Homework 3
Homework 3
Benjamin Harter
April 2024
1 Problems
1. Investigating the statement seems to indicate P is true:
(i) ¬P → P
(ii) ¬P ∨ ¬P (conditional law)
(iii) ¬P (idempotent law)
(iv) P (¬P → P )
This can also be reasoned quickly. Since a statement is true whenever its
consequent is true, P → Q must be true whenever P is true. Since the
antecedent is the negative of the consequent by definition, it cannot be
true while the consequent is true. As a result, the statement is true if and
only if P is true.
2. Breaking down the statement yields:
(i) (P → Q) → P
(ii) (P ∨ ¬Q) ∨ ¬P (conditional law)
(iii) P ∨ ¬Q ∨ ¬P (associative law)
(iv) P ∨ ¬P ∨ ¬Q (commutative law)
(v) T ∨ ¬Q (tautology)
Since the statement is a tautology, it is true by definition. But the state-
ment does not obviously necessitate that P is true. Even with the original
statement taken as true, if P → Q is not true, then P may not be true.
Here is the truth table:
P Q P → Q (P → Q) → P )
T T T T
T F F T
F T T F
F F T F
Since P → Q and P are only true when the other is true, and false when
the other is false, showing that if (P → Q) → P is true, then P is true.
1
3. Let A(x) mean “x ∈ A”, and B(x) mean “x ∈ B”, and so on. Assuming
A \ B ⊆ C ∩ D is true, then:
From here we see that the statement has two conditions: A(x) and ¬B(x)∨
¬(C(x) ∨ ¬D(x)). Looking only at the second condition:
6. Let’s start with a seemingly true statement by the definition of the set:
“If R is in R, R is not in R.” Since R contains itself, it is not an element
of itself, and so doesn’t contain itself. This is a paradox: no matter what
condition R is in concerning if it can contain itself, that condition indicates
that the opposite condition should be true.
Assuming R ∈ R, we can state this as:
2
This seems to indicate that R(R) → ¬R(R) is a tautology.
Let’s assume R ∈
/ R: