A Short History of European Law - The Last Two and A Half - Tamar Herzog - 2018 - Harvard University Press - 9780674981744 - Anna's Archive
A Short History of European Law - The Last Two and A Half - Tamar Herzog - 2018 - Harvard University Press - 9780674981744 - Anna's Archive
A Short History of European Law - The Last Two and A Half - Tamar Herzog - 2018 - Harvard University Press - 9780674981744 - Anna's Archive
Tamar Herzog
Cambridge, Massachusetts
London, England
2018
Copyright © 2018 by Tamar Herzog
All rights reserved
Printed in the United States of America
First printing
part three The L
ater M
iddle Ages
5 The Birth of a European Ius Commune 75
6 The Birth of an English Common Law 93
part five Modernity
10 North American Developments 167
11 The French Revolution 183
Notes 245
Further Reading 255
Acknowledgments 279
Index 281
Introduction
the making of law in eur ope
Atlantic and mutated. Within a larger history of European law, the expla-
nation would have to engage with the question of not only why the Magna
Carta acquired this mythical status but also why similar feudal charters,
abundant and frequent elsewhere in Europe, did not.
As a legal historian I know that what the Magna Carta currently stands for
has nothing to do with the text itself and everything to do with how it was
used and remembered. If my student knew this history, I reasoned, she might
understand the past better, but she might also acquire a means to imagine
differently her present and f uture. It could supply her with instruments to
question narratives, understand the processes that led to their formation, and
suggest where they could take us next.
The Magna Carta, of course, is not the only legal remnant that still deter-
mines our present or allows us to imagine our future. Plenty of other instru-
ments, institutions, and texts inherited from the past fulfill the same role. As
both relics of a time gone and important features of our everyday life, they
give things certain meanings, they supply solutions, and they offer techniques
through which to analyze and understand reality. Take, for example, “due
process”—the obligation of courts to follow a particular procedure. Intui-
tively, many among us would consider it a relatively modern phenomenon
linked to society’s ambition to ensure the implementation of justice. Yet,
due process, if not in name then at least in practice, was born long ago in
medieval England. The story of its emergence is linked not so much to
guaranteeing the right result (which it did not) but to the insistence that
judges of common-law courts obey very strict procedural rules. Under-
standing why procedural rules became so important in English law and
how, over the years and because of very odd transformations, they came to
be seen also as instruments protecting litigants, would allow us to have a
better grasp, for example, of why certain things were covered by due process
while others were not, or why this set of rules developed in E ngland rather
than elsewhere.
Engagement with the past would also enable us to comprehend how Euro
pean law came to refashion itself both as the epitome of reason and as a system
with potentially universal applicability. The enormous influence Euro
pean law has had around the globe could of course be explained by political
and economic factors, but it also required an intellectual elaboration. An-
cient Romans already linked community membership to law and both of
these to the extension of political hegemony, but these links metamorphosed
Introduction 3
history, this presumption, however, could come to satisfy new needs. Used
under radically different social conditions, in present-day Spain, for example,
it authorizes the registration of a child born to a legally married gay c ouple
as the natural offspring of both spouses.
Roman law is an important point of departure for European legal his-
tory not only b ecause of its ongoing legacy but also b ecause this legacy was
eventually shared by most (if not all) Europeans. Penetrating slowly, first
with the expansion of the Roman Empire and then with the conversion to
Christianity, it became the common stock in Europe most particularly a fter
it was taken up by medieval scholars and reworked to fit contemporary
needs. Forming the basis also for the initial development of English common
law, its validity and influence w ere tested during the early modern period
and w ere affirmed or denied with the coming of modernity. Over the course
of this history, paradoxically, even those who rejected adherence to Roman
law often argued their case by analogy to it.
The understanding of Roman law, of course, changed over the course of
history, and so did its use. What it meant in the classical period had very
little to do with how medieval jurists used it, or what English common-law
lawyers and German nineteenth-century jurists made of it. Despite this huge
variation in the way it was understood and incorporated, Roman law never-
theless maintained its prestige, and so did some of its basic methodologies
and tenets. As usually happens, this interpretation and reinterpretation of
the past enabled a creative engagement, not only with what had transpired
in the past, but also with constructing the present and the future.
The constant invocation of Roman law also required as well as explained
the permanent strain experienced in Europe between stability and univer-
sality, on the one hand, and dynamism and local responses, on the other. If
Roman law supplied the backbone for a common European legal tradition,
it could not solve the constant tensions between local and global, individual
solutions and overreaching principles. Th ese tensions w ere already present
in Rome itself, where historians distinguished between law as practiced in
the center and as followed in the provinces, but they continued throughout
European history. It was precisely in order to overcome such tensions that
in the eleventh, twelfth, and thirteenth centuries, efforts w ere made, in both
Continental Europe and England, to create a unifying common law (Chap-
ters 5 and 6). This ius commune, a term the English initially also used to desig-
nate their common law, was meant to cement and give coherence to a legal
8 A Short History of European Law
away from the art of conserving a status quo (as has been the case before) to
the art of innovating in order to create a seemingly better world.
Having started this book with Roman law, I end it with the establish-
ment and growth of the European Union, which for me is both a point of
arrival and a point of departure. To what degree can Europe today have a
common law, and who are the agents and interests propelling such a legal
unification? Are these processes of unification particular to Europe or do
they also operate on a global scale? How can the nation-state, invented in
the late eighteenth century, cope with the challenges of both Europeanization
and globalization?
To answer some of these questions and make some of these points, the
individual chapters that follow each address a certain topic, as well as
describe its evolution. In order to make the narrative clearer, I sometimes
sacrifice chronology for the sake of illustrating better what I describe. I do
so, for example, in Chapter 1, where I discuss provincial Roman law codes
that were enacted a fter the empire converted to Christianity. Similarly, in
Chapter 2, which describes the Christianization of Rome, I deal with some
of the issues also covered in Chapter 3, which focuses on the early M iddle
Ages. In Chapter 6, where I study the foundational period of common law,
I sometimes venture into the early modern period.
If chronology is complex, so is the geographical and political entity I
identify as Europe. Evidently, over the course of the period I cover, Europe
and the definition of what belonged to it were both invented and had
greatly mutated. An idea rather than a continent, Europe changed forms
and shapes and eventually ventured overseas to territories we now identify
as colonial. The projection of European law was just as amorphous. During
Roman times, parts of the Mediterranean and Asia were subjected to it, as
were European overseas domains later on. By the eighteenth, nineteenth,
and twentieth centuries, the legal tradition I describe as European reached
its utmost expansion due to the growing hegemony of the Continent
but also b ecause elites around the globe chose to use and adapt European
law to their own needs and desires. B ecause of this extension, some of
the most important developments in European law happened outside the
Continent, as when the law of nations was turned into natural law in the
colonies, or as in the constitutional innovations introduced in North
Americ a. These not only were a consequence of European law, they also
greatly modified it.
10 A Short History of European Law
Ancient Times
1
Roman Law
now you see it, now you d
on ’ t
The city of Rome was probably founded in the early part of the seventh
century bce. Initially ruled by monarchs, at around 509 bce it had converted
into a republic, in which a senate (an assembly of elders) appointed annually
two public magistrates (consuls) to govern the community. This system of
government lasted until 27 bce, when the senate declared Augustus em-
peror. Having traded and fought extensively with its neighbors, Rome
gradually expanded its control, first throughout the Italian peninsula and
then throughout the Mediterranean and into parts of central and northern
Europe. In 285 ce, the empire was divided into a western and an eastern part.
This division, justified by the enormous size of the territories under Roman
control, gradually gained political saliency. In 476 ce, Germanic troops in-
vaded the city, forcing the abdication of the emperor, thereby bringing about
what has come to be known as the “fall of the Roman Empire.” Despite these
developments, which terminated Roman political hegemony in the west, the
Eastern empire, with its capital in Constantinople (present-day Istanbul),
survived until its conquest by Ottoman tribes in 1453.
Rome left an enduring legacy in many areas and multiple ways. How-
ever, one of its clearest bequests was its influence over the development of
law. Th
ere is a saying attributed to Goethe according to which Roman law
was like a diving duck. It could be swimming on the surface or diving
deep in the water, but whether you saw it or not, it was always there.1 This
belief in the persistence of Roman law throughout European history was not
13
14 A Short History of European Law
reflected the evolution of Roman society and its needs. However, we know
that relatively soon, praetors began drawing up standardized formulas that
no longer included reference to the particular conditions of the case. Worded
hypothetically, these formulas could specify, for example, that the praetor
could rule against a seller who refused to hand to the buyer what was agreed
upon, unless the seller showed no fault.
As formulas became more abstract, they could easily apply to more than
a single case. Realizing this potential, some praetors began issuing lists of
formulas that they would be willing to use in the f uture. Praetors working
in Rome tended to post these lists in the Forum Romanum, the main
square of the city, for all to read. The lists enumerated, seemingly in random
fashion, the cases the praetor would agree to hear. For example, going back
to Titus and Agrippa, the list could include the praetor’s promise to rule in
favor of a person whose property was taken away without compensation.
Identified as edicts (edictum), eventually the lists of remedies w ere published
annually by praetors before they assumed office. From the mid-first century
bce they w ere considered binding on the individual praetor who published
them.
Initially each praetor published his own edict, with his particular list of
remedies that would be valid only during the year in which he was in office.
Yet gradually, first in the provinces and then in Rome, most praetors began
copying earlier lists and referring to formulas already in existence. By the
first century ce, repetition was so common and edicts w ere considered so
prescriptive that praetors could no longer disregard what they had included
by adding or subtracting from them. This became the rule in the second
century ce when, under Hadrian (r. 117–138 ce), edicts were collected in an
official compilation that was declared to be sufficient and final.
This development marked both the maturity and the end of an impor
tant period of Roman law. Before formulas w ere fossilized by the continuous
repetition of the same edicts, praetors could create new formulas as well as
deny the admissibility of old formulas. By granting or refusing to grant ac-
cess to the courts, by indicating which circumstances deserved a remedy and
which did not, and by allowing defendants to invoke certain defenses but
not o thers, praetors intervened in the legal order by creating or denying
what today we would identify as rights. Their intervention was so impor
tant and so massive that the norms they created by granting or refusing
to grant remedies were identified as forming a new source of law, which
20 A Short History of European Law
paralleled the old ius civile and was later designated as ius honorarium, liter-
ally, the law that was made while they exercised their office (honos).
The importance of ius honorarium as a legal source allowed historians to
characterize Roman law as a “law of remedies.” Focused on how to redress
the breach of peace and guarantee the return of the status quo, ius hono-
rarium was mainly concerned with what individuals could do when
they were wronged. It prescribed where they could go and which reme-
dies they could receive. Much less interested in coining general principles
or developing guidelines, this law was practical and casuistic. It collected
the accumulated experience of Roman praetors but also authorized legiti-
mate expectations as to what a wronged person could do. Alongside the
existing law (ius civile), this magistrate-made law (ius honorarium) shaped
Roman law as a synthesis between expert opinion based on customs, rit-
uals, and systematic presentation (ius civile), on the one hand, and everyday
conflicts and their resolution (ius honorarium), on the other.
imperial decision making. In the long run, imperial control over this legal
source was achieved more efficiently by co-opting jurists, not by at-
tempting to manage the normative reception of their opinions. To this end,
several emperors employed prestigious jurists in their court or arranged for
them to give responses on their behalf. Some jurists even became mem-
bers of the council that advised emperors on the most important m atters of
state.
