GORAKv 3
GORAKv 3
GORAKv 3
held, bottoms out in perception. Such knowledge can be transmitted to others through
testimony, preserved by memory, and amplified via inference. But there would be no
such knowledge in the first place without perception; it is where the rubber hits the
road. What about aesthetic knowledge? Does it too bottom out in perception? Is it
those very perceptual states that ultimately justify our empirical beliefs that also ground
aesthetic knowledge? Most say “yes”; we will call them Perceptualists.1 But
perception, where the rubber hits the road. Aesthetic knowledge, we argue, derives
1
This view is so ubiquitous that it is often regarded as a “truism” (Livingston 2003) or
Among the many Perceptualists, see Walton (1970) and (1993), Tormey (1973), Stokes
(2014) and (2018), as well as Hopkins (2006) and Lord (2019), both of whom we discuss
below.
2
Goffin (2018) also argues for a version of Affectivism but is blocked from the proper
account of aesthetic knowledge by his failure to identify the rational structure of the
emotions.
1
The virtues of Affectivism will be demonstrated in its solution to a thorny
problem that has bedeviled aesthetic epistemologists: how to reconcile the seemingly
direct character of aesthetic knowledge with the way we acquire knowledge from
criticism. One learns from criticism, we argue, when it guides one’s engagement with an
object so that one can appreciate it in virtue of those of its features that render it worthy
of appreciation; that is, when this affective guidance happens in virtue of criticism’s
their respective domains, a fact that helps to explain the appeal of Perceptualism. Using
(what we call) the Paradox of Aesthetic Criticism as our lodestar, we will show that
the long tradition—dating back to at least the 18th century—of thinking about aesthetic
knowledge as perceptual in a broader sense.3 Those 18th-century thinkers who held that
aesthetic knowledge is a matter of feeling called this knowledge aesthetic because they
regarded knowledge acquired from feeling as experiential and direct. This is precisely
3
More recently, James Shelley describes himself as a ‘Perceptualist’, but unlike those we
call Perceptualists in this paper, he also uses the term in the broader sense (see his
2003, 2004). Similarly, though in a different context, when McDowell (1978) argues
that one can perceive moral requirements, he too employs a broad sense of ‘perceptual’,
one on which a perceptual state can be (indivisibly) both receptive and conative.
2
narrow sense, and so as excluding the conative and the affective. We use the term
‘perception’ and its cognates to refer to these non-affective and non-conative receptive
states. On the view we will defend, primary aesthetically knowledge (as we will call it) is
deny that one can possess aesthetic knowledge in virtue of a justified belief. But such
Perceptualists take themselves to be heirs to the 18th-century tradition, but we claim this
The Paradox of Aesthetic Criticism (as we call it) involves a tension between the
and the (apparent) epistemic function of criticism on the other.4 Aesthetic knowledge is
widely held to be direct: it arises from an experience of the object, but not by way of any
rational transition from such experience. 5 But knowledge that arises from critical
instruction would seem to be derived via reflection from a critical text. Thus, it cannot
be a matter of one’s immediate response to the aesthetic object. To resolve the Paradox,
4
See Hopkins (2006) and Lord (2019) for extensive discussion.
5
See Livingston (2003), Schellekens and Goldie (2008), and Schellekens (2019). For
disagreement, see Dorsch (2013). The underlying intuition has been defended under a
variety of headings, e.g., in terms of principles such as Autonomy (e.g., Hopkins (2001)
and Nguyen (2020)) and Acquaintance (e.g., Wollheim (1980:3) and Tormey (1973)).
3
one must articulate the immediacy of the knowledge afforded by aesthetic experience in
a manner consistent with the power of good criticism to instruct. We formulate the
Paradox as follows:
knowledge.
In this section, we will diagnose the failure of two prominent approaches to the
aesthetic knowledge. To see the basic difficulty, we’ll discuss the tension between
Directness raises a serious challenge for any account of criticism for two closely
related reasons. First, critics do not pronounce mere verdicts about the excellence of the
relevant works, but explain how these works are excellent (or not) and why they are
excellent (or not) in the ways that they are. They point to those aspects of the works that
not only explain what led them (the critics) to respond to these works a certain way but
also justify these responses as correct. Critical discussions, in other words, invoke what
paradigm case, the critics, in giving the reasons that support their responses, articulate
their aesthetic knowledge of the works. This is what leads virtually everyone writing on
criticism in recent years to agree that criticism is a “rational activity” (Hopkins 2003:
4
137) or a “rational enterprise” (Lord, 2019:810). At the very least, the idea that criticism
worthy of preservation and explanation. Yet according to Directness, one does not
acquire aesthetic knowledge via deduction from premises. And so the reasoning one
finds in aesthetic criticism cannot be inferential reasoning, in which one arrives at the
reasoning appears to be the source of the critic’s aesthetic knowledge, but also insofar as
it seems to be the source of the reader’s aesthetic knowledge. Criticism is, after all, not
the audience. Critics do not simply express aesthetic reasons but communicate these
reasons as reasons for their audience to respond in similar ways. Furthermore, critical
justified belief that the aesthetic object has certain properties. A critic shows her
audience how and why to respond directly to the relevant works in the way that she
does. But wait: how can taking in the critic’s remarks be the source of direct knowledge
of the absent artwork? The very idea would seem to be incoherent. If audiences arrive
at knowledge via criticism, they must arrive at it indirectly, mediated by the argument
and testimony of the critic. Hence the conflict between Directness and Criticism.
Philosophers who defend Directness from apparent conflict with Criticism often
try to point to a special mode of rationality, one that shapes direct experience. They
hope to explain thereby the reasoning that underlies critics’ aesthetic knowledge and
guides their readers’ aesthetic knowledge. And this is the right impulse. But those
taking this route have heretofore assumed that the relevant direct experience is
5
perception (Hopkins 2006: 137 ff., Lord 2019: 810ff). The resulting conception of
Errol Lord and Robert Hopkins have each defended a version of Perceptualism.
either deny that aesthetic reasons operate via the subject’s responsiveness to them or
locate rational responsiveness inside the act of perception itself. Lord is impaled on the
first horn, which misrepresents rationality, while Hopkins is impaled on the second,
which misrepresents perception. In the rest of this section, we explain their errors, and
in section four, after putting on the table the Affective View, demonstrate that the
dilemma is false.
the paradigmatic rational act, is mirrored by the justificatory relation between low-level
contents of perception—what can be simply seen, as one might put it—and high-level
he puts it: “the justification one gets from an aesthetic perception is dependent on one’s
justification to believe that the object has various features that indicate or ground the
aesthetic features” (Lord, 2019: 830). What distinguishes this form of rationality from
inference is partly that a subject, who, to use Lord’s example, believes that Olympia is
intense on the basis of seeing the painting, need have no inkling of the justificatory
connection between the perception of the lower-level properties and the perception of
intensity:
6
…[the] justificatory power of his perception of the intensity is
View does not predict that Alexander infers that the painting is intense
The job of the critic, on Lord’s view, is then to point out precisely those lower-
When all goes well, one ends up with justified judgments that are
features in just the right way, the critic both elucidates the structure of
her justification and points the consumer towards the features one
needs to process in order to see the aesthetic features for oneself. This, I
7
the normative order grasp of which culminates in the relevant belief. It is, for example,
precisely my grasp of the fact that the butler has an alibi together with the inferential
significance of this fact that leads me to believe that the butler is innocent. If I do not
grasp the rational connection between his having an alibi and his innocence, and do not
believe that he is innocent because I grasp this connection, then I do not believe that he
is innocent for the reason that he has an alibi. Paul Boghossian calls this
Lord would reject an analogous condition on aesthetic rationality for, on his view,
one appreciates aesthetically even if one does not grasp the rational connection between
one’s appreciation and the ground of it—in his terms, between the higher-level and the
lower-level features:
I am not claiming that one needs to have ex-post justified beliefs about the
The experiencing subject, he argues, need not even “believe the claims about” (ibid.) the
justifying features, let alone be conscious about the justificatory relation between these
and the relevant aesthetic judgment. As such, the perception of the higher-level content
6
Boghossian (2014), 5. This condition is first discussed in Longino (1978).
8
does not manifest the sort of rational sensitivity to justification that is the hallmark of
genuine rationality: it fails to meet the Taking Condition. This is not by itself an
objection to Lord’s theory of the relation between lower-level percepti0n and aesthetic
perception. It is rather an objection to Lord’s claim that this relation is rational, and to
his subsequent claim that critics, in virtue of making this relation explicit, are making
Lord might respond by pointing out that nothing precludes him from adopting
the thesis that the aesthetic judgment that the painting is intense is based on the
perception of the relevant lower-level features in the fulsome sense suggested by the
Taking Condition. His claim is just that the perception that the painting is intense is not
But part of his stated aim is to elucidate the nature of aesthetic justification, the sort of
thing that critics make explicit. If Lord were to concede that critical judgments
incorporate a kind of basing, he would thereby have admitted that the Enrichment
account does not do the job that it is supposed to do. Perceptualism itself would have no
perception itself does contain something like an inference, in which case he would
impale himself on the Hopkins horn of the dilemma. Barring horn-switching, the
burden of resolving the Paradox would have been shifted to the theory that elucidates
7
Lord seems to think Taking leads to regress (see Lord forthcoming, 5), but that’s not
9
Lord is more naturally positioned simply to reject the idea that aesthetic
justification requires this more demanding sort of rational responsiveness. After all, he
holds that the Enrichment view is correct about other domains of higher-level
perception and would argue that this provides a good reason to extend it to the aesthetic
realm. Why think that aesthetic judgment requires anything like basing, rather than a
the observation that there are plenty of kinds of epistemic dependence that do not
require any such thing. For example, my justification for believing that I have lived my
entire life on Earth is dependent on my not being a brain in a vat on Venus, but this
However, this rejoinder will not work. To see why, note first that the more
demanding requirement holds not only of the relation between premises and
conclusions of inference but also of the relation between the objects of the emotions and
the emotions themselves. Consider, e.g., Kaito, who is angry at his mother. We ask why
he is angry. Among those answers we would accept, some satisfy by giving an ordinary
causal explanation, e.g., he’s angry at his mother because he only slept for two hours last
night. This answer gives an explanation that does not depend on his knowledge of the
explanandum, i.e., of his recognizing that his sleep deficit contributes to his anger. The
relation between Kaito’s insomnia and his anger figures nowhere in Kaito’s experience,
and so, per (the affective analogue to) Taking, it cannot be part of the rational
explanation of his anger. Now consider the following explanation: Kaito is angry at her
because she singed his toast. This answer is not compatible with his being oblivious to
its being singed. Insofar as the toast being singed rationally explains his anger, this fact
is what he is angry about. And to have singed toast as the object of one’s anger is to view
10
the toast’s being singed as a reason to be angry at the one responsible. Kaito’s anger is
rationally explained by the toast being singed only insofar as he experiences his anger as
warranted by that very fact. It is not enough that the toast’s being singed confers upon
him ex-ante justification for being angry at his mother. Were he oblivious to its being
singed, if this did not figure in his experience, it could not be what he is actually angry
about, but only what he would be justified in being angry about in the event that he
learns of it.
The relation between aesthetic judgment and its grounds has the same structure:
to say that someone finds a work beautiful because R, where this is a rational
explanation, is to say that R is something that this person likes about the work. It is not
enough that the work’s being R confers upon her ex-ante justification for finding it
beautiful. For that by itself does not secure that R is what she actually likes about it.
Nor is it enough that she was led to find it beautiful by having R pointed out to her. So
long as she does not experience the beauty of the work as based on R, it is not what she
likes about it and so cannot rationally explain her appreciation. To secure that, she
must experience R as contributing to the beauty of the relevant work. For that reason,
Alexander (in Lord’s example) can’t judge the painting to be intense because (in the
does not experience the facial expression as contributing to the painting’s intensity.
It might be objected that, even if it’s not precisely like rationality in other
domains, it is close enough. And indeed, if this were the closest we could come to
genuine rationality in the aesthetic realm, we could console ourselves with the ersatz
rationality that Lord offers us. But the genuine article is, as we shall see, very much a
11
Importantly, neither Taking nor its analogues require that the subject be able to
articulate either the reason for her judgment or its rational significance. We suspect
that a confusion about this is behind Lord’s thought that it would “require too much” for
seeing the painting as intense because of the facial expressions that one has “ex-post
justification about the facial expressions” (829). He means to respect the fact that we
are often incapable of articulating why we love the works we do. This is true and
important. But there is much that figures in one’s experience and which is thus eligible
fact, it is, we would argue, crucial to a proper account of aesthetic criticism that it allow
for precisely this possibility. It is a common phenomenon that one goes to see a film
and is troubled by something but can’t say exactly what it is. One may then read various
reviews that specify something troubling about the film. About some, one says “nope,
that’s not it.” Finally, one reads the piece that illuminates what troubles one. “That’s it!”
No one else is in a position to say this, since what troubles one is not part of anyone
else’s experience. This is what we mean by saying that the rational significance of one’s
aesthetic reasons must be part of one’s experience. Otherwise, one would not be in a
and what lends support to it. But still, the connection must have an inchoate presence
in her mental life. Otherwise, she does not believe, act, or feel/appreciate for that
reason.
criticism. Criticism, according to Lord, points to what makes an artwork beautiful (or
12
intense or…) and makes explicit the critic’s justification for making the aesthetic
conclusion. That is, seeing the daintiness moves one to see the
of the daintiness.8
Hopkins’s inclusion of the “argument” inside perception shows that, unlike Lord, he
rational, rather than a matter of “mere causal connections” (Hopkins 2003:152). But he
The core difficulty is connected to the mismatch between perception and the
rational basing relation, one that we will explore more fully below. Hopkins models the
8
Hopkins (2006): 150
9
Grant (2013) also seems to recognize this requirement, at least in the context of
criticism and appreciation. But this insight is spoiled by his non-affective picture of
appreciation. For more on his view, see Gorodeisky (2021b).
.
13
By getting you to see these things, and to see them as organized in these
ways, I bring you, if I’m successful, to see the deer. But the subsidiary
deer involves, and does not merely require as a causal condition, seeing
the two patches near the flower as part of the flank, or seeing the
Seeing the deer as a whole, we agree, depends on seeing the patches as ears. But
whatever else must be said to distinguish it from a mere causal condition—and we have
responsiveness. Why not? Because you do not see the deer in virtue of taking seeing its
ears to be showing that one should see the whole as the deer, that is, as warranting or
meriting the latter. Rather, you cause yourself to see the deer by trying to see its ears
near the flower, etc. Perhaps you also believe you should see the deer, in the sense that
you believe a properly functioning visual system serves up a deer in these circumstances.
And perhaps it is because you believe this that you try so hard and eventually succeed in
seeing the deer. But this still does not amount to seeing the deer precisely insofar as one
views seeing it as what one should see in seeing the ears; one does not take seeing the
ears as warranting seeing the dear. Yet this is how it is with rational responsiveness in
general and aesthetic responsiveness in particular. One appreciates the excellence of the
Souvenir precisely insofar as one appreciates its being moving, where the relation of the
latter appreciation to the former appreciation is constituted by one’s recognition that its
being moving makes the film (or helps to make it) excellent. In this case, one takes the
14
film’s being moving as warranting and meriting the appreciation of the film as
normative-explanatory nexus. Perception does not comprise such a nexus and thus
does not reflect the rationality of aesthetic experience and criticism. Accordingly, Lords’
and Hopkins’ positions reflect the Perceptualist’s dilemma: in order to accommodate the
rationality of criticism, they must either misrepresent the nature of aesthetic rationality
character of aesthetic knowledge and the rationality of criticism. It’s time to introduce
this view of aesthetic knowledge and defend it. We will do so in two steps: first, in the
next section, we distinguish feeling from perception and characterize the distinctive
character of affective knowledge. In section III, we then show that, given the character
appreciation that shows how it incorporates the sort of rational responsiveness that
Lord eschews and Hopkins mislocates. Equipped with this understanding of aesthetic
knowledge, we will return, in section IV, to the Paradox of Criticism, proving Affectivism
15
II. Perception and Feeling
differing from other sorts of knowledge only in its topic: the aesthetic properties of
objects, rather than, say, their color properties or their atomic properties. There are
many ways of construing this thesis, some of which would no doubt be perfectly
congenial to our aims here. But we will begin this section by laying out, in rough terms,
According to this model, the mark of empirical knowledge is its causal and
empirical fact, then someone must have perceived that p or have learned it from
someone who perceived that p, or inferred it from what was perceived, or from what was
itself inferred, etc. And it is in virtue of the very perceptual states from which our
empirical beliefs derive that those beliefs constitute empirical knowledge. We will call
knowledge that is derived from perception empirical knowledge. Our claim is that
aesthetic knowledge is derived from affective rather than perceptual states and so is not
empirical (in that sense). It will thus be crucial to say what the differences between
We discuss two broad contrasts between affective and perceptual states, the first
concerns the rational structure (or lack thereof) of the relevant state, and the second, its
motivational power (or lack thereof). The rough idea is this: feelings10 (e.g., fear) present
10
In this paper, we use the terms “feeling” and “emotion” interchangeably. We do not
mean to imply that these terms as they are ordinarily used have precisely the same
16
the facts on which they are based (e.g., the approaching man is a violent criminal) as
having a certain normative significance (e.g., the man is to-be-feared), and present them
in a manner that engages the will. Unlike affective states, sensory perceptions neither
have rational bases nor as such motivate actions. These two contrasts will be explored
in the abstract here and developed in more detail in relation to aesthetic feeling in the
next section. In elucidating these differences and the intimate connection between
them, we will begin to see how feelings can constitute a distinctive source of our
knowledge of the world. In paradigmatic cases, the feeling itself is knowledge of the
normative fact (e.g., knowledge that the man is to-be-feared). Such facts are the objects
(a) feelings are based on their objects, which (b) warrant them in the paradigmatic case.
Regardless of whether they are in fact warranted, however, (c) they are experienced as
Start with basing. Perceptions are not based on the facts they present, whereas
feelings are. To see this, consider two kinds of defects to which an emotion is
susceptible. Suppose one finds oneself grieving over the loss of one’s favorite team, the
extension; however, everything we say here is (we take it) true of what they both
paradigmatically denote.
17
Tigers. One’s grief can be (a) grounded in falsehood (if the Tigers didn’t lose) or (b)
misplaced (if the Tigers’ loss does not warrant grief). Suppose, by contrast, that one
looks out onto the field and announces “the Tigers are taller than their opponents.” The
perceptual state one thereby gives voice to is not rationally based on the corresponding
fact or putative fact. Whatever else is true of the rational basing relation, it requires that
the subject have a separate grasp of ground and grounded. One cannot base a belief,
emotion, action, or anything else on p, unless the relevant belief (or emotion or…) is,
from the point of view of the subject, notionally separable from p. When a belief (or …)
is rationally based on p, the subject understands the belief (or…) as her own response to
something else, where the something else is itself or by proxy an element of her mental
life. But when I perceive that p, there is no distinct element of my mental life to which I
It might be doubted whether basing must always relate distinct elements of one’s
mental life. The point (of course) is not that one necessarily makes an error in using the
something and the object of that perception. But, all other things being equal, it is best
not to use technical terms to corral items that are (in the relevant respects)
fundamentally unlike one another. Paradigmatically, when one’s belief (or action or
emotion) is based on something, one can explain why one holds the belief (or...) by
11
Although we will not explore the connection in detail here, we would argue that the
underlying point is closely connected with G.E. Moore’s famous observation concerning
perception: “when we try to introspect the sensation of blue, all we can see is the blue:
18
pointing to (what one conceives of as) something else. The relation between ground and
grounded thus yields a rational explanation of the belief (or..), one which posits an
asymmetric dependence of the latter on the former. It would make no sense for the
subject to explain why she holds the relevant belief (or…) by citing the relevant ground
unless there were (at least from the subject’s point of view) some such separation.
Nothing rationally explains itself. But when I perceive that p, p is precisely what is given
to me in perception. Its presence in my mind is simply the perception itself: there is not
enough space, so to speak, for the transition essential to basing. Thus, one cannot point
to the fact that p as one’s ‘reason for perceiving’ p. (Hence also the difficulty of making
sense of the phrase ‘reason for perceiving’.) In this respect, affective states are more like
Because emotions are based on rational grounds, the notion of warrant gets a
distinctive sort of grip on the connection between an emotion and its object (e.g.,
grieving and the Tiger’s loss). When we feel grief (or another emotion) about
12
Susanna Siegel has recently (2017) argued that perception itself is rationally
assessable. But the disagreement between us and Seigel does not so much concern
perception as it does the nature of rationality. Unlike Hopkins, Siegel would reject
including ‘the argument’ inside perception; her point is partly that rationality does not
require Taking. Although we cannot adjudicate this dispute here, if the view of aesthetic
knowledge on offer in this essay is an illuminating one, then the general conception of
19
asserted that the relevant something was worthy of grief. How warranted the grounded
is in specific cases reflects on the rationality of the person who feels the emotion.
Someone is silly to grieve the loss of their favorite team, as this overvalues the place of
sports in human life. Unlike, say, the death of a loved one, the Tigers’ loss does not
warrant grieving.
This notion of warrant does not apply to perception in part for the reason just
discussed: where there is warrant there is space in the mind between what warrants and
what is warranted. But it is also because perceptual success is simply a matter of our
sensory apparatus presenting what is indeed the case: of accuracy. There is no question
of whether I have reacted inappropriately.13 This helps to explain the fact that where it
failure of the perceiver. By contrast, the question of this sort of warrant is always at
stake when it comes to feelings and emotions. Even if one’s grief is based on a truth (as
when the Tigers indeed lost), there is a question of whether I have responded to it
the emotion, whereas nothing of the sort is true of perception. The sense of a feeling’s
appropriateness is internal to the feeling itself. To grieve about the loss of a loved one is
to experience this loss as meriting grief. The emotion presents its object as warranting
itself—that very emotion—as a response. We are crying about what is sad, laughing
about what is funny, frightened at what is dangerous, etc. (or so it seems from the point
of view of the emotion). This is the internal perspective of the emotion. A perception,
13
Cf., Gregory (2018: 1066).
20
on the contrary, simply presents what is there (or so it seems from the point of view of
the perception). This helps to explain the fact that we do not consider a defect in my
perception. And although we can distance ourselves from a feeling, it’s hard. It’s hard
compelling, called for, or even obligatory—precisely because we feel the emotion and so
unwarranted—say, that a joke that I find funny is in fact deeply offensive—I am at odds
with myself. By contrast, if my vision is blurry, my body has betrayed me. The fact that
themselves helps us to locate the source of the charge of inappropriateness for grieving
over the Tiger’s loss: to have the emotion is therein for the subject to take their loss as
possessing existential profundity. This is an error of the person. Chris curses his luck
for his poor eyesight but feels shame that he grieves the loss of his team more than the
loss of his mother. Rather than mere tools for measuring the world, our emotions
measure us.14
We now turn to the second difference between affective and perceptual states. It
14
In this we are particularly inspired by Hamawaki (2006), Moran (2012) and
Friedlander (2015).
21
motivating state.15 But this is not so with perception, that is, with the sort of receptive
pleasurableness and painfulness. The fact that feelings are pleasurable or painful as
15
A few have raised doubts about the idea that feelings are motivating, e.g., Robinson et
al (2015), Corns (2014), and Corns and Cowan (2021)). But their arguments establish
only that the so-called “affective” and “motivating” sub-personal processing systems are
two separate systems, though often working in tandem. Even if true, it does not follow
that the emotions, which are person-level states, do not on their own motivate and
rationalize behaviors. What we say in this section is meant to intuitively support the
motivating power of feelings by means of examples. We would also argue that alleged
by Corns and Cown (2021) misfire insofar as (a) they target only the view that affect is
constituted by desire, a view we reject below; (b) assume that sensory perceptions and
feelings have analogous rational structures, a view that we refute; and (c) address
mainly moral internalism, to which we are not committed here. Furthermore, the fact
that even Perceptualists about emotions accept the challenge of reconciling their view
with the truism that emotions are intrinsically motivating (e.g., Tappolet 2016) speaks
to its intuitiveness. The connection is so tight that some suggest that it is part of the
etymology of the term, going back to the “Old French ‘emouvoir,’ which means to stir
up, itself going back to the Latin emovere, meaning to move out, remove, agitate”
22
perception. It is tricky to characterize this connection, however. We will do so here by
distinguishing motivation both from the mere having of reasons and from having
conative pro-attitudes.
To feel is not simply a matter of having and knowing oneself to have a reason to
act, although it includes it. To experience grief over the loss of one’s friend is to take his
death to be grief-worthy. The pain of his loss gives one has reason to do various things,
for example, to take time out to reflect on his life. Yet it’s possible to have all of the
reasons and to know that I have these reasons, but nonetheless to lack the motivation to
act on them. If, for example, I simply believe that I have reasons to spend time
reflecting on Morgan’s life, I may not act on these reasons—I may simply not feel like it.
Nor is motivation simply a matter of possessing the desire to do it, at least insofar as one
desire (so understood) might be a matter of holding the aforementioned belief that I
have certain reasons to perform the action.17 Such a desire may even be associated with
a feeling of dread about performing the relevant action. But to grieve is not merely to
have and know that one has the reason, and so not simply to desire (in the ‘pro-attitude’
16
This conception of motivation is developed and defended at length in Marcus
(forthcoming).
17
The distinction between desiring to do something and believing it would be good to do
is emphasized in, e.g., Stampe (1987). We do not, in any case, commit ourselves to a
presentational and internally evaluative, see, for example, Tenenbaum (2007) and
Brewer (2009).
23
sense) to perform the action. Prompted by the pain of someone’s loss, one feels like
doing the things that the reasons are reasons to do; that is, one is motivated to do those
know various facts on the basis of perception, facts that, once grasped, can figure in our
practical deliberations in various ways. But to perceive that things are thus-and-so is
particular manner in which they motivate is inextricable from a feature they share with
perception: they are presentational, i.e., they present the world as being a certain way.
Mark Johnston has argued along these lines that if affective experiences were not
presentational, we could not account for their power either to motivate or to rationalize
intelligible what we then go on to desire and do.”19 This authoritativeness is due to the
presentational purport of feelings. He argues that the analogy between perception and
feeling is something like this: whereas perception, precisely insofar as it discloses the
environment, makes our own beliefs about the world intelligible to ourselves (and so
they are sustained by our viewing them as true), feeling, precisely insofar as it discloses
the good, makes those feelings and consequent behaviors intelligible to ourselves: they
18
The wide tendency to understand affective motivation in terms of desire is thus
misguided. See Prinz 2004, Tappolet 2016, though with qualifications, and Corns &
24
are sustained by the continuing sensuous apprehension of the worthwhile. It is
precisely because emotions present the world as having certain goods that they have the
pursuit/avoidance, etc. I need nothing other than to be in touch with my grief to spend
time reflecting on Morgan’s life, to visit his parents, to keep playing James Brown, etc.
Note too that we need only cite a past or current feeling in order to rationally explain
such behaviors. Saying: “I am so taken back by Morgan’s death” suffices on its own both
to articulate my motivation and to justify the time I spend listening to Star Time. I need
not say, and standardly don’t say in response to the question “why do you spend so
Morgan’s life.” In fact, standardly such answers would be weird. To answer this
When our emotions present the world as it really is, we acquire knowledge of the
world directly.20 We can learn from grief that a specific person’s life was important, that
they mattered, that they were a special and irreplaceable being. Furthermore, we do not
20
Our view of the emotions thus differs both from the standard cognitivist’s view,
according to which emotions are beliefs or judgments about values (e.g., Solomon 1993,
emotions just are perceptions—in the narrow sense—of value (e.g., Tappolet 2016,
Milona 2016).
25
learn this by inferential reasoning: “I feel terrible that Morgan died, so he must have
been a special person.” Rather, it is simply by experiencing grief that one can come to
know that he is a special person. Emotions are responses to facts (and events and
objects) that present those very facts (and events and objects) as having a certain
significance. They present those facts (and events and objects) as warranting and
motivating actions and mental states of various types, in addition to warranting the very
emotion being experienced. In the paradigm case, we know that those facts possess the
relevant significance by experiencing the relevant emotions. To feel grief about what
merits grief because it merits grief is to have knowledge of, in the broad sense, value.
This is not to say that one can’t know the significance of this person in some other way.
One can know it from testimony or inference. But the feeling of grief is itself a way of
Our point is not that one feels grief and is thereby caused to believe that, e.g.,
Morgan’s death merits sadness and reflection on his life. Rather, the feeling itself,
which like perceptions comes upon the griever unbidden, simply presents Morgan’s
death as worthy of grief. Unlike the case of belief, there is no proposition, mediating
between the emotion and the world. Affective knowledge is in this sense non-
example, I know that I am walking to the zoo not because I have adequate doxastic
justification (e.g., I can smell the animals), but simply because I am intentionally
26
walking to the zoo.21 Analogously, affective knowledge is factual knowledge we have not
a feeling. I know that Morgan was a special person not because I have doxastic
justification (e.g., having read the obituaries), but simply through grief.
Is there a tension between arguing that emotions are motivating and that they are
direct ways of knowing? No. To regard the emotions as motivating is not to regard
them as non-cognitive states (as the Humean typically has it). The emotions are not
motivating states as opposed to being ways of knowing the world. To assume otherwise
both a way of knowing the world and motivation to act a certain way—a knowing
feeling.22 Feelings provide excellent ground for challenging these alleged divisions,
given that, as argued above, their motivational and cognitive powers are
interdependent.
