0% found this document useful (0 votes)
30 views43 pages

Lecture 6 Utility SP23

Uploaded by

Zülal Demirtaş
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
30 views43 pages

Lecture 6 Utility SP23

Uploaded by

Zülal Demirtaş
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 43

Utility

ECON201- MICROECONOMICS
SPRING 2023
1
Consumer Theory
• We consider a rational consumer.
• We address the following two questions:
• Which combinations of goods is the consumer able to buy?
• Among the combinations of goods that the consumer is able to buy, which
combination(s) does the consumer prefers to buy?

2
Today’s goal
• Can we generate a utility function from preferences?

3
Today’s goal
• Can we generate a utility function from preferences?
• Consider a set of preferences ≿ on a choice set X (i.e., the set of
different bundles of goods)
• Can we build a utility function u that represents (or contains the
same information as) ≿ ?

4
Today’s goal
• Can we generate a utility function from preferences?
• Consider a set of preferences ≿ on a choice set X (i.e., the set of
different bundles of goods)
• Can we build a utility function u that represents (or contains the
same information as) ≿ ?
• Find a way of assigning utility numbers to bundles such that, for any
two bundles x and y,

x ≿ y if and only if u(x) ≥ u(y)

5
From Preferences to Utility Functions
• Can we build a utility function u that represents (or contains the
same information as) ≿ ?
• Yes, as long as the preference relation is complete, reflexive,
transitive!

6
From Preferences to Utility Functions
• Can we build a utility function u that represents (or contains the
same information as) ≿ ?
• Yes, as long as the preference relation is complete, reflexive,
transitive!

• Technical note: If the choice set is an uncountable set, then we also


need continuity of preferences.
Ø Continuity means that small changes to a consumption bundle cause only
small changes to the preference level.

7
From Preferences to Utility Functions
• A utility function u(x) represents a preference relation if and only if:

xʹ ≿ xʺ ⇔ u(xʹ) ≥ u(xʺ)

xʹ ≻ xʺ ⇔ u(xʹ) > u(xʺ)

xʹ ~ xʺ ⇔ u(xʹ) = u(xʺ)

8
From Preferences to Utility Functions
• Suppose there are three alternative bundles x,y and z, and consider
your preferences ≿ over these bundles
• Say, a utility function u(.) that represents these preferences are the
following:
u(x)= 1, u(y)= 2, u(z)= 3
• Does it mean anything that the utility of z is three times the utility of
x?

9
From Preferences to Utility Functions
• Suppose there are three alternative bundles x,y and z, and consider your
preferences ≿ over these bundles
• Say, a utility function u that represents these preferences are the following:
u(x)= 1, u(y)= 2, u(z)= 3
• Does it mean anything that the utility of z is three times the utility of x?
• Consider instead the following utility numbers
u(x)= 1, u(y)= 1.9, u(z)= 2

• These represent the same preferences!

10
From Preferences to Utility Functions
• Utility is an ordinal (i.e., ordering) concept.
• E.g., if u(x) = 6 and u(y) = 2 then bundle x is strictly preferred to bundle y. But
x is not preferred three times as much as is y.
• Utility numbers do not have a cardinal meaning
• The difference between the numbers does not matter
• Therefore, many different utility functions represent the same
preferences!

11
From Preferences to Utility Functions
• Utility is an ordinal (i.e., ordering) concept.
• E.g., if u(x) = 6 and u(y) = 2 then bundle x is strictly preferred to bundle y. But
x is not preferred three times as much as is y.
• Utility numbers do not have a cardinal meaning
• The difference between the numbers does not matter
• Therefore, many different utility functions represent the same
preferences!
• Can we determine the relationship between utility functions that
represent the same preferences?

12
From Preferences to Utility Functions
Theorem: Consider two utility functions u and v. They both represent
the same preferences if and only if there is a strictly increasing
function f such that
v(x)=f(u(x)) for all x.

13
Utility Functions & Indifference Curves
• An indifference curve contains equally preferred bundles.
• Equal preference Þ same utility level.
• Therefore, all bundles on an indifference curve have the same utility
level.
• We have one utility level for each indifference curve.

14
Utility Functions & Indifference Curves
• Consider the bundles (4, 1), (2, 3), and (2, 2).
• Suppose (2, 3) ≻ (4, 1) ~ (2, 2).
• Assign to these bundles any numbers that preserve the preference
ordering; e.g.,

• Call these numbers utility levels.

15
Utility Functions & Indifference Curves

16
Utility Functions & Indifference Curves

17
Utility Functions & Indifference Curves

18
Utility Functions & Indifference Curves
• Comparing more bundles will create a larger collection of all
indifference curves and a better description of the consumer’s
preferences.
• This complete collection of indifference curves completely
represents the consumer’s preferences.

