Explaining Qualia

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 11

181

EXPLAINING QUALIA
ARPITA SINGH

Introduction
Consciousness is at once the most familiar and the most mysterious aspect in
our life. It is the very core of our existence yet it is very difficult to describe and
explain consciousness. The word “consciousness” and “conscious” have been used in
many ways. We talk of losing and regaining consciousness, of being conscious of
one's appearance and of taking conscious decisions. The original meaning of
‘consciousness’ was awareness or knowledge. It is used to describe our state of
awareness of our surroundings and self. Consciousness has been the subject of study
of many diverse disciplines, though the study of consciousness is as old as
philosophy. Despite of being the medium of all worldly knowledge and knowledge of
inner self, consciousness still is an intractable problem. Consciousness has some
features which make it puzzling, such as: subjectivity, phenomenality, intentionality,
and qualia. For a conscious mind there is a subjective point of view, which is
accessible only to the conscious being itself and can be known only from first- person
perspective. So, self is subjectivity, which covers one’s feelings, thinking and
perception. David Chalmers has divided the problems of consciousness into “hard”
and “easy” problems. The easy problems of consciousness are concerned with
explaining the functions, dynamics and structure of consciousness as they are directly
receptive to the standard methods of cognitive science, so the phenomena are
explained in terms of neural mechanism. On the other hand, hard problem of
consciousness is to talk about subjective experiences associated with physical
mechanism or processes of brain. In other words, the hard problem is the problem of
explaining the relation between physical phenomena, such as brain processes, and the
subjective/phenomenal experiences associated with these physical mechanism or
processes. For example, while watching the blue sky we experience visual sensation:
the felt quality of blueness. These qualitative or phenomenal properties of experiences
are named as “qualia”, which is the heart of hard problems of consciousness. The
phenomenal structure of conscious experience involves both sensory ideas and
qualities and complex representations of time, space, cause, body, self, and the
organized structure of lived reality in all its conceptual and non-conceptual forms.
182

Intentionality is the characteristic of consciousness whereby it is conscious of


something-i.e., its directedness toward an object. The raw feelings of experience are
known as qualia. Let us discuss the problem of qualia.

The Problem of Qualia:


The qualitative properties of our conscious experience are called ‘qualia’. For
example, when we see a rose in the sunlight; the way it looks to us- the particular,
personal, subjective visual quality of the rose is the quale (singular of “qualia”) of our
visual experience at that moment. What it is like to be sad or happy, to have pain, etc.
also are examples of qualia. According to Shoemaker: Qualia - the qualitative or
phenomenal features of sense experiences, in virtue of having which they resemble
and differ from each other, qualitatively, in the ways they do.1 Thus, qualia are the
properties of experiences what give each of experiences its characteristic “felt
quality” and also what distinguish them from one another. Apart from above simple
definition of qualia some philosophers have defined qualia variously on the basis of
use of the term.

Historically, the term “quale” was first introduced by C. S. Peirce into


philosophy in the context of phenomenal character of experiences.2 The phenomenal
character of an experience is what it is like to have subjectively in the experience. For
example, let’s consider our gustatory experience: there is something it is like for us
subjectively to undergo the experience of tasting a ripe tomato. Now, this experience
will be very different from what it is like for us to experience a ripe mango. This
difference in experiences is often called ‘phenomenal character’. While focusing on
our experience we can figure out that phenomenal character of experiences has
certain qualities, these are accessible by introspection and these together form the
phenomenal character of experiences and known as ‘Qualia’. C. I. Lewis in his
discussion of sense-data theory used the term “qualia” as the properties of sense-data
themselves. His notion of qualia is very close to the contemporary use of the term,

1
Shoemaker, S. (1982). “The Inverted Spectrum”. Journal of Philosophy. Vol. 79, No. 7, p.
367.
2
For detail see Crane, T. (2000). “The Origins of Qualia”, In Tim Crane & Sarah Patterson,
eds., The History of Mind- Body Problem, London: Routledge. <http:/www.timcrane.com>
access September 30, 2020-09-30. P. 14.
183

though Lewis uses it in the context of sense data. According to the Lewis qualia are
introspectible, intrinsic and non- representational features of sense data and other
non-physical objects and these are responsible for their phenomenal character.3 In the
contemporary period, the term has been used in aforesaid sense, though it now refers
more generally to properties of experiences rather than sense-data. Standard examples
of experiences with qualia are perceptual experiences, bodily sensations, emotions,
and moods. The philosophers like Thomas Nagel 4 and Ned Block5 maintain this sense
of qualia. But these interpretations of qualia as phenomenal character of experiences
invoke the controversy: whether qualia, so defined, can be characterized in
intentional, functional or purely cognitive terms. Opponents of qualia, e.g. Dennett,
define the term in a restricted way in order to that qualia are intrinsic properties of
experiences that are ineffable, nonphysical and ‘given’ to their subjects incorrigibly
and thus nonscientific in nature: So, to summarize the tradition qualia are supposed to
be properties of a subject’s mental states that are:

a. Ineffable
b. Intrinsic
c. Private and
d. Directly or immediately apprehensible to consciousness.6