This cooperation between jurists and the emperor led to important
changes. By the third century ce, most juridical activity was centered on
jurists giving responses as members of the imperial bureaucracy. In their
capacity as imperial officials, their determinations were now binding not
because of their inherent goodness but because they were considered orders
of the emperor.
Juridical Training
Initially jurists had no special preparation other than living in the commu-
nity and being involved in its affairs. As members of the Roman elite, most
were trained in rhetoric, the art of persuasion, but they had no legal training
per se. With the growing importance and number of jurists, however, some-
thing akin to a professional preparation began appearing. Instruction
mostly took place orally, with a group of apprentices following a master as
he gave advice or delivered speeches. As this practice became popular, indi-
vidual preparation was replaced by communities, or groups of people, who
came to listen to jurists publically expound their opinions on points of the
law. Although teaching continued to be informal and voluntary, t hose ha-
bitually listening w ere sometimes identified as “students” who formed “socie
ties” and paid some remuneration to their “teachers.”
By the first c entury ce, the following of masters became so institutional-
ized that two rival schools of thought made their appearance. Identified as
the Proculians and the Sabinians, these schools w ere named after the jurists
who founded them. Historians disagree as to the difference between the two
schools. Most believe that they were probably distinct in their approach to
legal analysis, one adhering more closely to the letter of the law and the other
caring more about material justice.
The congregation of students around masters was particularly noticeable
in the second c entury ce, when several locations w ere identified as places
Roman Law 25
where law teaching habitually took place. In t hese locations, teachers gave
courses on a variety of subjects, including juridical thought and imperial leg-
islation. At the end of their studies, students received a certificate. By the
fourth century ce these schools came u nder the control of emperors, who
appointed the teachers and gave them the status of civil servants. In 425 ce,
Theodosius II (r. 408–450 ce) declared illegal the teaching of law outside
these state-sanctioned institutions.
Legislation
Another means to create legal norms was legislation. Assemblies (meet-
ings of all male, adult, Roman citizens) could pass statutes (leges) as well
as plebiscita (laws made in assemblies of plebeians). According to some
historians, the Senate, where leading men of the republic met to discuss the
affairs of the day, was a legislative body that not only recommended but
also prescribed certain solutions (senatus consulta), most particularly u nder
the Republic (ca. 509–27 bce). In the late Principate (ca. 27 bce–284 ce),
a new form of legislation, the oratio principis, appeared, allowing emperors
to deliver speeches telling the Senate which norms it should adopt.
These various legal sources fared differently in diverse periods. Laws and
statutes passed by assemblies were an important source of law until the first
century bce. Senate decrees were important in the first and part of the
second century ce. The accumulation of imperial legislation led to the appear-
ance of collections of imperial constitutions such as the third-century ce
Codex Gregorianus, which included legislation from Hadrian to Emperor
Diocletian (r. 284–305 ce), or the more famous early fifth-century Codex
Theodosianus, formally promulgated by Theodosius II and including sixteen
books divided into titles and covering legislation dating from 306 to 437 ce.
But even at the height of their prominence, these sources were of little weight
when compared to the production of praetors and jurists. Among other
things, legislation tended to add to and explain, rather than change, the legal
situation. Furthermore, its most frequent field of action was public, not pri-
vate, law. Legislation also covered such issues as criminal law, testamentary
succession, and f amily law.
The relatively secondary role of legislation in the making of Roman
law was paradoxically confirmed with the advent of the empire. Roman
emperors, who sought to influence the legal order, legislated massively.
26 A Short History of European Law
Ius Gentium
Owing to the conviction that polities depended on agreement among mem-
bers to live together under the same normative order, Roman law was ap-
plied exclusively to the citizens of Rome. Because each community had its
own laws, which w ere the laws of its civitas (its community of citizens), in
theory foreigners (peregrini) had no right to Roman law even when they were
present in Rome. Foreigners of the same group were to use their own ius
civile, that is, their own communal law. But what would happen when indi-
viduals of distinct communities came into contact? Which laws would apply?
To take care of such situations, a different system had to be devised. Born
sometime in the fourth or third c entury bce—the dates are not very clear—
this system was eventually identified as ius gentium (literally, the Law of
Nations, P eoples, Gentiles, or Tribes). Managing it would be a new figure,
a special praetor for foreigners (praetor peregrinus), a post created in 242 bce.9
The emergence of ius gentium rested on the assumption that while some
norms were particular to a specific community, others were common to all.
Ius civile represented the former; ius gentium represented the latter. From its
birth, therefore, ius gentium was imagined as a universal system that could
fit any person of any community or legal tradition. To discover what it
included, in theory the praetor peregrinus (or provincial governor) was to
identify the legal principles shared by all humans. Because what this meant
in practice was not always clear, t hose dealing with ius gentium had a much
greater liberty to add, subtract, or change the law than did other officials
Roman Law 27
who w ere charged with applying Roman law. Thus, although much is un-
known about how the praetor peregrinus proceeded to identify the contents
of ius gentium and w hether his understanding of it truly differed from his
understanding of Roman ius civile, it is nevertheless clear he enjoyed a rela-
tive liberty that allowed him to, for example, abandon the old causes of
action and, as we saw earlier, and introduce new formulas. The quest to
identify a ius gentium also allowed the praetor peregrinus the pioneering
adoption of important principles, such as the obligation to have good faith
(bona fides) in contracts. The formulas the praetor peregrinus created, the rem-
edies he supplied, and the edicts he published established important new
practices and doctrines soon imitated by other praetors and since used by
jurists.
Imagined as a law that was not based on the specific historical experi-
ence of a particu lar community but instead was anchored in h uman expe-
rience, eventually ius gentium was said to represent h uman reason and the
nature of t hings. As a result of this understanding, on occasions Romans
considered it also as embodying a natural law (ius naturale). They suggested
that it was so reasonable and compelling that nature, rather than h uman
convention, was responsible for its creation.
rather than arguing that Roman law should be universally applied, they
redefined the extension of the Roman community by including in it all the
inhabitants of the empire. Roman law theoretically remained the same;
what changed was the definition of who Romans were.
The expansion of citizenship and, with it, of Roman law, throughout the
empire led to important developments. One that has drawn the attention of
many scholars was the emergence of a series of peripheral or provincial
Roman legal systems. These included local expressions of Roman law,
which were radically different from place to place and vastly diverse over
time. Once portrayed as “vulgar” b ecause of their distance from the centers
of creation and from juridical debates, their more salient feature was that
they were greatly influenced by local conditions and customs, most partic-
ularly in the Hellenistic East, where Romanization was harder to achieve
than elsewhere.
Although the emergence of local variations of Roman law probably
predated the extension of Roman citizenship to all the inhabitants of the
empire, it is generally believed that this extension accelerated the frag-
mentation of Roman law. By ordering that Roman law would immedi-
ately replace all previous legal traditions, the Antonine Constitution, which
sanctioned the extension of citizenship in 212 ce, unilaterally imposed the
trappings of Roman law onto preexisting native systems. In theory man-
dating a complete legal overhaul, in practice, however, this goal was unat-
tainable. The result was an extremely complex structure that allowed the
development of multiple and parallel legal systems that, although formally
identified as Roman and sharing some characteristics, w ere nevertheless radi-
cally different from one another.
This extreme pluralism was not formally acknowledged. Roman jurists, of
course, knew that differences, sometimes substantial ones, existed among the
laws operating across the empire, but they did their best to conceal this.
They did so by redefining the scope of customary law. They argued that, after
the imposition of Roman citizenship, all persisting differences between the
(original) Roman law and the (local) Roman law w ere but exceptions an-
chored in local customs. Reimagining all legal differences as part of a local
customary law allowed jurists to sanction and legitimize the survival of a
vast body of native law despite the fact that, in theory, the empire tolerated
only the existence of one common (Roman) law.
Whether they predated the imposition of Roman law or emerged after it
was imposed, paradoxically, the reclassification of legal differences as customs
Roman Law 29
reproduced some essential Roman texts, such as abstracts from the second-
century Institutes of Gaius or the fifth-century Theodosian Code, compilers
of this law selected which parts to include and how to interpret them. They
incorporated and reproduced in their collection a simplified and abbrevi-
ated version of Roman law based on very few sources that were repeatedly
used and cited. It is also possible that by the time the Lex Romana was
enacted, Roman law was already u nder the influence of not only local Ibe-
rian customs but also the laws and customs that the Visigoths brought with
them to Iberia. If this was true, then not only did the Lex Romana capture
only some parts of Roman law, but it is possible that it contained a not
particularly faithful representation of how Roman law fared in Iberia be-
fore, during, or a fter the Visigoth conquest.
If the extension of citizenship was one challenge, another was Emperor
Diocletian’s (r. 284–305) decision in 285 ce, in the midst of a prolonged crisis,
to divide the empire into two parts. Diocletian apparently wished to facilitate
the administration of this vast polity by naming two rulers and building two
capitals. Yet what began as a mere administrative and political tool ended up
forming a true divide. In the post-Diocletian period, Constantine (r. 306–337)
materialized the division of the empire by erecting in the east a New Rome,
which he called Constantinople, where he transferred his residence.
The growing distinction between East and West was also noticeable le-
gally with the gradual emergence of an Eastern and a Western Roman law. It
became particularly prominent after the Western empire fragmented in the
fifth c entury and was overrun by a g reat variety of tribes we now identify as
Germanic (see Chapter 3). Thereafter, Western Roman law became heavily
influenced by Germanic legal traditions. Meanwhile in the East, Roman law
came under the renewed yet intense influence of Hellenistic culture.
Most historians tend to categorize the survival of Roman law in the East
as marking the emergence of a separate and distinct legal tradition, which
they identify as Byzantine. Yet, paradoxically, this so-called Byzantine law
eventually gave rise to the most important compilation of Roman law that
survives to date, the Corpus Iuris Civilis.
(r. 527–565), emperor of the Eastern empire in the sixth century ce (that is,
after the fragmentation of the Western empire), in reality the Corpus included
several independent compilations that were enacted successively. Common
to all of them was that they were prepared by a committee of experts with
the aim of guarding, even restoring, the glory of Roman law as well as sup-
plying a practical code for the Eastern empire and a teaching tool for
students.
First among t hese compilations was the Code (Codex), which in a first edi-
tion of 529 and a second edition of 534 outlined various texts of imperial
legislation, some ancient, some less so, some general and some pertaining
specifically to the Eastern empire. The Codex mostly sought to fuse selec-
tively three preexisting compilations (the Codex Gregorianus, the Codex Her-
mogenianus, and the Codex Theodosianus), adding to them the most recent
imperial legislation and omitting what was considered obsolete or contra-
dictory. The second edition of the Codex also included decisions by Justinian
as to how to solve certain conflicts and promote reform. The Code, which
was meant to replace earlier collections, was arranged according to subject
matter, and inside each subject the laws were arranged chronologically.