Because feeling is, in the ideal case, an awareness of a normative fact, we describe
is not based on feeling in the way doxastic knowledge might be based on feeling—as
when I infer that Morgan meant a lot to me from the fact that I can’t stop crying. The
latter is a theoretical judgment, consisting of a true belief based on good evidence. The
21
This thesis is defended at length in Marcus (2018) and Marcus (2019).
22
Cf. Zagzebski (2003), Döring (2007), Brewer (2009): 32-34 and Helm (2001), mainly
chapter 2.
27
itself. As we will use the term, then, a judgment is a possible knowledge-state. Not all
affective judgments are knowledge, of course. One who grieves over their team’s loss
does not, in so doing, know that it was grief-worthy. But when an affective judgment is
what it should be—a feeling that presents itself as merited by its object and is felt
Given the ultimate objectives of this paper, a full defense of the general approach
to the emotions and to affective knowledge is not possible here.23 But consideration of
some objections and queries will clarify and support the central idea.
measured by accuracy, just not exhausted by that measure.24 If a grown man cries when
23
For a fuller defense, see Gorodeisky (MS).
24
See Gorodeisky (2021b). This is why some of those working on emotions agree that
emotions cannot be desires if the latter are characterized by what is often known as a
world-to-mind direction of fit (e.g., Helm (2001), Döring (2003), Raz (2011)). The point
is that, like beliefs and doxastic judgments, the emotions are measured partly by their
28
the Tigers lose, we would (ordinarily) view him in his grief as wrongly valuing the
outcome of football games. His emotional response falls short of the relevant standard
of success since it is not warranted by their loss. Similarly, someone who flies into a
rage at being asked by a waiter whether they want a lemon in their water finds offense
where there was none. We view someone who grieves at the loss of a friend, on the
contrary, as properly registering in their grief the value of a human being. The
possessing a significance that it really does have, and of being responsive to it. Accuracy
grieved) or just value-facts for the experiencing subject (a man’s death is to be grieved
by me)? A complete answer to this question would require more work on the ontology
of value than we can do here. But we would argue that the character of disagreements
fueled by conflicting emotions strongly suggests that emotions, on their face, present
value facts simpliciter. Someone who feels sympathy for a migrant child being
separated from their parents will take someone who feels none to be both missing
tragedy). Even when it comes to less weighty matters, there is something slightly
doesn’t share one’s emotional response (“you didn’t find it funny??” “you dislike
Hitchcock??”). And emotions are always subject to a “why” question, one that asks not
answerability to the facts: their success depends (partially) on correct reflection of the
world.
29
only for what led you to feel that way (or to lack the feeling) but at the same time what
justifies this feeling (or lack thereof). The best explanation of this and related
phenomena is that, when our emotions present something as having a certain value, we
do not understand the relevant value as merely of the ‘for me’ variety.
As our topic is not the ontology of value, we will not consider here arguments that
there are no values ‘out there’ as part of the fabric of reality.25 It is worth emphasizing,
however, that our opponent in this paper, the Perceptualist, is also a realist about
aesthetic value. And their theory attempts to show how the aesthetic has a real foothold
in the world. We contend that our view accomplishes this aim without distorting the
Still, it might then be wondered, thirdly, why in presenting this view of feelings a
specific stance on the question of value realism is required and, relatedly, why the
theory of the emotions on offer is committed to any particular story about affective
knowledge? Why not, it might be asked, simply introduce the notion of affective (and
The short answer is that emotions are normative kinds, in the sense that part of
what it is to be a state of, say, grief is to be measurable according to a standard. And the
relevant standard is to feel grief about what merits grief because it merits grief. So grief
is inappropriate when it is about something that does not merit grief. But a suitable
25
For arguments supporting the view that affective values, including aesthetic properties
are not merely projected on to the world, but part of the fabric of the world, see, e.g.,
30
match is not sufficient for an exemplary instance. It must also be felt because its object
revert to our earlier example, Kaito is not angry at his mother because she singed the
toast unless he takes it that she singed the toast. For this reason, the same strange
possibilities that threaten our perceptual judgments (defeaters of various sorts) also
make vulnerable our emotional responses to what is (or seems to be) learned through
experience. If Kaito merely speculates (but does not know) that she singed the toast
then his anger is to that extent unjustified. More interestingly, if (as seems fair) singed
toast is a bad reason for anger, then his anger does not embody knowledge of the
singing’s meriting anger. Because grief is a normative kind, governed by the above
standard, one cannot say what grief is without invoking the extra-mental. It just is the
Fourth, the former query and our repeated discussion of merit may raise a
further question: what role does the appeal to meriting play in distinguishing affect
from perception? We answer as follows. The rational ‘because’ means roughly ‘in light
of the fact that…’.26 To say that a man grieves the death of his friend because it merits
grief is to say that he reacts in light of the death’s grief-worthiness; the point of view of
his grief includes a view of Morgan’s death as worthy of grieving. We do not emphasize
this merely because it accounts for a central feature of the phenomenology of feeling,
but because a crucial element of the sort of knowledge that a feeling provides is a
consciousness of the feeling’s own appropriateness, i.e., its being a suitable response to a
26
For extensive discussion of rational explanation, see Marcus (2012).
31
grasp (often inchoate) of the justification that the relevant circumstance actually
provides for grieving. Emotions are, in this sense, occupants of the space of reasons.
‘why grieve about him?’. To which one might respond, as the Ghost of Christmas Future
does to Scrooge: “It may be that, in the sight of Heaven, you are more worthless and less
fit to live than millions like this poor man's child”. In the exemplary case, the subject
understands her grief (again perhaps inchoately) as justified by a state of affairs that in
reality does justify her grief. The internal perspective of the emotion is thus itself
evaluative, and it is partly in virtue of the correctness of the evaluation that the emotion
is at the same time knowledge of a value-fact. Meriting is thus at the core of affective
knowledge.
But, fifth, what about when an emotion is not based on a fact at all, but only on
what the person took to be a fact? Since the ground cannot be the fact, what is it? And
doesn’t the difficulty of answering this question favor a story on which emotions are
pressures familiar from the philosophy of perception. There too an account that posits
its topic-state as a mode of access to what is ‘out there’ runs up against the fact that
sometimes its putative object is absent. But few nowadays would insist on the basis of
this argument that one only ever really perceives internal items.27 There is a plethora of
strategies for avoiding this conclusion, as the explosion of disjunctivist responses to the
27
Contemporary skepticism about this style of argument traces back to Austin 1962.
32
argument from illusion shows.28 We will not commit ourselves to any detailed reply to
the analogous argument here. But we see no reason why the correct solution to the
way they challenge the false division between the cognitive and the conative. And it is
precisely in this regard that a theory of the aesthetic that identifies aesthetic judgment
next section, the structure of aesthetic experience, its motivating character, and its
epistemic profile.
