PIL Sources of International Law: - Sakshi Dhaddha
PIL Sources of International Law: - Sakshi Dhaddha
PIL Sources of International Law: - Sakshi Dhaddha
Article 38
1. The Court, whose function is to decide in accordance with international law such disputes as are
submitted to it, shall apply:
a) international conventions, whether general or particular, establishing rules expressly recognized by the
contesting states;
b) international custom, as evidence of a general practice accepted as law;
c) the general principles of law recognized by civilized nations;
d) subject to the provisions of Article 59, judicial decisions and the teachings of the most highly qualified
publicists of the various nations, as subsidiary means for the determination of rules of law.
2. This provision shall not prejudice the power of the Court to decide a casecex aequo et bono, if the parties
agree thereto.
TREATIES
STATE PRACTICE
OPINIO JURIS
Opinio juris sive necessitatis,” which means "an opinion of law or necessity” – psychological
element.
Opinio juris denotes a subjective obligation, in that a state perceives itself to be bound by the law in
question.
Opinio juris can be inferred by the context and manner in which states comply with customary
international law.
North Sea Continental Shelf cases. The Court noted that:
“for a new customary rule to be formed, not only must the acts concerned ‘amount to a settled practice’, but
they must be accompanied by the opinion juris sive necessitatis. Either the States taking such action or other
States in a position to react to it, must have behaved so that their conduct is ‘evidence of a belief that this
practice is rendered obligatory by the existence of a rule of law requiring it. The need for such a belief, i.e.
the existence of a subjective element, is implicit in the very notion of the opinio juris sive necessitates”
ICJ in a number of cases utilized General Assembly resolutions, Conventions, declaration as
confirming the existence of the opinio juris, focusing on the content of the resolution and the
conditions of their adoption.
QUESTIONS TO CONSIDER
Jus cogens (or ius cogens) is a latin phrase that literally means “compelling law.”
It designates norms from which no derogation is permitted by way of particular agreements.
Art 53 of VCLT:
“A treaty is void if, at the time of its conclusion, it conflicts with a peremptory norm of general international
law. For the purposes of the present Convention, a peremptory norm of general international law is a norm
accepted and recognized by the international community of States as a whole as a norm from which no
derogation is permitted and which can be modified only by a subsequent norm of general international law
having the same character. “
Art 64 of VCLT”
“If a new peremptory norm of general international law emerges, any existing treaty which is in conflict
with that norm becomes void and terminates. “
Various examples of rules of jus cogens have been provided, particularly during the discussions on
the topic in the International Law Commission, such as an unlawful use of force, genocide, slave
trading and piracy etc.
General principles of law are used primarily as "gap fillers“ to prevent a non liquet when treaties or
customary international law do not provide a rule of decision. International tribunals rely on these
principles when they cannot find authority in other sources of international law.
Examples of these general principles of law are laches, good faith, res judicata, and the impartiality
of judges.
In Chorz´ow Factory case, the Permanent Court of International Justice declared that ‘it is a general
conception of law that every violation of an engagement involves an obligation to make reparation’.
The International Court of Justice in the Corfu Channel case, when referring to circumstantial
evidence, pointed out that ‘this indirect evidence is admitted in all systems of law and its use is
recognized by international decisions’.
In the Genocide Convention case (Bosnia and Herzegovina v. Serbia and Montenegro) the principle
of res judicata was recognized.
Gabcıkovo–Nagymaros Project (Hungary v Slovakia) case- ex injuria jus non oritur.
Rann of Kutch Arbitration between India and Pakistan – Equity
JUDICIAL DECISIONS
There is no rule of stare decisis in international law.
Court often refers to its past decisions and advisory opinions to support its explanation of a present
case.
One example of this is part of the decision in the Lotus case, which was criticized and later
abandoned in the Geneva Conventions on the Law of the Sea.
