Corruption Criminal Law
Corruption Criminal Law
Corruption Criminal Law
By Susan Rose-Ackerman1
Abstract
The criminal law can play a back-up role in the fight against corruption.
The present article discusses five aspects of the criminal law on corrup-
tion. First, corruption may be reduced by legalizing some formerly illegal
activities and criminalizing others. Second, penalties need to be set to
achieve effective deterrence. Third, law enforcement authorities need tools
such as plea-bargaining to encourage bribe payers and recipients to
cooperate with authorities to uncover corruption. Fourth, corporations
and other organizations need to be held responsible for the corrupt
actions of their employees. Fifth, because corruption is often a side effect
of organized crime activity, authorities need to design strategies to deal
with this overlap. In general, the goals of law enforcement should be to
determine those corrupt systems that are doing the most damage and to
organize the deterrence effort to make corruption costly and to give
participants an incentive to report corrupt deals.
Introduction
Corruption cannot be fought solely through criminal law. Too often, Govern-
ments announce a crackdown on corruption and a spate of high-profile
prosecutions take place, only for the problem to re-emerge soon after-
wards as a new group of people takes advantage of the opportunities that
remain. A serious anti-corruption effort requires the State to re-examine
the relationship between government, citizens and businesses. Govern-
ments may need to redesign public programmes, overhaul the public ad-
ministration and the operation of the political system and become more
open to outside scrutiny and input from citizens. Nevertheless, the crimi-
nal law can play a role as a backstop lying behind the needed structural
changes. Unfortunately, it does not always play that role, even in coun-
tries where prosecutions for corruption are common. Sometimes, the
1
Henry R. Luce Professor of Law and Political Science, Yale University, and author of
Corruption and Government: Causes, Consequences, and Reform (1999). Portions of this article
are derived from that book. Aleksandra Sznajder provided help with the material on French and
Polish law.
4 Forum on Crime and Society, Vol. 2, No. 1, December 2002
problem is the biased use of the criminal law to target members of the
political opposition; in the extreme, such prosecutions deter opposition to
the regime in power but have little impact on corruption. Sometimes, the
problem is the weakness or venality of the judicial system. Then, even
cases based on strong evidence may fail in court and this possibility
deters prosecutors from bringing cases in the first place.
The present article considers the back-up role of the criminal law as
an aid to deterrence. There are several aspects to this problem: first, the
legalization of certain illegal activities can remove incentives for corruption;
conversely, some formerly legal activities may need to be criminalized to
deter activities that have much the same effect as outright bribes. Sec-
ond, penalties should be set to achieve optimal deterrence. Third, law
enforcement authorities should have the tools to encourage bribe payers
and bribe recipients to cooperate with authorities to uncover corrupt
transactions. Fourth, as bribes are frequently paid by people acting in the
interest of their employers, corporations and other organizations should
be held accountable under the criminal or civil law. This is an issue of
particular salience, given the new Organisation for Economic Cooperation
and Development (OECD) treaty that requires States to punish overseas
bribery by corporations engaged in international business. Finally, corrup-
tion is often a side effect of organized crime activity. Authorities need to
design strategies to deal with the intersection between organized crime
and corruption.
there are some areas where criminalization is providing few social benefits
and encouraging corruption and illegal business.
On the other side of the ledger, new criminal and civil offences may
need to be created. Many new democracies have not come to terms with
the problem of conflicts of interest among executive branch officials and
members of the legislature. Most developed countries use a mixture of
criminal sanctions, administrative penalties and ethical codes to regulate
civil servants and politicians involvement in decisions in which they have a
financial interest. Emerging democracies can learn from examining this
experience.
In the United States, a mixture of ethical codes and statutory re-
quirements constrains public officials (Gilman 1995, p. 65). Officials are
not permitted to use public office for private gain and are not to hold
financial interests that conflict with their duties, use inside information for
personal profit or accept gifts. Both the payment and receipt of bribes
are criminal offences. The receipt of a salary from sources outside the
Government is against the law, as are payments to officials for represent-
ing a private party in a particular matter in which the United States
has an interest. The law applies to both public officials and those who pay
them (Chakrabarti, Dausses and Olson 1997, pp. 597-605).2 Officials must
avoid the appearance of violating the law, even if their conduct technically
complies with it.
By way of comparison, French and Canadian conflict-of-interest re-
strictions have similar goals but use different methods. French law fo-
cuses more on administrative than criminal remedies, but shares the
fundamental goal of avoiding an unwholesome alliance between personal
financial interest and the exercise of the power of the state (Rohr 1991,
p. 284). Nevertheless, French restrictions seem, in practice, less strin-
gent. Financial disclosure of assets is not required as a routine matter,
and post-employment restrictions are poorly enforced (Rohr, pp. 284-286).
Canadian (and British) rules are also less restrictive. Parliamentary govern-
ment puts the prime minister in charge of the legislative agenda. This
means that, unlike the United States, conflict-of-interest laws are unlikely
to impose more stringent controls on members of the executive branch
than on members of parliament. Civil servants are regulated by administra-
tive rules, not statutes (Stark 1992, p. 429).
In practice, the most difficult enforcement problems concern job-
seeking. Although, in the United States, government outright quid pro
quos seem fairly well controlled by the code of conduct and the legal
sanctions behind it, officials are often hired after they leave government
service by firms that have business with their previous government em-
ployer. The code of conduct states that employees shall not engage in
outside employment or activities, including seeking or negotiating for em-
ployment, that conflict with official government duties and responsibilities.
Subject to several conditions, former officials cannot represent others
before their former employer within two years of termination. The ban is
2
18 USC 201, 203, 207, 208.
6 Forum on Crime and Society, Vol. 2, No. 1, December 2002
All countries draw the line somewhere between illegal bribery and accept-
able gifts of good will. They criminalize certain businesses such as the
drug trade and legalize others. Countries differ in where the dividing line is
set, and in this section that judgement is taken as given and an effective
deterrence strategy is sought. The sanctioning strategies proposed in the
present article are quite different from the conventional penalties, even in
developed countries. They focus both on improving the deterrent effect of
arrest and punishment and on rewarding those who come forward with
documentation on corrupt deeds.
The optimal amount of corruption is not zero, even if no value is given
to the benefits received by bribers. Once the costs of prevention are
taken into account, the level of deterrence expenditures should be set
where the marginal benefits equal the marginal costs (Anechiarico and
Jacobs 1996; Becker and Stigler 1974; Rose-Ackerman 1978, pp. 109-
119). The deterrence of criminal behaviour depends on the probability of
detection and punishment and on the penalties imposed, both those im-
posed by the legal system and more subtle costs such as loss of reputa-
tion or shame (Becker 1968). Law enforcement authorities can vary either
3
18 USC 207 (a)-(d).
Corruption and the criminal law 7
4
One study using United States data from the period 1970-1984 showed that both a
greater probability of conviction and longer prison terms deter corruption (Goel and Rich 1989).
5
In an interview in Taiwan Province of China in 1995, the Justice Minister Ma Ying Jeou
complained that Taiwanese law did not make it a crime for a citizen to offer a bribe. He claimed
that the lack of such an offence seems to encourage businessmen to give out all kinds of gifts
and has been a major obstacle to rooting out the hung bao culture [of giving money in red
envelopes to officials] (Far Eastern Economic Review 1995).
6
Law and economics scholars distinguish between bribery and extortion, depending upon
whether the payer receives better than fair treatment or must pay to be treated fairly (Ayres
1997, pp. 1234-1238; Lindgren 1988, p. 824); however, both are often combined in practice
(Ayres 1997, pp. 1236-1237).
8 Forum on Crime and Society, Vol. 2, No. 1, December 2002
tions that affect the allocation of legal benefits. The social costs depend
upon the damage done by using a willingness-to-pay criterion, on the one
hand, versus the inefficiencies and inequities of officials efforts to design
in bottlenecks and scarcity, on the other.
Regarding punishment strategies, a ranking of the social harm of
different kinds of corruption can help set enforcement priorities. However,
the penalties actually levied on the convicted should be tied not to these
social harms, but to the benefits received by the corrupt. Assuming that
society does not give positive weight to corrupt gains, the goal is to
reduce corruption as far as possible in spite of limited law enforcement
resources. In order to deter bribery, at least one side of the corrupt
transaction must face penalties that reflect its own gains. Because the
chance of detection and conviction is far less than one, those convicted
should sacrifice a multiple of these gains. From a pure deterrence point of
view, either side of the corrupt deal can be the focus of law enforcement
efforts. From the point of view of public acceptability, however, bribers
who seek legal benefits are likely to arouse public sympathies, not blame.
Whatever the focus, actors should face expected penalties tied to their
own benefits from corruption.
The penalties imposed on officials should be tied to the size of the
pay-offs they receive and the probability of detection. If penalties are not
a function of the size of the bribe, an anti-corruption drive would quickly
confront a paradox. A high fixed penalty will lower the incidence of corrup-
tion, but increase the size of bribes paid. If the penalty is high, officials
must receive a high return in order to be willing to engage in bribery.7
Thus, the expected penalty should increase by more than a dollar for every
dollar increase in the size of the bribe (Rose-Ackerman 1978, pp. 109-
135). This could be done either by tying the penalty levied upon conviction
to the size of the bribe or by increasing the risk of detection as the size
of the bribe increases. However, if the probability of detection is lower for
small pay-offs, the penalty for each detected offence should reflect the
low incidence of detection. This could mean that those convicted of petty
bribery could face harsher penalties than those found to have taken larger
bribes.
On the other side of the corrupt transaction, a fixed penalty levied on
bribers will lower both the demand for corrupt services and the level of
bribes. However, it will have no marginal impact once the briber passes
the corruption threshold. To have a marginal effect, the penalties imposed
7
For example, anecdotal reports by correspondents with Radio Free Europe/Radio Liberty
claim that in Kiev, a drunk-driving ticket can be avoided with a bribe of US$ 50. In Prague, by
comparison, a similar ticket will be forgiven for a $100 donation. The claimed reason for the
difference between Prague and Kiev is that the average monthly salary of a traffic policeman in
Prague is five times higher than that of his counterpart in Kiev (Radio Free Europe/Radio Liberty
2001). Perhaps the chance of being caught is higher as well. Other sources find that the overall
incidence of corruption is lower in the Czech Republic than in Ukraine. Thus, when accepting a
bribe has a high expected cost, this will both deter corruption and raise the size of the bribes
that are paid.
Corruption and the criminal law 9
on bribe payers should be tied to their gains (their excess profits, for
example), not to the size of the bribe.8 Bribes represent a cost to those
who pay them; thus penalties should not be tied to these costs unless
they are a good proxy for the bribers benefits.
United States law does little to recognize this asymmetry between
bribe payers and bribe recipients in its prescribed punishments. The crimi-
nal penalties are equivalent: both payers and recipients of bribes can be
fined not more than three times the monetary equivalent of the thing of
value [that is, the bribe] or imprisoned for not more than fifteen years, or
both.9 This is appropriate for officials who receive bribes, except that
multiplying by three may be a poor measure of the risk of detection and
punishment. The actual probability of detection is likely to be well below
one third. The law, however, does recognize the asymmetry of corrupt
transactions by permitting the President to rescind any contract or other
benefit if there has been a conviction under the statute governing bribery,
graft and conflicts of interest. The United States can also recover, in
addition to any penalties, the amount expended or the thing transferred
or delivered on its behalf, or the reasonable value thereof.10 This right of
recovery is designed to avoid losses to the Government. It is a weak
deterrent to corrupt pay-offs because the recovery is not multiplied by a
factor that reflects the probability of detection.
If expected penalties do not increase along with the benefits of cor-
ruption for bribers and the recipients of bribes, the Government may be
caught in a trap where high corruption levels beget high corruption levels.
A low-corruption equilibrium may also exist, but be unreachable in small
steps from the status quo. A high-corruption equilibrium occurs when the
net rewards of corruption increase as the incidence of corruption in-
creases. This might occur, for example, if the probability of detection falls
when corruption is widespread and if penalties levied upon conviction are
not adjusted to take account of that fact. If most public officials take
bribes, overwhelmed law enforcement officials may uncover only a small
proportion of the corrupt transactions.
Any multiple-equilibrium case, however, can be converted into a single-
equilibrium, low-corruption case with the appropriate choice of law enforce-
ment strategy or a change in the information conditions. Strategies that
tie expected penalties to marginal gains can remove a society from a high-
corruption trap. Doing so, however, may require a large increase in law
enforcement resources to tip the system to a low-corruption equilibrium.
8
Alternatively, if potentially corrupt firms are repeat players, they can be deterred by
debarment procedures that prohibit corrupt firms from contracting with the Government for a
period of years. To have a marginal effect, the debarment penalty should be tied to the serious-
ness of the corruption uncovered. For examples of debarment see Nikkei Weekly (19 February
1996) and Thacher (1995), who describes the practices used by the New York City School
Construction Authority.
9
18 USC 201 (a).
10
18 USC 218.
10 Forum on Crime and Society, Vol. 2, No. 1, December 2002
The good news is that the sharp increase in enforcement resources need
not be permanent. It must simply be sufficient to tip the system to a
lower corruption level (Lui 1986, pp. 21-22). The idea is to change expec-
tations. A concentrated clean-up campaign can change expectations about
others cooperation in the corrupt system. Once a new low-corruption
equilibrium has been established, it can be maintained with reduced en-
forcement resources provided the honest are willing to report corrupt
offers and law enforcement officials follow up on reports of malfeasance
(Cadot 1987; Rose-Ackerman 1978, pp. 137-151).
11
Fassler (1991, p. 246) cites the relevant articles in English.
12
31 USC Sections 3729-3731.
13
Pub. L. No. 101-12, 5 USC 2302 (b) (8).
12 Forum on Crime and Society, Vol. 2, No. 1, December 2002
that the suit was clearly frivolous or vexatious (Howse and Daniels 1995,
p. 526).14 The law also protects whistle-blowers from retaliation by their
employers.
A number of objections have been raised to this statute but, on
balance, the law appears to serve a valuable purpose and can complement
efforts at internal monitoring. In particular, the idea that corporate
whistle-blowing will undermine internal control efforts seems misplaced. As
Robert Howse and Ronald Daniels (1995, p. 537) argue, the fear of being
exposed to prosecution as a consequence of external whistle-blowing may
be an important incentive for some corporations to adopt credible internal
disclosure policies and procedures. The main problem in countries in the
process of establishing the rule of law will be to clarify what practices are
illegal and subject to criminal penalties. It will not make sense to protect
or reward whistle-blowers unless it is made clear what they should be
looking for.
Sometimes public officials claim that large firms virtually force bribes
upon them. This seems a little disingenuous because the pay-offs are a
cost to the firms involved. Nevertheless, to the extent this claim is cred-
ible, public officials could come forward with evidence of corrupt offers and
seek protection under the Whistle Blower Protection Act. Firms would
predictably defend themselves by arguing that the official demanded the
pay-off. The distinctions in United States law may be useful here. Under
the False Claims Act, the court can reduce the award for a whistle-blower
who was involved in wrongdoing, but only if he or she planned or initiated
the wrongful conduct. The award need not be eliminated, however, unless
the whistle-blower is convicted of a crime.15 Prosecutors with the author-
ity to grant criminal immunity can thus set up a kind of a race in which
the first to report the corrupt transactions will be rewarded, while the
others are punished.
Corporations have legal personalities, but this does not turn them into
real human beings. For some commentators, this lack of humanity implies
that corporations ought not to be subject to the criminal law because
they cannot have mental states and so cannot be guilty. Applying the
criminal law to corporations gives them procedural protections and a
presumption of innocence that are designed to protect the rights of
individuals, not legal constructs (Thompson 1987, pp. 76-77; Khanna
1996).
The potential criminal liability of legal persons is an accepted part of
United States law. By contrast, in many civil-law countries, organizations
are excluded from criminal liability, although the trend may be changing
14
31 USC 3730 (d) (4).
15
31 USC 3730 (d) (3).
16
For a fuller discussion of the issues raised here see Rose-Ackerman (2002).
Corruption and the criminal law 13
with the incorporation of corporate criminal liability into the French crimi-
nal code in 1992 and into the Council of Europes Criminal Law Convention
on Corruption (Council of Europe 1999, art. 18). After the French revolu-
tion, France was the source of the prohibition of organizational criminal
liability. Its code was adopted widely in Europe and has influenced criminal
law in parts of the world where the civil-law tradition has been exported.
Current French law, however, establishes criminal liability for organizations
for a set of specified offences, including active corruption or peddling of
influence (Orland and Cachera 1995, p. 114 and appendix, arts. 433-1 and
433-25). The law includes some special penalties for legal persons,
including the possibility of larger fines, exclusion from government procure-
ment contracts and placement under various types of probation or court
supervision (Code Pénal 2001, arts. 131-38 and 131-39).