In what follows, we will take for granted that emotions and perceptions differ along the
lines just sketched. Now we will show that aesthetic knowledge bottoms out in affective
states rather than perceptual states. We will argue that the three characteristics of
epistemic directness—are precisely what makes the feeling of aesthetic appreciation the
most plausible source of aesthetic knowledge. In making this argument, we will rely on
model of knowledge, any instance of such knowledge traces back to perception. We will
describe those who know that p in virtue of perceiving or having perceived that p as
28
Influential versions of disjunctivism include Hinton (1973) Snowdon (1979),
33
possessing primary empirical knowledge that p. Those who have never perceived that p
knowledge is to have acquired beliefs about the relevant objects without having
perceived them.29
argue in this section. More precisely, we do not possess primary aesthetic knowledge in
virtue of being in (or having been in) an affectless state.30 This is not to deny that we can
form aesthetic beliefs without affect, nor to deny that such beliefs can constitute
29
To say that a piece of aesthetic knowledge is primary is to say that its justification has
not been transmitted by testimony or inference. But aesthetic justification does not
operate independently of our being justified in holding other attitudes and so is not
position to respond to the world emotionally. Our argument here is thus consistent with
qualities are “perceptual” in the sense of being “open to direct sensory awareness”
(Beardsley 1958: 31), or more generally, what’s wrong with “aesthetic empiricism,” the
view that (in the words of Gregory Curry, who rejects it), “the boundaries of the
aesthetic are set by the boundaries of vision, hearing or verbal understanding” (An
Ontology of Art, p. 18). One can also think of the argument in this section as the
argument that Carroll demands for “demonstrating” that aesthetic experiences (at least
insofar as they amount to primary aesthetic knowledge) must be affective (Carroll 2012:
169).
34
knowledge. One could acquire this sort of derivative knowledge on the basis of
testimony. For example, one could come to believe that a movie is good on the basis of
reading a favorite critic’s review of the film and one could act on the basis of this belief
by streaming the film. But aesthetic knowledge does not originate in a belief,
can know the aesthetic features of objects independently of feeling anything for them,
To frame the issue differently: the Perceptualist does not dispute that aesthetic
knowledge stems ultimately from a direct experience. Our disagreement concerns the
nature of this experience. We use the term ’aesthetic judgment’ for the cognitive state
that, in the paradigm case, constitutes primary aesthetic knowledge. The Perceptualist
affective judgment (distinguished from every belief by its being a kind of feeling).
Our defense of Affectivism will revisit the comparison of the previous section,
using it to show that aesthetic judgments fall into the category of feeling. Aesthetic
judgments have rational bases that warrant or fail to warrant and they engage the will as
such. Nonetheless, like perceptual judgments, they are a source of primary knowledge.
Aesthetic experience yields knowledge of value facts; specifically, the facts that
35
merit or demerit, voicing approval or disapproval of what we have experienced. When
we say “The Souvenir is moving”, we are putting into words an experience through
which we seem to be in touch with a property of the film in virtue of which it is worthy of
being appreciated, that is, with a value property. And we experience the film as being
moving in light of, e.g., the candid yet expressive acting, the complicated and powerful
plot, etc., which are themselves value-facts: aspects of the film to-be-appreciated.
perceptions, raise a rational “why” question. This question asks for one’s reasons for
finding it worthy of appreciation, reasons that in the good case both justify and explain
one’s aesthetic judgment. If Mary judges the Souvenir to be an excellent film and is
asked why she does so, she might appeal to its being moving. The judgment of
excellence (in the form of feeling) is justified by appeal to a feature or features of the
film in virtue of which it merits such a judgment, that is, such a feeling. Mary might cite
the fact that the film is moving as rationally explaining her liking for the film; in so
doing, she portrays this fact as a cause of her liking, one that operates through her
recognition that this same fact justifies this liking. The film is to-be-appreciated—as
Mary knows through her appreciation of it—because its being moving confers this status
upon it. In giving the explanation, Mary represents her aesthetic judgment as explained
by a certain aspect of the film, and this explanation operates through her recognition of
its justifying function: she recognizes it as showing the film to be worthy of appreciation.
Now consider an ordinary emotion: If Sal is scared of the approaching man, their
evaluative judgment, but one that, unlike belief, takes the form of feeling. If they are
36
asked why they fear the man’s approach, Sal might reply that it is because he is a violent
criminal. This is an explanation of why they are scared, one that also justifies their fear.
question—must cite something that shows (or purports to show) that the object of their
fear in fact warrants that very feeling. Sal cites the fact that the approaching man is a
violent criminal as a way of rationally explaining her fear; in so doing she portrays this
fact as a rational cause of their fear, one that operates through their recognition of this
fact as justifying this fear.31 The common rational structure (alien to perceptual states)
of aesthetic and affective judgment is due to the former being an instance of the latter.
Let us return to valence. Aesthetic experience, like the emotions, has valence: it
experience must be valanced,33 but we would argue that this is chiefly based on a
experience need not be a fluffy, warm experience (or its opposite). A valenced
31
For more on rational causes, see Marcus (2012).
32
E.g., Prinz (2011), Dokic (2016), Nanay (2016), Goffin (2018), Robinson (2020).
33
E.g., Carroll (1999) and (2004).
34
E.g., Scheller (1973) and Poellner (2016).
37
of value property and also has a specific motivational structure.35 Positive (or negative)
valence is not to be understood as a hedonic tone, i.e., in terms of ‘feeling good’ (or
‘feeling bad’) as that expression is typically used. This would wrongly exclude the
possibility that an experience of a work both presents it as excellent and as, in a familiar
sense, painful to read or watch or listen to (and as painful precisely in the experience of
the works’ aesthetic virtues). And it would wrongly suggest that experiences with the
same valence feel the same. An aesthetic experience that has a positive valence is felt as
to-be-sustained insofar as it presents the object as meriting the very feeling one is
unpleasant or difficult. Even then, one is conscious not just of one’s pleasure in taking
in the work, but of the correctness of one’s own pleasurable response to it.
the characteristically affective manner: it is through valence that we make contact with
value. This is not to say that we infer value from our feeling pleasure, but rather that the
and therein a way of coming to know its value. To see this, consider the corresponding
claim about perception. One does not infer from the qualitative character of one’s visual
experience that the world is laid out a certain way. Rather, this qualitative character
constitutes one’s grasp of what characteristics one’s visual experience presents objects
35
E.g., Prinz (2011).
36
Dispositionalist accounts of color go wrong precisely by denying this intuitive idea.
38
constitutes one’s grasp of what aesthetic properties such experience presents the objects
displeasure) that is exemplified by the very experience one is having, and as possessing
Mere belief, even belief about value, is not like this. If one, for example, merely believes
knowledgeably that the Souvenir is excellent one might nonetheless lack the motivation
to finish watching it, let alone to re-watch it with commentary and recommend it to
others. But feeling as such motivates. We saw above how emotions such as grief
standardly motivate by themselves; we can now extend this point to the aesthetic realm.
motivated to continue the relevant experience. This is another way of putting Kant’s
appreciate the beauty of the Souvenir means that no additional motivation is needed to
keep watching it. This is not to say that one will necessarily act on this motivation—
other sources of motivation may interfere. But nothing further in the way of motivation
is needed to continue.
aesthetic experience that aestheticians today widely agree upon. We explain this feature.
37
Kant 2000 [1790]: 107. Cf. Dokic on what he calls the “characteristic motivational
profile” of aesthetic experience (Dokic 2016), Matthen (2017), and Hopkins (ms.).
39
judgment—i.e., to experience the relevant feeling—is to take the object at stake to merit
this feeling indefinitely (and often further mental states and actions). And it is to take in
the object as valuable by feeling its value. The same cannot be said of any merely
perceptual judgment or, more generally, any judgment that is not at the same time an
affective judgment. To see that the table is red is not thereby to be motivated to
continue gazing at. If aesthetic judgment were perceptual, it could not as such motivate.
But it does, and this fact helps to establish that aesthetic judgment is affective rather
than perceptual.
