Comments On Danielle Macbeth's Realizing Reason A Narrative of Truth and Knowing
Comments On Danielle Macbeth's Realizing Reason A Narrative of Truth and Knowing
Comments On Danielle Macbeth's Realizing Reason A Narrative of Truth and Knowing
Ray Brassier
To cite this article: Ray Brassier (2017): Comments on Danielle Macbeth’s Realizing Reason:
A Narrative of Truth and Knowing, International Journal of Philosophical Studies, DOI:
10.1080/09672559.2016.1275333
Article views: 5
Download by: [University of South Carolina ] Date: 04 February 2017, At: 07:43
International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 2017
http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/09672559.2016.1275333
reason is compelled to overstep. Kant limits the grasp of the concept to the
empirical, barring it from reality in itself. Pure reason, unconstrained by sensi-
bility, is demoted, becoming the source of transcendental illusion. But Macbeth
argues that Kant’s compromise was shattered in the course of the nineteenth
century when both mathematics and physics began to systematically relinquish
sensible intuition: the former to become a pure ‘thinking in concepts’ with
Riemann and Dedekind, the latter to transform the relative into a portal onto
the absolute with the advent of general relativity and quantum mechanics.
The third stage, and the proper culmination of scientific modernity accord-
ing to Macbeth, is knowing as a power of reason exercised in and through con-
cepts alone. Reason is purged of the recourse to intuition and realizes itself as
a pure ‘thinking in concepts’. Macbeth credits Frege with forging the resources
required to achieve this purification. By making a ‘distinction of distinctions’
between sense (Sinn) and signification (Beudeutung) on one hand, and con-
cepts and objects on the other, Frege overcomes Kant’s opposition of concept
to intuition and of logical form to semantic content as well as his conflation
of objects and objectivity. Sense is objective, but not object-bound. Logic is
concerned with content, not just form. Thus, on Macbeth’s account, Frege’s
mathematization of logic is not only the mathematization of sense but also its
ontologization: ‘Fregean sense (Sinn) is that through which, as the medium or
vehicle of awareness, we are in direct cognitive contact with reality’ (RR 448).
Since concepts have referents as well as senses, we need to acknowledge their
reality and objectivity as well as that of objects. Reason allows us to uncover
different dimensions of sense just as perception allows us to uncover different
features of objects.
The sense/signification, concept/object pairs of distinctions are put to work
in Frege’s ‘concept-script’, a mathematical language that permits the ampliative
and discursive elaboration of the content (sense) of concepts, now conceived
as intelligible unities. An intelligible unity, says Macbeth, is ‘something that
possesses independently intelligible parts but is also a whole that is not merely
reducible to its parts’ (RR 291). Frege’s concept-script allows us to express ‘the
inferentially articulated content of concepts in a way that enables deductive
proofs’ (RR 378). Proofs employing linear and joining inferences are essential
unities; they employ the laws of logic alone to move from one proposition
to the next. For Macbeth Frege’s proof of theorem 133 in his Begriffschrift is
precisely such an intelligible unity: ‘The proof is a whole, a unity, because its
steps are necessary, deductively valid. But because some of its steps are not
logically necessary, the proof also has real parts’ (RR 399). The necessity at
issue is not just logical because it involves rules depending on the definitions
(i.e. the senses) of concepts.
Thus Macbeth’s contention is that logic does not just pertain to form; it is a
contentful science: the science of concepts qua concepts. Moreover, Macbeth
suggests, acknowledging the objectivity of sense allows us to understand how
INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES 5
mathematics can have cognitive purchase on reality. Thus Frege’s logical work
reconnects with the Aristotelian model of science as pertaining to domains of
being. Indeed, as Macbeth shows, Frege explicitly espouses the Aristotelian
model of science, according to which a system of concepts and judgments
constitutes a science just in case:
• All those concepts and judgments concern a certain domain of being(s).
• Among the concepts, some are primitive and the rest are defined by appeal
to those primitive concepts.
