Marxism in The Twentieth Century - Garaudy, Roger - Volume 0, 1970 - New York, Scribner - Anna's Archive
Marxism in The Twentieth Century - Garaudy, Roger - Volume 0, 1970 - New York, Scribner - Anna's Archive
Marxism in The Twentieth Century - Garaudy, Roger - Volume 0, 1970 - New York, Scribner - Anna's Archive
iry~i4~
CIAL ACTION drive
' 8200 MA
DETROIT, RVgrqve
MARXISM IN THE
TWENTIETH
CENTURY
Roger Garaudy
MARXISM IN THE
TWENTIETH
CENTURY
A-i.7i[c]
SBN684-71783-2
Library of Congress Catalog Card Number 70-106527
'Por eso no me espero de regreso
No soy de los que vuelven de la luzd
Introduction page 9
Postscript 198
Acknowledgements 213
Index 2 15
Introduction
alone stood free while nearly the whole of Europe was en¬
slaved, and at Stalingrad saved the world from reverting for
a thousand years to barbarism. And then again there came
the rebuilding of thousands of towns that had been destroyed,
and man’s first achievements in space as he burst out into the
cosmos.
That story contains the solid foundation on which to base,
the enduring landmarks within which to contain, our critical
judgment.
To this must be added all the hopes born of this new life:
the Spanish war which made of that people the first of the
patriotic resistances against Hitlerian fascism, and the out¬
standing part played in the struggle for freedom against
Nazism by the Communist parties: the Long March and the
triumph, in the middle of the century, of the Chinese revolu¬
tion, and, at the other end of the world, Cuba, whose
revolutionary romanticism linked hands with Marxism-
Leninism.
Faced with what was in process of birth and development,
the world was entering an agonising era: the 1914-18 war
had already challenged many values; the Versailles treaties
were creating new hotbeds of war; the horror of colonialism
was reaching — in the inter-war period — its culminating point ;
the 1929 crisis swept away the last illusions about an econ¬
omic order that allowed the law of the jungle to prevail in
a world of iron.
19
'
CHAPTER ONE
26
THE TERMS OF THE PROBLEMS
33
MARXISM IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY
35
MARXISM IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY
past.
What we have to do is to work out an authentically
universal humanism, losing nothing that has been won by
reason but ready to embrace new cultural areas.
By its very nature, Marxism is capable of this universality,
and the rich experience of the battles for national freedom
fought by hitherto colonised peoples and of the construction
of socialism along roads proper to each one of them, will
make a very considerable contribution to the richness of
Marxism’s own humanism.
If Marxism is not to become ‘provincial’, it cannot develop
through monologue; it can do so only through dialogue with
all man’s creations.
The problems raised by decolonisation, in giving back their
own history to formerly colonised peoples, guide us to a re-
THE TERMS OF THE PROBLEMS
37
CHAPTER TWO
43
MARXISM IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY
45
MARXISM IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY
53
MARXISM IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY
54
FROM DOGMATISM TO THOUGHT
55
MARXISM IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY
57
MARXISM IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY
always identical with itself: the ‘in-self’ (an sick) answers ‘No’
to such an hypothesis. Sometimes, too, it answers ‘Yes’. This
answer has a. practical character: nature either allows itself to
be handled, or refuses. By acting according to one particular
hypothesis my action miscarries; by acting according to an¬
other I have power over nature. It is true that the hypotheses
destroy themselves and that none of them can claim to dis¬
close an ultimate structure of being. But every dead hy¬
pothesis, simply because it has been alive, bequeaths to us
a new power over nature. This power and this knowledge
59
MARXISM IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY
have survived it. The new hypothesis is the heir of the hy¬
pothesis it replaces and has destroyed. These powers, accord¬
ingly, have accumulated, and my acts of today, making use
of them in order to handle nature, carve out at any rate a
rough model of its structure, which is known to me in ever
greater detail.
