Ayres y Gertner para Traducir
Ayres y Gertner para Traducir
Ayres y Gertner para Traducir
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Yale Law Journal
INTRODUCTION
The legal rules of contracts and corporations can be divided into two
distinct classes. The larger class consists of "default" rules that parties can
contract around by prior agreement, while the smaller, but important,
class consists of "immutable" rules that parties cannot change by contrac-
tual agreement.' Default rules fill the gaps in incomplete contracts; they
govern unless the parties contract around them. Immutable rules cannot
be contracted around; they govern even if the parties attempt to contract
around them. For example, under the Uniform Commercial Code
(U.C.C.) the duty to act in good faith is an immutable part of any con-
tract,2 while the warranty of merchantability is simply a default rule tha
parties can waive by agreement.3 Similarly, most corporate statutes
t Assistant Professor, Northwestern University School of Law; Research Fellow, American Bar
Foundation. B.A., Yale University; J.D., Yale Law School; Ph.D. (Economics), Massachusetts Insti-
tute of Technology. The support of Northwestern's Corporate Counsel Center is gratefully
acknowledged.
fl Assistant Professor, University of Chicago, Graduate School of Business. A.B., Princeton Uni-
versity; Ph.D. (Economics), Massachusetts Institute of Technology. The authors would like to thank
Douglas Baird, Randy Barnett, Richard Craswell, John Donohue, Frank Easterbrook, Mark Grady,
David Haddock, Steve Harris, Oliver Hart, Ian MacNeil, Joel Rogers, Steve Salop, David
Scharfstein, David Van Zandt, Robert Vishny and seminar participants at the University of Chicago,
Georgetown, Michigan, Northwestern, and Illinois law schools, and at the U.S. Department of
Justice for helpful comments. Rebecca Mitchells and Jerry Richman provided excellent research
assistance.
1. See B. Black, Corporate Law As Neutral Mutation, (Nov. 1988) (unpublished manuscript on
file with authors) (arguing that few corporate laws are immutable). Immutable rules are similar to
what Calabresi and Melamed call "inalienable" rules, Calabresi & Melamed, Property Rules, Liabil-
ity Rules, and Inalienability: One View of the Cathedral, 85 HARV. L. REV. 1089, 1093 (1972),
except that immutable entitlements are created by and conditioned upon contract, while inalienable
entitlements exist outside of contract. See Schwab, A Coasean Experiment on Contract Presumptions,
17 J. LEGAL STUD. 237, 239 n.6 (1988) (distinguishing between inalienable and immutable rules).
2. U.C.C. ? 1-203 (1976); see Morin Bldg. Prod. Co. v. Baystone Constr., Inc., 717 F.2d 413,
414-15 (7th Cir. 1983); RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF CONTRACTS ? 205 (1979); R. POSNER, Eco-
NOMIC ANALYSIS OF LAW 81 (3d ed. 1986).
3. U.C.C. ? 2-314 (1976). U.C.C. ? 1-102 (1976) distinguishes between default and immutable
rules and states its preference for the former:
(3) The effect of provisions of this Act may be varied by agreement, except as otherwise pro-
vided in this Act and except that the obligations of good faith, diligence, reasonableness and
care prescribed by this Act may not be disclaimed by agreement but the parties may by agree-
ment determine the standards by which the performance of such obligations is to be measured
if such standards are not manifestly unreasonable.
(4) The presence in certain provisions of this Act of the words "unless otherwise agreed" or
87
words of similar import does not imply that the effect of other provisions may not be varied by
agreement under subsection (3).
U.C.C. ? 1-102 (1976).
4. See, e.g., DEL. CODE ANN. tit. 8, ? 211(c) (1974).
5. See, e.g., DEL. CODE ANN. tit. 8, ? 214 (1974).
6. DEL. CODE ANN. tit. 8, ? 223 (1974).
7. U.C.C. ? 2-206 (1976).
8. 382 P.2d 109 (Okla. 1962), cert. denied, 375 U.S. 906 (1963).
9. Whether the Peevyhouse majority actually intended for prospective parties to be able to
the "cost of performance measure" is discussed more fully infra text accompanying notes 15
10. The consideration requirement is not immutable if written agreements "under seal" serv
contractual substitute for consideration. See U.C.C. ? 2-203 (1976) (making inoperative "the law
respect to sealed instruments").
This default rule/immutable rule dichotomy also pervades other areas of the law that have con
tual components. In the law of divorce, for example, wealth accrued before marriage is alloc
according to default rules that can be altered in pre-nuptial agreements, while income earned
marriage is immutably divided. Similarly, the repayment priorities set by state debtor-credit
can, like default rules, be reordered through private contract. The laws of intestacy are also d
rules: they fill any testamentary gap, but can be contracted around. As discussed below, infr
accompanying notes 83-91, one can distinguish between defaults that must be bilaterally cont
around and defaults that may be unilaterally overcome.
11. See I. MACNEIL, CONTRACTS: EXCHANGE TRANSACTIONS AND RELATIONS 346-47 (
Calabresi & Melamed, supra note 1; Easterbrook & Fischel, The Economic Structure of Cor
Law, 89 COLUM. L. REV. (forthcoming 1989) (manuscript at 21-30; on file with authors).
12. Note that even when there are negative externalities, third parties may be able to pro
themselves without immutable rules. One implication of the Coase theorem is that in a world wit
transaction costs, third parties will have an incentive to contract to reduce externalities to an eff
level. See Coase, The Problem of Social Cost, 3 J. LAW & ECON. 1 (1960). There are no extern
if the class of parties to the potential contract is defined broadly enough. G. Priest, Internalizing
(Yale Law School Program in Civil Liability 1988; working paper no. 93) (explicating pervasiv
of private incentives to internalize costs).
13. A recent conference (Dec. 9-10, 1988) on "Contractual Freedom in Corporate Law" at Co-
lumbia's Center for Law and Economic Studies focused directly on the appropriate application of
immutable rules. For example, Jeffrey Gordon argued that having multiple precedents that construe
single legal standard produces positive externalities that might justify imposing an immutable rule. Se
J. Gordon, The Mandatory Structure of Corporate Law (Dec. 2, 1988) (unpublished manuscript on
file with authors).
14. Courts or legislatures are inevitably forced to set defaults, because contracts with gaps need t
be interpreted. Courts must do something-even if that something is non-enforcement. As discusse
infra text accompanying notes 51-52, defaults of non-enforcement can play an important role in
efficient law.
15. For instance, Anthony Kronman has written:
[E]x ante arguments for the efficiency of a particular legal rule assume that individuals remain
free to contract around that rule, and a legal system that denies private parties the right to
vary rules in this way will tend to be less efficient than a system that adopts the same rules but
permits contractual variation.
Kronman, Specific Performance, 45 U. CHI. L. REV. 351, 370 (1978). See Haddock, Macey &
McChesney, Property Rights in Assets and Resistance to Tender Offers, 73 VA. L. REV. 701, 736
(1987) ("The ability of firms to contract around costly legal rules when lower-cost private alternatives
are available must be a feature of any efficient standard-form contract."); see also Goetz & Scott,
Liquidated Damages, Penalties and the Just Compensation Principle: Some Notes on an Enforce-
ment Model and a Theory of Efficient Breach, 77 COLUM. L. REV. 554 (1977) (arguing that "immu-
table" standards for determining enforceability of liquidated damages clauses should be relaxed). But
see Clarkson, Miller & Muris, Liquidated Damages v. Penalties: Sense or Nonsense?, 1978 Wis. L.
REV. 351 (providing efficiency rationale for immutable liquidated-damages rules).
16. For example, Haddock and Macey have suggested that immutable rules against insider trad-
ing are inefficient but have remained agnostic about whether corporations wishing to allow their
insiders to trade should be forced to "opt out" of an insider trading prohibition, or whether corpora-
tions wishing to prohibit insider trading should be forced to "opt in" to such a system. Haddock &
Macey, A Coasian Model of Insider Trading, 80 Nw. U.L. REV. 1449 (1987).
17. See, e.g., Easterbrook & Fischel, Limited Liability and the Corporation, 52 U. CHI. L. REV.
89, 102 (1985) ("In light of the ability of firms to duplicate or at least approximate either limited or
unlimited liability by contract, does the legal rule of limited liability matter? The answer is yes, but
probably not much.").
18. Looking backward to what the present litigants "would have wanted" is analytically analo-
gous to looking forward to what prospective contractors will want. It is to ask (as Lea Brilmayer often
does) "who are the prospective parties rooting for?" In both cases the court examines ex ante incen-
tives. While ex post each party will have economic incentives to shift costs to the other side, ex ante
the parties have an incentive to place the risks on the least-cost avoider. Kronman, Mistake, Disclo-
sure, Information and the Law of Contracts, 7 J. LEGAL STUD. 1 (1978). If a court can identify that
ex ante the parties to the contract had identical interests in allocating a certain risk or duty of per-
formance, then it can, in a sense, pierce the ex post adversarial veil. Thus, for example, even if ex post
a particular tenant wants to avoid the risk of fire damage, ex ante both landlords and tenants may
have preferred to have tenants bear this risk as the least-cost avoider. Thus, the fact that after a fire a
tenant tries to avoid liability is not dispositive of what prospective tenants would contract for or,
Frank Easterbrook and Daniel Fischel have championed the "would have
wanted" theory in a number of articles suggesting that "corporate law
should contain the [defaults] people would have negotiated, were the costs
of negotiating at arms'-length for every contingency sufficiently low.""9
Similarly, Richard Posner has argued that default rules should "econo-
mize on transaction costs by supplying standard contract terms that the
parties would otherwise have to adopt by express agreement." Douglas
Baird and Thomas Jackson have argued that the default rules governing
the debtor-creditor relationship "should provide all the parties with the
type of contract that they would have agreed to if they had had the time
and money to bargain over all aspects of their deal."'21 While this litera-
ture has vigorously examined what particular parties would have con-
tracted for in particular contractual settings,22 it has failed to question
whether the "would have wanted" standard is conceptually sound.23
Thus, although the academy recognizes the analytic difference between
24. The "default" characterization seems currently in vogue. Professor Robert Clark explains its
etymology:
For those who haven't been exposed to this jargon from the world of computers, "default
rules" are the rules that a program follows in "default" of an explicit choice by the user to
have some other principle apply. For example, your word processing program may set paper
margins of 1 inch on all sides unless you take the trouble to learn the relevant commands and
set the margins otherwise.
Clark, Contracts, Elites, and Traditions in the Making of Corporate Law, 89 COLUM. L. REV.
(forthcoming 1989) (manuscript at 3 n.9; on file with authors).
25. See Bebchuk, Limiting Contractual Freedom in Corporate Law: The Desirable Constraints
on Charter Amendments, 102 HARV. L. REV. 1820 (1989) (using "opt-out" and "opt-in"); Coffee,
The Mandatory/ Enabling Balance in Corporate Law: An Essay on the Judicial Role, 89 COLUM. L.
REV. (forthcoming 1989) (using "enabling"); Easterbrook & Fischel, supra note 11 (using "standby,"
"enabling," "presets," and "fallback"); Eisenberg, The Foundational Model of the Corporation, 89
COLUM. L. REV. (forthcoming 1989) (using "enabling" and "suppletory" terms); Goetz & Scott,
supra note 21, at 971 (using "preformulated"); Haddock, Macey & McChesney, supra note 15, at
736 (using "default" and "standard-form"); Schwab, supra note 1, at 237 (using "presumptive" and
"off-the-rack"); Speidel, Restatement Second: Omitted Terms and Contract Method, 67 CORNELL L.
REV. 785 n.2 (1982) (using "gap-filling").
26. RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF CONTRACTS ? 204 ("Supplying an Omitted Essential Term")
(setting default for missing term to be "a term which is reasonable in the circumstances"). See Speidel,
supra note 25, at 792-809.
27. For example, U.C.C. ? 2-306, governing output and requirement contracts, establishes as a
default that: In the absence of a stated estimate, "no quantity unreasonably disproportionate . . . to
any normal or otherwise comparable prior output or requirements may be tendered or demanded."
U.C.C. ? 2-306(1) (1976). In determining reasonableness, courts are expressly asked by the U.C.C. to
look at specific characteristics of the contracting parties. For example, "[a] shut-down by a require-
ments buyer for lack of orders might be permissible when a shut-down merely to curtail losses would
not." U.C.C. ? 2-306(1) comment 2 (1976).
28. Goetz & Scott, supra note 21, at 971 (emphasis in original).
29. There are two distinct ways for a contract to be incomplete. First, a contract may fail to
specify the parties' duties for specific future contingencies. For example, a contract for the construc-
tion of a third floor to a house may not state the parties' respective rights and responsibilities should
the entire house burn down before construction is started. Since construction of a third floor is impos-
sible (without the lower two floors), the contract does not cover the contingency of the house burning
down.
The second form of contractual incompleteness is more subtle. A contract may also be incomplete in
that it is insensitive to relevant future contingencies. Under this second form of contractual incom-
pleteness, parties' duties are fully specified, but the contracts are incomplete because those specified
duties are not tailored to economically relevant future events. See K. Spier, Incomplete Contracts in a
Model with Adverse Selection and Exogenous Costs of Enforcement (Dec. 1988) (unpublished manu-
script on file with authors) (discussing causes for such incompleteness). For example, consider a con-
tract that simply obligates one party to construct a garage adjacent to a house. On the face this
contract imposes a duty to build a garage whether or not the adjacent house burns down before
construction of the garage is complete. The contract is incomplete in this second sense, however, be-
cause the duty to build a garage is not sufficiently dependent on future contingencies. If the adjacent
house burns down, the parties probably would want to adjust the terms of contract. Such contracts we
call insufficiently state-contingent.
Courts recognize the first form of incompleteness and know they must decide how to fill the gap.
For instance, non-enforcement is one way courts can fill the gap. Courts seldomly recognize the sec-
ond form of contractual incompleteness. That is, they are generally unwilling to alter (they strictly
enforce) the terms of a contract that is insufficiently state-contingent. The main exception to strict
enforcement is the doctrine of impossibility (or economic impracticability) with which courts some-
times refuse enforcement when performance, although literally possible, is not ex post efficient. See
Posner & Rosenfield, Impossibility and Related Doctrines in Contract Law: An Economic Analysis, 6
J. LEGAL STUD. 83, 87 (1977) (discussing legal contours of impossibility doctrine).
30. See 0. WILLIAMSON, THE ECONOMIC INSTITUTIONS OF CAPITALISM 70 (1985); MacNeil,
Contracts: Adjustment of Long-Term Economic Relations Under Classical, Neoclassical and Rela-
tional Contract Law, 72 Nw. U.L. REV. 854, 871-73 (1978); Shavell, Damage Measures for Breach
of Contract, 11 BELL J. ECON. 466, 468 (1980) ("[Bjecause of the costs involved in enumerating and
bargaining over contractual obligations under the full range of relevant contingencies, it is normally
impractical to make contracts which approach completeness.").
31. See infra Section II.
32. Id.
33. Jeffrey Gordon argues that the "would have wanted" approach is also flawed b
risks to the ex ante least-cost avoider but, as applied by most courts, does not in fact co
ex post risk bearer. Gordon, supra note 13, at 61 (problem with hypothetical bargain
other Kaldor-Hicks arguments, is that it doesn't guarantee that each party will in fact r
slice, or a slice of the right size." (citation omitted)).
34. See infra Section II for examples of strategic incompleteness. A third reason for contractual
incompleteness is that some contingencies may simply be unforeseen by all contracting parties. In this
case, the default rule will not affect the actions of the parties since by definition they do not consider
the contingency in deciding what to do. There will normally be no reason to consider the rule's ex
ante effect because it will have none.
There is one caveat to this statement: Behavior may be affected if parties are aware that unforeseen
contingencies exist but are unable to ascertain the nature of these contingencies. For example, parties
who are aware that a variety of unforeseen contingencies may affect the price at which they should
transact may choose a contract that includes a reasonable price clause rather than fixing a price or a
price rule as a function of foreseen contingencies. In this way the price can respond to unforeseen
contingencies. See D. Kreps, Static Choice in the Presence of Unforeseen Contingencies (Aug. 1988)
(unpublished manuscript on file with authors) for a utility-theoretic characterization of behavior in
the presence of unforeseen contingencies. The choice of optimal defaults for such unforeseen contin-
gencies is beyond the scope of this article. For a discussion of the appropriate default, see Posner &
Rosenfield, supra note 29.
35. See K. Spier, supra note 29 (formalizing this strategic reluctance to reveal information).
36. See infra Section I-C.
37. Inefficient strategic behavior will often induce efficiency-promoting counterstrategies by other
economic actors. See Easterbrook, Predatory Strategies and Counterstrategies, 48 U. CHI. L. REV.
263 (1981).
38. See infra text accompanying notes 113-16.
39. We will sometimes find it useful to distinguish between situations in which the parties negoti-
ate in ignorance of the default rule and situations in which the parties negotiate in the shadow of the
default rule. In the former case, the parties do not know how the courts will decide if the contingency
in question occurs, while in the latter case the parties know the legal default (but may not know
certain information about the other party). See infra text accompanying notes 58-60.
40. See infra Section III.
41. See Easterbrook & Fischel, supra note 11, at 21-30.
42. U.C.C. ? 2-305(1) reads: "The parties if they so intend can conclude a contract for sale even
though the price is not settled. In such a case the price is a reasonable price at the time for deliv-
ery...." U.C.C. ? 2-305(1) (1976).
43. U.C.C. ? 2-201 states that a "contract ... is not enforceable under this [provision] beyond the
quantity of goods shown...." U.C.C. ? 2-201(1) (1976). The official comment adds that "[tlhe only
term which must appear is the quantity term which need not be accurately stated but recovery is
limited to the amount stated." U.C.C. ? 2-201(1) (official comment) (1978). In some cases, lack of a
quantity term will merely be evidence that the parties did not have a meeting of the minds. But even
if there are sufficient objective indicia of an intent to contract (and even if the statute of frauds is not
raised as an affirmative defense), courts may refuse to enforce the contract because it is indefinite. See
Jessen Bros. v. Ashland Recreation Ass'n., 204 Neb. 19, 281 N.W.2d 210 (1979) (contract for sod
unenforceable for lack of specific quantity term); Burke v. Campbell, 258 Mass. 153, 154 N.E. 759
(1927) (contract unenforceable in part because contract did not state how much stock defendant would
receive in exchange for financing corporation); King v. Krischer Mfg. Co., 220 A.D. 584, 222 N.Y.S.
66 (1927) (contract unenforceable because "a quantity of merchandise" too indefinite).
44. A simple "what parties would have wanted" approach has trouble explaining why the parties
would choose reasonable price at time of delivery instead of at the time of contracting. There is no
reason to think that parties would systematically prefer one risk allocation to the other. However, one
can determine the efficient default rule by asking the question, "why didn't the parties explicitly
contract for price?" Those parties who wish to allocate the risk of cost fluctuations to the seller will
most likely contract for a price at the time of contracting. Those who wish to allocate the risk to the
buyer will attempt to contract for a time-of-delivery, cost-based price. Such a clause may be costly to
write into the contract explicitly because of the difficulty in measuring the seller's cost exactly. The
parties may instead prefer to rely on reaching an agreement in the shadow of the court's reasonable-
price default rule.
45. This analysis suggests that courts would be less likely to enforce contracts in "thin" markets
in which the market price is not readily ascertainable. See Haddock, McChesney & Spiegel, An Ordi-
nary Economic Rationale for Extraordinary Legal Sanctions, 78 CALIF. L. REV. (forthcoming 1990)
(discussing how efficient legal rules will turn on "thickness" of market).
46. Even if the judicial system were not subsidized, the zero-quantity default might be justified on
parentalistic concerns. For example, if private parties are uninformed or systematically underestimate
the costs of ex post judicial determination of a "reasonable" quantity, it might be in society's interests
to dissuade parties from mistakenly failing to negotiate the contract quantity ex ante.
This rationale for this penalty default depends on the assumption that the private parties pay less
than the full costs of their ex post litigation. The parties may lower their transaction costs by shifting
the privately funded ex ante negotiations to publicly subsidized ex post litigation. If parties fully
internalized ex post litigation costs, at first cut they should be able to choose the cheaper type of
negotiation.
47. In encouraging the revelation of information, lawmakers should be sensitive to the influence
that defaults can have on the incentives for private parties to acquire information in the first place. See
infra notes 93-94 and accompanying text.
48. Penalty defaults may be established to provide information to third parties other than the
courts. For example, in corporate law certain alterations to the default corporate governance can be
accomplished through a by-law amendment, while other alterations can only be made by changing the
articles of incorporation. See infra note 148 and accompanying text. Requiring certain amendments in
the articles of incorporation reveals information to interested third parties, such as creditors, because
these articles are publicly filed with the Secretary of State. See, e.g., REVISED MODEL BUSINESS
CORP. ACT ANN. ? 2.01 (1987) (requiring filing of articles of incorporation).
49. Steinberg v. Chicago Medical School, 41 Ill. App. 3d 804, 807, 354 N.E.2d 586, 589 (1976);
see also Parks v. Atlanta News Agency, 115 Ga. App. 842, 156 S.E.2d 137 (1967); 1 A. CORBIN,
CORBIN ON CONTRACTS ? 95 (1952 & Supp. 1989); 1 S. WILLISTON, A TREATISE ON THE LAW OF
CONTRACTS ? 37 (3d ed. 1957 & Supp. 1978).
50. See REVISED MODEL BUSINESS CORP. ACT ANN. ? 2.02 (1987).
51. Posner defines opportunism (in relation to the common-law contractual duty to act in good
faith) as "taking advantage of the vulnerability of the other party to a contract . . . that is due to the
sequential character of performance." R. POSNER, supra note 2, at 81.
52. Similar opportunistic incentives have been analyzed in other areas of contract law. See, e.g.,
Clarkson, Miller & Muris, Liquidated Damages Versus Penalties: Sense or Nonsense?, 1978 WIS. L.
REV. 351 (non-enforcement of penalty clauses prevents opportunistic breach inducement); Goetz &
Scott, supra note 15, at 586 (mitigation requirement eliminates incentive for opportunism by obligee
in case of breach). More generally, the inefficiency of excessive penalties has been detailed in the
economics-of-crime literature. See, e.g., R. POSNER, supra note 2, at 205-12; Becker, Crime and
Punishment: An Economic Approach, 76 J. POL. ECON. 169 (1968).
53. See infra text accompanying notes 57-73.
split between the seller and the broker if their agency contract does not
address this contingency? Some courts have adopted a "what the parties
would have wanted" approach and have awarded all the earnest money to
the seller."4 We agree with this outcome, but for different reasons. The
real estate broker will more likely be informed about the default rule than
the seller. Indeed, the seller may not even consider the issue of how to
split the earnest money in case of default.56 Therefore, if the efficient con-
tract would allocate some of the earnest money to the seller, the default
rule should be set against the broker to induce her to raise the issue. Oth-
erwise, if the default rule is set to favor the broker, a seller may not raise
the issue, and the broker will be happy to take advantage of the seller's
ignorance. By setting the default rule in favor of the uninformed party,
the courts induce the informed party to reveal information, and, conse-
quently, the efficient contract results.
Although social welfare may be enhanced by forcing parties to reveal
information to a subsidized judicial system, it is more problematic to un-
derstand why society would have an efficiency interest in inducing a rela-
tively informed party to a transaction to reveal information to the rela-
tively uninformed party. After all, if revealing information is efficient
because it increases the value created by the contract, one might initially
expect that the informed party will have a sufficient private incentive to
reveal information-the incentive of splitting a bigger pie. This argument
ignores the possibility, however, that revealing information might simulta-
neously increase the total size of the pie and decrease the share of the pie
that the relatively informed party receives. If the "share-of-the-pie effect"
dominates the "size-of-the-pie effect," informed parties might rationally
choose to withhold relevant information.57
Parties may behave strategically not only because they have superior
54. See, e.g., Dennis Reed, Ltd. v. Goody, 2 K.B. 277 (1950); see also J. DUKEMINIER & J.
KRIER, PROPERTY 554-55 (2d ed. 1988) (discussing evolution of common-law rule).
55. Earnest money is used to force the purchaser to internalize the cost to the seller of taking the
property off the market during the time from the signing of the sale agreement to the closing or, in
this case, the breach. Since these costs are largely incurred by the seller, she should receive the com-
pensation. Furthermore, the seller may wish to give the broker incentives to find a buyer who will not
default. Allowing the broker to share in the earnest money will lower or eliminate this incentive. One
reason, however, that the broker and the seller would ex ante contract for the broker to receive some
of the earnest money is that the breach by the initial buyer may necessitate a quick sale which may
cause the seller to lower the selling price. This, in turn, would lower the broker's commission. Thus, a
"what the parties would have wanted" approach might yield a default in which a risk-averse broker
receives a portion of the earnest money.
56. Of course, people hire lawyers in part to ascertain the relevant negotiation issues, contingen-
cies, and default rules. Our argument is therefore most applicable in contractual settings in which
lawyers are not employed.
57. Withholding socially valuable private information to obtain private gains is common. Compa-
nies may withhold information about innovations from competitors to increase profits; car buyers may
withhold information about particular options or accessories that they value if this information signals
to car dealers a greater willingness to pay for the underlying automobile; and professional athletes
may withhold information about injuries to increase their salaries, even though as a result their team
may inefficiently hire reserves.
How can it be that by increasing the total gains from contracting (the
size-of-the-pie effect) the informed party can end up with a smaller share
of the gains (the share-of-the-pie effect) ?58 This Article demonstrates how
relatively informed parties can sometimes benefit by strategically with-
holding information that, if revealed, would increase the size of the pie. A
knowledgeable buyer, for example, may prefer to remain indistinguishable
from what the seller wrongly perceives to be the class of similarly situated
buyers. By blending in with the larger class of contractors, a buyer or a
seller may receive a cross-subsidized price because the other side will bar-
gain as if she is dealing with the average member of the class. A knowl-
edgeable party may prefer to remain in this inefficient, but cross-
subsidized, contractual pool rather than move to an efficient, but unsub-
sidized, pool. If contracting around the default sufficiently reduces this
cross-subsidization, the share-of-the-pie effect can exceed the size-of-the-
pie effect because the informed party's share of the default pie was in a
sense being artificially cross-subsidized by other members of the contrac-
tual class. Under this scenario, withholding information appears as a kind
of rent-seeking59 in which the informed party foregoes the additional
value attending the revealed information to get a larger piece of the con-
tractual pie.60
58. If, under a given set of default rules, a seller wants to sell a sweater that she values at $50 to a
buyer who values it at $150, then without contracting around any of the defaults the parties' agree-
ment will create $100 of value. The total gain from contracting, in other words, will be $100. The
parties will split this gain in value between themselves by bargaining for a price between $50 and
$150. Suppose, however, that the buyer (and only the buyer) has information that would make the
sweater worth $200 to him if the seller would take on a duty that is outside of the default provisions
and that would cost the seller $10. The total gains from this non-default exchange would be $140
($200 - $50 - $10). How could the buyer lose by revealing information that increased the size of the
pie by $40? If the parties accept the default provisions and negotiate a $100 price (implying that each
party receives a $50 share of the total gains), how can it be that revealing the value-enhancing infor-
mation-by contracting for the non-default duty-would reduce the buyer's share to less than $50
(implying that the negotiated price would exceed $150 and that the seller's share would exceed $90)?
59. Most broadly, rent-seeking "arises wherever parties have an incentive to expend real resources
to capture something of value." V. GOLDBERG, READINGS IN THE ECONOMICS OF CONTRACT LAW
49 (1989). Strategic withholding represents a species of rent-seeking because the relatively informed
party commits the real resources of an inefficient contract to capture the cross-subsidization.
60. An equity-minded court might encourage information revelation to foster an equitable distri-
bution of the gains from contracting, even if doing so reduces those gains.
61. 9 Ex. 341, 156 Eng. Rep. 145 (1854). William Bishop has also discussed how the Hadley rule
could promote efficient revelation of information. See Bishop, The Contract-Tort Boundary and the
Economics of Insurance, 12 J. LEGAL STUD. 241, 254 (1983); L. Bebchuk & S. Shavell, Information
and the Scope of Liability for Unusual Damages from Breach of Contract, (March 1983) (unpub-
lished manuscript on file with authors).
62. Hadley, 9 Ex. at 356, 156 Eng. Rep. at 151-52.
63. There is some evidence that the miller in fact attempted to inform the carrier of the probable
damages. Thus, it may be difficult for parties to contract around the Hadley default. For a discussion
of how courts can alter the mutability of a default rule by varying the requirements for contracting
around it, see infra Section III.
64. The efficient risk-sharing agreement between symmetrically-informed shippers (e.g., the
miller in this case) and carriers will depend upon their relative attitudes toward risk, the ability of the
carrier to prevent the damages, and the ability of the shipper to mitigate damages in case of breach.
Richard Posner and Richard Epstein argue that in many situations there are actions the shipper
could take to reduce consequential damages. See R. POSNER, supra note 2, at 114-15; Epstein, Be-
yond Foreseeability: Consequential Damages in the Law of Contract, 18 J. LEGAL STUD. 105,
121-25 (1989). In such situations the parties would choose to share consequential damages through
appropriate liquidated damage clauses. See Cooter, Unity in Tort, Contract, and Property: The
Model of Precaution, 73 CALIF. L. REV. 1, 15 (1985). In Evra Corp. v. Swiss Bank Corp., 673 F.2d
951, 955-59 (7th Cir. 1982), Judge Posner attempts to determine what insurance arrangement the
parties would have contracted for. Epstein prefers a less tailored rule that does not require the courts
to analyze the relative abilities of both sides to reduce damages.
We proceed under the assumptions that the miller had no economically practical means of reducing
the losses from delay (e.g., keeping a spare crankshaft in inventory would have been too expensive)
and that both parties were risk-neutral. Under these assumptions the efficient contract is for the
carrier who is the least-cost avoider to bear the costs of delay.
65. This is one lesson from Goetz and Scott's analysis of the anxious alumnus: A bus company
driving Dean Smith to the Final Four would probably take more efficient precautions if it were
warned of how large Dean Smith's consequential damages would be were he to miss the game. Goetz
& Scott, supra note 15, at 578.
66. The uninformed parties, the carriers, could simply exclude unforeseeable consequential dam-
ages from their standard-form contract (thereby contracting around the default at very low cost), and
high-damage millers, if they want insurance, could simply contract around the contract default. In
other words, if the legal default rule is inefficient, contracting parties may have ways of supplanting it
with a default of their own. (This point can also be made with regard to Posner's story about film
development; see infra text accompanying note 67.) The limits to this contractual response to the
contra-Hadley default are discussed infra notes 70-71 and text accompanying notes 69-71.
67. R. POSNER, supra note 2, at 114 (emphasis in original).
68. In the economics literature several articles examine situations in which asymmetric informa-
tion induces inefficient contracting. See, e.g., Akerlof, The Market for "Lemons": Quality Uncertainty
and the Market Mechanism, 84 Q.J. ECON. 488 (1970); Myerson, Mechanism Design by an In-
formed Principal, 51 ECONOMETRICA 1767 (1983).
74. Goldberg, An Economic Analysis of the Lost-Volume Retail Seller, 57 S. CAL. L. REV. 283
(1984).
75. See U.C.C. ? 2-708(2) (1976); Goetz & Scott, Measuring Sellers' Damages: The Lost-Profits
Puzzle, 31 STAN. L. REV. 323, 323 (1979); Speidel & Clay, Seller's Recovery of Overhead Under
UCC Section 2-708(2): Economic Cost Theory and Contract Remedial Policy, 57 CORNELL L. REV.
681, 694 (1972).
76. Goldberg, supra note 74, at 291.
77. In this situation the uninformed party, the consumer, probably could not offer a menu of
contracts to the informed retailer to induce revelation of the markup. See supra text accompanying
notes 69-71. The information requirements, complexity, and transaction costs of such a scheme would
be prohibitive.
78. This is similar to our earlier discussion of what the real estate default rule should be for
her liable for lost profits, the seller will have little incentive to bargain
about damages.79 Consumer liability for lost profits can lead to efficient
breach and precaution only if consumers know the amount of their liabil-
ity. The zero-damages penalty default encourages the retailer to reveal her
markup.80
Although consumers would value this markup information, retailers
still have incentives to withhold it.81 By revealing their profits, retailers
may simultaneously reduce their bargaining power. Even Goldberg's pen-
alty default, therefore, could be too weak to induce information disclosure.
Retailers may sometimes prefer to take their chances with zero damages
for breach rather than disclose a high markup. If the zero-damage penalty
default is insufficient to induce information revelation, a stiffer penalty
may be necessary to induce the parties to contract for liquidated
damages.
splitting earnest money between the seller and the broker when a buyer breaches a purchase contract.
See supra text accompanying notes 54-56.
79. If the seller raises the issue of damages, thereby revealing her markup, consumers can more
efficiently take precautions to avoid breach. Since the consumer will learn she is liable for damages,
however, she will insist on a lower price for the good.
80. Similarly, the common-law doctrine of construing ambiguities in contracts against the drafter,
see I. MACNEIL, supra note 11, at 372, can be viewed as a penalty default. The doctrine is not based
on the judgment that the parties would have wanted the anti-drafter provision, but that such a penalty
encourages drafters to draft more precise contracts.
81. For a fuller discussion of this point, see Ayres & Miller, "I'll Sell It To You At Cost": Legal
Methods to Promote Honest Retail Markup Disclosure, 84 Nw. U.L. REV. (forthcoming 1990) (man-
uscript on file with authors).
82. It is not necessarily true, however, that retailers will reveal their markups via their choice of
liquidated damages. All retailers may uniformly negotiate for minimal liquidated damages that pro-
vide no more information than the zero-damage default.
83. U.C.C. ? 2-206(1) (1976).
84. 251 Minn. 188, 86 N.W.2d 689 (1957).
85. The court concluded that the newspaper advertisements constituted offers and not merely
tations to make an offer. Id. at 192, 86 N.W.2d at 691.
D. Summary
information, it may be desirable for the law to give them a nudge. The
possibility that efficient defaults will at times be used to reflect what most
people want while at other times be used to encourage the revelation of
information is analogous to the disparate uses of presumptions in the laws
of evidence."' In both instances, the law is sometimes chosen to promote
the revelation of information.
Finally, having shown that lawmakers will sometimes want to set de-
faults that encourage one or both parties to reveal information, we now
should warn lawmakers that they should sometimes protect the private
incentives to become informed. In some instances forcing parties to reveal
information will undermine their incentives to obtain the information in
the first place.9" Lawmakers therefore should not impose penalty defaults
that have a net effect of reducing the amount of socially useful informa-
tion. But in some instances, a particular party may need to acquire certain
types of information before contracting, so that forcing disclosure would
have minimal disincentive effects. For instance, in Goldberg's example of
lost-profit damages, retailers naturally knew the profits from a sale. It is
hard, therefore, to conceive how forcing retailers to disclose their profits
would undermine their private incentives to calculate the profitability of a
sale.94
92. The list of penalty defaults analyzed above is far from exhaustive. For example, the U.C.C.
sections which establish implied or default warranties, U.C.C. ?? 2-314 and 2-315, cannot easily be
justified as "what the parties would have contracted for." Instead, the defaults, consistent with the
foregoing analysis, force sellers to reveal information to consumers about the extent of their coverage.
Indeed, one way to identify penalty defaults is to investigate the pervasiveness with which parties
contract around them, as is done with the seemingly ubiquitous use of limited warranty disclaimers.
U.C.C. ? 2-207 is also inconsistent with "would have wanted" default analysis. This section sup-
plants the common-law mirror-image rule with the default that additional terms in an acceptance that
do not materially alter the terms of the offer become part of a contract between merchants. This
default cannot be reconciled with a "what the parties would have contracted for" analysis, because
there is no reason to think that the merchants would have wanted to include the additional terms of
their contract. Instead, the rule places an informational burden on the party with the last clear chance
to come forward and notify the other side if the additional terms are objectionable.
Evidentiary presumptions in litigation are sometimes used to reflect a relationship between facts
and at other times to place the burden of producing evidence on the party who is more likely to be
informed. See Allen, Presumptions in Civil Actions Reconsidered, 66 IOWA L. REV. 843, 845 (1981)
(suggesting that presumptions are used "to construct rules of decision to avoid factual impasse at trial;
to allocate burdens of persuasion; to instruct the jury on the relationship between facts; and to allocate
burdens of production").
93. See R. POSNER, supra note 2, at 115; Easterbrook, Insider Trading, Secret Agents, Eviden-
tiary Privileges, and the Production of Information, 1981 SuP. CT. REV. 309, 359; R. Allen, M.
Grady, D. Polsby & M. Yashko, Confidentiality of Legal Affairs (1988) (unpublished manuscript on
file with authors); cf Laidlaw v. Organ, 15 U.S. (2 Wheat.) 178 (1817) (permitting relatively in-
formed contracting party to profit by keeping information to himself). Of course, much of patent law
is justified as a means of encouraging the private production of information.
94. Anthony Kronman distinguishes "deliberately acquired information" from "casually acquired
information." For example, he suggests that if one side to a contract is aware that the other has
entered a mistaken bid, the special knowledge of the non-mistaken party "is unlikely to be the fruit of
a deliberate search." Requiring disclosure by the knowledgeable party of this casually acquired infor-
mation will accordingly not undermine incentives to become informed. Kronman, Mistake, Disclosure,
Information, and the Law of Contracts, 7 J. LEGAL STUD. 1, 32 (1978) (revealing lost profits from
contract can undermine incentives for parties to search for undervalued assets). There may be a trade-
off between inducing efficient search by one party and efficient breach by the other. Retailers do not
We assume that all parties are risk neutral, so the only goal of the
insurance aspect of the contract is to induce the carrier to take efficient
precaution. As argued above, in a world with full information, both high-
and low-damage millers would contract for the carrier to pay for their
consequential damages.96 If the carrier knows the miller's type and bears
all damages, she will choose the optimal level of precaution.97 Let KH and
KL equal the carrier's optimal investment in precaution for the two types
of millers, respectively. Let qH and qL equal the probability of damages
for each type of miller given the optimal level of precaution for the class.98
Before analyzing the likely equilibrium associated with each default, we
must say a bit more about the carrier's price. Assume for the moment that
the carrier is in a competitive market in which, by definition, there are
zero economic profits.99 Let the competitive price of shipping crankshafts
for known high-damage millers be PH and for known low-damage millers
be PL With this notation, if MC is the marginal cost of shipping with no
precaution, then the following equations will hold:
(1) PH MC + KH + qHDH'
(2) PL =MC + KL + qLDL
(6) PHin PH + fH
when they fail to contract around the Hadley low-damage default.
If the high-damage millers contract around this default, they should
expect to bear the costs of the increased precaution as reflected in a higher
shipping price (PH rather than PL) as well as the additional transaction
costs of contracting around the default (cH).'02 This total cost would be:
(7) PH + CH.
Thus, the high-damage mille
fault if the total cost of failin
costs of contracting (PH + CH):
(8) PH + fH > PH + CH,
or more simply if:
(9) fH > CH.
High-damage millers will c
fault when the cost of ineff
contracting around the def
around the Hadley default a
will contract for the efficie
ers will effectively pay PH
ers will pay PL
Now consider the non-Had
age of high-risk millers, a H
produce an equilibrium in which no one contracts around the default and
the carriers take only low levels of precaution, KL.104 If the carriers can-
not distinguish between high- and low-damage millers, competition would
cause the shipping price to become:
(1 0) P = aLPL + aHPH
Since in a competitive market, carriers
expected average cost of serving both h
represents a weighted average of these
the carriers PL' while the high-damage
inefficient, low level of precaution is ta
This will be the equilibrium if neithe
millers have an incentive to reveal to t
might think that the low-damage mille
forward and reveal their status in orde
But they will do so only if:
(11) cL < P* - PL- 06
Contracting around the high-damage default
savings from the reduced shipping price (P*
additional transaction cost, CL. But from equation (10) we see that the
equilibrium price, P*, is a positive function of aH, the percentage of high-
damage millers.107 If this percentage (aH) is sufficiently low, the transac-
tion costs (CL) will keep the low-damage millers from contracting around
the high-damage default. Note that this is unlike the low-damage default
in which the incentives to contract around the default rule are based on
the gains to the high-damage millers and are independent of the percent-
age of the population that has high damages (aH).
The high-damage millers will not reveal their true status to the carriers
because they would be forced to pay more (PH - P*) but would gain no
additional coverage. The high-damage millers fail to distinguish them-
selves not because of transaction costs, but because they prefer to withhold
this information strategically and to receive the subsidized shipping
price.108 The shipping price is subsidized because transaction costs preve
low-damage millers from contracting around the default. Even though the
information is socially valuable because it leads to more efficient precau-
tion and even though this value exceeds the transaction costs, the high-
damage millers prefer to remain undistinguished from their low-risk
counterparts. The high-damage millers do not mind that carriers take in-
efficiently low levels of precaution because, like all shippers, high-damage
millers are fully insured. The low-damage millers bear the costs of this
inefficiency, but are not hurt enough individually to distinguish them-
selves contractually.
Prior analyses of incomplete contracts have suggested that parties fail to
contract around inefficient defaults because of transaction costs.109 Our
analysis is striking because it demonstrates the possibility that parties may
fail to contract around defaults for strategic reasons.110 A relatively in-
formed party may strategically withhold information that would increase
the joint gains from trade.111 Moreover, the example illustrates two ex-
treme forms of default equilibria. The Hadley, low-damage default caused
all high-damage millers to contract around the rule and thus engendered
107. One could imagine situations in which the costs for low-damage millers of contracting
around a high-damage default would be small. For example, the Federal Express standard-form con-
tract limits consequential damages if the sender does not contract for more insurance. See supra note
70. Such a standard form would allow low-damage millers to cheaply opt for low-damage protection
and consequently a lower price.
108. In other words, even if the costs of contracting for higher precaution were zero, the high-
damage millers would not reveal their status.
109. See supra note 30.
110. In our simplified model, low-damage millers failed to contract around the pooling equil
rium because of transaction costs. See supra inequality (11). In a more general model, however, e
without transactions costs the informed cross-subsidizing parties (such as the low-damage mil
may fail to contract around pooling equilibria if in doing so they reveal information which redu
their bargaining power. See K. Spier, supra note 29 for a more formal demonstration of why sim
strategic concerns can keep contracts from being efficiently state-contingent.
111. This, then, is an example in which the "share-of-the-pie effect" exceeds the "size-of-the-
effect. See supra text accompanying note 57.
But the commonly accepted notion that untailored defaults should be set
at what the majority of parties wants does not hold in a more general
model of default choice in which the pooling and separating equilibria are
not extreme. To extend the Hadley model, consider the choice between
112. This analysis is consonant with the economics of insurance literature. See, e.g., Rothschild &
Stiglitz, Equilibrium in Competitive Insurance Markets: An Essay on the Economics of Imperfect
Information, 90 Q.J. ECON. 629, 634-37 (1976) (discussing "separating" and "pooling" equilibria).
Low-risk insureds will have incentives to drop out of (or separate from) pools in which they cross-
subsidize the premiums of high-risk insureds. See generally Priest, The Current Insurance Crisis and
Modern Tort Law, 96 YALE L.J. 1521 (1987) (arguing that this sort of separation has occurred in
third-party insurance pools and is largely responsible for recent "insurance crisis").
113. In this model all millers continue to ship crankshafts regardless of the default rule. If, how-
ever, the cross-subsidization of the non-Hadley default reduced the consumption of the low-damage
millers (who must pay P* - PL more) or increased the consumption of the high-damage millers (who
have to pay PH - P* less), then the pooling equilibria would additionally entail the dead-weight losses
associated with inefficient amounts of contracting. See Note, Contract Damages and Cross-
Subsidization, 61 S. CAL. L. REV. 1125 (1988).
114. a1 +a2 = 1.
115. See supra text accompanying note 100.
116. Because we assume that parties would never bargain for a less efficient contract, a, and a2
will always be greater than or equal to ,1 and ,2 respectively.
al > a2.
Indeed, exploiting the fact that a2 1 - a1,117 one can rearrange condi-
tion (12) in terms of a1. Default one will be efficient if and only if:
which again implies that default one will be efficient only if a majority
prefers it. Majoritarians are forced to make highly restrictive (and some-
times contradictory) assumptions to produce their desired rule. Most fun-
damentally, the majoritarian analysis errs by looking at only one of the
relevant variables, a.
As an alternative, some commentators have suggested that courts fill
gaps with the provisions that most parties bargain for in actual con-
tracts.120 Some academics have labelled this style of gap-filling as "mim-
icking-the-market."'121 The "mimic-the-market" approach to default rules
ignores the fact that the type of parties who contract around a given rule
depends upon the rule itself. Parties who dislike a given default rule will
contract around it; if we change the default rule to mimic the contracts
these parties write, other types of parties may contract around the new
default back to the original rule. This process could cycle forever.122 Set-
120. See Epstein, In Defense of the Contract at Will, 51 U. CHI. L. REV. 947, 951 (1984) (a
default rule "is normally chosen because it reflects the dominant practice in a given class of cases and
because that practice is itself regarded as making good sense for the standard transactions it gov-
erns."). Epstein argues that the default for consequential damages should be limited because this "is
what the express contracts have typically provided." Epstein, supra note 64, at 118. Frank Easter-
brook orally suggested a similar standard for choosing corporate default rules at the Columbia confer-
ence. See supra note 13.
The NLRB has looked at actual collective bargaining agreements in deciding whether there should
be a default limiting management's right to transfer work. See Milwaukee II, 268 N.L.R.B. Dec.
(CCH) 601, 603 (1984) (quoting Ozark Trailers, Inc., 161 N.L.R.B. Dec. (CCH) 561, 570 (1966)
(citing M. CHANDLER, MANAGEMENT RIGHTS AND UNION INTERESTS 217 (1964))). The Supreme
Court has at times looked to actual contracting practices to determine whether a particular issue
should be a mandatory subject of bargaining. See, e.g., First Nat'l Maintenance Corp. v. NLRB, 452
U.S. 666, 684 (1981); see also Alchian, Decision Sharing and Expropriable Specific Quasi-Rents: A
Theory of First National Maintenance Corporation v. NLRB, 1 SuP. CT. ECON. REV. 235 (1982)
(suggesting how "decision sharing" default should be set); Wachter & Cohen, The Law and Econom-
ics of Collective Bargaining: An Introduction and Application to the Problems of Subcontracting,
Partial Closure, and Relocation, 136 U. PA. L. REV. 1349, 1364-77 (1988) (suggesting how "de-
fault entitlements" in labor market should be set). However, in Lewis v. Benedict Coal Corp., 361
U.S. 459 (1960), discussed supra note 21, the Court eschewed any empirical analysis of the private
reaction to a particular contract.
121. See Schwab, Collective Bargaining and the Coase Theorem, 72 CORNELL L. REV. 245,
286-87 (1987).
122. This is not to say that the mimic-the-market rule would never be desirable. If, for instan
filling a particular type of contractual gap is an issue of first impression, it may be reasonable f
court to look at existing contracts as a guide to what the parties would have wanted. If parties w
unaware of the default rule when they were contracting, the cycling problem would not arise. If
well-established default exists, many contracting parties may explicitly contract for what they wan
order to avoid the penalty of ex post uncertainty. In this case existing contracts provide evidence f
what the parties would have done, so mimicking the market may be justified. For example, Epste
uses this approach to argue that one can ascertain the efficient form for workers' compensation leg
tion by observing the contractual insurance provisions that existed prior to legislation. Epstein, sup
note 64, at 118-19.
Mimicking the market may also make sense when parties have failed to record any contract. For
example, in devising their estates, many parties may not go to the trouble of writing a will, but those
that do may restate even well-established intestacy defaults. Thus, looking at actual wills can give
some guide to what the general populace wants. But even this argument fails if the contracting sample
misrepresents the intestate class. If the reason certain parties fail to contract is related to the substan-
tive provision that those parties want, then the inference between actual and hypothetical contracts is
attenuated. For example, if only upper-class people can afford to write wills, then an upper-class
preference for children over parents may not be relevant in determining the intestate preferences of
ting defaults that mimic the market therefore will not assure efficiency. A
slightly more sophisticated version of mimicking the market would set the
default at what most people would contract around another default for.
This approach would focus solely on the 3's. For example, if a larger
percentage of parties were willing to contract around the first default than
the second default ((2 > (1), then rule two would be chosen as the de-
fault. But maximizing the 3's suffers the same flaw as maximizing the
a's-neither choice rule conforms with the efficiency criterion in inequal-
ity (12).123
Implementing a complete theory of default choice requires attention to:
1) what the parties want (the a's),
2) whether they will get it (the d's), and
3) the costs associated with getting it (the c's) or not getting it (the f's).
It is especially important that lawmakers ascertain the degree of separat-
ing and pooling that each default engenders. For in determining the equi-
librium levels of the A associated with each default, the court must esti-
mate the importance of transactional and strategic barriers to contracting
around particular default rules, as well as understand the costs associated
with failing to strike the efficient contract.
We have shown that at times the efficient default will be one that a
majority of contracting parties disfavors. As the number of different types
of preferred contracts (and consequently the number of possible defaults)
increases, any untailored default is likely to be disfavored by the majority
of contractors.124 Untailored defaults act as penalty defaults with regard to
the costs of contracting around it are low (Cj 0, for all j).
For example, consider our earlier discussion of the zero-quantity default, supra text accompanying
notes 42-46. The default choice is non-dichotomous. Numerous quantities could be chosen as the
default. Although contracting parties would not contract to exchange zero quantity (x. = 0), most
people contract around this default, and the costs of contracting around it are low.
125. Any untailored quantity default would be, except for the smallest proportion of transactions,
a penalty default. For example, only the smallest percentage of contracting parties would actually
want a default quantity of some randomly chosen number such as, say, 39 or 2003.
126. Richard Epstein criticizes Judge Posner's analysis in EVRA Corp. v. Swiss Bank Corp., 673
F.2d 951, 954 (7th Cir. 1982), because contributory negligence requires costly ex post tailoring by
courts. Epstein, supra note 64, at 134.
127. 815 F.2d 429 (7th Cir. 1987).
128. Id. at 436; id. at 446-47 (Posner, J., dissenting).
133. At an even more basic level, courts will not be able to determine whether a contract has gaps
without a prior theory of contract formation. In general, courts will need to determine:
1) whether the parties have formed a contract,
2) whether the contract has gaps, and
3) how the gaps should be filled.
We implicitly assumed in Sections I and II that there were sufficient objective indicia of the parties
meeting of the minds to infer contractual formation. See Barnett, A Consent Theory of Contract, 86
COLUM. L. REV. 269 (1986) (discussing competing theories of contractual formation). This Section's
focus on legal formalities should inform courts' theories of contractual formation and contractual gaps.
134. This point is also made in M. Freed & D. Polsby, Hard Cases Make Bad Law: Employ-
ment at Will at the Edge (1988) (unpublished manuscript on file with authors). For example, Freed
and Polsby criticize Richard Epstein's analysis, see Epstein, supra note 120, at 980, that the court
supplied the correct "gap-filling" default in Coleman v. Graybar Elec. Co., 195 F.2d 374 (5th Cir.
