GEETHIC Midterm Notes
GEETHIC Midterm Notes
Morality
•Morality refers to the set of standards an individual person or society uses to judge whether an
act is good or bad, whether someone is virtuous or not, or whether we ought to do this or that.
Ethics
•The word “Ethics” is sometimes used to refer to one’s set of moral beliefs and practices. Strictly
speaking, however, it refers to the discipline that examines the moral standards of an individual
or society. Being a branch of philosophy that studies the nature of morality, it is sometimes also
called moral philosophy.
1.Metaethics
•It looks into the nature, meaning, scope, and foundations of moral values, beliefs, and
judgments. Examples of metaethical questions are: Is morality objective or relative? Is morality
based on reason, emotions, intuition, or facts? What are moral persons? What does it mean to
be morally accountable?
2. Normative Ethics
•It is concerned with the formulation of moral standards, rules, or principles to determine right
from wrong conduct or ways of life worth pursuing.
•Normative ethical theories are generally built on 3 considerations about acts: (a) that they lead
to consequences; (b) that they follow or violate rules; and (c) that they are done by persons with
character traits. Accordingly, these theories are generally classified into consequentialism,
deontology, and virtue ethics.
3. Applied Ethics
•It examines the particular moral issues occurring in both the personal and social spheres. It
determines the moral permissibility of actions and practices in specific areas of human concern
like business, medicine, nature, law, sports, and others.
•Areas in applied ethics include business ethics, bioethics, environmental ethics, computer
ethics, and social media ethics.
__________
Descriptive Ethics
•Metaethics, normative ethics, and applied ethics are areas of Ethics taken as a philosophical
study of morality. A non-philosophical study of morality which seeks to objectively record and
present how people in a certain community make moral judgments or develop their capacity for
such is called descriptive ethics. Descriptive ethics can be done in the disciplines of sociology,
anthropology, and psychology.
Examples:
•Ethical Relativism: the view which states that all moral principles are valid relative to a
particular society or individual.
1.Ethical relativism must be true since moral beliefs and rules vary from culture to culture (and
within the same culture, they vary over time). (Diversity Argument)
3.Relativism must be the right way to view the nature of morality since acknowledging the
differences among various societies in terms of their moral beliefs and practices leads to
respect, social harmony, and peaceful co-existence among the different cultural, religious, and
social groups. (Toleration Argument)
3.Despite the fact that some moral beliefs and practices vary among cultures, there are still
universal moral standards that exist, such as those that respect life and promote the pursuit of
truth, justice, and peace.
•Cultural practices may differ but the fundamental moral principles underlying them do not.
•Module 2
Moral Personhood
and Accountability
•Moral persons are beings or entities having moral status or standing. They are the appropriate
objects of moral concern.
•The actions which we subject to a moral evaluation are those that concern moral
persons—either as the doers or recipients of these actions.
•At the minimum, to be a moral person is to be a bearer of moral rights. All moral persons have
moral rights but some have moral duties as well.
•Rights are entitlements; they are interests one is allowed to pursue or actions one is allowed to
do. Duties, in contrast, are what we are obliged to do.
•Rights correlate with duties: one’s rights impose duties on other people; and one’s duties are
intended to respect the rights of other people.
•Not exercising rights will not merit sanctions (penalties or punishments), while not performing
duties will merit such.
Classifying Rights
•Rights are classified according to (1) the duties they impose (the duties having such rights
impose on other people), and (2) the manner of their acquisition.
•All moral agents are moral patients; but not all moral patients are moral agents. Accordingly, we
can distinguish between agentive and and non-agentive moral persons.
•Agentive Moral Persons: moral persons who can be both moral patients and agents. E.g.,
normal human adults
•Non-agentive Moral Persons: moral persons who can only be moral patients. E.g., animals,
mentally challenged humans, infants
•Both theories are criticized for justifying inhumane treatment of one group of persons by
another group. The social theory may justify, for instance, the practice of slavery. The gradient
theory may justify, for instance, the practice of ethnic cleansing—where the perpetrators think of
themselves as belonging to a superior race or as having moral ascendancy over those they
exterminate.
Accountability in General
•The natural product of a person’s intelligence and freedom: a person’s Intelligence enables
him/her to know what is right and wrong; while a person’s freedom enables him/her to choose
whether to do what is right or what is wrong.