The second compilation carried out u nder the auspices of Justinian was
the Digest (or Pandects). Finalized in 533 ce, it reproduced extracts from the
writings of some of the most influential Roman jurists who had worked
between the first c entury bce and the fourth century ce. Arranged by
topic, the Digest dealt with important areas of private law, mostly family
law, property law, contract law, and inheritance.11 It was divided into
fifty books that followed the arrangement of the Code.
The third compilation, titled Institutes, was promulgated in 533. Mainly
based on the manual for students authored by Gaius in the second c entury
ce as well as containing elements from other students’ manuals, Justinian’s
Institutes described the principles of Roman law and divided them by the
law of persons, t hings, and actions.
Although meant to collect and reproduce the law, the Corpus Iuris Civilis
nevertheless innovated a great deal. The quantity of material considered for
inclusion was enormous, forcing the editing committee to choose what
should be incorporated and what not. Historians have estimated that, to pre-
pare the Digest, which compiled jurists’ opinions, some thirty-eight authors
and two thousand books were consulted but that only about 5 percent of
this material made it into the last version. Committee members were also
32 A Short History of European Law
told to settle conflicts and produce a unitary body of law and were man-
dated to adapt this law to the conditions and legislation of their time.
If the process of elaboration implied change, so too did the inclusion of
this material in legislation sanctioned by the emperor as the law of the realm.
The juridical opinions that w ere reproduced in the Digest now acquired the
status of law. The same happened with the Institutes, a manual for students
that thereafter was authorized as the formal vehicle with which to under-
stand Roman law. Justinian was so adamant about giving his collections the
power of law that he prohibited references to the original material or to pre-
vious recompilations. He also forbade the elaboration of commentaries and
glosses, forcing jurists to center their attention on his compilations and on
them alone. Often unsuccessful, these measures nevertheless exemplified the
degree by which Justinian desired to ensure the beginning of a new age.
that never formed part of the empire, this introduction created a space we
now identify as Latin Christendom.1 What it meant for European legal de-
velopment is the subject of this chapter.
Rome Christianized, Roman law and the behavior of Romans would have
substantially mutated.
But many historians now disagree about how important or pervasive the
influence of Christianity on Roman law was or, most particularly, how im-
mediate. They also question whether legal changes (even when they occurred)
affected practices, or whether they remained a dead letter, more revealing of
the intentions of a small elite than of what happened in society at large.
Those holding the view that little changed a fter the Christianization of
the empire argue that the new conceptualization of law as divinely mandated
did not immediately influence Roman law. As long as the empire lasted,
Roman officials continued to operate as before, inventing, reinterpreting,
and applying the existent law. Criminal law also continued to uphold Roman
traditions and was not greatly affected by the new, radically distinct, Chris-
tian morality. Families continued to function as they did in the past, with
children maintaining their role as guardians of familial memory despite the
new Christian promise of afterlife and Christian criticism of Roman earthly
commemorations. Social stratification and status w ere essentially preserved
despite the new ethos that Christians were to live in brotherly and nonhier-
archical communities.
While many historians sought to answer the question whether the con-
version of the empire affected Roman law by comparing the norms before
and a fter it took place, others suggested that not all contemporary legal
changes w ere necessarily tied to the adoption of the new religion. Mutations,
they argue, could easily be motivated by an evolution common to both Chris-
tians and non-Christians. A fter all, Roman law had constantly changed
even when the religious belief of Romans did not. Was it possible, for ex-
ample, that some innovations, such as demands for female chastity, reflected
notions coming from the provinces and from non-aristocratic circles that ad-
hered to customary practices rather than to the new Christian beliefs?
Some historians reached the conclusion that Christianity introduced no
substantial or immediate changes. Others affirmed that even if the authori-
ties, modalities, and language remained the same, the contents of Roman
law shifted in what was to become a long and slow process of integrating
Christianity with Roman law. Th ese scholars point to legal adjustments
adopted a fter the conversion of the empire, mainly through imperial legis-
lation. For example, beginning in the fourth century ce, sins were added to
the existing lists of crimes, and new regulations were made regarding pious
The Creation of Latin Christendom 37
bequests. Also innovative was the distinction between appropriate and in-
appropriate public entertainment, the idea of indissoluble marriage, the le-
gitimization of natural c hildren, and the duty to pay alimony to wife and
offspring. Beyond imperial legislation, it is possible that Christianity might
have influenced the way Romans conceptualized and sought to control sexual
conduct. It might have led to new practices regarding charity and welfare.
In short, Christian elements and a Christian agenda may have gradually pen-
etrated Roman law, and Christianized Romans behaved (at least to some
degree) differently than pagans.
Historians of late Roman law also debated why Roman emperors intro-
duced Christian ideas into their legislation (when they did). Some argued
that the emperors w ere motivated by true religious belief; o thers said that
they were politicians seeking to maximize their power and capitalize on new
societal trends that w ere beneficial to them. For example, was Constantine’s
legislative work motivated by Christian zeal or by traditional Roman con-
cerns? By referencing customary legal practices, was it possible that Constan-
tine nevertheless created new norms that introduced Christian ideas, fusing
them with Roman precedents and values? Taking into account his legislation
regarding the emancipation of slaves, was his support for the idea of freedom
a result of his wish to free individuals who were enslaved because of their
Christian belief (as some have argued), or was it part of a more general move
against his opponents, allowing him to portray these opponents as tyrants
and himself as a liberator? How did introducing new methods for emanci-
pation, mainly by allowing Christian masters to f ree their slaves in church,
affect Roman laws on slavery? How did it help the propagation and consoli-
dation of Christianity?
Rome and became the official religion of the empire, Rome gradually emerged
as an important Christian center, and in many areas Latin replaced Greek
as the main vehicle of communication.
Other important changes also took place. Early Christianity was very
local in character and contained many different communities who agreed
on hardly anything. Th ese communities w ere self-regulated and often con-
fronted one another. A fter Christianity became the religion of the empire,
this extremely nucleated structure gradually came under attack. Now that
Christianity was endowed with a state (the Roman state), an additional system
of law (to Church law was now added Roman law), and a series of authori-
ties (Roman authorities), t hese began regulating Christian life. What followed
was a slow process of centralization that eventually led to the formation of
the Church as we think of it today—a structure of authority with a more or
less fixed canon of beliefs and a set of authorized texts.
The institutionalization of Church authorities and the definition of a
common creed was a mission that late Roman emperors undertook with g reat
expediency. This imperial positioning vis-à-vis the Church had Roman pre
cedents. Pagan Roman emperors were considered representatives of the gods,
with whom they were believed to have direct communication. Because the
gods favored them, the emperors were u nder the obligation to ensure that
the gods would be worshipped. Applying this understanding to Christianity,
late Roman emperors presented themselves as defenders of the correct faith
and as leaders responsible for its propagation. As benefactors of the Church,
they adjudicated conflicts among Church members and among different
Christian communities and decided who was right and who was wrong in
matters of faith.
Following t hese beliefs, from as early as the fourth c entury ce emperors
also called meetings to declare the basic tenets of Christianity. The Council
of Nicaea (325 ce), organized by Constantine, settled the issue of who Jesus
was and what his relationship to God was. It adopted the so-called Nicene
Creed, later expanded at the Council of Constantinople (381 ce), which
affirmed the divinity of Jesus and the existence of a trinity (the f ather, the
son, and the Holy Spirit). The Council of Carthage (397 ce) identified the
official canon of the Church and selected the texts that would be included
in the authorized scripture.3 Early councils also provided procedures to or-
dain the clergy and to call for meetings of bishops (synods) and adopted
some of the principal liturgical practices.
The Creation of Latin Christendom 39
Defining Heresy
The gradual definition of what Christianity was and what believers should
follow also led to the identification of what it was not. This process of
delegitimizing certain positions began long before the conversion of the
empire, but it greatly accelerated thereafter. It was so quick and powerf ul
that, disregarding past divisions, by the fifth century ce Christian authors
could argue that Christianity included “all which has been believed every-
where, always, by anyone.” 4 Recognizing some debates among the faithful as
legitimate (these w
ere identified as schisma) and others as not (heresy), the
result was the division of Christians into orthodox (those who believed cor-
rectly) and heterodox individuals (those who did not).
As t hese opinions propagated, Roman emperors began legislating against
heretics. B ecause of the identification between empire and Church, they
defined heretics as criminal offenders. Their disobedience, it was argued,
constituted contempt for the emperor and his imperial law and endangered
the community. It therefore could, and indeed was, equated with treason
and was punishable by death. Thereafter, St. Augustine (354–430 ce) could
advocate persecution of heretics, believing that they were dangerous dis-
senters whose opinions could pollute the community and bring about its
downfall.
Promoting Conversion
If the union of empire and Christianity generated mechanisms leading to a
single dogma imposed on all believers and punishment of t hose who refused
to adhere to its tenets, it also provided opportunities to promote conversion.
Wishing to achieve this goal, different emperors legislated in this direction,
granting converts special privileges. They also inflicted on pagans legal and
40 A Short History of European Law
The Church’s adoption of Roman structures and laws was also clear in
other ways. Dioceses were conceptualized as Roman units, and the Church
itself was legally constructed as a corporation (universitas), a status that in
Roman law was held by the state and other public bodies, allowing them to
own property, receive gifts, and make contracts. Church buildings were
called basilicas after the old Roman spaces where assemblies met and where
praetors rendered judgments on elevated platforms. Church canons (rules)
used the imperial style and were read, interpreted, and obeyed as if they were
imperial decrees. Roman jurisprudence became a vehicle through which to
discuss theological questions, and bishops responded to petitioners by using
the forms and formulas of Roman jurists. One result of this merger was
various books, such as a fourth-century discussion of why paganism was false
and Christianity was true that was titled “Divine Institutes” after Gaius’s
manual for law students. This allusion was purposeful, according to the au-
thor, because just as Roman jurists used Gaius’s Institutes to settle juridical
disputes, his book would do the same with regard to religious creed.
Historians thus conclude that early ecclesiastical law grew out of the con-
stant interaction between Roman legal practices and the requirements and
needs of the Church. The Church, of course, also preserved the Roman lan-
guage (Latin) as well as Roman forms of oratory, expression, literature, ar-
chitecture, and art. By the time of Pope Gregory I (590–604) some authors
portrayed their world as one “in which most Romans had been Christened,
the empire itself sometimes was called a res publica christiana and the
Church long since granted peace (tranquilitas).”5 Criticizing this situation
a thousand years later in 1651, Thomas Hobbes remarked that “the papacy
is no other than the ghost of the deceased Roman empire, sitting crowned
upon the grave thereof.” 6 As for historians, they have long asked if the
empire was swallowed up by the Church, or the Church by the empire.