What we say and do on the basis of our affective experiences support the view
that they give us cognitive purchase on value properties. We take it that someone
undergoing these experiences can discover and learn new things about the objects of
these experiences through the experiences themselves. It is often through grieving that
the significance of a loved one manifests itself to us, and it is the disclosure of this
significance that explains why we reflect upon the loved one’s life. It is often by feeling
angry and morally indignant that we make cognitive contact with the corruption of
someone’s act, and this discovery then explains why we choose to stay away from the
person or try to explain to him or to others the wrongness of his act. Similarly, it is
through our enjoyment of The Souvenir that we discover the film’s aesthetic excellence,
and it is this experience that explains why we watch the film again with full commentary
deny that we can come to learn about those (dis)values in non-affective ways. But feeling
40
these emotions is a paradigmatic way of coming to know these (dis)values, a way of
knowing to which we often appeal when we are asked: “why do you think the act was
morally outrageous?” or “why do you take the film to be so good?” Our ways of thinking
and acting indicate that we take our feelings, aesthetic and otherwise, to reveal values to
us.38
Our claim, then, is that aesthetic knowledge bottoms out in affective experiences.
Aesthetic pleasure reveals objects as beautiful, which is to say, as meriting the very
In the paradigmatic case, appreciation puts one in touch with the object’s beauty.39 This
Someone who understands the medium of film and possesses the relevant knowledge
38
Clearly, this is not meant as a complete defense of the presentational power of
feelings, but along with the responses to the queries above, it suffices for our purposes in
presents not itself as finally valuable (as Iseminger has it) but the appreciated object as
meriting appreciation. Our view is thus not empiricist: it is not committed to the claim
that aesthetic value is the value of its appreciation. Furthermore, since Carroll (2012)
understands both what he calls the affective approach and the valuing approach as
41
can exercise her understanding (and other relevant cognitive powers) in an enjoyment
of the film, one that is derived in part from an enjoyment of the features of the film that
make it—a film of this sort—worth enjoying. Her knowledge of its excellence consists in
this pleasure. She has primary aesthetic knowledge, knowledge whose form is aesthetic.
But since beauty is part of the fabric of reality, it is also among possible objects of belief,
communicate her own aesthetic appreciation of the film to another, who might then
Before we move on, a note on the role of pleasure in our argument. Our goal in
this paper is to argue that primary aesthetic knowledge is constituted by feeling rather
aesthetic feeling (for that, see Gorodeisky 2021(a), Gorodeisky MS). But here is the
basic idea: pleasure, we would argue, is not so much a state as it is a class of states. A
pleasure is a felt endorsement. The pleasure of sipping a hot toddy on this chilly
December day is a felt approving apprehension of the drink as meriting such a felt
song’s groove, the pleasure of reading a good book to one’s child is an approving
approving apprehension of the film as excellent, etc. These are all instances of pleasure,
42
And so, given that it is a self-maintaining and (as we have now argued) direct
presentation of normative fact, it satisfies the criteria for the fundamental aesthetic
knowledge-state: it has the same rational structure, epistemic profile, and motivating
The point of this paper is to argue for Affectivism, the view that aesthetic
knowledge bottoms out in feeling. Our strategy has been to demonstrate its superiority
in this regard over Perceptualism, the view that the source of aesthetic knowledge is
structure of aesthetic experience, its motivating character, and its epistemic profile—and
the connections between them. In this final section, we show exactly how Affectivism
Recall first that the Paradox arises from the seeming conflict between
40
We have shown elsewhere (Gorodeisky and Marcus 2018) that this distinction is also
crucial for solving another puzzle that has bedeviled aestheticians since at least Kant:
how to reconcile the (at least seemingly) first-personal nature of aesthetic judgment (its
independence of the judgments of others) with our rationally doubting such judgments
43
Directness: Direct experience is the only source of aesthetic
knowledge,
and
How, then, does Affectivism resolve the Paradox? Like so: Affectivism is the view that
rational structure. The rationality of aesthetic criticism thus helps to confirm our
that writings about the aesthetic take the form of making that structure explicit. The
reasoning of the critic is of a perfectly familiar sort, the sort we engage every day, for
example, when we dispute that the loss of the Tigers is worthy of grief; when we explain
articulates the critic’s aesthetic knowledge is puzzling only if one has somehow fallen out
of touch with this familiar phenomenon and so with the affective nature of aesthetic
knowledge. Our view predicts and explains the nature of criticism straightforwardly and
This takes care of Criticism, but what about Directness? We are still left with
the puzzle of how criticism could be the source of its audience’s aesthetic knowledge
given that, per Directness, the source of aesthetic knowledge is direct experience. The
affective account of aesthetic knowledge does not seem to help here, since one cannot
feel what is to be felt merely by taking the word of someone else that such a feeling is
44
merited. The core of our solution is a distinction between the nature of the relation that
the critic stands in to her own reasons and the relation that the audience stands in to
those same reasons. A critic’s aesthetic judgment that The Souvenir is excellent is
derived, say, from her being moved by its perceptive portrait of a talented and ambitious
mysteriously charismatic older man. But simply imbibing the critic’s words does not
justify any aesthetic judgment on the part of a reader who has yet to see the film, for she
is not yet in a position to make an aesthetic judgment about the film. So what does
Two things. First, as Sibley held, and both Lord and Hopkins emphasize, critics
guide their readers’ aesthetic experience. But only Affectivism can account for how
critics do this by virtue of the rational character of criticism. For example, suppose
upon first viewing the film, we failed to notice just how blind the Souvenir’s heroine is to
her lover’s manipulations. We might then come to appreciate the film better after
reading Anthony Lane’s invocation of Henry James: “we pay more for some kinds of
knowledge than those particular kinds are worth” (Lane, 2014). This remark might alert
us to what Julie, the heroine, does not know, and in some sense chooses not to know.
We might then become concerned about her willful blindness. We might also come to
recognize our own anxiety on her behalf as crucial to the film’s aesthetic achievement.
In other words, if we watch the film with these critical remarks in mind, then the critic’s
reason, which initially served merely as a guide to appreciation, becomes a reason for
our own aesthetic judgment: we can now appreciate the film for the reasons that it is
about Julie and moved by her innocence, her ambition, and the way the former
45
undermines the latter. In the ideal case, a critic’s reason becomes a reader’s reason: not
by testimony, but by leading the reader to a more attuned engagement with the work,
thereby allowing her to experience this reason for herself as supporting appreciation.
Second, even apart from any such engagement, the critic’s reasoning can also
function as testimony in support of an ordinary belief that the film has the qualities that
the critic describes. Criticism could thus also be the source of the audience’s merely
derivative aesthetic knowledge, the source of their justified belief that the relevant work
is excellent or poor in the manner specified by the critic. Such derivative knowledge is
derivative aesthetic knowledge. But, more importantly, it also helps audiences acquire
Critics model primary aesthetic knowledge; they are our appreciative mirrors, showing
us how to take in a work so as appreciate its beauty. Criticism is thus, via testimony, the
epistemic source of derivative aesthetic knowledge. It is, via guidance, the causal or
guiding source of primary aesthetic knowledge.41 But Directness concerns the epistemic
of Criticism and Directness, one that neither obliterates the rationality of aesthetic
Here are our two principles again, now refined so as to reveal their consistency:
41
By ‘causal’, we do not mean ‘mechanistic’. The point is simply that criticism leads one,
46
Directness*: Direct experience is the only source of primary aesthetic
knowledge.
to account for the truth of Directness* given that a perception of p is necessarily the
object without any direct contact. But to account for Directness* we do not need to
show that feelings typically arise from direct contact or even that affective knowledge
generally bottoms out in direct contact, as empirical knowledge does with perception.
We just need to show that aesthetic experience is a direct way of acquiring knowledge.