• Among the judgments, some are primitive and the remainder are proven
as theorems from those primitive judgments.
• The judgments of the science are true, necessary, and universal.
• The judgments are known to be true, either directly or through proof.
• The concepts are adequately known, either directly or through definitions.
(RR 386)
Interestingly however, on Macbeth’s account it is precisely this pre-modern
Aristotelian model that provides Frege with a criterion of cognitive fallibility
consonant with the modern post-Kantian conception of reason as a ‘self cor-
recting enterprise’. For Frege, it is
only by adhering to the [Aristotelian] model and thereby making as explicit as
one can just how one understands things to be that one is put in a position to
discover that one does not know something one had thought one knew. (RR 375)
Moreover, Macbeth continues,
we discover those imperfections in our understanding by reasoning on the basis
of concepts insofar as we understand them, that is, grasp the senses through
which they are disclosed. But such a process of reasoning can reveal imperfections
[in Frege’s words] ‘only . . . if the content is not just indicated but is constructed
out of its constituents by means of the same logical signs as are used in the
computation.’ (RR 377)1
Interestingly, this form of logical fallibilism is importantly unlike the brand
of skepticism inspired by the ‘sideways on’ view. The objectivity of concepts is
independent of objects. Moreover, because conceptual senses are the condition
of access to objects, concepts cannot be held accountable to objects as though
these directly indexed non-conceptual reality. Thus, unlike skepticism, fallibi-
lism does not hold concepts accountable to a notion of ‘things being otherwise’
that is simply a vacuous possibility abstracted from the way we take them to be.
The upshot is that mathematical language is not an empty formalism; yet nor
does it derive its content from sensible intuition. It is a priori yet fallible, and it
yields ‘knowledge of concepts of various sorts of entities; it is most immediately
the medium of our cognitive grasp of mathematical concepts’ (RR 448). As
deployed in fundamental physics, Macbeth insists, those concepts enable us to
discover how things are for all rational beings, not just how they appear to us.
In general relativity and quantum mechanics, the relative is that through which
6 R. BRASSIER
we have access to the absolute. These theories are not mathematical models
representing an underlying physical reality: the mathematics are disclosive of
the structure of reality as such, ‘not what matter is “made of ” but what it is in
its own nature’ (RR 442, my emphasis). Thus, ‘the mathematics of Einstein’s
relativity directly discloses to pure thought a fundamental aspect of reality,
namely, the space-time field that is the cosmos’ (RR 433). Similarly, Macbeth
suggests, quantum theory discloses ‘evolutionary time’ as another fundamental
aspect of reality. A process in evolutionary time is such that ‘there is no fact of
the matter regarding what is now going on except in the light of what will be,
how things in fact turn out’ (RR 443). To say that quantum processes occur in
evolutionary time is to say that
what state a system is in now is a function not only of the past, including past
measurements on it, but also of the future, what measurements will be made, how
things will turn out. By measuring we thus can bring it about that something in
particular was true in the past in much the way the emergence of some species
brings it about that it was the case in the past that the evolution of that species
was taking place. (RR 445)
This speculative proposal, coming as it does in the book’s final section, forges
an extremely suggestive link between natural and historical being. Evolutionary
time is the time in which we can determine what has been only once we know
how things will have turned out. Only once a potential has been realized can the
process of its actualization be retroactively traced. It is the book’s confidence in
the actualization of reason’s power of knowing that provides the condition for
its reconstruction of the process through which that potential came to be real-
ized. Moreover, although this involves a critical reconstruction of modernity’s
‘sideways on’ perspective on mind and world, it is equally critical of attempts
to abandon the project of modernity and recover a more authentic relation to
the world by returning to Aristotle:
We cannot merely turn our backs on the practice of science, directly recover a
more Aristotelian conception of our being in the world, because we know as
Aristotle did not that we (and other living beings) are not natural in precisely
the way that non-living things are natural. (RR 447)
That the book repurposes the critique of Cartesianism to serve the realization
of modern reason is among its most striking achievements.