•The deservingness of blame or punishment for doing what is wrong or not doing what is right,
and praise or reward for doing what is right or not doing what is wrong.
•Though related, these two concepts should not be confused. There are three senses of
responsibility, one of which equates it with accountability.
1.Responsibility as Accountability
•A responsible person is one who deserves blame or praise for his/her actions.
2.Responsibility as Agency
•A responsible person is one who does or causes the action. An agent is not necessarily
accountable for his/her actions.
3.Responsibility as Duty
•A responsible person is one who does his/her duties or obligations. One is accountable for
failing to perform one’s duties.
•Degree Conditions: conditions that determine the extent or gravity of a person’s moral
accountability. They may be mitigating, if they tend to lessen the degree of moral accountability,
or aggravating, if they tend to increase the same.
Incriminating Conditions:
1.Agency: the person causes the action.
2.Knowledge: the person knows whether the action is good or bad.
3.Intentionality: the person is free to perform the action and intends to do it.
•For a person to be morally accountable for an action, all conditions should be present:
he/she causes the action, knows the morality of the action, and is free to perform the action.
Excusing Conditions
1.Non-agency: the person does not cause the action.
2.Ignorance: the person does not know the morality of the action (Note: the person should be
blamelessly ignorant—see next slide).
3.Non-intentionality: the person is not free to perform the action or does not intend to perform
the action.
●
•For a person to be excused from moral accountability for an action, at least one condition
should be present: either he does not cause the action, is ignorant of the morality of the
action, or is not free to perform the action.
•
Excusable and Non-excusable Ignorance
•Real / Blameless Ignorance: the excusable ignorance; the ignorant person cannot be said to
have known better.
•Irresponsible / Blameful / Blameworthy Ignorance: the non-excusable ignorance: the ignorant
person can be said to have known better.
•
Some Factors to Consider
•The ignorant person’s mental and physical conditions.
•The ignorant person’s access to the relevant information.
•Whether the ignorant person has the duty to know what he does not know.
•
Degree Conditions
1.Knowledge: the greater the knowledge, the greater the accountability; the lesser the
knowledge, the lesser the accountability
2.Pressure or Difficulty in Life: the greater the pressure, the lesser the accountability; the
lesser the pressure, the greater the accountability
3.Intensity of the Injury: the greater the intensity of the injury, the greater the accountability;
the lesser the intensity of the injury, the lesser the accountability
4.Degree of Involvement: the greater the involvement, the greater the accountability; the
lesser the involvement the lesser the accountability
•
Module 3
Consequentialism
1. Consequentialism
•The consequences of actions are the fundamental morally relevant consideration in making
moral judgments.
• An action is morally good if it results in good or desirable consequences, while it is morally bad
if it results in bad or undesirable consequences.
2. Deontology
•The rules that actions follow are the fundamental morally relevant consideration in making
moral judgments.
• An action is morally good if it is done in conformity with a good rule, while it is bad if done in
conformity with a bad rule.
•
3. Virtue ethics
• The character of agents is the fundamental morally relevant consideration in making moral
judgments.
•An action is morally good if it is done by a virtuous person (a person with good character traits)
while it is morally bad when done by a vicious person (a person with bad character traits).
•
First General Division:
Hedonism vs. Non-hedonism
•Hedonism: pleasure is the only inherent good.
1.Pleasure is inherently good.
2.Pleasure is the only inherent good.
•Non-hedonism rejects hedonism in two ways:
1.Exclusive Non-hedonism: pleasure is not inherently good. Something else is (which may be
power, preference-satisfaction, and others).
2.Inclusive non-hedonism: pleasure is inherently good but there are others (such as power,
preference-satisfaction, truth, beauty, and knowledge).
•Agent-relative consequentialism: the consequences to the agent are primary; they outweigh the
consequences to other people.
•Agent-neutral consequentialism: the consequences that promote the greatest overall benefits
of all affected persons, regardless of their recipients, are primary; personal good or happiness
may sometimes be necessary to sacrifice to promote the same.
●
• The two general divisions of consequentialism overlap and qualify each other. Accordingly,
they combine to form four complex types of consequentialism, which may be termed as:
1.Agent-relative Hedonism
2.Agent-relative Non-hedonism
3.Agent-neutral Hedonism
4.Agent-neutral non-hedonism
1.Agent-relative hedonism: an action is morally good if it promotes the agent’s own pleasure
or happiness.