1952), an employment at will/wrongful termination case: "The contract in Graybar was anything but
silent . . . . Such an agreement could hardly 'provide otherwise' with more clarity, short of specifi-
cally reserving the employer's right to act in bad faith." M. Freed & D. Polsby, supra, at 2.
135. 815 F.2d 429 (7th Cir. 1987); see supra text accompanying notes 127-31.
136. Judge Posner argued in the alternative. Although he concluded that the contract did not have
a gap, id. at 449 (Posner, J., dissenting) ("the parties were not silent"), he alternatively found that
even if there were a gap, it should be filled differently than the way Easterbrook recommended. See
supra text accompanying note 129.
137. 815 F.2d at 436.
138. Id. at 447 (Posner, J., dissenting) (quoting majority).
139. Id.
140. These costs were represented as ci in the early model of default choice. See supra Section II.
141. But see Black, supra note 1 (arguing that corporate default rules are trivial). Black's argu-
ments imply that corporate formalities do not impede corporations from establishing tailored forms of
corporate governance. But the costs of contracting around some "strong" defaults (that is, fulfilling
certain corporate formalities) are likely to give some formalities a more substantive or nontrivial na-
ture. See, e.g., infra notes 148-50.
142. See, e.g., U.C.C. ? 2-303 (1976).
143. U.C.C. ? 2-206 (1976) (emphasis added).
144. Id. at Official Comment 1 (emphasis added).
145. 222 F. Supp. 936 (S.D. Iowa 1963).
146. Id. at 939.
147. Id. at 942. The holding is consistent with the common-law doctrine of construing contr
It should be noted that the rule as stated does not interfere with the
property owner's right to "do what he will with his own," or his
right, if he chooses, to contract for "improvements" which will actu-
ally have the effect of reducing his property's value. Where such re-
sult is in fact contemplated by the parties, and is a main or principal
purpose of those contracting, it would seem that the measure of dam-
ages for breach would ordinarily be the cost of performance.155
There can be good economic reasons for "strong" defaults in which the
courts intentionally increase the procedural costs to parties of contracting
around the default. These reasons parallel the rationales given in one of
the first intuitively economic analyses of contract law, Lon Fuller's classic,
Consideration and Form.'62 Fuller suggested that legal formalities serve
157. Tracking the majority's language, we suggest that prospective parties attempting to overcome
the diminution-in-value standard include the following covenant:
The parties specifically intend and contemplate that the lessee shall restore the land, even if
the costs of performance are grossly disproportionate to the diminution in value from failing to
restore the land. This is a main and principal purpose of the lease. In writing this provision,
we are explicitly contracting around the holding of Peevyhouse v. Garland Coal.
If this provision were not sufficient, the Peevyhouse rule would, in fact, be immutable.
158. See, e.g., Birmingham, Damage Measures and Economic Rationality: The Geometry of Con-
tract Law, 1969 DUKE L.J. 49.
159. Peevyhouse, 382 P.2d at 114.
160. Courts may face the constitutional limitation of resolving only "cases or controversies" at
issue. U.S. CONST. art. III, ? 2, cl. 1. But other decisions have established prospective safeharbors.
See, e.g., Miranda v. Arizona, 384 U.S. 436 (1966) (establishing fair and effective warning require-
ment to persons in police custody).
161. The purpose of such contractual safeharbors should not be to preclude the parties from tai-
loring other standards. The safeharbor alternatives might additionally provide benefits as common-law
interpretations would more fully specify their meanings. See J. Gordon, supra note 13
162. Fuller, Consideration and Form, 41 COLUM. L. REV. 799 (1941). In truth, the fact that the
article is claimed by economists (it is, for example, reprinted in A. KRONMAN & R. POSNER, THE
ECONOMICS OF CONTRACT LAW 40 (1979)) is as much a tribute to the soundness of its insights as to
its nexus with economics.
170. 52 Misc. 2d 26, 274 N.Y.S.2d 757 (Dist. Ct. 1966), rev'd 54 Misc. 2d 119, 281 N.Y.S.2d
964 (App. Term 1967).
171. Frostifresh Corp. v. Reynoso, 54 Misc. 2d 119, 281 N.Y.S.2d 964 (App. Term 1967).
172. 270 Wis. 133, 70 N.W.2d 585 (1955).
173. The majority reconstructed the contract to have a covenant of "reasonable" duration. 270
Wis. at 146-47, 70 N.W.2d at 592. The dissent would have penalized the employer by allowing the
employee to compete immediately. Id. at 148-52, 70 N.W.2d at 593-94 (Gehl, J., dissenting).
174. A penalty for even attempting to contract around a legally immutable provision may b
necessary to deter attempts in a world where some disputes are not litigated. If all disputes were
litigated, attempts to contract around an immutable rule would never succeed. But if some contractual
parties fail to challenge unenforceable immutable rules, then imposing a penalty whenever a case does
come to court might be justified to prevent underdeterrence. For example, it is widely believed tha
CONCLUSION
creditors and residential landlords make a practice of including all sorts of illegal clauses in their
contracts not because they think the clauses will stand up in court, but because they know that most
debtors and tenants have more respect for written contracts than most courts do. The authors are
indebted to conversations with Richard Craswell for this point. See Craswell, supra note 22, at 64-65.
175. See supra Section I.B.
176. See Fullerton, 270 Wis. at 43, 70 N.W.2d at 590. The "blue pencil" test is the traditional
test of severability. If, after removing the unconscionable terms, the contract is still comprehensible in
that the parties might have still entered into it, the court will enforce it.
177. In many settings, such as simple contracts for small transactions, it is easy to point to trans-
action costs as the source of incompleteness. In other settings, however, parties write complicated,
lengthy contracts that are carefully considered by both parties and their lawyers. In these situations a
contingency that is not contracted for may be sufficiently important that it is unreasonable to ascribe
incompleteness to transaction costs. Some omitted clauses, for example, may be very inexpensive to
include from a transaction cost perspective, such as liquidated damage clauses or non-refundable de-
posits. In such cases courts will find it difficult to point to transaction costs as the source of incom-
pleteness, so penalty defaults should be considered.
178. For example, we suggested that Goldberg's zero-damage penalty default would not suffi-
ciently encourage retailers to contract for liquidated damages, and even if a larger penalty would, the
amount of liquidated damages in equilibrium might "pool" at a non-informative low level. See supra
Section I.C.2. Courts should also consider the possibility that some parties will fail to contract around
penalty defaults out of ignorance or oversight.
179. The Hadley rule is an example of a penalty default that 1) is cheap to contract around by
including a liquidated damage clause, 2) will likely cause damage information to be revealed, and 3)
will facilitate more efficient precaution.
We must add an important transitional caveat. A legal change from one default to another can be
costly-especially if the move is to a penalty default. Until parties become informed about the new
default, there may be transitional costs as the parties continue to bargain in the shadow of an invalid
law.
Finally, we note that in many contractual settings, both parties may have private information which
they choose to withhold. In such settings of "dual asymmetric information," penalty defaults may not
be sufficient to ensure that all private information is revealed.
188. For example, the statute of limitation gap of RICO in Malley-Duff is hard to explain as
hidden pork-barrel legislation.
189. In corporate law especially, the mechanism for contracting around the default may be ob-
lique. For example, while corporate statutes do not give the board of directors the right to disapprove
a merger, certain "poison pill" plans have the effect of making the board sign off on any hostile bid.
See Dynamics Corp. of Am. v. CTS Corp., 805 F.2d 705 (7th Cir. 1986) (analyzing economic impact
of "poison pill").