I will conclude with two questions suggested by Macbeth’s narrative. The
first is about the link between potentiality and nature. In Aristotle, potentiality
is circumscribed by essence: what something can become depends upon what
it essentially is: this is its nature. But this essential being is its actuality; essence
is what substance always already has been. One of the things that Heidegger
does in Being and Time is propose a notion of potentiality unconstrained by
any essence understood as a past actuality: this is Dasein’s existence as ‘pure
potentiality to be’ (Seinkönnen), which Dasein realizes by relating to its future
in a way that transforms both its past and its present. This rearticulation of
INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES 7
past, present, and future – transforming what has been into what will have
been – is the key to historical being for Heidegger. It is also what distinguishes
historical being from natural being: the human potentiality to be is historical
precisely because it is unnatural. To exist historically is to exist in a state of
perpetual ‘afterwardness’, in which what has been depends on what will be.
Is the account of evolutionary time sketched in Realizing Reason one way of
reconnecting nature and history? If so, is the afterwardness through which
reason retrospectively establishes its own history natural after all? This would
mean that science transforms our understanding of history as much as history
transforms our understanding of science.
The second question is about concepts and history. Given its rejection of
Kantian transcendentalism and its defense of the objectivity and reality of con-
cepts, Realizing Reason seems sympathetic to Hegelian rationalism, wherein
subject and object are reciprocally articulated to achieve a ‘mediated imme-
diacy’ (a phrase Macbeth reiterates throughout the book). Some of Macbeth’s
formulations are certainly redolent of Hegel: ‘The radical otherness of the world,
its full objectivity, completes the spontaneity of thought, in just this way that
the spontaneity of thought and the objectivity of the world form an intelligible
unity’ (RR 451). However, for Hegel, this unity is never permanent because of
the irreducible dissonance between spontaneity and objectivity. Their relation is
marked by a negativity which is the source of their difference, but also of their
identity. This dissonance fuels history (Hegel’s ‘highway of despair’). Moreover,
Hegel inscribes concepts into history while injecting becoming into concepts,
so that while his Phenomenology charts the successive shapes of spirit, his Logic
charts the internal development and transformation of concepts. This stands
in stark contrast to Frege’s anti-historicism, which Macbeth emphasizes using
Frege’s own words:
A logical concept does not develop and it does not have a history . . . If we said
instead ‘history of attempts to grasp a concept’ or ‘history of the grasp of the
concept’, this would seem to me much more to the point; for a concept is some-
thing objective: we do not form it, nor does it form itself in us, but we seek to
grasp it, and in the end we hope to have grasped it, though we may mistakenly
have been looking for something when there was nothing. (Frege, ‘On the Law
of Inertia’, quoted in RR 377)
Although both Hegel and Frege espouse forms of conceptual realism, Frege’s
anti-historicism about concepts is more Platonic than Hegelian. My question is
whether Macbeth’s apparent endorsement of Frege’s anti-historicism conflicts
with her claim that reason becomes, that it needs history to realize its own
power. I take Macbeth’s fundamental contention to be that the realization of
reason is an evolutionary process. Recall that for Macbeth, an evolutionary pro-
cess is one such that ‘there is no fact of the matter regarding what is now going
on except in the light of what will be, how things in fact turn out’ (RR 443). If
reason unfolds in evolutionary time, if its realization takes time, then the truth
8 R. BRASSIER
about what concepts are and have been is indissociable from what they will be.
More precisely: if reason’s self-understanding (or self-consciousness) is decisive
for its self-realization, can one cleanly separate the objectivity of concepts, i.e.
what concepts are, from the history of the senses through which we grasp them?
Note
1.
Macbeth here quotes from Frege’s ‘Boole’s Logical Calculus and the Concept-
Script’ in Posthumous Writings, edited by H. Hermes, F. Kambartel, and F.
Kaulbach, translated by P. Long and R. White (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1979), pp. 9–46.