukikamārga): A Trilingual
Edition(Sanskrit, Tibetan, Chinese), Annotated Translation and Introductory Study (2 vol), pp.
157-18. Tokyo:International Institute for Buddhist Studies.
158. Xuanzang; Bianji; Li, Jung-hsi (1996). The great Tang dynasty record of the western regions
(https://books.google.com/books?id=5ABuAAAAMAAJ). Numata Center for Buddhist
Translation & Research. ISBN 978-1-886439-02-3.
159. Wayman, Alex. Untying the Knots in Buddhism: Selected Essays. 1997. p. 213
160. Tucci, Giuseppe (1975). On Some Aspects of the Doctrines of the Maitreya (Natha) and
Asanga: Being a Course of Five Lectures Delivered at the University of Calcutta \ (https://boo
ks.google.com/books?id=-VVXPwAACAAJ). Chinese Materials Center.
161. D’AMATO, M. “THREE NATURES, THREE STAGES: AN INTERPRETATION OF THE
YOGĀCĀRA ‘TRISVABHĀVA’-THEORY.” Journal of Indian Philosophy, vol. 33, no. 2, 2005,
pp. 185–207. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/23497001. Accessed 16 Feb. 2024.
162. Makransky, John J. Buddhahood Embodied: Sources of Controversy in India and Tibet
SUNY Press, 1997, p. 187.
163. Williams, Paul, Mahayana Buddhism: The Doctrinal Foundations, Routledge, 1989, p. 103.
164. Gold, Jonathan, Paving the Great Way: Vasubandhu's Unifying Buddhist Philosophy,
Columbia University Press, 2014, p. 2.
165. Delenau, Florin. Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation (https://www.acade
mia.edu/106604621/_Mind_Only_and_Beyond_History_of_Yogacara_Meditation_Oxford_le
ctures_2010_), 2010, pp. 17-20. Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies).
166. Takasaki, Jikido (1966). A Study on the Ratnagotravibhāga (Uttaratantra) Being a Treatise on
the Tathāgatagarbha Theory of Mahāyāna Buddhism (Rome Oriental Series 33). Rome:
Istituto Italiano per il Medio ed Estremo Oriente, pp. 45–52.
167. Dreyfus, Georges B. J. Recognizing Reality: Dharmakirti's Philosophy and its Tibetan
Interpretations, Suny, 1997, pp. 15-16.
168. "Śaṅkaranandana" in Silk, Jonathan A (editor in chief). Brill's Encyclopedia of Buddhism
Volume II: Lives.
169. Brunnholzl, Karl, When the Clouds Part: The Uttaratantra and Its Meditative Tradition as a
Bridge between Sutra and Tantra, Shambhala Publications, 2015, p. 117.
170. Lusthaus, Dan, Buddhist Phenomenology: A Philosophical Investigation of Yogacara
Buddhism and the Ch'eng Wei-shih Lun, Routledge, 2014, p. 274.
171. Lusthaus, Dan, Buddhist Phenomenology: A Philosophical Investigation of Yogacara
Buddhism and the Ch'eng Wei-shih Lun, Routledge, 2014, pp. 8-10.
172. Brunnholzl, Karl, When the Clouds Part: The Uttaratantra and Its Meditative Tradition as a
Bridge between Sutra and Tantra, Shambhala Publications, 2015, p. 118.
173. Kano, Kazuo. "Sajjana and Mahājana: Yogācāra Exegeses in the Eleventh Century
Kashmir." Indogaku Bukkyogaku Kenkyu (Journal of Indian and Buddhist Studies) 69, no. 2
(2021): 118–124
174. Komarovski, Yaroslav, Visions of Unity: The Golden Paṇḍita Shakya Chokden's New
Interpretation of Yogācāra and Madhyamaka. Albany, New York: State University of New
York Press, 2011, p. 74.
175. Garfield, Jay L.; Westerhoff, Jan (2015). Madhyamaka and Yogacara: Allies Or Rivals? p.
142. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-023129-3.