The history of the sciences teaches us that the demands of
the object have in turn exploded and rendered useless the
principles of the mechanics of Descartes, Newton and Lap¬
lace, the laws of logic of Aristotle and Kant, and Euclid’s
principles of geometry.
From physics to biology, the natural sciences have con¬
tinually exerted an increasing pressure on our habits of
thought.
They have obliged those who investigate such matters to
invent other models than those of traditional logic, of Eucli¬
dean geometry, of classical mechanics.
Now, if a hypothesis to explain structure is confirmed, if
it is shown to be effective, if it enables us to grasp things
and allows us even to discover new properties in them, how
can we conceive that there is no relationship (I do not say
61
MARXISM IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY
73
MARXISM IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY
74
FROM DOGMATISM TO THOUGHT
75
CHAPTER THREE
77
MARXISM IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY
81
MARXISM IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY
of morality, was raised for the first time in its full force by
Fichte in his Sittenlehre. In this System of moral science the first
chapter is directed against dogmatism. Its aim is to lay down
the first principle: the freedom of the ego, ruling out all
transcendence, both transcendence from above — that of God
and his revealed commandments — and transcendence from
below, that of the thing as datum. The second chapter, by
contrast, is directed against formalism, and aims at providing
morality with a concrete content.
Fichte thus offers us an exemplary model of the effort to
keep hold of both ends of the chain, ethics and society.
The compound was so unstable that its unity was soon
broken :
with Hegel there is already a return to dogmatism, which
makes subjectivity a moment of objective morality, but one
that is so completely and definitively left behind that the
individual subject has no existence or value except as a
function of the rational and social totality.
with Stirner and also, from a very different point of view,
with Kierkegaard, it is the totality, the social totality for the
former and the rational totality for the latter, which is
abandoned : in the case of Stirner, in favour of the exclusive
83
Hegel? And cannot we Marxists, inspired by Fichte’s efforts
to keep hold of both ends of the chain, interiorise and inte¬
grate Sartre’s demand and so make of it an element of our
own thought?
A Marxism which never forgets Kant or Fichte, a Marxism,
MARXISM IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY
The second thesis is that the self can be seen in fixed con¬
ceptual terms, as showing forth the ambiguity of subject and
object, of constituent and constituted, of facticity1 and free¬
dom.
The third thesis is that the absolute ego is absolute freedom ;
but the constraint inherent in its make-up involves, besides
the existence of choice, the obligation to choose. Fichte’s
fourth thesis, from which existentialism derives, is that the
ego is project: it continually leaps ahead of itself, urged on
by the unrealisable desire to win or create what it lacks, in
other words always to be both in-self (an sich) and for-self
(fur sich) .
In short, we find in Fichte all the key themes of existential
philosophy, but within a rationalist philosophy.
Fichte can help us to keep hold of both ends of the chain.
or exists. The facticity of freedom is the fact that freedom is not able “not
to be free” ’ (Being and Nothingness, trans. Hazel E. Barnes, London, 1966:
from the ‘Key to special terminology’, p. 631).
MARXISM IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY
She writes, for example, ‘Do what you must, whatever hap¬
pens.’ ‘That is,’ she adds, ‘the result is not external to the
good will which is realised in aiming at it.’
What we have, then, is an abstract, formal, metaphysical
94
MARXISM AND ETHICS
95
MARXISM IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY
canvas what the best informed brain of his time has con¬
ceived or is conceiving . . . Giotto echoes Dante . . . Poussin
‘The individual,’ said Marx, ‘is the sum total of his social
relationships.’ Saint-Exupery (Pilote de Guerre, p. 347) was to
find the same thing: ‘Man is no more than a knot of relation¬
ships; only relationships count for man.’
Consciousness of self, with the split it involves, is already
an interiorised dialogue : it entails, within my self, a tension
between me and the other.