Given that aesthetic experience is affective experience, there is no mystery about how
direct aesthetic knowledge is possible. This result fits into the large aims of the paper
like so: If not for the introduction of Affectivism, only Perceptualism would be able to
account for Directness. But since Perceptualism cannot account for Criticism, there
aesthetic reactions. Sometimes, this is simply because our judgment has no rational
47
ground. I just, e.g., find a certain shade of blue beautiful.42 Often, however, there is a
reason for one’s response but one cannot put one’s finger on it. Its presence is inchoate
in one’s experience. Good criticism can help us articulate our experience of the work. In
this way, a good critic contributes to our own self-understanding. This too is an aspect
of the rational character of criticism. The best art touches us deeply, and the best
V. Conclusion
Some hold that our approach cherry-picks the data, emphasizing those acts and
activities to which feeling is essential while ignoring everything else.43 The judgments
42
Someone might think that this shows aesthetic judgments need not be rational after
all, but that is not so. To make this judgment is to experience the color as to-be-
appreciated. As such, the question: “Why do you find it beautiful?” has application. But
one way of showing it to have application is to say: “No reason, I just like it; that’s all.”
Our view thus does not require that, in every case, one’s feelings have a rational cause.
Cf., Anscombe on the distinctive ‘Why?’ question that marks intentional action: “Now of
course a possible answer to the question ‘Why?’ is one like ‘I just thought I would’ or ‘It
because the answer to it says that there is no reason, any more than the question how
48
and activities of curators, art historians, preservationists, art educators, after all, often
do not involve feeling (of pleasure) in any direct way. We contend, nonetheless, that the
view defended here is the only one that can make sense of the full range of the practices
that are built up around the aesthetic dimensions of human life. Independently of the
appreciation that aesthetic value merits, and through which it is revealed, none of these
practices would be intelligible as aesthetic practices, nor, for that matter would they
make sense as human activities more generally. There would be no reasons to exhibit a
painting or preserve a building on account of its aesthetic value if there were no reasons
to appreciate the painting or the building. The distinctive sort of pleasure that we take
in beautiful things thus grounds the activities of the curator, historian, and others. This
is not to suggest that the point of these practices is to feel pleasure, as if we go to see The
Souvenir again for the same sort of reason that a raver takes another hit of ecstasy. No:
excellence that merits and is fundamentally known through a certain kind of pleasure.
Appreciation, then, is the key to the aesthetic. It is through appreciation that aesthetic
value is, in the first instance, known. And it is in virtue of this pleasurable engagement
44
This article evolved from our response to comments on Gorodeisky and Marcus (2018)
by Robbie Kubala and Aaron Meskin at the 2020 Eastern Division Meeting of the APA.
We thank Kubala and Meskin for those comments, and are grateful to Arata Hamawaki
for conversations that helped to inspire this article. We also extend our thanks to Ram
Neta and James Shelley, to anonymous reviewers of this journal, and to audiences at an
49
“Aesthetic Epistemology Workshop” at the University of Georgia and at a meeting of the
50
References
Austin, J. L., 1962, Sense and Sensibilia, G. J. Warnock (ed.), London: Oxford
University Press.
Beardsley, Monroe (1982). “The Aesthetic Point of View,” in the Aesthetic Point of View,
Debates in Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art, ed. Mathew Kierean, Wiley-Blackwell.
51
Corns, Jennifer and Cowan Robert (2021). “Moral Motivation and the Affective
Döring, Sabine (2007). “Seeing What to Do: Affective Perception and Rational
52
Gorodeisky, Keren (2021a).“On Liking Aesthetic Value,” Philosophy and
10.1080/00048402.2021.1910964.
Gorodeisky, Keren (MS). The Authority of Pleasure: Aesthetic Value, Rationality, and
Agency.
Gregory, Alex (2018). “Why Do Desires Rationalize Actions?” Ergo: An Open Access
Journal of Philosophy.
53
Hopkins, Robert (2006). “Critical Reasoning and Critical Perception,” in Matthew
Kieran & Dominic Lopes (eds.), Knowing Art: Essays in Epistemology and Aesthetics.
Hopkins, Robert (ms). “Aesthetic Engagement, Imagining, and the Draw of the Real.”
Iseminger, Gary (2004). The Aesthetic Function of Art. Ithaca: Cornell University
Press.
Johnston, Mark (1992). “How to Speak of the Colors,” Philosophical Studies 68 (3): 221-
263
Kant, Immanuel [1790] (2000). Critique of the Power of Judgment, ed. and trans. Paul
Lane, Anthony (2020). “’Booksmart’ and ‘The Souvenir,’ Reviewed”, The New Yorker
5/17/2019.
54
Lord, Errol (2020). “The Vices of Perception,” forthcoming in Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research.
Lord, Errol (2019). “The Nature of Perceptual Expertise and the Rationality of
Marcus, Eric (2012). Rational Causation. Cambridge, MA.: Harvard University Press.
Marcus, Eric (2019) “Reconciling Practical Knowledge with Self-Deception”. Mind 128
(512): 1205-1225.
Marcus, Eric (2021). Belief, Inference, and the Self-Conscious Mind. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Martin, M.G.F. (2002). “The Transparency of Experience”, Mind and Language, 17:
376–425.
55
McDowell, John (1978). “Are Moral Requirements Hypothetical
42.
McDowell, John (1983). “Aesthetic Value, Objectivity, and the Fabric of the World,” in
Eva Schaper (ed.), Pleasure Preference, and Value. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
McDowell, John (1987). “Singular Thought and the Extent of Inner Space”, in McDowell
and Pettit (eds.) (1987) Subject, Thought, and Context. Oxford: OUP.
Milona, Michael (2016). “Taking the Perceptual Analogy Seriously,” Ethical Theory and
Moran, Richard (2012). “Kant, Proust, and the Appeal of Beauty,” Critical Inquiry 38
(2):298-329.
Nguyen, C. Thi (2020). “Autonomy and aesthetic engagement,” Mind 129 (516):1127-
1156.
56
Prinz, Jesse (2011). “Emotion and Aesthetic Value,” in The Aesthetic Mind: Philosophy
and Psychology, eds. Elisabeth Schellekens and Peter Goldie, Oxford, UK: Oxford
Robinson, M. J. F., Fischer, A. M., Ahuja, A., Lesser, E. N., & Maniates, H. (2015).
Pictorial Experience and Aesthetic Appreciation, eds. Jerome Pelletier and Alberto
Scheller, Max (1973). Formalism in Ethics and Non-Formal Ethics of Values. Evanston:
Aesthetics, 43(4):363-378.
Shelley, James (2006). “Critical Compatibilism,” in Matthew Kieran & Dominic McIver
57
Snowdon, P.F., (1979). “Perception, Vision and Causation”, Proceedings of the
Solomon, Robert C. (1993). The Passions: Emotions and the Meaning of Life. Hackett
Publishing Company.
Stampe, Denis (1987). “The Authority of Desire,” Philosophical Review, 96(3), 335–381.
Stokes, Dustin (2014). “Cognitive Penetration and the Perception of Art,” dialectica 68
(1):1-34.
Stokes, Dustin (2018). “Rich perceptual content and aesthetic properties,” in Anna
Bergqvist & Robert Cowan (eds.), Evaluative Perception. Oxford, UK: OUP.
Tappolet, Christine (2016). Emotions, Values, and Agency. Oxford, UK: OUP.
Wollheim, Richard (1980). Art and Its Objects, 2nd ed. New York: CUP.
58
Zagzebski, Linda (2003). “Emotion and moral judgment,” in Philosophy and
59