176. Garfield, Jay L.; Westerhoff, Jan (2015). Madhyamaka and Yogacara: Allies Or Rivals? p. 6.
Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-023129-3
177. Shantarakshita & Ju Mipham (2005) pp.117-122
178. Komarovski, Yaroslav, Visions of Unity: The Golden Paṇḍita Shakya Chokden's New
Interpretation of Yogācāra and Madhyamaka. Albany, New York: State University of New
York Press, 2011, p. 10.
179. Komarovski, Yaroslav, Visions of Unity: The Golden Paṇḍita Shakya Chokden's New
Interpretation of Yogācāra and Madhyamaka. Albany, New York: State University of New
York Press, 2011, p. 81.
180. Komarovski, Yaroslav, Visions of Unity: The Golden Paṇḍita Shakya Chokden's New
Interpretation of Yogācāra and Madhyamaka. Albany, New York: State University of New
York Press, 2011, p. 80.
181. Paul, Diana. Philosophy of Mind in Sixth-Century China: Paramartha's Evolution of
Consciousness. 1984. p. 6
182. Paul, Diana. Philosophy of Mind in Sixth-Century China: Paramartha's Evolution of
Consciousness. 1984. pp. 32-33
183. Muller, A.C. "Quick Overview of the Faxiang School 法相宗 " (http://www.acmuller.net/yogacar
a/schools/faxiang.html). www.acmuller.net. Retrieved 2023-04-24.
184. Jorgensen, John; Lusthaus, Dan; Makeham, John; Strange, Mark, trans. (2019), Treatise on
Awakening Mahāyāna Faith, New York, NY: Oxford University Press, in Introduction (pp. 1–
10).
185. Liu, JeeLoo. An Introduction to Chinese Philosophy: From Ancient Philosophy to Chinese
Buddhism. 2006. p. 220
186. Wei Tat. Cheng Weishi Lun. 1973. p. li
187. Tagawa, Shun'ei (2009). Charles Muller (ed.). Living Yogacara: An Introduction to
Consciousness-Only Buddhism. Wisdom Publications. p. xx-xxi (forward). ISBN 978-0-
86171-589-3.
188. Liu, JeeLoo. An Introduction to Chinese Philosophy: From Ancient Philosophy to Chinese
Buddhism. 2006. p. 221
189. Green, Ronald S. (2020). Early Japanese Hosso in Relation to Silla Yogacara in Disputes
between Nara'€™s Northern and Southern Temple Traditions. Journal of Korean Religions,
11(1), 97–121. doi:10.1353/jkr.2020.0003
190. Makeham, John. Transforming Consciousness: Yogacara Thought in Modern China, pp. 13-
14. Oxford University Press, 2014
191. Khyentse Rinpoche, Dzongsar Jamyang (2003). "Introduction". In Alex Trisoglio (ed.).
Introduction to the Middle Way: Chandrakirti's Madhyamakavatara with Commentary (http://w
ww.siddharthasintent.org/) (PDF) (1st ed.). Dordogne, France: Khyentse Foundation. p. 8.
Retrieved 7 January 2013. "In the 8th century, Shantarakshita went to Tibet and founded the
monastery at Samyé. He was not a direct disciple of Bhavaviveka, but the disciple of one of
his disciples. He combined the Madhyamika-Svatantrika and Cittamatra schools, and
created a new school of Madhyamika called Svatantrika-Yogachara-Madhyamika. His
disciple Kamalashila, who wrote The Stages of Meditation upon Madhyamika (uma'i sgom
rim), developed his ideas further, and together they were very influential in Tibet."
192. Germano, David F.; Waldron, William S. (2006), "A Comparison of Alaya-vijñāna in Yogacara
and Dzogchen" (PDF), in Nauriyal, D. K.; Drummond, Michael S.; Lal, Y. B. (eds.), Buddhist
Thought and Applied Psychological Research: Transcending the boundaries, Abingdon,
Oxon.: Routledge, pp. 36–68, ISBN 978-0-415-37431-6
193. Brunnholzl, Karl. Luminous Heart: The Third Karmapa on Consciousness, Wisdom, and
Buddha Nature, Introduction. Snow Lion Publications, The Nitartha Institute (2009).