97
MARXISM IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY
man’s work from animal activity (that of the beaver, the ant,
the bee) is the anticipation of the act, which makes of this
project the law of its action. It is this possible, this project,
which enables man to move towards the future along an
original road that the animal was incapable of knowing, the
road that entails freedom and choice.
Man does not make a choice between given terms but be¬
tween possibles (projects). Freedom is born with this possi¬
bility of projecting a number of possible acts. In action we
confront the future with our possibles, just as in knowledge
we confront reality with our hypotheses.
The future enters into consciousness only through the
5. Alienation.
I do not propose to enlarge here either on the nature of
alienation or on its genesis, which I have dealt with else¬
where, but to look at its relationship with the four proposi¬
tions put forward above.
From the point of view of the ‘we’, alienation is the split¬
ting of the ‘we’, its mutilation; alienation is what stands in
the way of world-wide participation in human culture.
From the point of view of possibles and projects, alienation
is man robbed of his specifically human dimension : the de¬
termination of possibles and projects (economic, political,
cultural, etc.). This determination becomes a class privilege:
the ruling class (the class which owns the means of produc¬
tion and the State) makes of man a means, an object.
From the point of view of choice, the ruling class arrogates
to itself, in addition to the privilege of culture, a monopoly
of decision and command.
Finally, from the point of view of needs, and the means of
99
MARXISM IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY
act, then it is just as though the norm and its violation were
presented to us simultaneously.
The transcending of contradictions no longer, henceforth,
comes from outside: communism is no longer an Utopia or a
moral system, but the expression of a real movement.
(c) The birth of a need. This real movement is experienced
subjectively by a social class as a need. This can be clearly
seen in the industrial revolts of the silk- workers of Lyons, the
Chartists in England, the Silesian weavers, and later the Paris
rising in June 1848.
Marxism is the theoretical expression of this coincidence of
a concrete project and a real need, of scientific socialism and
the working-class movement.
It no longer has a moral character; it is no longer an ideal
divorced from life, but is instead fundamentally the develop¬
ment of a praxis.
It was in this sense that Marx could write in The Holy
finite and the infinite (that is, between the I and the totality
of others) makes possible the reciprocal involvement of trans¬
cendence and immanence. Already, for Fichte, the finite I
was an absolute, only because it included in itself, in its
activity, this affirmation of finite and infinite which Spinozist
dogmatism projected outside it into being.
We can therefore define transcendence by emptying it of
all the meaning which it contains only in virtue of an obsolete
conception of the world.
To investigate the dimension of transcendence, conceived
not as an attribute to God but as a dimension of man, is
not to start from something which exists in our world in a
vain attempt to prove the existence of what can exist only in
another world : it is simply to investigate all the dimensions
of human reality.
When I love a human being, I make a wager — I put my
money on that being — in a way that goes beyond all his acts.
The closest image, then, we can form of this transcendence
is perhaps that of the love, of the strictly human love, through
which we learn to see, or rather to postulate, in the loved
being, a quality which shares no common measure with the
contents of his acts.
In an enthralling passage on St John of the Cross, Aragon,
105
CHAPTER FOUR
people.’
Accompanying, however, the element of reflection, there is
also that of protest. This latter is the element of religion in
virtue of which it is not simply an ideology — the quest for
an explanation of unhappiness and helplessness — but is an
attempt to find a way out from unhappiness : in other words,
it is no longer just a way of thinking, but a way of acting :
no longer an ideology but a faith, a way of confronting the
world and behaving in it.
Here we meet phenomena of great complexity. This faith
is expressed in a very different way in history.
daily : a ban that was to persist until the fourth century. Thus
in the person of Christ, magnified by the collective imagina¬
tion of the first Christians and accepted as the heir of
1 16
MARXISM AND RELIGION
of the individual’s real life in civil society (as Hegel and the
young Marx said) and of the ‘citizen’s’ abstract life in a
community in which he exercises absolute sovereignty. ‘It
can dispense with religion, because in this case the human
national religions'
Il8
MARXISM AND RELIGION
the socialists’ (p. 323). Such is the first aspect of this human
core, this consciousness of a lack and this protest against it :
even if the protest sometimes takes a purely moral utopian,
and mythical, form.