The Netherlands has permitted corporate criminal liability since the
mid-1970s, but Italy and Germany have constitutional provisions precluding
corporate guilt, and the Belgian courts have refused to find corporations
guilty of crimes. In Germany, however, administrative bodies can impose
fines on corporations as well as on natural persons (Orland and Cachera
1995, p. 116; Khanna 1996, pp. 1488-1491). In Poland, corporate crimi-
nal liability does not exist, although legal persons can be required to pay
damages for the negligence of their representatives (Council of Europe
2000, p. 21). The key issue for law reform in these and other countries is
to find ways to hold legal persons responsible for organizational acts.
Organizations should not be anthropomorphized when discussing rights
and responsibilities. Nevertheless, corporations can have responsibilities
that cannot be reduced to individual obligations (De George 1993;
Donaldson 1989). These responsibilities stem from the practices of the
organizationsthe internal and external patterns of relationshipsthat
persist even as the identities of the individuals who participate in them
change (Thompson 1987, p. 76; French 1979; Cooper 1968). The issue
of corporate responsibility is important in the corruption context because,
in the business world, most bribes are paid by employees and agents, not
by top management. If pay-offs help a firm obtain business, managers and
owners may hope to facilitate their subordinates bribery, while remaining
ignorant of the details.17 Thus, one would like the law enforcement system
to give top management an incentive to control the corruption of their
subordinates. The important issue for policy is whether corporate criminal
liability is the best way to do this or whether a system of civil fines and
injunctions can serve the same purpose more effectively.
According to Jennifer Arlen (1994), if corporations are held criminally
liable for the corrupt acts of their employees and agents, top manage-
ment may not support an effective monitoring system. She analyses this
17
Top managers will hope to rely on their subordinates ability to rationalize such pay-offs.
In one experimental study, business students and managers expressed a strong commitment to
honesty as a value, but over 70 per cent were willing to pay a bribe to obtain business. The most
frequently expressed justification was that the first duty of a manager is to reach the com-
panys goals. Therefore, it sometimes becomes necessary to forget about ethics (Rosenberg
1987).
14 Forum on Crime and Society, Vol. 2, No. 1, December 2002
problem for the general case of corporate crimes and concludes that a
number of alternative rules are superior to present United States law
that imposes pure strict liability on firms. One possibility is a negligence
rule, under which firms are only liable if they have neglected their internal
enforcement responsibilities. For such a rule to be workable, however, the
courts must be able to evaluate internal firm behaviour, which is a difficult
task. One solution may be the drafting of quite precise directives that
state what type of internal monitoring is required.
The United States Foreign Corrupt Practices Act does this by supple-
menting its prohibitions against paying bribes with accounting provisions
that apply to firms within the jurisdiction of the Securities and Exchange
Commission. These firms must establish accounting systems that accu-
rately reflect transactions involving the firms assets, and they must have
an effective system of internal accounting controls. Firms and their man-
agers can be subject to both civil and criminal penalties for violating these
accounting provisions (Jadwin and Shilling 1994, pp. 679-680; Nobles and
Maistrellis 1995, pp. 9 and 19; Pickholz 1997, p. 237). There is no formal
due diligence defence to the Act but, in practice, firms that establish and
enforce effective internal control systems appear to experience more
lenient treatment. The Federal Sentencing Guidelines also reward internal
firm efforts to detect and punish violations of the law (Nobles and
Maistrellis 1995, pp. 18-24). Thus, United States law attempts to coun-
ter managements incentive to insulate itself from the profit-maximizing
malfeasance of employees and agents. Nevertheless, some insulation is
currently possible through the use of foreign firms as sales agents
(Nobles and Maistrellis 1995, p. 25). The OECD Convention on Combating
Bribery of Foreign Public Officials in International Business Transactions
holds firms responsible for the corrupt acts of their agents in interna-
tional business transactions. This Convention has the potential to spur an
interest in the promulgation and enforcement of corporate codes of con-
duct among multinational firms throughout the world.
Illegal businesses seek to operate securely by paying off the police, politi-
cians and judges or by permitting them to share in the profits of illegal
businesses. But such businesses are also vulnerable to extortionary de-
mands. Law enforcement authorities, from the police to prosecutors and
judges, can demand payments to overlook criminal law violations or limit
penalties. If the evidence of criminal behaviour is clear, such businesses
will be unable credibly to threaten to report corrupt demands.