One of the most outstanding instances of this occurred in the Anglo-Norwegian Fisheries case, with
its statement of the criteria for the recognition of baselines from which to measure the territorial sea,
which was later enshrined in the 1958 Geneva Convention on the Territorial Sea and Contiguous
Zone
JURISTIC WRITINGS
'Teachings of the most highly qualified publicists of the various nations' are also among the
'subsidiary means for the determination of the rules of law’.
Writers such as Gentili, Grotius, Pufendorf, Bynkershoek and Vattel were the supreme authorities of
the sixteenth to eighteenth centuries and determined the scope, form and content of international law.
With the rise of positivism and the consequent emphasis upon state sovereignty, treaties and custom
assumed the dominant position in the exposition of the rules of the international system, and the
importance of legalistic writings began to decline.
OTHER SOURCES
In the post Second World War period the question of validity of the resolutions and declarations of
the General Assembly and Security Council of the United Nations as a source of international law
has emerged time and again.
UN Security Council, has the competence to adopt resolutions under articles 24 and 25 of the UN
Charter binding on all member states of the organization.
Resolutions of the Assembly are generally not legally binding and are merely recommendatory- Soft
Law
The ICJ in the Nicaragua case expressed the view that the opinio juris requirement could be derived
from the circumstances surrounding the adoption and application of a General Assembly resolutions.
The effect of consent to resolutions such as this one ‘may be understood as acceptance of the validity
of the rule or set of rules declared by the resolution by themselves.
The ICJ in the Legality of the Threat or Use of Nuclear Weapons Advisory Opinion obdereved that
General Assembly resolutions, even if they are not binding, may sometimes have normative value
For example, the 1960 Declaration on the Granting of Independence to Colonial Countries and
Peoples, which was adopted with no opposition and only nine abstentions and followed a series of
resolutions in general and specific terms attacking colonialism and calling for the self-determination
of the remaining colonies, has marked the transformation of the concept of self-determination from a
political and moral principle to a legal right and consequent obligation, particularly taken in
concurrence with the 1970 Declaration on Principles of International Law.
The International Law Commission was established by the General Assembly in 1947 with the
declared object of promoting the progressive development of international law and its codification.
Many of the most important international conventions like the international conventions on the Law
of the Sea, convention on Diplomatic Relations, have grown out of the Commission’s work.
ILC will prepares a draft convention which submitted to the various states for their comments and is
usually followed by an international conference convened by the United Nations which eventually
emerges as treaty.
The drafts of the ILC are often referred to in the judgments of the International Court of Justice
UNILATERAL ACTS
In certain situations, the unilateral acts of states, including statements made by relevant state
officials, may give rise to international legal obligations.
Such unilateral acts include recognition and protests, which are intended to have legal consequences.
Unilateral acts, while not sources of international law as understood in article 38(1) of the Statute of
the ICJ.
Such unilateral statements may be used as evidence of a particular view taken by the state in
question.
Most of the jurists of 16th and 17th century were of the view that the basis of any law is law of
nature and international law being part of law has the same basis and for the same reason is binding
on the states.
Natural Law- Ideal Law
Normative in nature which differentiated right and wrong behavior of human.
According to this approach, states, as members of universal community, are obliged in order to
conserve peace and security to act always in accordance with the principle that the common good of
mankind is paramount to their individual interest.
Thus, international law was considered to be binding in nature by this school of thought because its
basis was natural law.
This school of thought was in vogue in the 19th century and was of the view that people would be
bound to obey law if it was created by appropriate legislative authority or sovereign irrespective of
its being reasonable or unreasonable.
Morality, ethics, Reason, Natural Law was rejected because they were vague and unscientific
According to them, law must be analyzed empirically, irrespective of its ethical elements, i.e., law
must be studied as it exists and law is the command of the sovereign having sanction.
Hart says that the rules of international law do not as yet constitute a ‘system’ but are merely a ‘set of
rules’.