John of the Cross, you are but the name the Christian gives
to all who in their love
write their own doom.
And I, as you whose passion knows no bourne,
I pass by the bed on which, beyond the love of God, you mourn.
For from this world must come the answer to the question that is me:
And he who casts away this world is lost: he finds,
As he cuts short his road,
121
MARXISM IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY
This is not to say that religion will never die : it means the
determination to lose no part of the human riches that have
given you eyes with which to see it, and hands with which
to mould it, so that it may depend on you alone whether
you degrade yourself to the lower level of the brute beasts or
138
MARXISM AND RELIGION
become poetry.’
It would be easy to make a mistake here, and liken Ara¬
gon’s position to Feuerbach’s, who substitutes for ‘God is
love’ the phrase ‘love is God’.
Just as the ‘reversal’ of Hegel by Marx cannot be likened
to the ‘reversal’ of Hegel by Feuerbach, so the inversion of
141
MARXISM IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY
alone?’
Here we see the radical difference between Aragon’s atheism
and the Christian concept, even in the secularised but still
‘naturalist’ form given to it by Feuerbach.
Bearing that in mind, it still remains true that it is to
Christian love that love owes, in Aragon, its being rooted in
so great a depth of being.
In this connection, the poem to St John of the Cross, in
Le Fou d’Elsa, is illuminating.
‘John of the Cross , I ask you
What is man , and what is love . . .
John of the Cross, you are but the name the Christian gives to
all who in their love write their own doom .’
Surrealism saw in love the metaphysical experience of the
marvellous, the most intimate form of man’s relations with
the world. For Aragon, it was the first stage of the ‘reversal’,
corresponding to the Feuerbachian stage of Marx’s reversal
of Hegel.
all the culture which that society brings with it. But it has
above all an historical character. Thus its effectiveness is not
defined simply by the immediate result and the profitability
of an action which at every moment is an absolute beginning.
The act and its value are judged first in terms of a human
history whose meaning is not patient of arbitrary revision
simply the activity of man pursuing his end’ (cf. The Holy
Family, trans. R. Dixon, London, 1957, p. 125).
This shows how wrong it would be to interpret in a mech¬
anistic or positivist sense the phrase that Engels borrowed
from Hegel, ‘Freedom is the recognition of the inevitable.’
This should be understood in the light of another of Marx’s
definitions: ‘Freedom is the consciousness man has of himself
in the element which is at work in practice. In other words
151
MARXISM IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY
that battle unless the fighting is shared by all who have the
future at heart.
*
if they are not to lag behind life’ (Works, Vol. IV, pp. 217-18).
Every attempt to imprison Marxism in a closed system of
principles or laws is contrary to its very essence.
Contemporary theology, too, seems to be moving towards
the idea that the original conceptualisation of the faith in
the forms of Greek thought is no more than one of its possible
cultural forms.
The same massive facts of our century as oblige us to think
Marxism in the spirit of our time, have led Christians to
reflect deeply on the significance of their faith and the his¬
toric forms of its expression.
1. The building of socialism on a global scale, a major reality
of our time, raises completely new problems both for Chris¬
tians and for Marxists.
:55
For every Christian who can distinguish, in the building
of socialism, what derives from the actual principles of
MARXISM IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY
158
MARXISM AND RELIGION
‘We must dream,’ said Lenin, who knew that myth is life
in action.
From this humanist point of view, myth lies at the level of
man’s creative art, neither above nor below.