The philosophical question related to qualia is whether it can be or cannot be


explained in scientific terms.

For some aspects of consciousness, it is relatively direct to see how they can
be suit within a physicalist picture. For example, our abilities to access, report on, and
attend to our own mental states. It is reasonable to presuppose that as neuroscience
progresses and we learn more and more about the brain, we will be able to explain

3
For detail see Keeley, B. L. (2009). “The Early History of the Quale and Its Relation to the
Sense”, In J. Symons & P. Calvo, eds., Routledge Companion to Philosophy of psychology,
London: Routledge. pp. 71-89.
4
Nagel, T. (1974). “What Is It Like to Be a Bat?” in Ned Block, Owen Flanagan, and Guven
Guzelder, eds., The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates, A Bradford Book. The
MIT Press: Cambridge. pp. 519-527.
5
Block, N. (1990). “Inverted Earth” in Ned Block, Owen Flanagan, and Guven Guzelder,
eds., The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates, A Bradford Book. The MIT Press:
Cambridge. pp. 677-693.
6
Dennett, D.C. (1997). “Quining Qualia”. in Ned Block,Owen Flanagan, and Guven
Guzelder,eds., The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates. A Bradford Book. The
MIT Press: Cambridge. p. 622
184

these abilities in terms of neural mechanisms. Aspects of consciousness that can be


explained in this way are referred as the easy problems of consciousness by David
Chalmers. But what kind of mechanism could give reasons for qualia? Though we
strongly suspect that the physical system of the brain gives rise to qualia, we do not
have any understanding of how it does so. The problem of accounting for qualia has
thus become known, following Chalmers, as the hard problem of consciousness.7

Explaining Qualia
In this section we will discuss critically various arguments put forth to
explain qualia. We will analyze four arguments such as, knowledge argument,
inverted spectrum argument, absent qualia argument and explanatory gap argument as
follows.
The Knowledge Argument
The knowledge argument is the most popular argument against the
Physicalist explanation of qualia, given by Frank Jackson in his famous paper “What
Marry didn’t know”.8 The fundamental idea lies in the argument is that there is some
knowledge about the experience that can be gained only by having the particular
experience oneself. No physical knowledge of what goes in brain while having that
experience would suffice to know the phenomenal character of the experience.
Jackson presents the hypothetical case of Mary, the super colour scientist, who has
spent her whole life raised in black and white environment in which she learns all the
physical and functional facts about the colour vision. However, she moves outside for
the first time and according to Jackson she learns a new fact: what it is like to see red.
Thus he concludes what it is like to see red cannot be merely a functional or physical
fact.
A wide variety of objections have been raised against the knowledge
argument: Does Mary in fact learn new knowledge? What sort of knowledge does she
acquire? Paul Churchland has raised three objections against Jackson’s claim. First
objection is that the knowledge argument contains the defect of “simplicity itself” and

7
Chalmers, D.J. (1995). “Facing Up to the Problem of Consciousness”. Journal of
Consciousness Studies, Vol. 2, No. 3, p. 201
8
Jackson, F. (1986). “What Mary Didnt Know.” Jpurnal of Philosophy. Vol. 83, No. 5: pp.
291-95.
185

argument carries an equivocation on “knows about”.9 Second objection made by


Churchland is that knowledge argument is an exclusive argument in sense that it
proves too much. So the argument works against both physicalism and
dualism.10Paul’s third objection is that knowledge argument claims that Mary
couldn’t even imagine what the relevant experience would be like, despite her
thorough knowledge about neuroscientific functions, and so must still be missing
certain crucial information.11 David Lewis holds the view that Mary gains know- how
(dispositional abilities), not knowing- that (knowledge of facts or propositions).
Lewis negates the argument and gives the ability analysis, according to this, what
Mary gains after leaving the gray environment is the only new practical abilities to
recognize and imagine and remember the pertinent phenomenal properties of
experiencing red.12 But the ability reply doesn’t seem plausible to many philosophers,
as Van Gulick writes:

...and like many other philosophers I find that claim not very plausible. Part of what
Mary gains is know- how, but that does not seem to be all she gains. There seems to
be a fact about how phenomenal red appears that she apprehends only after her
release.13
Here is a different and more strengthen objection to Jackson is raised by Loar
and also supported by Van Gulick. Loar argues that what Mary acquires when she
experiences red is a new phenomenal concept; a recognitional disposition that let her
to distinguish a certain type of phenomenal feel (acquired discriminative abilities).
This new phenomenal concept is component of veritably new knowledge, which is
the knowledge of what it is like to see red. But this new concept adopts the old
properties which are assigned by physical or functional concepts that she already had.
So, difference is here nothing but ways of knowing: before leaving the room, her
knowledge to see red was of third- person way; after leaving the room, she acquires a

9
Churchland, P. (1985). “Reduction, Qualia, and the Direct Introspection of Brain States”.
The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 82, No. 1: p. 23.
10
Ibid. 24.
11
Ibid. 25.
12
Lewis, D. K. (1983). “Postscript to ‘Mad Pain and Martian Pain’,” Philosphical Papers,
Vol. 1, p. 131.
13
Van Gulick, R. (1997). “Understanding the Phenomenal Mind: Are We All Just
Armadillos? Part I: Phenomenal Knowledge and Explanatory Gaps”. in Ned Block, Owen
Flanagan, and Guven Guzelder,eds., The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates A
Bradford Book. The MIT Press: Cambridge. p. 560.
186

new way (first- person way) of knowing the same fact.14 Conclusively, what she gains
does not eliminate any possible worlds that were not already obviated by the facts
that she already knew, and knowledge argument sets no danger to physical doctrine
of qualia. Eventually, recognitional disposition hints how qualia could come out to be
relational: a relational physical state of the brain or even a functional state.

The Inverted Spectrum


The inverted spectrum argument is based on a thought experiment about two
different people with behaviourally identical (including verbal) but different qualia;
for example, I see ‘red’ the way you see ‘green’. There is the possibility that the brain
state that I have when I see red is the same as the brain state that you have when you
see green, and vice versa. So, it might be said, our experiences are inverted. The
assumption here is a supervenience doctrine that the qualitative content of a state
supervenes on physiological properties of the brain. The possibility of inverted qualia
sometimes objected on the verificationist grounds that we could never know that
anything different is going on, so that there could be no real difference. Chalmers
refuses the objection and says that the nature of qualia is not conceptually tied to
behaviour.15 To reply inverted spectrum Dennett uses intuition pump 4: the
brainstorm machine. In the thought experiment one could report your visual
experiences accurately with the help of some neuroscientific apparatus fits in your
head and feeds your experiences in one’s brain. Eventually we find that no
intersubjective comparison of qualia is possible. As Dennett says:

Designing and building such a device would require that its “fidelity” be tuned or
calibrated by the normalization of the two subjects’ reports- so we would be right
back at our evidential starting point. The moral of this intuition pump is that no
intersubjective comparison of qualia is possible, even with perfect technology.16

14
Loar, B. (1997). “Phenomenal States”. in Ned Block, Owen Flanagan, and Guven Guzelder,
eds., The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates A Bradford Book. The MIT Press:
Cambridge. pp. 597-616. For detailed argument see pp. 598-600.
15
Chalmers, D. J. (1996). The Conscious Mind: in Search of Fundamental Theory, New York
Oxford: Oxford University Press. p. 264.
16
Dennett, D.C. (1997). “Quining Qualia”. in Ned Block, Owen Flanagan, and Guven
Guzelder, eds., The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates. A Bradford Book. The
MIT Press: Cambridge. p. 623.
187

Defenders of inverted spectrum move a step ahead and discuss about


improved version of inverted qualia: intrapersonal inverted spectrum- in this version
the experiences to be compared are all in one mind. Dennett describes this version in
intuition pump 5: the neurosurgical prank. According to this thought experiment, evil
neurophysiologists tampered with your neurons so that you have undergone visual
colour qualia inversion. It has gone like, (1) you have normal colour vision. (2)
Neurophysiologist has inserted colour inverting devices your retinas, now you see the
grass has turned ‘red’ the sky ‘yellow’ and so forth. (3) No one else notices any
colour anomalies, so the problem must be in you. (4) Conclusively you have
undergone visual colour qualia inversion. Dennett attacks on this improved version in
his intuition pump 6: alternative neurosurgery and concludes that intrapersonal,
inverted spectrum is an illusion, since the link to earlier experiences, the link via
memory, is analogous to the imaginary cable that might link two subjects in original
version. Thus, according to Dennett, the result of this series of thought experiment
creates a paradox of qualia: if there are qualia they are less accessible to our
cognizance than we thought. Not only are the classical intersubjective comparisons
impossible, but we can’t say anything in our own cases whether our qualia have
inverted (intrapersonal inversion); even not by introspection.17