This approach to law in society reached its height with Kelsen’s ‘Pure Theory of Law’
For Kelsen international law is a primitive legal order because of its lack of strong legislative,
judicial and enforcement organs and its consequent resemblance to a pre-state society
ACCORDING TO KELSEN
The discussion of Natural Law increased and gained in importance following the Nazi experience. It
stimulated a German philosopher, Radbruch, to formulate a theory whereby unjust laws had to be
opposed by virtue of a higher, Natural Law.
Many of the ideas and principles of international law today are rooted in the notion of Natural Law
and the relevance of ethical standards to the legal order, such as the principles of non-aggression and
human rights.
REALIST THEORY
According to Realist legal scholars, states adopt only international legal norms that either enhance
their power, formalize the subordination of weaker states, or that they intend to violate deliberately to
their own advantage.
International Law may thus address only peripheral matters that do not impact the states' power or
autonomy.
Realists believe that international politics in modern times generally recognizes no authority above
the nation-state.
Agreements among states are enforceable only by the agreeing states themselves.
Reciprocity serves as the main tool to enforce agreements in international politics.
Enforcement of an agreement is devolved to the parties themselves. Damaged parties have the option
to respond with retaliatory sanctions to a violation of an agreement thereby enhancing
the deterrent and coercive effects of a stable balance of power
The threat of reciprocal sanctions may be sufficient to deter violations, and so agreements can be
enforced in international politics.
Perceives international law as facilitating the continuing exploitation of the Third World through
subordination to the West.
International law was created during the colonial era and that it was used to legitimize the global
processes of marginalization and domination of the colonized people by Western powers.
TWAIL scholars seek to change what they identify as international law's oppressive aspects, through
the re-examination of the colonial foundations of international law.
They refuse to accept the universal character of the international legal system as it emerged solely
from the European.
International law tries to put a limitation of the Third World states’ sovereignty through transferring
their autonomous powers to international institutions controlled by the First World. Ex. Humanitarian
Intervention.
Indian Scholars : R.P.Anand, Upendra Baxi, B.S.Chimni
Assumes the use of feminist theory as a basis for critical analysis, that is to show how the structures,
processes, and methodologies of international law marginalize women by failing to take account of
their lives or experiences
A feminist approach takes as its central concern the position of women and denotes a form of
analysis. It takes gender as its primary organizing category, places women at the center of inquiry,
and works for an end to the oppression of and discrimination against women.
Women’s campaigning for the international legal system to address structural inequality in global
political, social and economic systems and to take account of particular concerns, for example
modern forms of slavery, human trafficking, gender-based crimes, and the nationality of married
women.
The emergence of a global women’s movement gained impetus from the International Women’s Year
proclaimed by the United Nations (UN) in 1975 and subsequently extended to the International
Decade for Women, 1975–85.
Lack of representation of women interests - World and international politics are controlled by men. Very
little scope of representation of women interests like domestic violence, lack of political participation.
Reforms – CEDAW
Lack of women decision makers - No Women SG of the UN, Very less number of women judges in the ICJ
(4 out of 15)
Human rights violation different for both men and women. State-building, or post-conflict reconstruction are
all experienced differently by women and men. However, it is the male experiences and male knowledge
that are privileged and have shaped the framework for traditional legal inquiry and analysis. These are made
to appear objective, natural, and universal in contrast to women’s experiences that appear as exceptional,
deviant, and the other. Example GBV, genital mutilation, rape, trafficking, wartime rape.
Contemporary liberal theory is grounded on the assumptions that people are morally equal and that
each individual should be free to pursue his or her own conception of the good life, constrained by
the requirement that one’s actions not cause harm to others.
The subject of international law is state – very little opportunity for individuals to be part of the
global order through international law. Liberalism counters this place of international law by putting
the individuals at the center point of international law.
Classic Marxist theory described law and politics as the means whereby the ruling classes maintained
their domination of society.
Classical International Law founded on the idea of Nation State and National states were dominated
by the capitalist class and would have to disappear in the re-organizing process.
Professor Tunkin emphasized on new series of international legal ideas:
a. principles of socialist internationalism in relations between socialist states,
b. principles of equality and self-determination of nations and peoples, primarily aimed against
colonialism, and
c. principles of peaceful coexistence aimed at relations between states with different social
systems.