Most agree, however, that Christianity transformed Rome and that Roman
society transformed Christianity, and that, in the process, law acquired a
new character.
of diffusion was long and complicated. Initially, conversion efforts were fairly
feeble. As long as the Church consisted of a multiplicity of bishops, each
working in his diocese, there were insufficient means or coordination with
which to bring about the conversion of large populations. However, with the
foundation of the monastic o rders (which produced dedicated missionaries,
most particularly from the sixth century onward) and the gradual affirma-
tion of the papacy (during approximately the same period) the Church moved
into an expansionist mode.
From the sixth to the twelfth century, Christianity gradually established
itself in most of central, northern, and eastern Europe. Expanding westward
from the Italian peninsula to present-day France and Germany, it reached the
British Isles, and to the east it spread into Moravia, Slovakia, Serbia, Bul-
garia, Poland, Hungary, and the Baltic states. Next came northern Europe,
with the Netherlands, Denmark, Sweden, Norway, and Iceland. At times
incremental, at others advancing and retreating, by the end of the twelfth
century this process of conversion produced an important homogenizing ef-
fect that, among other things, introduced Roman law and Roman struc-
tures all over Europe.
As a result of these processes, the new Christianized understanding of
Roman law, which initially was limited to the territories of the empire, won
primacy throughout much of European territory. Missionaries and Church
officials responsible for this dissemination might have cared about the con-
version of the so-called pagans, but while they spread the word of the gospel,
they also propagated the language, rhetoric, art, ceremonies, culture, and
law of Rome. They introduced Roman administrative structures, formulas,
and procedures and imposed Roman ways of thinking, arguing, and re-
solving conflicts.
Particularly transformative in this regard were the proc esses taking
place in territories that had not been part of the Roman Empire. There,
the accumulated effect of Christianization and Romanization was especially
noteworthy, eventually replacing earlier traditions. According to some histo-
rians, the diffusion of Romanized Christianity throughout much of the
Continent resulted in the “making of Europe.” That is, it brought about the
gradual buildup of the cultural, administrative, legal, and political charac-
teristics that enabled Europe to cohere.7 By the tenth century if not earlier,
Europeans of very distinct regions with vastly diverse pasts and cultures
could feel themselves identified with Christianity and present themselves as
heirs to Rome.
The Creation of Latin Christendom 43
differ substantially from one place to the next, and, lacking an efficient cen-
tral authority, different Christian communities could disagree about almost
everything.
In the quest to reinstitute a central authority for the Church, beginning in
the sixth c entury and more clearly in the following centuries, successive
bishops of Rome began claiming a special role for themselves. Arguing that
after the demise of Rome the Church was the only structure that could claim
universality and the only administration left with an imperial vocation, these
bishops identified themselves as Pontifex Maximus (the high priest in ancient
Rome) as well as popes (from the Greek term pappas, meaning “father”). As
such, they insisted they w ere to lead the Church and be superior to all other
bishops.
Although it took several centuries to complete, the institution and con-
solidation of the papacy led to the desired centralization. So did the calling
of periodic assemblies of bishops. Having begun in the fourth century u nder
the auspices of Roman emperors, by the early M iddle Ages t hese assemblies
became important agents in regulating the relations among the different
Church authorities and communities, as well as in defining the content of
Christian dogma.
The massive accumulation of norms that resulted led to the need for com-
pilation. From the sixth c entury onward, different individuals and organisms
sought to collect canon law and ensure that copies of its main tenets would
be available at least to those in leadership positions. Well known among
these efforts w
ere the collections made during the reign of Charlemagne, the
late eighth-and early ninth-century Frankish ruler. Charlemagne’s aim was
to create authorized versions of important texts and ensure their distribution
throughout his realm. Despite these and other efforts, however, no single
authoritative compilation of Church law came into existence before the
twelfth century.2
The plurality of sources and the absence of a general and authoritative
compilation led to the emergence of a great assortment of canon laws that
were radically distinct. Local churches formed their own collections, which
they followed, often disregarding instructions from Rome. There was so
much uncertainty as to what the common tenets of Christianity w ere, that
even as late as the ninth c entury savvy authors could introduce into the
Christian dogma what today we know w ere forgeries. One famous ex-
ample is the production and dissemination of false papal decrees, including
50 A Short History of European Law
t hose involved in their elaboration must have had access to rich enough li-
braries and sufficient knowledge to obtain such trustworthy results.
existence of a res publica, or a state, the Germanic family of laws did not.
Germanic society was divided into large kin groups led by elders, who were
responsible for rendering judgment on disputes among members as well as
making most other decisions regarding the management of communal life.
In their deliberations, the elders appealed to an unwritten and flexible order
that could be constantly negotiated. Although we have very limited infor-
mation regarding how this transpired, the assumption is that, rather than
being abstract, these legal systems w ere concrete, relational, and strongly in-
fluenced by rituals and formulas. The decisions reached by the assemblies of
elders reflected a constantly mutating normative horizon that was meant to
fit the circumstances of place, time, case, and parties rather than to pursue
an abstract justice or obey an abstract principle.
Regardless of the important question of whether the northern immigrants
did in their origin share a common legal Germanic tradition, it is clear that
by the third and fourth centuries ce their members (who gradually came to
dominate Europe) w ere already greatly affected by both Roman law and
Christianity. Under Roman influence, the newcomers’ legal attitude changed
and their political structures underwent centralization and aristocratization.
There is some evidence, for example, that by the sixth and seventh centuries,
participation in assemblies was mostly restricted to the elites, and military
leaders began claiming the status of hereditary kings. Other areas of the law
might also have undergone dramatic transformations. Gradually the popular,
oral, and flexible elements of legal creation disappeared and, under Roman
influence, leaders of the so-c alled Germanic tribes began promulgating
statutes. In the sixth, seventh, and eighth centuries, law books that sought
to record and reproduce the erstwhile oral normative system also made
their appearance. Mainly written in Latin rather than German, these books
sometimes w ere used as instruments to ensure the survival of what was de-
fined as “the good old order,” but more often than not they confirmed the
degree to which this order had already been altered. The written law that
they included tended to be more systematic and abstract than what we be-
lieve the original law might have been, and it established kings as the main
instruments for authorizing (if not outright creating) the legal order.
These important mutations were already evident in the sixth-century Salic
laws (Pactus Legis Salicae, also known as lex salica) that both collected older
norms and sought to replace vengeance by compositio, that is, a monetary
arrangement. Best known today as the legal basis by which European
54 A Short History of European Law
monarchs excluded from succession t hose who descended of female line, the
Salic laws enumerated a long list of remedies available to injured parties
instead of violence. Written in Latin and organized to some degree as a
Roman edict, the laws were nevertheless interwoven with German terms
and also sought to reproduce Germanic traditions.
Another striking example of the fusion between Roman, canon, and Ger-
manic law was the mid-seventh c entury Liber iudiciorum (also known in
the M iddle Ages as Lex Gothica or Forum Iudicum), which collected laws of
both Germanic and Roman origin and also included royal legislation en-
acted by the Visigoth kings. The Liber, which was greatly influenced by the
writing of theologians and was approved by local bishops in the eighth
Council of Toledo (653), was applied by the Visigoths to their Iberian sub-
jects of both Roman and Germanic origin. Written in Latin and demon-
strating familiarity with Roman concepts, it covered such diverse aspects as
legislation, the administration of justice, family law, obligations, penal law,
and sanctions against Jews and heretics. Designating a territorial rather than
a personal law, its success was so spectacular that it survived the conquest of
Iberia by Muslims in 711 ce. Thereafter it regulated the life of Christians
living under Islamic rule.
Changes in administrative practices were also noticeable. Th ere is ample
evidence, for example, that orality, usually associated with Germanic tradi-
tions, by the eighth century was no longer as central to the medieval legal
order as it had been. By that time, codices appeared across Europe enumer-
ating legal arrangements. Some were conceived as collections of laws, whereas
others sought to reproduce different types of legally useful documents. Most
popular among the latter w ere books containing formularies that scribes
could copy, amend, abridge, or reorganize. During this period, recording
offices (chanceries) w ere also founded, and seals became instruments dem-
onstrating the authenticity of their production. Thereafter, written law and
written records circulated in a legal world that was still profoundly oral but
that was gradually undergoing important transformations.
As a result of all t hese processes, by the tenth c entury it becomes extremely
difficult to distinguish Germanic from Roman law, or Germanic from canon
law. Of course, some legal institutions clearly originated in one system or
the other, but in practice, Latin expressions and Latin and Christian ways
of thinking, interpreting, and organizing the material dominated to such
an extent that a Germanic law was no longer easily recognizable.
An Age with No Jurists? 55
Divine Intervention
ntil the thirteenth century, God’s direct participation in communal assem-
U
blies was considered both possible and desirable. This mostly happened in
difficult cases, in which it was hard to establish what had happened. In such
cases, contemporaries believed that God would intervene by indicating who
told the truth and who lied, who was guilty and who innocent. His ruling
would take the form of a miracle that would save the person who was worthy
of being defended from suffering unnecessary injury. To solicit this inter-
vention, assemblies would subject the parties to an ordeal, that is, to a test.
There were several ways in which this could be done. The defendant could
put his or her hand in boiling w ater, walk on fire, or eat too much bread too
fast. These activities, it was reasoned, would normally result in an injury. If
this did not happen, it was b ecause God wanted to help the defendant. This
was his way of indicating that the person was innocent or was telling the
truth. Thus, t hose who were not harmed during an ordeal w ere held to have
proved their case.
The Church initially encouraged these tests b ecause they gave concrete
proof of the immediateness and mercy of God and helped solve difficult ques-
tions, but by the turn of the millennium it began disapproving them, and
in the thirteenth century (in the Fourth Lateran Council of 1215) it with-
drew its support for them altogether by prohibiting the participation of the
clergy. During this period, ordeals w ere gradually reclassified as both irra-
tional and pagan. Historians have long debated why these changes took
place. Some have suggested the aim was to cleanse the Christian commu-
nity from its pagan past or to ensure that only practices that found backing
in the scriptures would be authorized. It is also possible that the authorities
of the Church were unhappy with “demanding” that God perform a miracle
(to prevent an innocent person from suffering) or with involving clerics,
who w ere present in all ordeals, in decisions regarding the shedding of blood.
Also essential to the gradual abandonment and then prohibition of ordeals
might have been the fact that by the early thirteenth century ius commune
(see Chapter 5) provided society with new professionals, identified as jurists,
who w ere experts on how to manage (and solve) conflicts. To the difficult
problems ordeals sought to solve these professionals offered new solutions
based on the collection, examination, and evaluation of both written and
oral proof. Attempts to centralize criminal justice in the hands of both
56 A Short History of European Law
King of a Frankish empire that covered large parts of present-day France and
Germany, expanded north to the Netherlands and east to the Baltic region,
and that was also in control of Northern Italy and the northern fringes of
what is now Spain, Charlemagne was a secular ruler of Germanic origin who
also oversaw spiritual m atters. Ruling over a loose association of territories,
some more Latinized than others, in the year 800, he was anointed by the
pope as “emperor of the Romans.” For the pope, this move guaranteed Char-
lemagne’s mostly military support and was also a step in freeing the Western
Church from control by the Eastern Roman Empire. For Charlemagne, this
coronation suggested that he was both king and emperor and that he, in
this later capacity, could also intervene in ecclesiastical affairs as Roman
emperors once did.