194. Taranatha. "An Ascertainment of the Two Systems" (https://web.archive.org/web/201212130
65516/http://www.jonangfoundation.org/great-madhyamaka). Jonang Foundation. Archived
from the original (http://www.jonangfoundation.org/great-madhyamaka) on December 13,
2012. Retrieved 19 December 2012. "Accordingly, those who adhere to rangtong take the
first wheel of the Buddha's teachings which is the Wheel of Dharma that teaches the Four
Noble Truths to be provisional in meaning, the middle Wheel of Dharma that teaches the
absence of characteristics as ultimately definitive in meaning, and the final excellently
distinguished Wheel of Dharma as teaching the circumstantial definitive meaning, which is
provisional in meaning. Those who uphold zhentong take the first Wheel of Dharma to be
provisional, the middle Wheel of Dharma to teach the circumstantial definitive meaning, and
the final Wheel of Dharma to teach to ultimate definitive meaning."
195. Je Tsongkhapa (1993). Kapstein, Matthew (ed.). Ocean of Eloquence: Tsong kha pa's
Commentary on the Yogacara Doctrine of Mind (https://books.google.com/books?isbn=0791
414795/) (in Tibetan and English). Sparham, Gareth, trans.; in collaboration with Shotaro Iida
(1st. ed.). Albany, NY: State University of New York. ISBN 0791414795. Retrieved
18 December 2012.
196. Berzin, Alexander. "Brief Survey of Self-voidness and Other-voidness Views" (http://studybud
dhism.com/web/x/nav/group.html_943849830.html). Retrieved 20 June 2016.
197. Dumoulin, Heinrich (2005). Zen Buddhism: A History. Vol. 1 India and China. Bloomington,
IN: World Wisdom. p. 52. ISBN 0-941532-89-5.
198. Kapstein, Matthew T. Tibetan Buddhism: A Very Short Introduction. New York: Oxford
University Press, 2014, p. 64.
199. Torella, Raffaele. "The Pratyabhijñā and the logical-epistemological school of Buddhism" in
Goudriaan ed. (1992) Ritual and Speculation in Early Tantrism: Studies in Honor of Andre
Padoux pp. 327-346. SUNY Press.
200. Stcherbatsky, Fyodor Th. Buddhist Logic. Vol. I, p. 51. Dover Publications.
201. Keown, Damien (2004). A Dictionary of Buddhism, p. 302. Oxford University Press.
ISBN 978-0-19-860560-7.
202. Powers, John. The Yogācāra School of Buddhism: A Bibliography, p. 18. American
Theological Library Association, 1991.
203. Paul Williams; Anthony Tribe; Alexander Wynne. Buddhist Thought: A Complete Introduction
to the Indian Tradition. p. 121. 2012.
204. Muller, A.C. "Quick Overview of the Faxiang School 法相宗 " (http://www.acmuller.net/yogacar
a/schools/faxiang.html). www.acmuller.net. Retrieved 2023-04-24.
205. Makeham, John. Transforming Consciousness: Yogacara Thought in Modern China, p. 6.
Oxford University Press, 2014
206. Kritzer (2005), p. xii.
207. Fernando Tola, Carmen Dragonetti. Being as Consciousness: Yogācāra Philosophy of
Buddhism, p. xii
208. Foundations of Buddhism, by Rupert Gethin. Oxford University Press: 1998. ISBN 0-19-
289223-1
209. Williams, 2008, p. 103.
210. Harris, Ian Charles (1991). The Continuity of Madhyamaka and Yogācāra in Indian
Mahāyāna Buddhism, p. 78. BRILL.
211. "Ghanavyūhasūtra - Buddha-Nature" (https://buddhanature.tsadra.org/index.php/Texts/Ghan
avy%C5%ABhas%C5%ABtra). buddhanature.tsadra.org. Retrieved 2023-08-07.