Introduction
Nothing is more essential in International law than having a comprehensive understanding of its relationship
with the Municipal law of a State.
This article will be talking only about the theoretical aspect of International law on Municipal law however,
there are two governing principles of International law relating to the Municipal application of treaties, and
they are:
To have a better understanding of this topic it is crucial to understand what natural law is; natural law is
something that exists in isolation with the positive law. As the name suggests, it is determined by nature, the
law of nature is objective and universal in nature. From the time of inception, natural law is referred to
analyze human nature to deduce moral behaviour from nature.
The argument from the side of a Monist is pretty simple, they believe Municipal law and International law if
looked together is nothing but a single system. Modern writers who favor the monistic approach endeavors
that a major portion of their views are based on a strictly scientific analysis of the Municipal structure of
legal systems.
In a true monist country, there is no need for the translation of International law into Municipal law. Once
the state gives assent to the treaty, it automatically gets incorporated in its municipal law. This act of giving
assent to an International treaty or obligation will immediately incorporate international principles into
states’s Municipal law, (this is inclusive of customary International law).
International law can be applied by a Municipal Court, and can be invoked by citizens, contingent on the
fact that the international law is translated into the state’s Municipal law. A municipal court can declare a
law as unconstitutional if it contradicts International principles.
In a true monist state, if a national law contradicts International law then it becomes null and void, no matter
whether it is of constitutional nature or not. For example, a state gives assent to the Convention on the
Rights of Persons with Disabilities, however, a few of its national laws are in contradiction with the
conventions rights of the individuals who suffer from a disability. Then, a citizen of that country, who is not
getting deprived of the rights conferred by the treaty, can ask the national courts to apply the treaty.
In a Monist State, the International law gets automatically accepted and the contradicting part automatically
gets translated away the moment the State ratifies the treaty.
International law is supreme in nature as it represents a legal order which is higher than Municipal laws, it is
because the International law is derived from the state’s practice on the other hand the Municipal law gains
its power from the state’s internal affairs.
Once it is accepted that International law is a system of rules of a legal character, it becomes impossible
according to kelson to deny that the two systems constitute as a single system.
The theory of International law and Monism doesn’t have any halfway house. Kelson observed natural law
and International law as a single and coherent system. According to him, International law is placed at the
top of the pyramid (as per his grundnorm hypothesis).
Dualist theory
Unlike Monists, dualists have stressed on the difference between International law and Municipal law and
have argued for the adoption of International treaties in the Municipal law of the State. According to
dualists, in absence of this adoption by the State the International law will not exist as a law.
The reason why dualists have this view is because they believe International law and Municipal law are two
different aspects of law and it would be unreasonable to take the two as a unity. As per their belief,
International law and Municipal law are two distinct and independent systems in itself.
In a dualist State, it is of utmost importance that International law has to be drafted in its Municipal law in
order to give it an effect. Apart from drafting it is the duty of the state to omit those laws which contradicts
the newly adopted International law.
If a dualist State ratifies a treaty or a convention, but does not create a law explicitly incorporating the treaty,
then their act of non incorporation violates the International law. If the State has not incorporated the
principles of a treaty as per its local laws which it has ratified earlier in the International sphere then, neither
the citizens of that country can invoke the International laws nor the courts can give its decisions based on
the principles of that treaty.
The United Kingdom is a country in which a dualist approach is dominant. International law becomes the
national law in the UK only if it is translated.
For Lauterpacht, International law is more superior than municipal law, the rationale behind this view is
because it offers the guarantee rights for the individuals notwithstanding anything from which state he
belongs to. As per Lauterpacht the hierarchy of legal orders was:
1. Natural law
2. International law
3. Municipal law
For him whether it is International law or Municipal law, it is the individual who is the definitive unit of all
law. He answered a few fundamental questions of international law philosophy regarding the concept and
origin of international law.
