Division of Labour
Division of Labour
Division of Labour
That is, society is organized collectively and all members of the group share the
same beliefs. The bond that binds the individual to society is this collective
conscious, this shared belief system.
With organic solidarity, on the other hand, society is a system of different
functions that are united by definite relationships. Each individual must have a
distinct job or action and a personality that is his or her own. Individuality
grows as parts of society grow. Thus, society becomes more efficient at moving
in sync, yet at the same time, each of its parts has more movements that are
distinctly its own.
The members of that society are more likely to resemble each other and share
the same beliefs and morals. As societies becomes more advanced and civilized,
the individual members of those societies start to become more unique and
distinguishable from each other. Solidarity becomes more organic as these
societies develop their divisions of labor.
Durkheim also discusses law extensively in this book. To him, law is the most
visible symbol of social solidarity and the organization of social life in its most
precise and stable form. Law plays a part in society that is analogous to the
nervous system in organisms, according to Durkheim. The nervous
system regulates various body functions so they work together in harmony.
Likewise, the legal system regulates all the parts of society so that they work
together in agreement.
Two types of law exist and each corresponds to a type of social solidarity. The
first type of law, repressive law, imposes some type of punishment on the
perpetrator. Repressive law corresponds to the ‘center of common
consciousness’ and tends to stay diffused throughout society. Repressive law
corresponds to the mechanical state of society.
The second type of law is restitutive law, which does not necessarily imply any
suffering on the part of the perpetrator, but rather tries to restore the
relationships that were disturbed from their normal form by the crime that
occurred. Restitutive law corresponds to the organic state of society and works
through the more specialized bodies of society, such as the courts and lawyers.
This also means that repressive law and restitutory law vary directly with the
degree of a society’s development. Repressive law is common in primitive, or
mechanical, societies where sanctions for crimes are typically made across the
whole community. In these lower societies, crimes against the individual are
common, yet placed on the lower end of the penal ladder. Crimes against the
community take priority because the evolution of the collective conscious is
widespread and strong while the division of labor has not yet happened. The
more a society becomes civilized and the division of labor is introduced, the
more restitutory law takes place.
According to Giddens (p. 73), the main substantive problem for Durkheim
stems from "an apparent moral ambiguity concerning the relationship between
the individual and society in the contemporary world." On the one hand, with
specialization and the highly developed division of labour, individuals develop
their own consciousness, and are encouraged in this specialization. On the other
hand, there are also moral ideas encouraging people to be well rounded, of
service to society as a whole. These two seem contradictory, and Durkheim is
concerned with finding the historical and sociological roots of each of these,
along with how these two seemingly contradictory moral guidelines are
reconciled in modern society.
This book can also be read with a view to illuminating Durkheim's methods. In
the first chapter, he outlines his method, and the theory which could be falsified.
By looking at morality, he is not pursuing a philosophical course, mainly in the
realm of ideas. Durkheim is critical of "moral philosophers [who] begin either
from some a priori postulate about the essential characteristics of human nature,
or from propositions taken from psychology, and thence proceed by deduction
to work out a scheme of ethics." (Giddens, p. 72). That is, Durkheim is
attempting to determine the roots of morality by studying society, and changes
in society. These forms of morality are social facts, and data from society must
be obtained, and these used to discover causes. The data used by Durkheim are
observable, empirical forms of data in the form of laws, institutions (legal and
other), norms and behaviour. In this book, Durkheim adopts a non-quantitative
approach, but in Suicide his approach is more quantitative.
