Explaining Qualia
Explaining Qualia
Explaining Qualia
EXPLAINING QUALIA
ARPITA SINGH
Introduction
Consciousness is at once the most familiar and the most mysterious aspect in
our life. It is the very core of our existence yet it is very difficult to describe and
explain consciousness. The word “consciousness” and “conscious” have been used in
many ways. We talk of losing and regaining consciousness, of being conscious of
one's appearance and of taking conscious decisions. The original meaning of
‘consciousness’ was awareness or knowledge. It is used to describe our state of
awareness of our surroundings and self. Consciousness has been the subject of study
of many diverse disciplines, though the study of consciousness is as old as
philosophy. Despite of being the medium of all worldly knowledge and knowledge of
inner self, consciousness still is an intractable problem. Consciousness has some
features which make it puzzling, such as: subjectivity, phenomenality, intentionality,
and qualia. For a conscious mind there is a subjective point of view, which is
accessible only to the conscious being itself and can be known only from first- person
perspective. So, self is subjectivity, which covers one’s feelings, thinking and
perception. David Chalmers has divided the problems of consciousness into “hard”
and “easy” problems. The easy problems of consciousness are concerned with
explaining the functions, dynamics and structure of consciousness as they are directly
receptive to the standard methods of cognitive science, so the phenomena are
explained in terms of neural mechanism. On the other hand, hard problem of
consciousness is to talk about subjective experiences associated with physical
mechanism or processes of brain. In other words, the hard problem is the problem of
explaining the relation between physical phenomena, such as brain processes, and the
subjective/phenomenal experiences associated with these physical mechanism or
processes. For example, while watching the blue sky we experience visual sensation:
the felt quality of blueness. These qualitative or phenomenal properties of experiences
are named as “qualia”, which is the heart of hard problems of consciousness. The
phenomenal structure of conscious experience involves both sensory ideas and
qualities and complex representations of time, space, cause, body, self, and the
organized structure of lived reality in all its conceptual and non-conceptual forms.
182
1
Shoemaker, S. (1982). “The Inverted Spectrum”. Journal of Philosophy. Vol. 79, No. 7, p.
367.
2
For detail see Crane, T. (2000). “The Origins of Qualia”, In Tim Crane & Sarah Patterson,
eds., The History of Mind- Body Problem, London: Routledge. <http:/www.timcrane.com>
access September 30, 2020-09-30. P. 14.
183
though Lewis uses it in the context of sense data. According to the Lewis qualia are
introspectible, intrinsic and non- representational features of sense data and other
non-physical objects and these are responsible for their phenomenal character.3 In the
contemporary period, the term has been used in aforesaid sense, though it now refers
more generally to properties of experiences rather than sense-data. Standard examples
of experiences with qualia are perceptual experiences, bodily sensations, emotions,
and moods. The philosophers like Thomas Nagel 4 and Ned Block5 maintain this sense
of qualia. But these interpretations of qualia as phenomenal character of experiences
invoke the controversy: whether qualia, so defined, can be characterized in
intentional, functional or purely cognitive terms. Opponents of qualia, e.g. Dennett,
define the term in a restricted way in order to that qualia are intrinsic properties of
experiences that are ineffable, nonphysical and ‘given’ to their subjects incorrigibly
and thus nonscientific in nature: So, to summarize the tradition qualia are supposed to
be properties of a subject’s mental states that are:
a. Ineffable
b. Intrinsic
c. Private and
d. Directly or immediately apprehensible to consciousness.6
For some aspects of consciousness, it is relatively direct to see how they can
be suit within a physicalist picture. For example, our abilities to access, report on, and
attend to our own mental states. It is reasonable to presuppose that as neuroscience
progresses and we learn more and more about the brain, we will be able to explain
3
For detail see Keeley, B. L. (2009). “The Early History of the Quale and Its Relation to the
Sense”, In J. Symons & P. Calvo, eds., Routledge Companion to Philosophy of psychology,
London: Routledge. pp. 71-89.
4
Nagel, T. (1974). “What Is It Like to Be a Bat?” in Ned Block, Owen Flanagan, and Guven
Guzelder, eds., The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates, A Bradford Book. The
MIT Press: Cambridge. pp. 519-527.
5
Block, N. (1990). “Inverted Earth” in Ned Block, Owen Flanagan, and Guven Guzelder,
eds., The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates, A Bradford Book. The MIT Press:
Cambridge. pp. 677-693.
6
Dennett, D.C. (1997). “Quining Qualia”. in Ned Block,Owen Flanagan, and Guven
Guzelder,eds., The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates. A Bradford Book. The
MIT Press: Cambridge. p. 622
184
Explaining Qualia
In this section we will discuss critically various arguments put forth to
explain qualia. We will analyze four arguments such as, knowledge argument,
inverted spectrum argument, absent qualia argument and explanatory gap argument as
follows.
The Knowledge Argument
The knowledge argument is the most popular argument against the
Physicalist explanation of qualia, given by Frank Jackson in his famous paper “What
Marry didn’t know”.8 The fundamental idea lies in the argument is that there is some
knowledge about the experience that can be gained only by having the particular
experience oneself. No physical knowledge of what goes in brain while having that
experience would suffice to know the phenomenal character of the experience.
Jackson presents the hypothetical case of Mary, the super colour scientist, who has
spent her whole life raised in black and white environment in which she learns all the
physical and functional facts about the colour vision. However, she moves outside for
the first time and according to Jackson she learns a new fact: what it is like to see red.
Thus he concludes what it is like to see red cannot be merely a functional or physical
fact.
A wide variety of objections have been raised against the knowledge
argument: Does Mary in fact learn new knowledge? What sort of knowledge does she
acquire? Paul Churchland has raised three objections against Jackson’s claim. First
objection is that the knowledge argument contains the defect of “simplicity itself” and
7
Chalmers, D.J. (1995). “Facing Up to the Problem of Consciousness”. Journal of
Consciousness Studies, Vol. 2, No. 3, p. 201
8
Jackson, F. (1986). “What Mary Didnt Know.” Jpurnal of Philosophy. Vol. 83, No. 5: pp.
291-95.
185
...and like many other philosophers I find that claim not very plausible. Part of what
Mary gains is know- how, but that does not seem to be all she gains. There seems to
be a fact about how phenomenal red appears that she apprehends only after her
release.13
Here is a different and more strengthen objection to Jackson is raised by Loar
and also supported by Van Gulick. Loar argues that what Mary acquires when she
experiences red is a new phenomenal concept; a recognitional disposition that let her
to distinguish a certain type of phenomenal feel (acquired discriminative abilities).
This new phenomenal concept is component of veritably new knowledge, which is
the knowledge of what it is like to see red. But this new concept adopts the old
properties which are assigned by physical or functional concepts that she already had.
So, difference is here nothing but ways of knowing: before leaving the room, her
knowledge to see red was of third- person way; after leaving the room, she acquires a
9
Churchland, P. (1985). “Reduction, Qualia, and the Direct Introspection of Brain States”.
The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 82, No. 1: p. 23.
10
Ibid. 24.
11
Ibid. 25.
12
Lewis, D. K. (1983). “Postscript to ‘Mad Pain and Martian Pain’,” Philosphical Papers,
Vol. 1, p. 131.
13
Van Gulick, R. (1997). “Understanding the Phenomenal Mind: Are We All Just
Armadillos? Part I: Phenomenal Knowledge and Explanatory Gaps”. in Ned Block, Owen
Flanagan, and Guven Guzelder,eds., The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates A
Bradford Book. The MIT Press: Cambridge. p. 560.
186
new way (first- person way) of knowing the same fact.14 Conclusively, what she gains
does not eliminate any possible worlds that were not already obviated by the facts
that she already knew, and knowledge argument sets no danger to physical doctrine
of qualia. Eventually, recognitional disposition hints how qualia could come out to be
relational: a relational physical state of the brain or even a functional state.
Designing and building such a device would require that its “fidelity” be tuned or
calibrated by the normalization of the two subjects’ reports- so we would be right
back at our evidential starting point. The moral of this intuition pump is that no
intersubjective comparison of qualia is possible, even with perfect technology.16
14
Loar, B. (1997). “Phenomenal States”. in Ned Block, Owen Flanagan, and Guven Guzelder,
eds., The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates A Bradford Book. The MIT Press:
Cambridge. pp. 597-616. For detailed argument see pp. 598-600.
15
Chalmers, D. J. (1996). The Conscious Mind: in Search of Fundamental Theory, New York
Oxford: Oxford University Press. p. 264.
16
Dennett, D.C. (1997). “Quining Qualia”. in Ned Block, Owen Flanagan, and Guven
Guzelder, eds., The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates. A Bradford Book. The
MIT Press: Cambridge. p. 623.
187
The hypothesis that it could be the case that a system that functionally duplicates the
mental states of a normal human being has no phenomenal consciousness (qualia).18
Absent qualia argument establishes that any system could instantiate the
functional state of any mental phenomena, for example- pain, without having any
pain qualia. Ned Block initiated this objection to functionalism with the thought
experiment of the homunculi- headed robot. This thought experiment appeals to
oddball realization of our functional organization by huge human-duplicates (artificial
17
Ibid. 624.
18
Tye, M. (2006). “Absent Qualia and the Mind-Body Problem”. philosophical Review. Vol.
115, No. 2. p. 140.
188
brainless robot). If this China- body system can share our functional organization,
then our functional organization cannot be sufficient for qualia.19 Many critics face
the difficulty to reply to case like China- body system and say that China- body
system could undergo qualia. According to functionalist like the oddness of this view
comes from our relative size. We are each so much smaller than the China-body
system that we are unable to get a general understanding of whole system. Just like a
creature the size of a neuron trapped inside a human head might well be wrongly
persuaded that there couldn’t be consciousness, so we also wrongly conclude as we
contemplate the China-body system.
The problem arises, I want to suggest, because we are cut off by our very cognitive
constitution from achieving a conception of that natural property of the brain (or of
consciousness) that accounts for the psychophysical link. this is a kind of causal
nexus that we are preclude from ever understanding, given the way we have to form
our concepts and develop theories. No wonder we find the problem so difficult!21
19
Block, N. (1978), “Troubles with Functionalism.”, In David Chalmers, Philosophy of Mind:
Classical and Contemporary Readings. New York Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002. pp.