Although Charlemagne is remembered as a formidable legislator, what
he instructed and what he enacted was not legislation in the sense we give it
today. Like all leaders at that time, Charlemagne had no pretension to create
a new order that would depend only on his will. Instead he sought to ar-
range and systematize existing solutions and ensure obedience to them. A
guarantor of justice rather than the maker of norms, and in charge of peace-
making rather than imposing his personal rule, theoretically his role was to
declare the law by making it manifest and to ensure obedience.
Charlemagne intervened in both religious and secular affairs and in-
structed both religious and civil authorities on how they should proceed.
Fashioning himself as the protector of the Church as well as of the physical
and spiritual well-being of his subjects and all Christians everywhere, he
reformed ecclesiastical institutions and sought to restore clerical discipline,
recover Church properties, and encourage the use of authorized collections
of canon law. Charlemagne also ordered the writing down of local laws and
the Romanization of norms of Germanic origin. Pursuing some measure of
unity in his kingdoms, he promulgated edicts that were designed to introduce
centralization, not necessarily standardization. His quest was to establish
the authority of his court, not to secure uniformity, and his empire indeed
remained a fragmented structure with a great diversity of regimes, norms, and
legal sources.
The actual management of this chaotic amalgamation of local, Roman,
Germanic, and canon law was not always easy. Canon law, for example,
which theoretically was relevant to all Christians, affected not only religious
duties but also such diverse activities as contract making or debt collection.
60 A Short History of European Law
local and canon law. Without the existence of such experts, the ninth-century
legal forgeries of canon law would not have succeeded. A fter all, the indi-
viduals who fabricated them must have been sufficiently familiar with both
Roman and canon law to create these successful imitations.
Expertise was also part of the day-to-day practice of the law. In the ninth
century, glosses and commentaries on different parts of Roman and local
law began appearing in Europe. In Pavia (present-day Italy), the study of law
was so intense that scholars w ere divided among the antiqui, who mostly
centered their attention on Roman law, and the moderni, who also dealt with
Germanic law. Roman and canon law also sustained the work of scribes and
notaries, two professions that came into prominence in Europe during this
period alongside the growing use of written documentation. Scribes and no-
taries were responsible for producing legally efficient documents. They drew
up and recorded a g reat variety of transactions, often by resorting to old for-
mulas they found in textbooks. The early Middle Ages, in short, was per-
haps a world with no jurists, but it was certainly a universe in which many
professionals gave advice, suggested to kings and their subjects how to pro-
ceed, indicated to their community what was right and what was wrong,
and pondered on how God’s laws could be discovered and implemented.
4
all been contested issues for many years. Yet most historians agree that what
ever forms existed in Europe around the year 1000, by the eleventh and
twelfth centuries they had come u nder attack. With new authorities who
identified themselves as kings, the eleventh and twelfth centuries also wit-
nessed the consolidation of the Church. The struggle for both secular and
religious centralization and the growing competition within kingdoms be-
tween kings and lords and within the Church between the pope and other
bishops was further complicated by the tense relations between secular and
religious authorities fighting over who was superior to whom. In what fol-
lows, I survey these developments, ask questions about them, and explain
how and why they were important to European legal history.
lord’s h ousehold as well as take a solemn oath of fidelity, usually on the holy
Scriptures or a relic. The lord then hugged and kissed the vassal and recog-
nized him as “his” man.
Feudal relations initially mostly covered mutual protection, which was
understood as military defense. By the tenth c entury, if not earlier, in many
areas these also began involving property relations. It is hard to establish why
this happened. Perhaps protection was now not only military but also eco-
nomic, including the duty to provide subsistence. Perhaps because of extreme
instability, landholding individuals and communities w ere willing to relin-
quish their control over their properties, which were transferred to a lord in
exchange for protection. Although we are not sure of the nature of these pro
cesses or their precise chronology, their results were fairly clear. In large
parts of Europe, powerful lords appeared who w ere now considered the pro-
prietors of large domains. In most places t hese lords allowed vassals to have
usufruct or tenure rights over the land in exchange for some sort of com-
pensation, either tribute, military service, or labor. Part of the payment vas-
sals made was also symbolic and included recognition of subjection and an
oath of allegiance.
As economic concerns became central to this system, lords began ensuring
that their vassals had the financial resources they deserved according to who
they were. This was typically done by giving them use of the land, but it
could also be achieved by granting them an office or another type of income.
Eventually the duties of lords also extended to judicial protection, and lords
began holding sessions in which they acted as judges, applying what was
said to be the customary law of the land. This allowed lords to acquire many
of the functions we identify today with government. They policed their
territories, adjudicated conflicts, and dispensed punishment. They collected
taxes and applied, if not outright created, the norms that governed the com-
munity. In many places these developments marked the end of the kind of
communal justice that was practiced by local assemblies and juries in the
early Middle Ages. In other places communal justice persisted, though rad-
ically modified because now controlled by the lord and his men.
Although according to the classical formulation feudalism was based on
an agreement between parties to constitute a personal relationship, it was
nevertheless clear that even if originally some choice was allowed, most vas-
sals did not enter into this relationship by exercising f ree w ill. By the tenth
century, furthermore, feudalism had lost most of its initial purpose as a
Lords, Emperors, and Popes around the Year 1000 65
A Feudal Society?
As a result of these developments, according to the traditional portrait, by
the year 1000 most Europeans lived on rural estates where they were tied as
vassals to a lord who exercised jurisdiction over them. In most places, the
lord accumulated what today would be classified as legislative, executive, and
judiciary powers. He made the rules, he applied them, and he adjudicated
conflicts. In his decision making, he might have been guided by the existing
local law—that was usually the pretension—and he was certainly supposed
to care about canon law, but it was his word and his interpretation that car-
ried the day.
Feudalism, however, was not a s imple two-tier system. Instead, it was
imagined as a multilayered one in which (minor) lords could be vassals of
(greater) lords. The hierarchical structure that resulted allowed a mega-
lord—for example, the German emperor—to be the master of several lords
who, in turn, had vassals of their own. Because the lords’ vassals were not
the emperor’s vassals, the emperor could not directly request their collabo-
ration. Instead he had to address them through their immediate lords. This
pyramid of command guaranteed the loyalty of important lords and the sub-
mission of their vassals, but it also imposed restrictions on the emperor.
Not being able to directly command the vassals of his vassals implied that
when the emperor wanted them to do or refrain from doing something, he
had to depend on the mediation of the lords, who could ask for concessions
in return.
This situation, which was necessary in the ninth c entury when feudalism
probably emerged, became unsustainable after some lords—now identified
as monarchs—began to expand their jurisdiction. Beginning in the eleventh
and twelfth centuries, they sought to diminish the power of their peers or
control them by summoning them to the courts and converting them into
66 A Short History of European Law
their servants. Through these mechanisms, lords not only became members
of royal h ouseholds, they also lost their power base in the countryside where
their vassals resided, from which they w ere mostly absent.
To further facilitate the submission of all those inhabiting their kingdoms,
kings also encouraged the growth of cities. Recognizing t hese cities as “free”
because not u nder obedience to a feudal lord, kings placed them and their
inhabitants under the king’s direct authority. Although this policy was
successful, and cities grew in number and size all over Europe, in the long
run the most efficient tactic kings used to consolidate their powers was to
institute themselves as supreme adjudicators. They claimed a role as arbiters
between lords and established royal courts throughout the realm. This method,
which most monarchs attempted to implement, first succeeded in England
and resulted in what we now identify as the Eng lish common law (see
Chapter 6).
Questioning Feudalism
For many years, the above description was the standard textbook narrative
regarding the nature and history of feudalism. Beginning in the 1990s, how-
ever, some historians began asking w hether there was one type of feudalism
or several, and w hether feudalism as classically defined had existed at all.
They questioned the term used to describe t hese developments (“feudalism”)
but they also disagreed over whether an institution that fit this description
ever materialized in real life. They suggested that it was only a model that
rarely (if ever) was put into place. Or they maintained that the large variety
of situations and practices they uncovered in the archives could never be re-
duced to a system with clear principles. In short, they saw “feudalism” as a
theoretical abstraction that obscured rather than enhanced our under-
standing of the past.
Scholars also insisted that despite the pervasive presence of lords and
vassals in many parts of Europe, not all contemporaries lived u nder a
feudal regime. Some territories were more “feudalized” than others, and
even where classic feudalism might have been the dominant form of eco-
nomic, social, political, and legal order, there also existed free peasants and
urban dwellers, their numbers varying by region and period. Feudalism,
these scholars sustained, had captured our imagination far more than it
ever deserved.
Lords, Emperors, and Popes around the Year 1000 67
recited in churches. Through the merits of Peter, he was holy. The Dictatus
Papae also asserted that one could not be a believer without being in har-
mony with the Church.
The Later M
iddle Ages
5
The Method
Satisfied with the text they had reconstructed, scholars began studying it.
The methodology they employed was innovative. Identified as Scholasticism,
it was based on the assumption (taken as a certainty) that Roman texts were
imbued with a hidden harmony. The obligation of readers was to prove that
such was the case by offering an interpretation that synchronized the dif
ferent parts and enabled the reconstruction of a coherent message.
Most scholars following the Scholastic method began with a philological
analysis of the texts, their terminology, order, and phrasing. Shaping their
observations as a dialogue, they asked questions and debated the answers.
This dialectical thinking and exposition was mainly geared toward com-
paring passages to one another. Working under the assumption that the
various parts w ere not contradictory, scholars employed logical arguments
in order to demonstrate that such was the case. One of their favorite tech-
niques was the distinctio. Analyzing two fragments that seemed similar yet
pointed to different solutions, these scholars proceeded to demonstrate that
although the fragments appeared identical, they w ere in fact profoundly dis-
tinct. B ecause they w ere different, the solutions offered could be diverse
without t here being a contradiction. Hence, what appeared at first glance as
a contradiction was instead part of a coherent system in which all the dif
ferent pieces pointed to the same rationale.
By following this method, scholars hoped to reveal the criteria that guided
Roman jurists and the techniques that organized their reasoning. Their aim
was not to uncover the particular solutions Roman jurists adopted but in-
stead to extract the rule (regula) that explained their consistency. By putting
together what they learned from individual examples and cases, these scholars
hoped to understand what they considered to be the inner core, the basic
essence, of Roman law.
The adoption of the Scholastic method converted the Digest, which was
unknown and hardly used in Europe up to this point, into a particularly
attractive source of Roman law. Reproducing the opinions of different ju-
rists, the Digest included an exceptional number of disagreements and con-
tradictions. It therefore was an excellent source allowing scholars to make
distinctions and elaborate terminology, concepts, and criteria.
Because Scholastic analysis used textual exegesis that paid close attention
to the specific terms Roman texts employed, their order, and their meaning,
The Birth of a European Ius Commune 79
it was essential for scholars to ascertain that the documents they examined
were accurate. If they w ere not, then their discussion of them would be based
on false evidence and would not lead to the ultimate truth. Thus, as the dis-
covery and reconstruction of ancient texts led to their study, their study led
to additional effort to ensure the accuracy of the texts. Textual reconstruc-
tion and textual exegesis, in short, mutually supported one another.