In these early societies, Durkheim argues that legal codes or the system of law
tends to be repressive law or penal law. If there is a crime in this society,
then this crime stands as an offense to all, because it is an offense to the
common morality, the shared system of values that exists. Most people feel
the offense, and regardless of how serious it is, severe punishment is likely to be
meted out for it. Zeitlin notes (p. 264):
Some of the following quotes from The Division of Labor in Society show the
nature of Durkheim's argument: In the quotes, note that the act is criminal
because the act offends the collective conscience. For Durkheim, the
collective consciousness reaches all parts of society, has a distinct reality and is
independent of individual conditions, and is passed on from one generation to
the next. In this, it differs from particular or individual consciences. (Division,
pp. 79-80).
the innocent, his wife, his children, his neighbours, etc. This is
because the passion which is the soul of punishment ceases only
when exhausted. If, therefore, after it has destroyed the one who
has immediately called it forth, there still remains force within it, it
expands in quite mechanical fashion. (Division, p. 86).
In contrast, modern legal codes are quite different, with punishment being less
important. Instead, society is concerned with restoration of the original
situation, rather than exacting revenge on the offender. "But today, it is said,
punishment has changed it character; it is no longer to avenge itself that society
punishes, it is to defend itself." (Division, p. 86).
This distinction between different types of legal codes and punishment may
provide a means of noting what mechanical solidarity means.
These quotes show how the collective consciousness works in societies without
a highly developed division of labour. The primary function of punishment,
therefore, is to protect and reaffirm the conscience collective in the face of acts
which question its sanctity. In order to carry this out, such societies develop
forms of repressive or penal law.
While the common values in these societies can change over time, this process
of change is generally quite slow, so that these values are generally appropriate
for the historical period in question. At other times, the laws may be
inappropriate, and might be maintained only through force. However, Durkheim
generally considers this to be an exceptional circumstance, and one that is
overcome.
2. Organic Solidarity
With the development of the division of labour, the collective consciousness
begins to decline. Each individual begins to have a separate set of tasks which
he or she is engaged in. These different situations lead to quite a different set of
experiences for each individual. This set of experiences tends to lead toward "a
‘personal consciousness,’ with an emphasis on individual distinctiveness."
(Grabb, p.81). The common situation which created the common collective
consciousness is disturbed, and individuals no longer have common
experiences, but have a great variety of different settings, each leading towards
its own consciousness.
Thus Durkheim argues that there are individual, and probably group,
differences, at the same time as there is a new form of social solidarity.
Durkheim speaks of the centripetal and centrifugal forces, and draws an organic
analogy:
As the division of labour develops, people do not have the same consciousness,
so that the form of law must change. "The very existence of restitutive law, in
fact, presupposes the prevalence of a differentiated division of labour, since it
covers the rights of individuals either over private property, or over other
individuals who are in a different social position from themselves." (Giddens, p.
76) Along with this could come Weber's rational law, perhaps much the same as
Durkheim's restitutive law. Systematic codes governing exchange and contracts
are necessary, but these are the result of the general acceptance of individual
rights within the system of a division of labour.
But this moral relationship can only produce its effect if the real distance
between individuals has itself diminished in some way. Durkheim refers to this
an increasing density. Moral density cannot grow unless material density grows
at the same time. The two are inseparable though. Three ways in which this
happens are:
ii. Cities. Formation of cities and their development. "Cities always result from
the need of individuals to put themselves in very intimate contact with others.
They are so many points where the social mass is contracted more strongly than
elsewhere. They can multiply and extend only if the moral density is raised."
(Division, p. 258).
The division of labor varies in direct ratio with the volume and
density of societies, and, if it progresses in a continuous manner in
the course of social development, it is because societies become
regularly denser and generally more voluminous. (Division, 262).
As a result of this greater contact, the "struggle for existence becomes more
acute" and this results in the development of the division of labour. If needs are
the same, then there is always a struggle for existence. But where different
interests can be pursued, then there may be room for all. Quote 8:
Social Structure (2nd part) In the same city, different occupations
can co-exist without being obliged mutually to destroy one another,
for they pursue different objects. ... Each of them can attain his end
without preventing the others from attaining theirs.