•But which among the agent’s pleasures are primary? (a) Active Hedonism: the agent’s
immediate though momentary pleasures are primary (Aristippus); (b) Passive Hedonism: the
agent’s long-lasting though non-immediate pleasures are primary (Epicurus).
3.Agent-neutral Hedonism: an action is morally good if it maximizes the overall happiness (or
pleasure) of all affected persons .
—————————
●
Lesson 4: Utilitarianism and Its Basic Forms
Utilitarianism: an action is morally good if it maximizes the overall welfare of all affected
persons / promotes ”the greatest good of the greatest number of people.”
2.Welfarist. Utilitarianism seeks to promote the welfare (well being, happiness, benefits,
advantages, etc.) of persons.
3.Aggregationist. Utilitarianism seeks to maximize the overall welfare of all persons involved in
an action.
•The overall welfare is the net sum total of benefits of all options: sum total of benefits minus the
sum total of costs.
Forms of Utilitarianism
Two Considerations:
1.Should the overall welfare to be maximized only involve pleasure (or happiness)?
•Yes à Hedonistic Utilitarianism
•No à Non-hedonistic Utilitarianism
2.Should the utilitarian principle (maximizing overall welfare or promoting the greatest good of
the greatest number of people) be applied directly to actions or to the rules governing these
actions?
•To the Actions à Act Utilitarianism
•To the Rules à Rule Utilitarianism
A. Hedonistic Utilitarianism
•The overall welfare to be maximized through our actions pertains only to pleasure or
happiness.
•Question: Is there is a qualitative difference between physical and mental pleasures? Are they
the same in terms of value?
1.Quantitative Hedonistic Utilitarianism: there is no qualitative difference between physical and
mental pleasures; there are only quantitative differences among pleasures (Jeremy Bentham).
2.Qualitative Hedonistic Utilitarianism: the value or quality of mental pleasures, because they
involve the exercise of the higher faculty of reason, is greater than that of physical pleasures
(John Stuart Mill).
•The systematic method developed by Bentham for calculating the quantity of pleasures (mental
and physical). Factors to consider in the calculation:
1.Intensity --(How engaging is the experience of pleasure): The more intense the experience of
pleasure, the greater the value of the pleasure.
2.Duration --(How long the pleasure lasts): The longer the experience of pleasure, the greater
the value of the pleasure.
3.Certainty --(The probability that the pleasure will occur): The greater the probability that the
desired pleasure will be experienced, the greater the value of the pleasure.
4.Propinquity (remoteness) –(How far off in the future will the pleasure be experienced) The
shorter the temporal distance between an act and the pleasure that it will produce, the greater
the value of the pleasure.
4.Fecundity --(The chance a sensation will be followed by sensations of the same kind:
pleasures, if it be pleasure; pains, if it be pain): The higher the probability that an experience of
pleasure will be followed by further experiences of pleasure, the greater the value of the
pleasure.
5.Purity --(The chance a sensation will not be followed by sensations of the opposite kind:
pains, if it be pleasure; pleasures, if it be pain): The higher the probability that the experience of
pleasure will not be followed by an experience of pain, the greater the value of the pleasure.
6.Extent --(The number of persons affected by the sensation): The higher the number of
persons to experience the pleasure, the greater the value of the pleasure.
B. Non-Hedonistic Utilitarianism
•The over-all welfare to be maximized through our actions is either not pleasure (or happiness)
or not limited to such.
1. Ideal (or Pluralistic) Utilitarianism
•For G. E. Moore, there are, in addition to pleasure, other things that are worth pursuing for
their own sake and thus are good regardless of whether they result in pleasure or not. They
include knowledge, beauty, and good relationships, among others.
2. Preference Utilitarianism
•For Richard Hare and Peter Singer, desire/preference-satisfaction is more fundamental than
the experience of pleasure, as we sometimes prefer to satisfy our desires/preferences even if it
would lead to the experience of pain. Desire/preference satisfaction is thus the inherent good,
not pleasure.
•
C. Act and Rule Utilitarianism
1. Act Utilitarianism
•The consequences of an act is primary. An action is morally good if it maximizes overall welfare
of all persons involved, regardless of the rule it violates.