From the twelfth to the sixteenth c entury (considered the formative pe-
riod of this new European legal science), scholars (now identified as jurists)
debated the principles, terminology, and structures of Roman law. Though
they were trying to explain ancient texts, their endeavor did not revive the
ancient law of Rome, but instead reinvented it. Medieval jurists came up with
new ways to assess, analyze, and relate to legal questions. Their interpreta-
tions were perhaps anchored in a prestigious Roman past, but, in reality, and
as would be forcefully argued in the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries (see
Chapter 7), they w ere entirely new.
The Environment
The individuals engaged in these debates mainly taught or studied in the
various study centers and universities that appeared in Europe in the late
medieval period. W hether universities formed part of a longer tradition or
were a completely new phenomenon is a m atter of debate. In late antiquity,
there w ere schools in which instruction was given to students, usually in
order to prepare them for a particular professional task. Th ese schools
taught grammar, dialectics (the art of reasoning), rhetoric (the art of expo-
sition), arithmetic (the study of numbers), geometry (the study of figures),
astronomy, and music. From as early as the first c entury ce if not ear-
lier, Rome also featured schools where students of law congregated. These
began as informal gatherings, but by the early fifth c entury they w ere
sufficiently institutionalized that emperors could limit the study of law
exclusively to them.
In the sixth c entury, monastic schools began appearing all over Europe.
First emerging spontaneously and then encouraged by popes and emperors,
these schools taught poetry, astronomy, and mathematics but w ere mostly
focused on understanding the Scriptures. In some places, rhetoric and Roman
law might have been studied, too. By the late eighth and ninth centuries,
monastic schools were joined by episcopal or cathedral schools, which
80 A Short History of European Law
covered similar subjects but were mostly located in the large urban centers
that began appearing throughout Europe.
Twelfth-and thirteenth-century study centers and universities w ere there-
fore both old and new. Appearing in several European cities where demo-
graphic growth, economic prosperity, and urban revival were particularly
strong, they drew crowds that came to listen to masters lecture. The congre-
gation of a large number of masters in certain locations, as well as urban
regulations favoring it, brought several of these new learning sites into prom-
inence. Paris, Bologna, Toulouse, and Oxford became famous among stu-
dents and teachers b ecause of the excellence of teaching but also b ecause of
the scope of what was being taught. Designated as studium generale—places
where it was possible to study (almost) everything, including theology, med-
icine, and law—these centers w ere transformed into “universities” after
they were legally recognized as corporations.
One of the most important characteristics of the new learning centers
was that they w ere truly pan-European. Teachers and students came from
all over Europe and they circulated from one university to the next. The
teaching language was Latin, and most of the universities employed a similar
curriculum and method. Popes and emperors, who fashioned themselves as
global figures, typically encouraged the founding of these centers, although
their enthusiasm sometimes met with opposition from local authorities,
who resented the arrival of many foreign teachers and students who w ere
habitually poor, unfamiliar, and—in the eyes of many—not particularly
productive. The new learning centers w ere also criticized occasionally
by local bishops who previously had controlled all education in their dio-
ceses and gave licenses to teach. Despite this (often fierce) opposition,
universities prospered. By the mid-fifteenth century, some sixty cities in
present-day Italy, France, Spain, Portugal, E ngland, Scotland, the Czech
Republic, Austria, Germany, Belgium, Croatia, Hungary, and Poland had
a university.
Universities were greenhouses for the creation of a group of scholars who
shared not only a way of life and a profession but also ideas and ways of
thinking. They produced the “intellectual,” a new sociological figure whose
main occupation was to study or teach. With the birth of states and with
growing municipal powers, many intellectuals would come to occupy impor
tant public offices. Thereafter, studying at the university would open new
c areer opportunities to individuals who could afford to invest time and
The Birth of a European Ius Commune 81
but instead a purposeful choice. It was meant to explain to law students that
even if the goal of dispensing justice was not reached, the intention to do
so was sufficient to qualify the action as just. By adopting this explanation,
Rogerius established the importance of “intent” in legal interactions. He
suggested that what you did and what resulted from your action was impor
tant, but no less essential was the state of mind (intention) that accompanied
your act.
Next Rogerius observed that, according to the Institutes, justice contained
three central mandates: to live justly, not to injure others, and to render to
each his own (ensure that each person received the treatment he or she de-
served). Asking why t here w ere three rather than one single mandate and
how each differed, Rogerius concluded that the first precept (“to live justly”)
referred to crimes against oneself (sins). The second and third precepts
(“not to injure another” and “render to each his own”) dealt, on the contrary,
with crimes against other p eople. He explained that b ecause crimes against
other individuals were more frequent and more severe, they w ere prohib-
ited twice. Yet their doubling did not diminish the fact that in reality t here
were two ways in which one could hurt other p eople. “Not to injure an-
other” (the first of the two precepts) pointed to “commission” whereby
to “render each one his due” (the second of the two precepts) pointed to
“omission.”
By studying only a few sentences of the Institutes and by observing rep-
etitions as well as the choice of words, Rogerius thus justified some of the
most basic categories we still employ today. He demonstrated the importance
of intent, and he clarified the distinction between performing a wrongful
act and failing to do the right t hing (commission and omission). None of t hese
observations was truly necessary in order to understand the Roman text, yet
the analysis of this text gave Rogerius an opportunity to imagine a new way
to categorize legal phenomena.
Starting in the late twelfth c entury, some scholars began collecting legal
questions and publishing them. These documents, reflecting intellectual
engagement with actual practice rather than with theory, usually centered
on real or hypothetical cases that jurists had to solve and presented points for
consideration and discussion. Also common w ere collections of glosses in
large bodies known as apparatus, some of which contained as many as
100,000 fragments. Other types of publications were the summae, which dis-
cussed the contents of an entire book such as the Institutes (the student
The Birth of a European Ius Commune 83
Canon Law
Scholars have long debated whether discussions in universities began by
studying Roman texts or canon law texts or whether both things coincided.
Questions of chronology aside, it is clear that the same methodology (Scho-
lasticism) and the same concerns expressed with regard to Roman law were
also applied to the study of canon law. H ere too, the first task scholars faced
was the reconstruction of the corpus of that law, which was dispersed in a
variety of sources and collections, some more global and authoritative than
others (see Chapter 3).
In the twelfth c entury, a successful compilation was proposed by Gra-
tian. Gratian (who may have also used the work of previous scholars) col-
lected, examined, selected, and systematized the different sources of canon
law (the Bible, legislation and decisions of Church councils, papal decisions,
and the writings of the Church f athers and early saints).6 Arranging this ma-
terial logically in three parts, he enumerated the sources, described Church
hierarchy, and listed the rules regulating the hierarchy’s activities. Also in-
cluded were instructions regarding judicial procedure, Church property, the
religious orders, marriage, sins, repentance, and penance. Matters of doc-
trine and matters of law were intermingled throughout the work, but the
latter predominated.
This compilation (Concordia Discordantium Canonum, literally the har-
mony of discordant canons, later known as the Decretum) was unofficial.
The Birth of a European Ius Commune 85
Feudal Law
Alongside Roman and canon law, scholars also turned their attention to
feudal institutions. Starting in the twelfth century they suggested that a
“feudal law” had existed in Europe as early as the eighth century. This law
governed relations between lords and their vassals as well as between the
86 A Short History of European Law
various lords. It identified lords and their duties and defined how individ-
uals became vassals and what they owed to their masters. Feudal law also
dealt with the jurisdiction of lords over their vassals, feudal courts, and con-
flicting claims of various lords over the same individuals or lands. It focused
on issues typical to feudalism such as access to and use of land, as well as
inheritance.
The genealogy of how this field of inquiry came into being is quite sim-
ilar to what we know of Roman and canon law, and it is probable that it
emerged contemporaneously. Already in the eleventh century, some scholars
had begun discussing feudal law, yet juridical interest in that law began
in earnest only with the publication in the mid-t welfth c entury of an au-
thoritative text, the Libri Feudorum. This text, compiled in present-day
Italy, collected decisions from so-called feudal courts, as well as feudal cus-
toms, legislation, and juridical writing. By the thirteenth century the litera
ture on feudalism had expanded so dramatically that there w ere now experts
(feudists) dedicated to writing commentaries on these laws.
The erudite literature on feudalism introduced the study of feudal law to
universities. The result was the gradual Romanization of feudal law, which
was discussed, analyzed, and understood by using Roman terminology, cat-
egories, and ways of reasoning. The fusion between the two fields was so
complete that, in practice, they merged. One indication of this was that by
the thirteenth c entury, for example, several scholars appended parts of the
Libri Feudorum to their copies of the Corpus Iuris Civilis and glossed them
together. Another was the influence of Roman law on discussions regarding
feudal law—for example, allowing feudal jurists to apply the Roman idea of
dominum to explain the relations between lords and vassals. They suggested
that lords had dominium directum of the land (allowing them to direct what
would happen on it, collect dues, and exercise authority) and vassals had do-
minium utile (giving them the right to use the land).
Why twelfth-century scholars cared about feudalism sufficiently to turn
their attention to it is one of the least studied questions. As described in
Chapter 4, by the time scholars began thinking about feudalism, it was al-
ready declining everywhere. Remnants of what it had been persisted in dif
ferent parts of Europe in various intensities, but the powers of lords, as well
as the number of unfree individuals, gradually diminished as monarchies,
the economy, and cities grew. Historians who argue that our vision of feu-
The Birth of a European Ius Commune 87
Ius Commune
The study of Roman, canon, and feudal law in medieval study centers and
universities by scholars who reconstructed texts and then applied the new
Scholastic method to them revolutionized European normativity. It created
innovative ways to think about, analyze, and discuss the legal order. Scholars
of course continued to disagree with one another, but they did so using
common terminologies, concepts, arguments, and techniques.
The complex system of knowledge, organization, and interpretation that
resulted included solutions to particular legal problems, such as who had the
right to use land or who was a citizen of which community. But above all it
proposed a new vision according to which, despite wide variations in the con-
crete answers proposed in different parts of Europe, juridical thought was
not particular to a place, a society, or a time. Instead, it was based on reason.
This implied that the new juridical method could have a universal vocation
and embody, as it came to be known, a ius commune—a law potentially
common to all. Thereafter, following the guidance of ius commune became
identified as rectum or directum; that is, the right way of doing t hings.9
Comprising centuries of juridical opinions, this new legal constellation,
now referred to as ius commune, was clearly different from classical Roman
law, that is, from the law that regulated life in ancient (both republican and
imperial) Rome. Said to be inspired by that ancient law, it was nevertheless
88 A Short History of European Law
entirely new in scope, method, intention, and solutions. It did share with
Rome, however, the idea that jurists were at the forefront of juridical creation
and that jurisprudence, the science of law, was the most important normative
source.
sustained, w
ere inconsequential b ecause all conditions w
ere directed to the
same end. They all sought to establish the same thing, namely, that the
person requiring naturalization had changed his nature and was no longer
a genuine foreigner.