Just as we do not believe, with Berkeley, that nature is the
symbolic language spoken by an infinite mind to finite minds,
so we do not believe, with Cassirer, that myth is the Odyssey
of the consciousness of God, with Gusdorf that it is immersion
and metaphysical reintegration in reality, or with Dumery
nature and from our own nature. Here Wallon’s analysis (see
above, pp. 55-6) coincides with that of Van der Leeuw: it is
‘a return to the fundamental: the man who “stands on his
own feet” and can say “no” about what is given to him as
reality’ (Vhomme primitif et la religion, p. 199).
Marx asks us to explain in this way the enduring fascina¬
tion through the centuries of the great myths of Greece, as
expressing the healthy infancy of man, refusing to define
reality solely by the ananke of the order existing in nature or
society, whether it be Prometheus, Icarus, Antigone or Pyg¬
malion.
176
MARXISM AND ART
character of its object, which does not claim identity with the
history of physics, of biology or astronomy, and which is a
history of men as beings responsible for the future. A man’s
life is really ‘historical’ (and not biological) when it is made
up of free decisions.
This conception of history is also a conception of life.
Marxism, by inaugurating, in alliance with historical ma¬
terialism, a new age of history, has provided man with new
means for building his own future. Because its materialist
conception of man and the world is based on man’s creative
practice, it is a methodology of historical initiative. At the
same time, this conception of the world is a moment in the
liberation of man.
When, under the claim of being scientific history, it be¬
comes fixed in dogmatism — in a scheme of development
divided into five stages, universal in value and immutable
— not only is there a reversion to a ‘philosophy of history’,
whose uselessness was demonstrated by Marx, but a new fate,
and a new inevitability are given currency, with all the
fanaticism in behaviour which is produced by dogmatism in
thought.
The time of history is not this empty framework into which
events and men must at all costs be thrust. If many of our
actions are not our own or are no longer our own, as a result
of a dialectic of ‘alienation’ and of the ‘fetishism’ the key to
which was given to us by Marx, and the analysis of which
we are still a long way from completing, then how can a
personal existence have any real meaning? Is man simply a
function of structure and conjectures?
This is a problem which the novelist has to face, since, as
Elsa Triolet writes in Le grand jamais, he is ‘his heroes’ pre¬
destined fate’. To what extent can one predict a man’s future
as one predicts that of the hero of a novel?
Is not the novelist’s time, 1made
95 up of man’s initiatives
more than of what he has to accept, closer to human, historical,
truth than the clock-time and calendar-time in which we
MARXISM IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY
197
Postscript
all such gains are preserved within new syntheses when the
preceding thesis is dialectically superseded. On the other
hand, it does rule out the aberrations of an over-simplified
scientism, which claims to be entrenched in a system of com¬
pleted concepts, and from them to deduce the whole of
earlier and later history: just as before our time a mechanistic
conception of determinism had led Laplace to maintain that
he could deduce in physics all the earlier and all the later
states of the world system.
In the field of action and men’s historical initiative, of
their practice in the strongest sense of the word, the abandon¬
ment of one of the terms indissolubly linked together by Marx
in his materialist and dialectical conception of history would
have consequences as disastrous as on the plane of theory.
Action is not the conclusion of a syllogism or of a demonstra¬
tion in elementary mathematics : when conceptual, scientific,
analysis of objective conditions has been carried as far as
possible, then responsible decision comes in. This is not an
arbitrary choice: it is, on the contrary, based on scientific
study, but it is not derived from it in the same way as
technical application results, with nothing to carry forward
beyond itself, from knowledge of existing laws.
To recall this is not to provide a solution to the problem;
but it does express the problem and show that there will
never be a complete and definitive answer.
We can never repeat too often that we must emphasise the
necessity of keeping hold of both ends of the chain, of main¬
taining, that is, the dialectical character of Marxism.
All Marxism’s vicissitudes, during these last twenty years,
have been caused by abandoning one or other of the aspects
of historical dialectics.