94-98.
20
Van Gulick, R. (1997), “Understanding the Phenomenal Mind: Are We All Just Armadillos?
Part I: Phenomenal Knowledge and Explanatory Gaps”. In Ned Block, Owen Flanagan, and
Guven Guzelde, eds., The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates A Bradford Book.
The MIT Press: Cambridge. p. 563.
21
McGinn, C. (1991). The Problem of Consciousness: Essays Towards a Resolution. Basil
Blackwell Inc. p. 2
189
Joseph Levine holds the view that psychophysical statements assert such
crude fact identities that those are unintelligible and they leave an explanatory gap
that we have no idea how to fill.22 Following the John Locke’s seventeenth- century’s
approved claim that sensory qualia are arbitrary,23 Levine attempts to support his
point by appeal to a standard philosophical case of hypothetical spectrum inversion
with red and green qualia switching causal roles in an otherwise normal subject. He
concludes that the important suggestion here is that the basic ideas, such as colour
qualia are simples. They have no structure and as each one is what it is sui generis, it
is hard to see how their connection to anything could fail to be anything but
arbitrary.24 On the basis of aforesaid suggestion Gulick reconstruct a deductive
argument form of the gap argument for consideration:
Since qualia such as phenomenal hues are basic simples; they have no structure.
Therefore: 1. Any links between such qualia and the organizational structure of their
neural substrates must be arbitrary. 2. The links between qualia and their neural bases
are unintelligible and present us with an unfillable explanatory gap.25
On the basis of this formulation of argument Larry Hardin replies that we
must reject first premise of given argument. Hardin says phenomenal hues are not in
fact such as sui generis simples, but rather elements within a highly organized and
structured colour space. Any attempt to invert them in undetectable ways would have
to preserve that structural organization. Moreover, the junction of organized structure
among colour qualia renders the basis for establishing explanatory connections
between them and their neural substrates.26
A number of philosophers argue that the unclosibility of the gap has nothing
to do with nature itself, but it has to do with our concepts. They have contributed to
22
Levine, J. (1983). “Materialism and Qualia: The Explanatory Gap”. Pacific Philosophical
Quarterly, p. 357.
23
Locke, (1690) An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed., Yolton, Everyman’s
Library, 1971, Bk. II, Ch. VIII, sec. 13, and Bk. IV, Ch. III. Secs. 12 and 13.
24
Levine, J. (1983). “Materialism and Qualia: The Explanatory Gap”. Pacific Philosophical
Quarterly, p. 357 & 358.
25
Van Gulick, R. (1997). “Understanding the Phenomenal Mind: Are We All Just
Armadillos? Part I: Phenomenal Knowledge and Explanatory Gaps”. in Ned Block, Owen
Flanagan, and Guven Guzelder, eds., The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates, A
Bradford Book. The MIT Press: Cambridge. p. 564.
26
Hardin, C. L. (1988). Color for Philosophers, Hackett Publishers, Indianapolis, In. pp. 134-
42.
190
produce the idea that reductive explanation in science depends on a priori analyses of
the phenomena to be explained, ordinarily in functional terms. For consideration
Chalmers gives the example of reductive explanation of life: life can be roughly
analyzed in terms of such general terms as metabolism and adaption or in specific
concepts like digestion and reproduction, and these concepts can themselves be given
a functional analysis.27 According to Chalmers to explain these functions, a priori, is
to explain life itself. But in some case, for example water, the a priori analysis
becomes more complicated. We can’t give an a priori analysis of water as colourless,
odourless liquid in rivers and ponds called ‘water’, because water might have colour
and odour, there might have not been ponds etc. but we can formulate an a priori
reference fixing definition of the sort that Kripke has underlined: Water = R (the
colourless, odourless liquid in rivers and lakes called ‘water’), where ‘R’ is a rigid
operator that turns a definite description into a rigid designator.28 (A rigid designator
takes the same thing in all possible worlds in which the thing exists.) The
consequence is that closing the gap requires an a priori functional analysis of qualia.
But if we choose qualia by their qualitative character then no a priori reference fixing
definition can be given for the qualitative concepts of the sort that can be given for
‘life’ and ‘water’. For example, pain= R can be true and necessary without being a
priori. And if the qualia inversion argument is right, there is no a priori conceptual
analysis of qualitative concepts either, and so the explanatory gap is enclosable. As
Chalmers points out that functional and physical account can explain only the
functions associated with qualia. But there will be curiosity remain that why these
functions are accompanied by qualia.
Conclusion
After a review of above arguments about qualia we can conclude that qualia
still remain as the most baffling feature of consciousness. Knowledge argument
creates the explanatory elusiveness of phenomenal qualities against the materialism,
but despite of being appealing it fails to maintain it standpoint clearly and it falls out
27
Chalmers, D.J. (1995). “Facing Up to the Problem of Consciousness”. Journal of
Consciousness Studies, Vol. 2, No. 3, p. 203.
28
Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and Necessity, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
191