19
Utility Functions & Indifference Curves

20
Utility Functions & Indifference Curves

21
Utility Functions & Indifference Curves
• The collection of all indifference curves for a given preference
relation is an “indifference map.”
• An indifference map is equivalent to a utility function.

22
Utility Functions
• There is no unique utility function representation of a preference
relation.

23
Utility Functions
• There is no unique utility function representation of a preference
relation.
• Suppose u(x1, x2)= x1x2 represents a preference relation.
• Can you use this utility function to rank the bundles (4,1), (2,3), and
(2,2)?

24
Utility Functions
• There is no unique utility function representation of a preference
relation.
• Suppose u(x1, x2)= x1x2 represents a preference relation.
• Can you use this utility function to rank the bundles (4,1), (2,3), and
(2,2)?

• u(2,3)=6 > u(4,1)=u(2,2)=4 (2,3) ≻ (4,1) ~ (2,2)

25
Utility Functions
• u(x1, x2)= x1x2 Þ (2,3) ≻ (4,1) ~ (2,2)
• Define V=u2. This implies V(x1, x2)= x12 x22 represents the same
preference relation.
• V(2,3)=36 > V(4,1)=V(2,2)=16
• (2,3) ≻ (4,1) ~ (2,2)
• V preserves the same order as u and therefore represents the same
preferences.

26
Utility Functions
• u(x1, x2)= x1x2 Þ (2,3) ≻ (4,1) ~ (2,2)
• Define V=u2. This implies V(x1, x2)= x12 x22 represents the same
preference relation.
• V(2,3)=36 > V(4,1)=V(2,2)=16
• (2,3) ≻ (4,1) ~ (2,2)
• V preserves the same order as u and therefore represents the same
preferences.
• Define W=2u+5. Does W preserve the same order as u?

27
Utility Functions
• Reformulation of the earlier theorem:
• If
• u is a utility function that represents a preference relation
and
• f is a strictly increasing function,
then V = f (u) is also a utility function representing the same preference relation.
This is known as a “monotonic transformation.”

28
Utility Functions & Indifference Curves
• u(x1, x2)= x1x2

29
Some Other Utility Functions
• Can you draw the indifference curves for the utility function u(x1, x2)=
x1+ x2?

30
Perfect Substitution Indifference Curves

All are linear and parallel.


31
Some Other Utility Functions
• Can you draw the indifference curves for the utility function u(x1, x2)=
min{x1, x2} ?

32
Perfect-Complementarity Indifference Curves

33
Marginal Utilities and Marginal Rates of
Substitution
• Marginal Rate of Substitution (MRS)
• Slope of the indifference curve
• Rate at which you would change one good for another while remaining indifferent
• How can we calculate the MRS from utility functions?

34
Marginal Utilities and Marginal Rates of
Substitution
• Marginal Utility
• The rate at which utility changes with the quantity of one good, keeping the other
constant
• The partial derivative of the utility function
• Recall that marginal means “incremental.”
• The marginal utility of commodity i is the rate of change of total utility as
the quantity of commodity i consumed changes.

35
Marginal Utilities and Marginal Rates of
Substitution
• The general equation for an indifference curve is u(x1, x2)≡k, where k is a
constant.
• Totally differentiating this identity yields:

• Rearranging the terms:

36
MU and MRS: An Example
• Suppose u(x1, x2)= x1x2. Calculate MU for each good and the MRS.

37
MU and MRS: An Example

38
Monotonic Transformations & MRS
• Applying a monotonic transformation to a utility function
representing a preference relation simply creates another utility
function representing the same preference relation.
• What happens to marginal rates of substitution when a monotonic
transformation is applied?

39
Monotonic Transformations & MRS
• Recall that for u(x1, x2)= x1x2 , MRS= -x2/x1.
• Define V=u2. What is the MRS for V?

40
Monotonic Transformations & MRS
• More generally, if V = f (u) where f is a strictly increasing function,
then the MRS remains unchanged by this positive monotonic
transformation.

41
Remark on MU and MRS
• Marginal Utility – depends on the specific utility function used
• Not very meaningful
• Marginal Rate of Substitution – does not depend on the specific utility
function used
• All utility functions which represent the same preferences yield the same MRS
• Behaviorally meaningful

42
Two other utility functions
• A utility function of the form u(x1, x2)= x1a x2b, with a>0 and b>0, is
called a “Cobb-Douglas” utility function.
• A utility function of the form u(x1, x2)=f(x1)+ x2, where f(.) is possibly
a non-linear function is called a “quasi-linear” utility function.
• Can you compute MUs and the MRS for each function?

43

You might also like