For Durkheim the result of the division of labour is positive in that there is no
need to compete in the sense of struggling just to survive. Rather, the division of
labour may signify that there are sufficient material resources for all in society,
and this division allows a certain form of co-operation. Quote 9:
Durkheim thus sets out an analysis of the division of labour which emphasizes
the special functions of each of type of occupation and endeavour. The
biological model, with a well functioning body, where each organ properly
serves it function seems to be uppermost in Durkheim's mind. Unlike some of
the structural functionalists, Durkheim's method distinguishes the cause of the
function from the actual function filled. That is, Durkheim observes the function
that the occupation fills in society, but attempts to investigate the development
of the cause in an historical manner, examining how this function emerged. In
this, one can consider there to be a certain "conflict as a mechanism, within a
quasi-Darwinian framework, which accelerates the progression of the division
of labour." (Giddens, p. 79).
Durkheim is also providing a criticism of the economic models which argue that
people with different specialties come together to trade the products of their
specialties. For Durkheim, specialties are not natural in any sense, but are
developed. Similarly, the division of labour is not natural either, but develops in
different forms in different societies. While there may be a great similarity
among these (perhaps like Weber's rationality), national differences emerge. In
that sense, Durkheim has an historical model, fairly solidly grounded on the
material realities.
a. Anomic Division of Labor. When there are industrial and commercial crises,
there may be a partial break in organic solidarity. Also, where there is conflict
between capital and labour, this may be an unusual situation. Part of this is
caused by the increased separation of employee and employer under capitalism
(Division, p. 354), so that the conditions for a lack of solidarity are expanded as
capitalism and the division of labour develop.
Irregular forms such as crime are not treated as part of the breakdown, rather
these are treated by Durkheim as differentiation (Division, p. 353), not part of
division of labour. Durkheim compares these with cancer, rather than with
normal organs.
If the division of labour does not produce solidarity in all these cases, it is
because the relations of the organs are not regulated, because they are in a state
of anomy. For the individual this means there are not sufficient moral
constraints and individuals do not have a clear concept of what is proper and
acceptable. (Ritzer, p. 85). See Appendix quote 10:
Durkheim also discusses conditions of the worker under capitalism in terms that
come very close to Marx's description of alienation and exploitation. He
discusses the degrading nature of the division of labour on the worker, the
possibility of monotonous routine, and the machine like actions of the worker.
(Division, p. 371). However, Durkheim does not consider these to be the normal
form, but one which results when the worker does not have a sufficient vision of
the whole process of production.
Of course, wealth interferes with this, but Durkheim views this as abnormal and
not the normal tendency.
even this last inequality, which comes about through birth, though
not completely disappearing, is at least somewhat attenuated.
Society is forced to reduce this disparity as far as possible by
assisting in various ways those who find themselves in a
disadvantageous position and by aiding them to overcome it."
(Division, p. 379).
One solution for regulation that Durkheim discusses is the state. In some senses,
Durkheim was a socialist, although not of the same type as Marx. Ritzer notes
that for Durkheim, socialism "simply represented a system in which moral
principles discovered by scientific sociology could be applied." (Ritzer, p. 73).
While the principles of morality had to be present in society, the state could
embody these in structures, fulfilling functions such as justice, education,
health, social services, etc., and managing a wide range of sectors of society
(Grabb, p. 87).
The state "should also be the key structure for ensuring that these rules are
moral and just. The appropriate values of individualism, responsibility, fair
play, and mutual obligation can be affirmed through the policies instituted by
the state in all these fields." (Grabb, p. 87).
The second major hope that Durkheim held was for what he called occupational
groups. The state could not be expected to play the integrative role that might be
needed, because it was too remote. As a solution, Durkheim thought that
occupational or professional groups could provide the means of integration
required. These would be formed by people in an industry, representing all the
people in this sector. Their role would be somewhat different from Weber's
parties, in that they would not be concerned with exercising power, and
achieving their own ends. Instead, they would "foster the general interest of
society at a level that most citizens can understand and accept." (Grabb, p. 88).
References
Durkheim, Emile, The Division of Labor in Society, New York, The Free
Press, 1933. Referred to in notes as Division. HD 51 D98
Aleem Akhtar.