He Criticized the doctrine of Heinrich Triepel’s doctrine of international legal obligation, meanwhile
agreeing with Kelsen that the binding force of law cannot be derived from the individual or common will of
the states.
For Lauterpacht, the international law is for the states and not for governments. For him, the international
community was a community of individuals, whose will is expressed by the states.
Triepel on dualism
Triepel treated the two systems of State law and International law as entirely distinct in nature. For him the
International and Municipal law exist as two separated, distinct sets.
Triepel made following contentions on the relationship between International law and state law:
Firstly he contended that, International law and Municipal law differ in the particular social relations
that they govern; State law deals with the individuals and International law regulates the relations
between States.
Secondly, he argues that their juridical origins are different; the source of Municipal law is the will of
the State itself, the source of International law is the common will of States.
There exist differences in: subjects, sources and content, also, it requires ‘transformation’ of
International law into Municipal law to make International law binding on Municipal authorities.
Triepel accepted that the basic will of the States was the premise of the legitimacy of International law; he
also pointed out that it is heavily relied upon the agreements between States, which not only includes treaties
but custom too and the common will was the most important and inventive source of International law.
In a monist country, a law emerges after the International law has been accepted and if it contradicts the
International law, it automatically becomes null and void. The International rule will continue to prevail.
In a dualist system, when the international law which is translated into a national law can be overridden by
another national law on the principle of “lex posterior derogat legi priori“, which means: the later law
replaces the earlier one.
This means that a dualist state willingly or unwillingly can violate international law. A dualist system
requires continuous screening of all subsequent national law for possible incompatibility with earlier
international law.
Dualism
1. Municipal law and International Law are two different and distinct legal systems.
2. It is supported by the advocates of positive law.
3. In a dualist country there exists a need for translation of International into Municipal law in order to
give it an effect.
4. In a true dualistic country, if a national law contradicts International law then it becomes doesn’t
becomes null and void, unless it is already translated in its municipal law
5. If a dualist State ratifies a treaty or a convention, but does not create a law explicitly incorporating
the treaty, then their act of non incorporation violates the International law.
6. International law does not get automatically embedded in the Municipal law.
7. Contradicting parts of the Municipal law has to be amended by the state, as it does not get
automatically translated away in a dualist country.
8. In the absence of translation of International law into Municipal law the International law will not
exist as a law.
9. Supporter: hersch lauterpatch, triepel.
10. Country which follows: United kingdom.
Judicial Discourse on Relationship Between International Law and Municipal Law
Civil Rights Vigilance Committee S.L.R.C. College of Law Bangalore v. Union of India and others
The High Court of Karnataka while deciding this case, defined the relationship between International Law
and the Municipal Law held that, as the increasing relevance of International law on the global and
municipal scenario, several unique and novel queries are starting to be raised regarding the relationship
between the two. However the Hon’ble High Court held that Municipal Law & International Law are
established on different sources can make different systems go simply incompatible.
Conclusion
Monism and dualism are usually conceived as two opposing theories of the International law and Municipal
law relationship. Monism and dualism are regarded by many modern scholars as having limited explanatory
power as theories as they fail to capture how International law works within States.
Notwithstanding anything, Monism and dualism hold power as analytical tools. They go about as predictable
beginning stages for examinations of the connection among International and Municipal law. Various late
choices in Municipal courts have seen a few researchers find Monism and dualism as potential approaches to
comprehend Municipal legal thinking on International law.
Introduction
Law of the sea is also known as Maritime law which is that branch of public International Law which
regulates the rights and duties concerning the regulation of states with respect to the sea. It governs the legal
rules regarding ships and shipping. It is one of the principal subjects of international law and is a mixture of
the treaty and established or emerging customary law.
The law of the sea forms the basis of conducting maritime economic activities, the codification of navigation
rules and to protect oceans from abuse of power. It covers rights, freedoms and obligations in areas such as
territorial seas and waters and the high seas, fishing, wrecks and cultural heritage, protection of the marine
environment and dispute settlement.