Historians have thus concluded that, rather than understanding ancient
Roman law, what medieval jurists did was to develop methods with which
to synchronize and integrate the various legal regimes that coexisted in Eu
rope and the many sources from which they had emerged. Their main task
was not to interpret ancient documents but to make Roman, Germanic,
local, feudal, and canon law as they w ere practiced in different parts of the
Continent cohere together into a common system, a ius commune.
The Results
The new techniques created by jurists did not remain an abstraction, nor
did they penetrate only the highest echelons of society. Instead they perco-
lated into and affected everyday life even in remote villages. In the late M iddle
Ages, ordinary peasants in tiny hamlets along the Spanish-Portuguese border
often fought over their right to use the land. Although their description of
why the land was theirs did not employ the correct terminology (possession),
it nevertheless faithfully reproduced juridical doctrine regarding land rights.
It suggested, for example, that entitlement depended on having utilized the
territory for an extended period of time without encountering opposition. It
also pointed out that the silence of rivals could be understood as consent.
This conclusion, which referenced a juridical presumption (under ordinary
circumstances, silence equaled consent) was also accompanied by the un-
derstanding that a violent response against invading neighbors did the con-
trary, that is, it manifested disagreement.
The illiterate peasants who engaged in t hese debates had not studied law,
nor were their vindications prepared by lawyers. However, what they said
and did was surprisingly identical to what ius commune jurists argued. It was
based on abstractions offered by t hese jurists after they studied a g reat variety
of customs and ways of doing.
How peasants came into this knowledge is hard to ascertain. They them-
selves gave no clear answer. When asked why they believed certain rules ap-
plied, they clarified that the norms they invoked w ere natural, that they
were universal and that, as a result, they needed no proof or explanation.
92 A Short History of European Law
Apparently, by that stage, the conclusions of ius commune were indeed seen as
so logical and reasonable and were so widely accepted that contemporaries
assumed that they were common to all humanity, they w ere immutable, and
they w ere true.
The study of law that began in the twelfth c entury thus revolutionized
European normativity. Having no formal means to impose itself, it spread
across borders and through institutions with or without authorities’ approval.
Carried from place to place by jurists who w ere convinced of its superi-
ority, it allowed them to rethink the existing normative order, refashioning
it anew. By the end of this process, there was no place that ius commune did
not touch, no field it did not affect.
6
England formed part of the Roman Empire until the fifth century,
and Roman and Romanized citizens as well as indigenous Celts and converts
to Christianity formed part of its community. Roman law was introduced
to the island and affected in diverse intensities both Roman citizens and
Romanized natives. What happened next is a m atter of debate. According
to most scholars, with the withdrawal of Roman troops, Roman law as well
as Christianity virtually ceased to exist in E ngland. According to o thers,
pockets of both persisted, most particularly among native Celts and in the
western regions.
But regardless of what happened in the fifth c entury, most historians agree
that in the late sixth c entury Roman and canon law w ere reintroduced to
the island by Christian missionaries. Equally present was some version of
Germanic law, carried to England by successive Germanic groups that in-
vaded its territory. As a result of these developments, from the seventh to
the eleventh century the legal situation in England was not dramatically dif
ferent from that in other parts of Europe where native, Germanic (including
Danish), canon, and Roman law all coexisted to some degree or the other.
Evidence from this period illustrates this complexity. In the seventh
century, for example, Roman law was taught at a school in Canterbury.
During the same period, Anglo-Saxon remedies for various offenses were
written down.1 The aim was to replace blood feuds with monetary payment,
a move indicating, according to some scholars, the growing influence of
Christianity and perhaps Roman law (the debate still lingers). In the sixth,
93
94 A Short History of European Law
however, they wished to limit the powers of t hese lords, obtain direct access
to their vassals, and acquire full mastery of the land. To achieve this goal,
they devised ways allowing them to relinquish gradually the mediation of
lords. The method they chose was to extend their jurisdiction throughout
the realm. Beginning with Henry I (r. 1100–1135) and substantially intensi-
fying with his grandson Henry II (r. 1154–1189), Norman monarchs began
instituting a system of royal courts, which were to be superimposed on all
previously existing jurisdictions.
How they accomplished this task was beautifully described at the very
end of the nineteenth century. Although many historians now contest this
narrative, believing it a legend, it is nevertheless a story that deserves telling.
According to it, initially Norman kings demanded the right to intervene in
disputes and guarantee their peaceful resolution only when they were phys-
ically next to the litigating parties. This usually meant that their jurisdic-
tion was limited to individuals who w ere in attendance at their court. In a
subsequent stage Norman kings began appropriating the power to ensure
peace on special days such as their coronation or the weeks of Christmas,
Easter, and Pentecost. Eventually they moved from protecting dates to
protecting territories. They first defined the jurisdiction of their court in a
comprehensive way that covered a perimeter of up to three miles from
where they were physically located and then applied special protections to
the main roads and waterways of the kingdom u nder the excuse that they
led to the court. Gradually the network of roads and waterways under royal
jurisdiction was broadened to include almost all roads and waterways. By
the close of the thirteenth century, lawyers at the service of the monarchs
developed a legal fiction according to which the king was present every-
where in the kingdom. Thereafter, the protection of the monarch, which
was once limited to his household, included the entire realm and “the
king’s peace had fully grown from an occasional privilege into a common
right.” 6
The imposition of royal jurisdiction throughout the realm, which was first
temporal (protecting certain dates) and then geographic (protecting certain
places), was also carried out by assigning certain matters to royal hands. Here,
too, the process was gradual. Norman kings justified their growing inter-
vention by indicating that certain issues w ere of particular interest to them
and w ere thus worthy of their attention. Among such issues w ere disputes
over the exercise of royal franchise or the protection of particular persons.
The Birth of an English Common Law 97
remedy at his lord’s court, he could take the issue to the king. If the king (or
his officers) thought the matter deserved their attention, they could issue a
writ that instructed the addressee, a man of royal confidence, to make sure
that the lord would not proceed to oust the tenant. Writs could instruct lords
how to h andle the conflict or they could order them to listen to the parties
and adjudicate their claims.
Writs included an executive peremptory instruction meant to guarantee
peace. They were considered an efficient tool allowing the king, who was
charged with overseeing the welfare of the kingdom, to intervene in selected
cases. Yet although they supplied an efficient and immediate solution to
problems that needed redress, they w ere easily abused. Issued ex parte at the
request of the interested party, their grant assumed that the petition was
justified. Nonetheless, b ecause those requesting royal intervention some-
times misrepresented what had transpired, in the twelfth c entury a further
development took place. Writs began allowing alleged wrongdoers to choose
between complying with the order or appearing before a royal delegate in
order to explain why he or she should not.
This development, which allowed wrongdoers to defend themselves, was
revolutionary. It transformed writs from administrative documents into
orders to initiate litigation. Writs now sent the parties to royal officials who
heard their cases and decided whether the remedy included in the writ should
be granted or not. The need to appear before royal officials, justifying why
the writ should be applied or denying that it should, gave rise in the thir-
teenth century to a procedure known as “pleading.” Armed with a writ, a
plaintiff would present himself or herself before a royal official in order to
narrate the facts that justified the concession of a remedy. The defendant
would respond by denying some or all the facts, by admitting the facts but
giving them another interpretation, by denying the relevance of the writ, or
by introducing additional factors (excuses) that explained why, notwith-
standing, a remedy should not be given. The plaintiff would then respond
by invoking a similar set of preestablished answers.
This exchange between the parties was extremely formal. Rather than de-
scribing the facts of the case, it consisted of a set of pre-ascribed positions
and responses that the plaintiff and the defendant could invoke. The ex-
change continued until it became clear what was agreed between the par-
ties, and what was contested. It was only a fter this clarity was achieved that
the case went to “trial.” Contrary to pleading (that concentrated on claim
The Birth of an English Common Law 99
making), during the “trial” the parties had to prove the facts upon which
their claims were based. Proof could be established in a variety of ways de-
pending on time, issue, and place. The parties could take an oath, be sub-
jected to an ordeal, or a jury could be called upon. A fter the facts of the
matter w
ere proven (or not), the adjudicating official (now properly func-
tioning as a judge) determined whether the remedy included in the writ
should be granted (or not).
rather than abstract and theoretical, writs existed b ecause there was a con-
flict that required resolution, a party who chose to bring it to a royal court,
and a chancery that, representing the king, decided to intervene. Writs thus
proliferated in areas in which individuals sought royal protection and the
king was willing to give it. This meant that the creation of writs was driven
by private interests rather than by considerations of public good, and it was
shaped by the economic, political, and social circumstances of the time.
important was the fact that judgment rendered by these courts was recorded
in rolls, which were safely stored in the Tower of London and could, in
theory, be found when needed. It is also possible that royal courts were re-
garded as instances in which, contrary to what transpired in other courts,
an impersonal, rule-bound process of dispute resolution took place.
The system of conflict resolution that emerged as a result of all these de-
velopments was gradually identified as “common law.” This system was
“common” b ecause it was superimposed onto local, municipal, and feudal
jurisdictions, it potentially encompassed the entire realm, and it was open
to all t hose under allegiance to the king.10 The commonness that it referenced
was politic al. This stood in clear opposition to ius commune, which, com-
bining Roman, canon, and feudal law, was identified as “common” because
it was theoretically shared by all the inhabitants of Latin Christendom.
These inhabitants w ere perhaps divided into a multiplicity of diverse,
even rival, polities, yet they adhered, so it was alleged, to a single culture,
a single religion, and a single (common) law.
inherited a fter the death of his kinsmen) or the right not to be charged
with a crime u nless there was an official indictment or presentment (es-
tablished by the assize of Clarendon, 1166). The linking of remedies to
rights became more pronounced as time passed. By the early modern pe-
riod it occupied such a central place that many began arguing that common
law was nothing other than a system of rights, which they identified as the
rights of Englishmen (see Chapter 8). During this period, old writs such as
habeas corpus (“have the body”) regained particular prominence. It was now
suggested that this writ, which ordered authorities to present the judge with
the body of the person in custody, constituted a remedy against unlawful
imprisonment. It was further argued that, by supplying this remedy, habeas
corpus indirectly recognized the right not to be imprisoned without cause.
Eventually the idea that remedies created rights would be so important
that it could lead to decisions that otherwise could be considered peculiar.
This happened, for example, in 1704 when the House of Lords, sitting as an
appeal instance, reversed a decision by the Queen’s Bench denying recourse
to an individual deprived of the right to vote in parliamentary elections. The
denial was based on the commonsense observation that the individual re-
quired no remedy b ecause his preferred candidate won the election even
without his vote. The House of Lords disagreed b ecause “if the plaintiff has
a right, he must of necessity have a means to vindicate and maintain it and a
remedy if he is injured.” It was a vain t hing, the lords argued, “to imagine
a right without a remedy, for want of right and want of remedy are recip-
rocal.”11 The lords’ conclusion was straightforward: though the inability to
vote made no difference because the candidate preferred by the plaintiff won
the election anyway, the petitioner must receive a remedy because, under
common law, the lack of remedy implied the lack of right. Thus, if the court
did not grant the petitioner a remedy, it would be as if it did not recognize
his right to vote.
attentive to procedural issues. It did not ask what the proper result should
be but whether the right procedure would be followed.