212. T1830 成唯識論述記 [T43.229c29-230a1], CBETA (https://cbetaonline.dila.edu.tw/zh/T1830)
213. Shih, Jen-Kuan (2006). Doctrinal Connection Between Panjiao Schemata and Human
Capacity for Enlightenment in Jizang's and Kuiji's Thought (https://books.google.com/books?
id=gnjTAAAAMAAJ&q=%22%E5%A6%82%E4%BE%86%E5%87%BA%E7%8F%BE%E
5%8A%9F%E5%BE%B7%E8%8E%8A%E5%9A%B4%22+yogacara). University of
Wisconsin--Madison.
214. Keenan, John P. The Interpretation of the Buddha Land, BDK English Tripitaka, Numata
Center for Buddhist Translation & Research, 2006.
215. Makransky, John J. (1997). Buddhahood Embodied: Sources of Controversy in India and
Tibet, p. 10. SUNY. ISBN 0-7914-3431-1. — a study of interpretations of the
Abhisamayalankara.
216. Brunnhölzl, Karl (2014). "The Meditative Tradition of the Uttaratantra and Shentong". When
the Clouds Part: The Uttaratantra and its Meditative Tradition as a Bridge between Sūtra and
Tantra. Boston: Snow Lion Publications. pp. 123–50.
217. Williams (2008), pp. 87-88.
218. Brunnholzl, Karl. Luminous Heart: The Third Karmapa on Consciousness, Wisdom, and
Buddha Nature pp. 10-11. Snow Lion Publications, The Nitartha Institute (2009).
219. D’AMATO, M. “THREE NATURES, THREE STAGES: AN INTERPRETATION OF THE
YOGĀCĀRA ‘TRISVABHĀVA’-THEORY.” Journal of Indian Philosophy, vol. 33, no. 2, 2005,
pp. 185–207. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/23497001. Accessed 16 Feb. 2024.
220. D’AMATO, M. “THREE NATURES, THREE STAGES: AN INTERPRETATION OF THE
YOGĀCĀRA ‘TRISVABHĀVA’-THEORY.” Journal of Indian Philosophy, vol. 33, no. 2, 2005,
pp. 185–207. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/23497001. Accessed 16 Feb. 2024.
221. Lugli, Ligeia, Asaṅga, oxfordbibliographies.com (http://www.oxfordbibliographies.com/view/d
ocument/obo-9780195393521/obo-9780195393521-0205.xml), LAST MODIFIED: 25
NOVEMBER 2014, DOI: 10.1093/OBO/9780195393521-0205.
222. Kalupahana 1992, p. 126.
223. Brunnholzl, Karl. Luminous Heart: The Third Karmapa on Consciousness, Wisdom, and
Buddha Nature p. 9. Snow Lion Publications, The Nitartha Institute (2009).
224. Lugli, Ligeia, Asaṅga, oxfordbibliographies.com (http://www.oxfordbibliographies.com/view/d
ocument/obo-9780195393521/obo-9780195393521-0205.xml), LAST MODIFIED: 25
NOVEMBER 2014, DOI: 10.1093/OBO/9780195393521-0205.
225. Makransky, John J. Buddhahood Embodied: Sources of Controversy in India and Tibet
SUNY Press, 1997, p. 187.
226. Brunnholzl, Karl, When the Clouds Part: The Uttaratantra and Its Meditative Tradition as a
Bridge between Sutra and Tantra, Shambhala Publications, 2015, p. 81.
227. "Śaṅkaranandana" in Silk, Jonathan A (editor in chief). Brill's Encyclopedia of Buddhism
Volume II: Lives.
228. Sinclair, Iain. Dharmakirti of Kedah: His, life, work and troubled times. (https://www.iseas.ed
u.sg/wp-content/uploads/2021/06/Sinclair_TWPS02_FINAL.pdf) Temasek Working Paper
No. 2: 2021. Temasek History Research Centre ISEAS – Yusof Ishak Institute

Sources
Bayer, Achim (2012). Addenda and Corrigenda to The Theory of Karman in the
Abhidharmasamuccaya, 2012 (https://web.archive.org/web/20140714232918/http://www.bud
dhismuskunde.uni-hamburg.de/fileadmin/pdf/digitale_texte/Bayer_2012-AS-Karman-Corrige
nda.pdf) Hamburg: Zentrum für Buddhismuskunde.