Major Maritime zones along with the rights and duties provided under the specific zones
Territorial seas
It is that part of the sea which is directly next to the coastline and bounded by the high seas. Article 2 of the
Geneva Convention on the Territorial Sea and UNCLOS Article 3 both express that states exercise
sovereignty over this zone subject to the provisions of the respective conventions and other rules of
international law. This was intended to highlight that the limitations upon sovereignty in this area set out in
the Convention are non-exhaustive. The territorial sea forms an undeniable part of the land territory to which
it is bound so that a cession of land will automatically include any band of territorial waters.
According to UNCLOS, it is believed that every coastal state has Territorial sea. The sovereignty of the
coastal state extends to the seabed and subsoil of the territorial sea and the airspace above it. The coastal
States exercise a wide variety of exclusive power over the territorial sea which depends largely on the
municipal law rather the international system. Coastal states can control the entry of foreign vessels from
trading or fishing activities to preserve it for their own citizens.
Contiguous zone
It is that part of the sea which is located beyond and adjacent to the territorial waters of the coastal states.
The development of this zone arose due to the need of the state to strengthen its regulation over the
territorial sea.
It extends up to 12 nautical miles from the territorial sea, the object of this zone is only for certain purposes
as provided in the article 24 of the convention like to prevent infringement of customs, immigration or
sanitary laws of the coastal state, or to conserve fishing stocks in a particular area, or to enable the coastal
state to have exclusive or principal rights to the resources of the proclaimed zone. The formation of this zone
is only for special purposes as prescribed in the convention, it does not provide any air and space rights to
the states.
Beyond territorial seas, a coastal state can exercise its jurisdiction for certain defined purposes only
up to 24 nautical miles from the baseline.
The purposes are:
To prevent infringement of customs;
Immigration;
Sanitary laws of the coastal state;
Conserve fishing stocks;
Coastal state to have principal rights to the resources of that zone
It enables the coastal state to protect its important interests while striking a balance with other
nations and their claim to the high seas.
While territorial sea gives direct and full jurisdiction to the coastal state, it is considered equal to the
land territory, contiguous zones have to be specifically claimed. (1958 Convention)
Customs as a purpose for claiming jurisdiction for contiguous zones is part of customary
international law. For eg. Much before the conventions came USA and UK had enacted laws
extending beyond their territorial waters to prevent smuggling.
Sovereign rights for the purpose of exploring, exploiting, conserving and managing the natural
resources either living or non living-water, currents and wind for energy.
Use of artificial installations, structures, protection and preserving maritime environment and
maritime scientific research.
Starts from the outer limit of territorial sea but not beyond 200 nautical miles from baseline.
Continental Shelf
This zone arose due to the concept of Geography wherein as per 1982 convention, it includes a natural
seaward extension of a land boundary. This seaward extension is geologically formed as the seabed slopes
away from the coast, typically consisting of a gradual slope (the continental shelf proper), followed by a
steep slope (the continental slope), and then a more gradual slope leading to the deep seabed floor. The limit
up to which its length extends up to 200 nautical miles.
These three areas, collectively known as the continental margin, are rich in natural resources, including oil,
natural gas and certain minerals.
The coastal states exercise an extensive sovereign-rights over this zone for the purpose of exploiting its
resources. The coastal state may, under article 80 of the 1982 Convention, construct and maintain
installations and other devices necessary for exploration on the continental shelf and is entitled to establish
safety zones around such installations to a limit of 500 metres, which must be respected by ships of all
nationalities.
EEZ and Continental shelf is almost similar in nature however the major point of difference between the two
is that under the 1982 convention a continental shelf can exist without an EEZ but there cannot be an EEZ
without the demarcation of the Continental shelf.