To confine ourselves to France, there were, immediately
after the Liberation, the numerous variations of a so-called
‘humanist socialism’ developed over fifteen years, from Leon
Blum to Pere Bigo, and from Maximilien Rubel to Pere
Galvez. Marxism was thus reduced to one of the forms of
202
POSTSCRIPT
206
POSTSCRIPT
212
Acknowledgements
213
Index
act; man’s creative, 173-4, 1 76, 178, modern conception, 63-4, 184, 185-
1 80, 1 8 1 , 1 83, 208 ; philosophy of, 66, 6; non-Westem, 186-7, >88, 189;
84, 130; and project, 98 romanesque, 189; and satisfaction
aesthetics, 42, 71, 176, 212; form in, of human needs, 178-9, 180, 184;
69; Marxist, 174-6, 193, 212; beauty
sociology of, 72-3. See aesthetics,
Marxist critique of Hegel’s, 182-4;
non-Aristotelian, 77, 159; and Asia, 21, 35, 36, 46-7
realism, 34, 190; in the Soviet atheism, 106-8, 141-3, 160-61, 162
Union, 28, 29; traditional, 189. atomic bomb, 22
See art, beauty atoms, 45, 48, 67-8
Africa, 21, 35, 36, 46 Augustine, St, 108-9, II2> '30, 134
‘agape’, 137 autonomy, concept of, 132
agnosticism, 58, 59, 127 ‘auto-regulation’, 63, 70
Averroes, 36
alienation, 31, 34, 88, 99-100, 139, aviation, 24
154, 181-2, 195; and Christian love,
134-5; distinction from objectiva-
Bachelard, Gaston, 37, 42, 64, 77, 95,
tion, 148, 183; and faith, 210;
Marx’s concept, 77, 122-3; and 191, 206
moral systems, 101 ; private owner¬ Balzac, H. de, 191
ship supreme form, 182; religious, Bannour, Wanda, 87-8
Barth, Karl, 159, 173
1 16-18, 120; and social stereotype,
165; and transcendence, 134 Batista, Fulgencio, 16
Althusser, L., 203, 205, 207. See anti¬ Baudelaire, Charles, 168, 186
humanism Bauer, Bruno, ti6, 118
analogy, reasoning by, 71 beauty, 62, 176, 178, 180, 187. See
aesthetics, art
anti-communism, 16-17, 152
Antigone, 81, 166, 167, 173, 174 Beauvoir, Simone de, 88, 90-1, 92, 93
anti-humanism, 205-7 Becquerel, Henri, 40
Apelles, 63 being; and act, 173, 208; Greek con¬
Apostel, L., 70 cept, 159; philosophy of, 66, 84, 130
Aragon, Louis, 64, 104, 12 1-2, 136, Bellarmine, Cardinal Robert, 138
Berkeley, George, 164
141-2
Bernard, Claude, 24
Aristotle, 57, 59, 60, 64, 66, 158, 159,
210 Bigo, Pere, 202
Armenia, 32 biology, 24-5, 39, 46, 48, 60, 71
Blanquists, 1 1
art, 56, 95-6, 125; Byzantine, 187,
189; and concept of decadence, Bloch, Joseph, 52
Cezanne, Paul, 64, 95, 171-2, 191, Communist party, 13; French, 15,
192
18-19, 1 14-15, 207; twentieth con¬
child, thought and reflection in, 127 gress of U.S.S.R., 17, 18, 29
choice, 98, 99 communists ; Christian, 1 1 1 ; and
Christ, in, 1 12, 1 18, 159, 167; Christians, 17, 12 1, 152
Resurrection, 173 composition in modern art, 188
Christianity; adapted to commercial computers, 23-4
society, 117-18, n8n, 119; contri¬ Comte, Auguste, 58, 65, 107
bution to concept of man, 129, 130- concept, 43, 44, 76, 207-8, 209; Carte¬