Kalupahana, David J. (1992), The Principles of Buddhist Psychology, Delhi: ri Satguru
Publications
Keenan, John P. (1993). Yogācarā. pp. 203–212 published in Yoshinori, Takeuchi; with Van
Bragt, Jan; Heisig, James W.; O'Leary, Joseph S.; Swanson, Paul L.(1993). Buddhist
Spirituality: Indian, Southeast Asian, Tibetan, and Early Chinese. New York City: The
Crossroad Publishing Company. ISBN 0-8245-1277-4
King, Richard (1998). "Vijnaptimatrata and the Abhidharma context of early Yogacara" (http://
ccbs.ntu.edu.tw/FULLTEXT/JR-ADM/richard.htm). Asian Philosophy. 8 (1): 5–18.
doi:10.1080/09552369808575468 (https://doi.org/10.1080%2F09552369808575468).
Kochumuttom, Thomas A. (1999), A buddhist Doctrine of Experience. A New Translation and
Interpretation of the Works of Vasubandhu the Yogacarin, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass
Norbu, Namkhai (2001), The Precious Vase: Instructions on the Base of Santi Maha Sangha.
Shang Shung Edizioni. Second revised edition. (Translated from the Tibetan, edited and
annotated by Adriano Clemente with the help of the author. Translated from Italian into
English by Andy Lukianowicz.)
Park, Sung-bae (1983), Buddhist Faith and Sudden Enlightenment, SUNY Press
Shantarakshita & Ju Mipham (2005). The Adornment of the Middle Way Padmakara
Translation of Ju Mipham's commentary on Shantarakshita's root versus on his synthesis.
Sponberg, Alan (1979). Dynamic Liberation in Yogacara Buddhism (http://archiv.ub.uni-heide
lberg.de/ojs/index.php/jiabs/article/viewFile/8477/2384), Journal of the International
Association of Buddhist Studies 2(1), pp. 44–64.
Stcherbatsky, Theodore (1936). Mathyanta-Vibhanga, "Discourse on Discrimination between
Middle and Extremes" (https://web.archive.org/web/20140130111607/http://assyriaca.orienta
lstudies.ru/rus/images/pdf/b_stcherbatsky_1936.pdf) ascribed to Bodhisattva Maiteya and
commented by Vasubhandu and Sthiramathi, translated from the sanscrit, Academy of
Sciences USSR Press, Moscow/Leningrad.
Timme Kragh, Ulrich (editor) 2013, The Foundation for Yoga Practitioners: The Buddhist
Yogācārabhūmi Treatise and Its Adaptation in India, East Asia, and Tibet, Volume 1 Harvard
University, Department of South Asian studies.
Zim, Robert (1995). Basic ideas of Yogacara Buddhism. San Francisco State University.
Source: [4] (http://online.sfsu.edu/~rone/Buddhism/Yogacara/basicideas.htm) (accessed:
October 18, 2007).

External links
Uncompromising Idealism or the School of Vijñānavāda Buddhism (https://www.wisdomlib.o
rg/hinduism/book/a-history-of-indian-philosophy-volume-1/d/doc209754.html), Surendranath
Dasgupta, 1940
"Early Yogaacaara and Its Relationship with the Madhyamaka School" (http://ccbs.ntu.edu.t
w/FULLTEXT/JR-ADM/king.htm), Richard King, Philosophy East & West, vol. 44 no. 4,
October 1994, pp. 659–683
"The mind-only teaching of Ching-ying Hui-Yuan" (https://www.jstor.org/stable/1398535?seq
=1#page_scan_tab_contents) (subtitle) "An early interpretation of Yogaacaara thought in
China", Ming-Wood Liu, Philosophy East & West, vol. 35 no. 4, October 1985, pp. 351–375
Yogacara Buddhism Research Association (http://www.acmuller.net/yogacara/); articles,
bibliographies, and links to other relevant sites.

Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Yogachara&oldid=1223959228"

You might also like