North Sea Continental Shelf Cases, [1969] I.C.J. 13 (Germany/Denmark; Germany/ Netherlands)
Facts:
The coasts of Germany, Denmark and the Netherlands are adjacent to the North Sea. By previous
agreements, areas of the North Sea continental shelf had been divided between Great Britain and
Denmark/Germany/Netherlands and between Norway and Denmark. These agreements divided the
shelf among states with opposite seacoasts by the equidistance principle, that is, by a line all points
of which were equally distant from the opposing state coasts.
An equidistance line drawn between opposite states is termed a median line; if drawn between adjacent
states, it is a lateral line. The dispute before the Court in North Sea was whether lateral lines should divide
the area of continental shelf left to Denmark, Germany and the Netherlands by the previous agreements with
Norway and Great Britain.
Denmark and the Netherlands wanted a continued use of the equidistance principle. Germany did not agree.
The German coastline curves inward in a concave manner, so that an equidistance extension of the partial
boundaries would result in lateral lines curving inward as well. Germany would thereby receive a smaller
portion of the North Sea continental shelf than if the partial boundaries were extended by a different
principle. The dispute, then, was whether the partial boundaries should be extended by use of the
equidistance principle or by some other principle and if so, what that other principle should be.
Germany did not regard the equidistance principle as binding for several reasons: (1) Germany is not a party
to the Continental Shelf Convention because it has not ratified its signature thereto; (2) Germany's past
conduct and reliance upon other principles of the Convention constitute neither an accession nor an estoppel
to deny the application of the Convention's principles; (3) the equidistance principle is not a rule of
customary international law. Rather, Germany thought that each state should be allocated a "just and
equitable share" of the available continental shelf in proportion to the length of its coastline.
Judgment :
Germany was not bound by the Convention on the Continental Shelf.
The principle of equidistance was not a customary international law and therefore Germany was not bound
to follow that principle either.
The Court thought equidistance more appropriate for opposite than adjacent states. In the case of adjacent
states, the Court found the use of lateral lines more appropriate for delimitation of territorial seas than of
continental shelf.
The Court then set forth those principles of international law which were binding upon Germany-
Delimitation is to be effected by agreement in accordance with equitable principles, and taking account of all
the relevant circumstances, in such a way as to leave as much as possible to each Party all those parts of the
continental shelf that constitute a natural prolongation of its land territory into and under the sea, without
encroachment on the natural prolongation of the land territory of the other;
Delimitation leaves to the Parties areas that overlap, these are to be divided between them in agreed
proportions or, failing agreement, equally, unless they decide on a regime of joint jurisdiction, user, or
exploitation for the zones of overlap or any part of them;
In the course of the negotiations, the factors to be taken into account are to include:
The general configuration of the coasts of the Parties, as well as the presence of any special or unusual
features;
So far as known or readily ascertainable, the physical and geological structure, and natural resources, of the
continental shelf areas involved;
The element of a reasonable degree of proportionality, which a delimitation carried out in accordance with
equitable principles ought to bring about between the extent of the continental shelf areas appertaining to the
coastal state and the length of its coast measured in the general direction of the coastline, account being
taken for this purpose of the effects, actual or prospective, of any other continental shelf delimitations
between adjacent states in the same region.
For the purposes of exploring and exploiting natural resources coastal state exercises sovereign right.
No other state can undertake such activities in that region without the express consent of the coastal
state.
These rights do not affect the superjacent waters as the high seas.
Exploration and exploitation of the resources must not result in unjustifiable interference with
navigation, fishing or conservation of living resources in the high seas.
Coastal states may construct or maintain installations or do as need be for purposes of exploitation
and can create safety zones which must be respected by all states. Such installations shall not create
rights of an island for the coastal state.
Conclusion
Law of the sea is concerned with public order at sea which has been codified in the form of United Nations
Convention on the Law of the Sea and signed on December 10, 1982. It provides rules and regulations that
helps to maintain peace and security over the usage of the sea.
The code provides a set of comprehensive rules which divides the oceanic region into 5 maritime zones and
it has set the limit to 12 nautical miles for the coastal states to exercise their sovereignty without any
conflict. It aims to resolve the dispute amicably with the help of international tribunal for the law of the sea.