1, 144; Hellenisation, 155, 158; sian and Spinozist theory, 206, 207
consciousness, 84, 85, 98
Helleno- Christian current, in,
conservatism, 211
1 12-13; heritage of, 162-3; Judaeo-
Christian current, in, 112, 130, Constantine, 109, no, 152, 162
131, 134, 158; and liberation of contradiction, 56, 70, 81-2
man, 163; primitive, 109-10, 113, Copernicus, 172
creation; attribute of man, 134;
1 14, 120, 130; ‘progressive role’,
labour and, 169; of man by man,
1 14; ‘religion of the absolute
future’, 167; religionless, 161 ; and 77. 79. '05, 1 19. !24. 1 37. M5> 164,
the world, 160 171, 176, 182, 209
2l6
INDEX
Fichte, J. G., 41, 66, 79, 83, 85, 97, Guesde, Jules, 203
Guillaumaud, 70
128, 182, 206; and art, 185; ethics, Gurvitch, G. D., 94
83, 94-5; idealism, 176, 186; source
Gusdorf, Georges, 164
of existentialism, 86-7; and syn¬
thesis of humanism, 108, 132-3
Hamlet, 174, 192
five-year plans, 12, 29, 33
Focillon, H., 72 Hammurabi, 80
formalism, moral, 89, 90 Hartmann, E. von, 39-40
Fourier, Charles, 41 Hegel, Friedrich, 36, 41, 59, 76, 77,
Francastel, Pierre, 72-3, 74 79. Si, 83, 122, 128, 147, 169, 176,
Franco, General Francisco, 17 185, 206, 207; and absolute
freedom, 36, 86, 96, 98, 99, 147, 150, knowledge, 49; absolute spirit of,
176; existentialist concept, 88-9, 144, 145, 150, 194; conception of
91, 92"3> 94. 204; and facticity, 87, history, 168; and conception of
87n, 88 myth, 170; dogmatism in ethics,
Freud, Sigmund, 165, 168-9, I7°. I9I 83; on fear of death, 18; ‘Hegelian
Freudism, 149
left’, 203; humanism, 108, 133;
future, 10, 12, 18, 98, 151, 155; idealist illusion, 42, 45; Marxist
building up of, 163, 166, 193, critique of aesthetics, 175, 182-4,
195, 208-g; man and, 160, 165, 166 192, 193; on religion, 116, 118;
‘reversal’ by Marx, 141, 142, 145
Garaudy, Roger; Perspectives de Heidegger, Martin, 159, 191
Vhomme, 198-9; Thiorie matirialisle Hellenism, 77, 130, 137, 138, 159
Helvetius, 90
de la connaissance, 19, 203
Heraclitus, 61
Gauguin, Paul, 186
geometry, Euclidian, 60 hero, mythical, 168, 170, 174
Georgia, 32 Hertz, Heinrich, 39
Gide, Andrd, 64 Hippocrates, 24
Hiroshima, 13, 22
Gilson, Etienne, 185
Giotto, 96 history, 10, 21, 46, 51; creation by
Girardi, Father, 144-5 man, 52-3, 77-8, 124, 149-50, 176,
Gladkov, F. V., 29 201; and dialectical reason, 56;
gnosticism, 137, 138 initiative in, 10, 195, 200-1, 202,
God, 95, 104, 107, 128, 130, 132, 140, 208; Marxist conception of mean¬
141, 143, 160, 161, 194; Christian ing, 102, 208; meaning, 167-8, 174,
concept, 158, 159; love of, 137, 138, 201; scientific, 194-5; and struc¬
142, 160; and transcendence, 63, turalism, 74-5 ; subjective factor, 95
133 Hitler, Adolf, 165
79. 83, 167; will of, 108, 109, 130, Hitlerism, 13, 29
Goethe, Wolfgang, 133, 185, 186 Holbach, P.-H. D. d’, 76, 85, 106,