Of course, illegal businesses are hardly innocent victims. They often
actively try to corrupt the police. They seek not only immunity from pros-
ecution for themselves, but also assurance of monopoly power in the illegal
market. Both in the United States and in Latin America, gamblers and
drug dealers have paid officials to raid their competitors or to restrict
entry (Rose-Ackerman 1978, p. 163; New York Times 12 May 1996; New
Corruption and the criminal law 15
18
United States v. Traitz, 871 F.2d 368, 375 (1989).
Corruption and the criminal law 17
Conclusions
Under criminal law, finding the right mix of penalties, rewards and under-
cover law enforcement is not easy. Nevertheless, one important lesson of
the economic analysis of crime is clear: anti-corruption policy should never
18 Forum on Crime and Society, Vol. 2, No. 1, December 2002
References
Chakrabarti, D., Dausses, M. D., and Olson, T. (1997), Federal criminal conflict of
interest, American Criminal Law Review, vol. 34, pp. 587-616.
Code Pénal (2001), Editions Dalloz, Paris.
Cooper, D. E. (1968), Collective responsibility, Philosophy and Public Affairs, vol. 43,
pp. 258-268.
Council of Europe (1999), European Treaties, STE No. 173, Criminal Law Convention on
Corruption, Strasbourg, 27 January.
Council of Europe (2000), Octopus II Country Report: Poland, Octopus (2000) 47 Final,
Strasbourg, 20 December. Available at web site <http://www.legal.coe.int/
economiccrime/octopus/Octopus2RepPoland.pdf>.
Criminal Code (2001), Warsaw.
De George, R. T. (1993), Competing with Integrity in International Business, Oxford
University Press, New York.
De Melo, M., Ofer, G., and Sandler, O. (1995), Pioneers for profit: St. Petersburg
entrepreneurs in services, World Bank Economic Review, vol. 9, pp. 425-450.
Donaldson, T. (1989), The Ethics of International Business, Oxford University Press,
New York.
Fassler, L. J. (1991), The Italian penal procedure code: an adversarial system of
criminal procedure in continental Europe, Columbia Journal of Transnational Law,
vol. 29, pp. 245-278.
French, P. (1979), The corporation as moral person, American Philosophical Quar-
terly, vol. 16, pp. 207-215.
Gambetta, D. (1993), The Sicilian Mafia, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mas-
sachusetts.
Gambetta, D., and Reuter, P. (1995), The Mafia in legitimate industries, in The
Economics of Organised Crime, eds G. Fiorentini and S. Peltzman, Cambridge Univer-
sity Press, Cambridge, United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland, pp.
116-139.
Gilman, S. C. (1995), Presidential ethics and the ethics of the Presidency, Annals,
AAPSS, No. 537, pp. 58-75.
Goel, R., and Rich, D. (1989), On the economic incentives for taking bribes, Public
Choice, vol. 61, pp. 269-275.
Handelman, S. (1995), Comrade Criminal, Yale University Press, New Haven, Connecti-
cut.
Howse, R., and Daniels, R. J. (1995), Rewarding whistleblowers: the costs and
benefits of an incentive-based compliance strategy, in Corporate Decision-Making in
Canada, eds R. J. Daniels and R. Morck, University of Calgary Press, Calgary,
pp. 525-549.
Jadwin, P. J., and Shilling, M. (1994), Foreign Corrupt Practices Act, American
Criminal Law Review, vol. 31, pp. 677-686.
Judge backs competition in trash-hauling industry, New York Times, 28 February
1994.
Kaufmann, D., and Siegelbaum, P. (1997), Privatization and corruption in transition
economies, Journal of International Affairs, vol. 50, pp. 419-459.
Khanna, V. S. (1996), Corporate criminal liability: what purpose does it serve?
Harvard Law Review, vol. 109, pp. 1477-1534.
Kovaćic, W. (1996), Whistleblower bounty lawsuits as monitoring devices in govern-
ment contracting, Loyola of Los Angeles Law Review, vol. 29, pp. 1799-1857.
Lindgren, J. (1988), The elusive distinction between bribery and extortion: from the
common law to the Hobbs Act, UCLA Law Review, vol. 35, pp. 815-908.
20 Forum on Crime and Society, Vol. 2, No. 1, December 2002