2. Rule Utilitarianism
•The consequences of following or violating the rule governing the act is primary. An action is
morally good if it conforms to an optimific rule, regardless of the consequences of the act.
•A rule is optimific if general conformity to it will maximize overall welfare of all persons involved.
----------------
•Act utilitarianism is the standard form of utilitarianism. Rule utilitarianism was developed to deal
with some challenging cases such as the morality of breaking contracts. Rule utilitarianism is
regarded by some as a compromise between utilitarianism and deontology.
•The hedonistic- non-hedonistic division overlaps with the act-rule division which gives rise to
complex forms of utilitarianism.
•Module 4
Deontology I
•Does God command what is good because it is good or it is good because God commands it?
(Plato’s Euthyphro: “Do the gods love what is holy because it is holy or it is holy because the
gods love it?”)
•Divine Command Theory (DCT): Whatever is good is good only because God wills it to be
good. DCT has two versions:
1.Strong Version: God’s will is the sole basis of morality.
2.Weak Version: Morality can be based on God’s will or some independent standard (usually
reason), but if a conflict arises between God’s will and some other standard, God’s will overrides
the other standard.
DCT-Strong Version
•The sole basis of morality is God’s will. As such, as Dostoevsky remarked, ”If there is no God,
everything is permissible.” Moral decisions should thus be made on the basis of what God
commands, not on what reason tells us.
DCT-Weak Version
•Best represented by Soren Kierkegaard’s theory of the teleological suspension of the ethical.
•Morality has an independent foundation in reason (and so even if there is no God, morality will
still stand by itself--contra Dostoevsky’s previous remark). But if one believes in God and His
commands conflict with the dictates of reason, God’s commands should override the dictates of
reason.
•Illustrated in the Biblical story where Abraham was asked by God to make his son, Isaac, as a
sacrificial offering.
•Elaborated in Kierkegaard’s three stages of life: (1) aesthetic stage (life of pleasure); (2) ethical
stage (life of reason); and (3) religious stage (life of faith).
2.If God can will anything and it would be good, the theory may lead to moral arbitrariness.
•But if God can only will what is good or those in conformity with His divine qualities (such as
goodness and justice), then these qualities would have value independent of God. Furthermore,
this would mean that there is a higher standard of good which God must conform to, which
contradicts DCT.
•Morality is part of the natural order of things. Actions are right by nature apart from the opinions
or practices of humans.
•Reason can discover valid moral principles by looking at the nature of humanity and society. If
something is “unnatural,” it is also immoral.
•Older versions of the theory share similarities with DCT in that they point to God as the source
of the natural law. Modern and recent versions, however, claim that natural law is inherent in the
universe and in humanity, and hence does not need a supernatural force.
Major Proponents
•Natural Law Theory (NLT) subscribes to the view of moral absolutism which claims that certain
kinds of actions are always wrong or always obligatory regardless of the consequences.
•When basic values conflict (or when forced to choose between two actions which both violate
some value), NLT appeals to the following principles:
•Principle of Forfeiture: a person who threatens the life of an innocent person forfeits his/her
own right to life.
•Principle of Double Effect: It is always wrong to do a bad act intentionally in order to bring
about good consequences, but that it is sometimes permissible to do a good act despite
knowing that it will bring about bad consequences.
•When an act has a good and bad effect, the act is good if:
1.The act, considered in itself and apart from its consequences, is good. (The Nature-of-the-Act
Condition)
2.The bad effect must not be the means by which one achieves the good effect. (The
Means-End Condition)
3.The intention must be the achieving of only the good effect, with the bad effect being only an
unintended side effect. If the bad effect is a means to the achieve the good effect, the act is bad.
The bad effect may be foreseen but must not be intended. (The Right-Intention Condition)
4.The good effect must be at least equivalent to the importance of the bad effect. (The
Proportionality Condition)
Some Criticisms
•Regarding the principle of double effect, how do we distinguish unforeseen from unintended
consequences?
•Hume’s challenge: how can we derive an ”ought” from an “is”? How can what is natural be
obligatory?
•The assumption of NLT that moral laws are written in natural laws is challenged by the
Darwinian evolutionary theory which claims that nature has no inherent design.