Gollwitzer, Pastor, 144, 147, 153, 154 177, 207
Homer, 190
Gorki, Maxim, 12, 105 ‘horizon’, 63, 157
Graeco-Roman thought, 129-30, 131
Greece, 112-13 human relationships, 27-30
Greek gods, 112, 170 humanism, 34; Marxist, 75, 107-8,
Guatemala, 14
150, 151, 154; modern, 64-6; new,
Guernica, 13
75; two currents, 13 1-3, 134;
Gueroult, M., 86 universal, 36, 37, 188
2l8
INDEX
t59
Husserl, Edmund, 191 Kautsky, Karl, 1 1
hypotheses, 53, 65; necessity for kerygma, 167, 210
Kierkegaard, S., 83, 85, 87, 133, 134,
plurality of scientific, 47-8; and
power over nature, 59-60; of
structure, 72 Klee, Paul, 171-2, 187, 189
knowledge;
84 ‘absolute’, 49, 63; active
I; and consciousness of self, 96-7; and character, 41, 53, 99, 125, 176, 205,
206; dialectical character, 37, 55,
the other, 93-4, 103-4; the pure and
the empirical, 94. See Ego 127, 20X-2 ; doubling of human, 25,
I bn Arabi, 141 26; Marxist theory, 42-3, 45, 125;
Ibn Khaldun, 36 non-Cartesian, 37, 158; pre-Marx¬
idealism, 62, 127, 177; German, 41, ist theory, 53-4; relative character,
45. t76; illusions, 42, 45, 79
Koestler, Arthur, 153
ideology, 49-51, no
impressionism, 191 Kornberg, Arthur, 25
Incarnation, 159 Kruschev, Nikita, 17
incentive, 30-1, 33 Kugelmann, L., 11-12
individual and social relations, 91-2,
148-9, 150
Laberthonniere, Lucien, 158, 173
individualism, Sartrian, go, 204 labour; and alienation, 181-2; and
information, theory of, 71-2 creative act, 183; dependence on
infrastructures, 33 nature, 124; and ethics, 105;
initiative, historical, 10, 195, 200-1, human, 167, 169, 176; and human
202, 208 needs, 180, 183-4; and myth, 165,
‘in-self’, 59, 60 167 ; at origin of all human activity,
integrism, 173, 210 125; social, 27; and transcendence,
intuition, 37
133-4. $ee work
labour-power, 32
Lacazette, 153
Jaspers, Karl, 159
Lactantius, 130
Jaur£s, Jean, 163
Jews, 1 16 Lafargue, Paul, 202
Langevin, Paul, 40
John of the Cross, St, 104, 12 1-2, 142,
160 language, 96, 97
Marx, Karl, 9-12, 27, 38, 42, 49, 51, 155; speculative, 48; and theory
52, 56, 61, 62, 84, 124, 128, 136, of reflection in knowledge, 44-5,
155, 160, 180, 185 et passim\ aesthe¬
‘sets’125
53. , 69, 71 42,
mathematics, 124; theory of
tics, 1 74-5 ; on alienation, 77, 122-3,
135, 181, 182; on art, 182-4, 1 90,
220
INDEX
Napoleon, 24 picture,
131-2 187-8
nature, 27, 54; contemporary arts planning, 27, 28, 29, 30, 31, 32-3
and, 63-4; dialectic of, 53, 59, 60- Plato, 76, 84, 85, 129, 158, 160, 210;
1, 69, 71; man and, 22-5, 55, and beauty, 176; ‘eros’, 137-8;
62
124; ‘second’, 124, 171, 177, 185, ‘Laws’, 81, 130; theory of ideas, 51,
186
Nazism, 12, 13, 121 Plekhanov, G. V., 1 1 , 12
221
INDEX
222
INDEX
224
HARYGROUE COLLEGE LIBRARY
Marxism in the twentieth centu
335.4 GIGm tHl
3 na? □□□oa?Eci i
DATE DUE
OCT 17 W
335.4
G16m
tHl