Absent Qualia Argument


The absent qualia argument states that mental state can be type-individuated
on the basis of the causal functional relation they bear to each other and to the inputs
and outputs of the relevant system. Michael Tye characterizes the absent qualia:

The hypothesis that it could be the case that a system that functionally duplicates the
mental states of a normal human being has no phenomenal consciousness (qualia).18
Absent qualia argument establishes that any system could instantiate the
functional state of any mental phenomena, for example- pain, without having any
pain qualia. Ned Block initiated this objection to functionalism with the thought
experiment of the homunculi- headed robot. This thought experiment appeals to
oddball realization of our functional organization by huge human-duplicates (artificial

17
Ibid. 624.
18
Tye, M. (2006). “Absent Qualia and the Mind-Body Problem”. philosophical Review. Vol.
115, No. 2. p. 140.
188

brainless robot). If this China- body system can share our functional organization,
then our functional organization cannot be sufficient for qualia.19 Many critics face
the difficulty to reply to case like China- body system and say that China- body
system could undergo qualia. According to functionalist like the oddness of this view
comes from our relative size. We are each so much smaller than the China-body
system that we are unable to get a general understanding of whole system. Just like a
creature the size of a neuron trapped inside a human head might well be wrongly
persuaded that there couldn’t be consciousness, so we also wrongly conclude as we
contemplate the China-body system.

The Explanatory Gap Argument


The underlying idea of the argument is that neither anything known about
brain nor anything for anyone has been imaginable that would explain the qualia. The
basic assumption of the argument aims to show unintelligibility of materialism in
respect to explain the phenomenal aspect of mind such as qualia, rather than proving
materialism false. According to Robert Van Gulick explanatory gap argument’s
strength derives from the above intuitive appeal of its conclusion.20 Despite of
agreement on the issue that the gap is unclosable difference in attitudes towards the
argument can be seen in philosophers (some has positive views and others have
negative explanation). Colin McGinn argues that the essential nature of consciousness
is not accessible to humans’ cognitive capacities so the gap is unclosable:

The problem arises, I want to suggest, because we are cut off by our very cognitive
constitution from achieving a conception of that natural property of the brain (or of
consciousness) that accounts for the psychophysical link. this is a kind of causal
nexus that we are preclude from ever understanding, given the way we have to form
our concepts and develop theories. No wonder we find the problem so difficult!21

19
Block, N. (1978), “Troubles with Functionalism.”, In David Chalmers, Philosophy of Mind:
Classical and Contemporary Readings. New York Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002. pp.
94-98.
20
Van Gulick, R. (1997), “Understanding the Phenomenal Mind: Are We All Just Armadillos?
Part I: Phenomenal Knowledge and Explanatory Gaps”. In Ned Block, Owen Flanagan, and
Guven Guzelde, eds., The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates A Bradford Book.
The MIT Press: Cambridge. p. 563.
21
McGinn, C. (1991). The Problem of Consciousness: Essays Towards a Resolution. Basil
Blackwell Inc. p. 2
189

Joseph Levine holds the view that psychophysical statements assert such
crude fact identities that those are unintelligible and they leave an explanatory gap
that we have no idea how to fill.22 Following the John Locke’s seventeenth- century’s
approved claim that sensory qualia are arbitrary,23 Levine attempts to support his
point by appeal to a standard philosophical case of hypothetical spectrum inversion
with red and green qualia switching causal roles in an otherwise normal subject. He
concludes that the important suggestion here is that the basic ideas, such as colour
qualia are simples. They have no structure and as each one is what it is sui generis, it
is hard to see how their connection to anything could fail to be anything but
arbitrary.24 On the basis of aforesaid suggestion Gulick reconstruct a deductive
argument form of the gap argument for consideration:

Since qualia such as phenomenal hues are basic simples; they have no structure.
Therefore: 1. Any links between such qualia and the organizational structure of their
neural substrates must be arbitrary. 2. The links between qualia and their neural bases
are unintelligible and present us with an unfillable explanatory gap.25
On the basis of this formulation of argument Larry Hardin replies that we
must reject first premise of given argument. Hardin says phenomenal hues are not in
fact such as sui generis simples, but rather elements within a highly organized and
structured colour space. Any attempt to invert them in undetectable ways would have
to preserve that structural organization. Moreover, the junction of organized structure
among colour qualia renders the basis for establishing explanatory connections
between them and their neural substrates.26

A number of philosophers argue that the unclosibility of the gap has nothing
to do with nature itself, but it has to do with our concepts. They have contributed to

22
Levine, J. (1983). “Materialism and Qualia: The Explanatory Gap”. Pacific Philosophical
Quarterly, p. 357.
23
Locke, (1690) An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed., Yolton, Everyman’s
Library, 1971, Bk. II, Ch. VIII, sec. 13, and Bk. IV, Ch. III. Secs. 12 and 13.
24
Levine, J. (1983). “Materialism and Qualia: The Explanatory Gap”. Pacific Philosophical
Quarterly, p. 357 & 358.
25
Van Gulick, R. (1997). “Understanding the Phenomenal Mind: Are We All Just
Armadillos? Part I: Phenomenal Knowledge and Explanatory Gaps”. in Ned Block, Owen
Flanagan, and Guven Guzelder, eds., The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates, A
Bradford Book. The MIT Press: Cambridge. p. 564.
26
Hardin, C. L. (1988). Color for Philosophers, Hackett Publishers, Indianapolis, In. pp. 134-
42.
190

produce the idea that reductive explanation in science depends on a priori analyses of
the phenomena to be explained, ordinarily in functional terms. For consideration
Chalmers gives the example of reductive explanation of life: life can be roughly
analyzed in terms of such general terms as metabolism and adaption or in specific
concepts like digestion and reproduction, and these concepts can themselves be given
a functional analysis.27 According to Chalmers to explain these functions, a priori, is
to explain life itself. But in some case, for example water, the a priori analysis
becomes more complicated. We can’t give an a priori analysis of water as colourless,
odourless liquid in rivers and ponds called ‘water’, because water might have colour
and odour, there might have not been ponds etc. but we can formulate an a priori
reference fixing definition of the sort that Kripke has underlined: Water = R (the
colourless, odourless liquid in rivers and lakes called ‘water’), where ‘R’ is a rigid
operator that turns a definite description into a rigid designator.28 (A rigid designator
takes the same thing in all possible worlds in which the thing exists.) The
consequence is that closing the gap requires an a priori functional analysis of qualia.
But if we choose qualia by their qualitative character then no a priori reference fixing
definition can be given for the qualitative concepts of the sort that can be given for
‘life’ and ‘water’. For example, pain= R can be true and necessary without being a
priori. And if the qualia inversion argument is right, there is no a priori conceptual
analysis of qualitative concepts either, and so the explanatory gap is enclosable. As
Chalmers points out that functional and physical account can explain only the
functions associated with qualia. But there will be curiosity remain that why these
functions are accompanied by qualia.

Conclusion
After a review of above arguments about qualia we can conclude that qualia
still remain as the most baffling feature of consciousness. Knowledge argument
creates the explanatory elusiveness of phenomenal qualities against the materialism,
but despite of being appealing it fails to maintain it standpoint clearly and it falls out

27
Chalmers, D.J. (1995). “Facing Up to the Problem of Consciousness”. Journal of
Consciousness Studies, Vol. 2, No. 3, p. 203.
28
Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and Necessity, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
191

to be weak in a wide variety of ways, so it couldn’t defend itself from opponents.


Likewise, the inverted spectrum and the absent qualia argument also fails in
providing an inevitably insurmountable hurdle to functionalist doctrine. Talking
about the explanatory gap we can conclude that it compels us to think that science of
mind has not yet generates the required concepts to explain qualia. But the
reductionists deny this, blaming the explanatory gap on our ordinary concepts, not on
science. The opponents of qualia try to define qualia objectively but fail to explain
qualia adequately. Neither they give it’s any functional or scientific explanation
correctly nor they get success to eliminate it. On the other hand, we can’t say that
proponents of qualia achieve their goal of explaining qualia accurately. So, in case of
explaining qualia we are still at the same position where we start from. The quale is
significant because as it is the properties of experience and these are the experiences
which make a person an individual and separate human from other creatures and
robots. Just because of qualia we can know ‘what it is like to be a human’.

You might also like