Pleading—how the parties translated their agreements and disagreements
into legal formulas that could be used at the court—was often considered
the most important issue. This translation began when the plaintiff chose to
invoke a specific writ, the defendant responded to it, and the plaintiff re-
plied. Because pleading was crucial to defining the issues at stake, experts
of common law insisted that it was essential to verify that it was done cor-
rectly. In the late M iddle Ages this became the main task of royal justices
who presided over these exchanges and ensured that the parties followed an
acceptable script. Because by that stage knowing which writs existed and how
to employ (and answer) them became a sophisticated pursuit, most legal lit
erature was dedicated to describing the complex ceremonies and formulaic
exchanges that ruled over the working of royal courts and advised practi
tioners on how to channel cases through them. The preparation of lawyers
followed this route, mostly centering on teaching candidates the art of
pleading and procedure. Yearbooks that reported on what happened in courts
did the same. Rather than describe rules and principles or narrate the deci-
sions reached by the judges, they reproduced the dialogues between the par-
ties and the judge, which led to the adoption of a commonly acceptable
question. The issue for them was how cases were actually formulated and
argued (that is, h
ow the facts of the conflict were transformed into legal argu-
ments), identifying what good claims w ere and how they could be presented.
Procedural rules were at the center of how the common-law courts op-
erated, but they w ere also important for safekeeping the prestige of royal
justice. For the royal system to operate well and compete successfully with
local, feudal, or ecclesiastical courts, it was essential to guarantee its repu-
tation. This could be done by, among other t hings, ensuring litigants that
a certain procedure would be followed without making exceptions b ecause
of the identity of the parties or the nature of the case. Among the instru-
ments devised to do so were the many rules we now identify as embodying
“due process.” These rules w ere designed to make sure that judges would be
impartial umpires whose main task would be to give the same opportunities
(that is, procedural rules) to both sides, allowing them to plead their cases
as if on equal grounds.
Because the task of common-law judges was mainly to oversee the ex-
changes between litigants at the court, not to verify the making of justice,
104 A Short History of European Law
common law left almost no room for appeals. “Writs of error” allowed a su-
perior court to review and correct the proceedings of lower courts, but these
were mostly restricted to procedural errors that w ere evident in the record
and did not extend to challenging, for example, the factual or legal basis for
the decision. In exceptional cases, rather than allowing to appeal, common-
law courts allowed revisiting a case by ordering a new trial.
It is therefore not surprising that even as late as the fifteenth century,
common law judges often refused to depart from the traditional system of
rules in order to ensure material justice. The contrast with the rest of Eu
rope could not be greater. Continental judges were charged with doing
justice. How they arrived at a just decision was not particularly consequen-
tial. Although litigants in most countries had to follow a certain procedure
in order for their cases to prosper, for much of the medieval and early modern
period, this procedure was based on the “practice of the court.” Rather
than prescribing a strict formula, it could be abbreviated if the judge con-
sidered it beneficial, or prolonged, if justice so required. Suspects of crim-
inal offenses, for example, had a right to trial, that is, the right not to be
sentenced without a court reviewing their case, but judges had a huge dis-
cretion as to what would actually happen once the case was brought to their
attention.12 U ntil the sixteenth and even the seventeenth century, Conti-
nental judges could render decisions “following their conscience” rather
than the law. As a result, while common law mostly admitted appeals on
procedural issues, European courts did not. There, appeals were always
based on the allegation that the decision was unjust, the question whether
a specific procedure had been followed or not being considered almost
irrelevant.
coherence and authority, the manual was composed in Latin rather than in
French (the language of the court), probably to bring it to European-wide
scholarly attention and have it taught in schools and universities.
Henry of Bracton (Bratton) had a similar profile. The alleged author of
De legibus et consuetudinibus Angliae (ca. 1220s–1250s), a work most scholars
now attribute to several authors rather than to a single individual, and not
necessarily to Bracton, he too was a royal official who was university trained.
Although his participation in the writing of De legibus is currently ques-
tioned, it is nevertheless clear that whoever authored this text was extremely
familiar with Roman law. De legibus collected the norms of common law
while constantly referencing Roman law in ways that echoed contemporary
discussions in universities. Among other t hings, it appealed to ius commune
categories and to Scholastics in order to lend coherence to the Eng lish
records. This was done by drawing similarities and distinctions between
different texts in order to demonstrate that they did not contradict each
other. De legibus also emulated the order and divisions employed in the
Justinian Corpus Iuris Civilis, and it cited numerous passages of it as well as
canon law texts.
It is now believed that t hese two cases, particularly notorious, were not
unique and that in the twelfth and thirteenth centuries common-law experts
looked to and often adopted Roman law solutions much more frequently
than we have imagined in the past. It is also clear, though, that beginning
in the fourteenth century, successive English monarchs began appointing
to the bench laymen with no university training. Instead of preferring ju-
rists, as has been the case before, the main qualification of royal judges was
now that they were obedient servants. Because by that time great practical
knowledge was required to discern, for example, which writ was appropriate
to which case and how it functioned, eventually most royal judges were se-
lected from among the advocates working at the king’s court.
By the fourteenth c entury not only royal judges needed a particular set
of skills, mostly acquired by working at the courts; so did the parties who
had to identify the correct writ, understand which procedural and eviden-
tiary rules were associated with it, and know how to plead affectively. Adju-
dication in royal courts also required knowledge of French and Latin, as
French remained the spoken language of the English royal courts, and Latin
(alternating on occasion with French) its written language, u ntil well into
the early modern period.
106 A Short History of European Law
The need for growing expertise led to the emergence of legal specialists.
ese included a variety of professionals such as procurators (who could stand
Th
for an absent party), barristers (who specialized in the a ctual pleading in the
courts), and attorneys (who counseled clients). Barristers eventually orga
nized themselves into guilds and began frequenting certain places. These
places, identified as “the Inns,” mostly began as residence halls but soon
emerged also as spaces for socialization and training, where young appren-
tices heard and observed masters perform different tasks. Th ere w ere four
“Inns at Court” where barristers trained, and an Inn of Chancery, where as-
piring attorneys watched how writs and other documents w ere drawn up.
By the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries, most Inns also offered apprentices
sessions of mock trials focusing on the process of obtaining evidence and
following procedures, lessons in argumentation of the law (“moots”), and lec-
tures (“readings”). Lectures required students to analyze written texts, mostly
statutes. Th
ese texts w ere often accompanied by factual cases, which were
meant to exemplify their meaning and extension. Moots w ere centered on
watching courts in action and conducting exercises mainly focused on pro-
cedure, the selection of writs, and pleading.
the judges stated, was owed to a physical person (James), not to a crown or
a kingdom (the English crown or E ngland). As a result, those born under
allegiance to James in one kingdom were subject to his royal jurisdiction ev-
erywhere. Thus, a Scot born in Scotland u nder allegiance to James could be
considered an English subject in England as long as James also reigned t here.
Today we know that Calvin’s case was a fabricated lawsuit. It was spon-
sored by a group of individuals who wanted to force a decision regarding
the status of Scots. This question had preoccupied James after he ascended
to the English throne. He appointed a commission that concluded that Scots
should be treated as English subjects, and he insisted that such was legally
the case. Yet the English Parliament refused to accept this solution. Because
under common-law remedies created rights, the only way to unblock the sit-
uation was to bring a case in which, by giving a remedy, the judges would
recognize a right, namely, the right of Scots to be treated as English subjects
in England. For this to happen, t hose interested in obtaining this recogni-
tion had to find a person who was in need of remedy.
The person they found was a young child born in Scotland a fter the u nion.
This child had inherited properties in England but his right to them was
denied b ecause, according to common law, foreigners could not inherit land
in E ngland. This child, who claimed to be a Scot in Scotland yet an English
subject in E ngland, thus had a reason to bring an action against t hose who
refused him his rightful inheritance. For the court to grant him the requested
remedy, it would have to recognize him as an English subject. This was
precisely what happened. The court gave Calvin a remedy allowing him to
inherit in England, thereby recognizing him as an English subject. There-
after, Scots born after the union would be identified as such without the
need for Parliament to acquiesce to that result.
This example makes it clear that even as late as 1608 basic questions such
as who was an Eng lish subject and who a foreigner could be resolved in
England not by a royal decree or a parliamentary act, but by appealing to the
courts and requesting a remedy. But Calvin’s case was also exemplary in other
ways. The judges reviewing it tied the right to inherit in E ngland to the status
of English subject. According to them, only English subjects could inherit
land in England; foreigners could not. But this rule too had developed because
of the particular characteristics of common law: its unique insistence on the
relations between remedy and right as well as on procedural requirements
that were often tied to the specific writ that was employed.
108 A Short History of European Law
Today we know that the distinction between those who could and could
not inherit land in England probably had nothing to do with foreignness
and that, initially, birth outside the kingdom did not make p eople alien. A
question therefore arises: Why and how did the rule connecting land inheri-
tance with foreignness and foreignness with foreign birth come about?
According to historians, the reason may have been procedural require-
ments. The common-law writ that regulated succession determined that, in
order to inherit land, petitioners had to prove their genealogy by supplying
local witnesses. In cases of petitioners born outside the jurisdiction of the
court, the king could order the sheriff of their hometown to send a group of
local men as witnesses. However, this solution was impossible when peti-
tioners were born abroad. As a result, those born abroad were eligible to in-
herit land, but because of the particular procedural requirement tied to the
writ regulating land inheritance, they faced real difficulties in proving their
right to do so. Initially, whether they were or were not English was com-
pletely irrelevant. Nonetheless, over time, because of the tight connection
in common law between remedy and right, the practical difficulty in proving
genealogy (and therefore securing a remedy) was interpreted as inability to
inherit (the absence of right). Thereafter, b ecause there was no remedy
(foreign-born individuals could not prove their genealogy and thus their right
to inherit), there was no right. The circle was now closed: foreign-born indi-
viduals no longer had the right to inherit land in England, and those who
could not inherit because born abroad w ere identified as foreigners.
The Backlash
The proliferation of writs and the growing presence of royal jurisdiction were
not always appreciated by the lords and barons who saw their powers and
privileges diminish. Protests against this state of affairs led to a rebellion that
ended with the adoption of the Magna Carta (1215).13 Contrary to what is
commonly believed, the Magna Carta sought to guarantee mainly the priv-
ileges of the barons and freemen, not the rights of all Englishmen. It was
concerned with ensuring feudal control over land and feudal inheritance,
which legal developments in the late twelfth and early thirteenth centuries
seriously threatened.
Because the Magna Carta failed to resolve t hese issues, King Henry III
(r. 1216–1272), under renewed pressure from the barons who again rebelled,
The Birth of an English Common Law 109
in 1258 ordered his officials to halt the creation of new writs. In 1285 his son,
King Edward I, made a similar promise that no new royal courts would be
established and none would extend its jurisdiction to new subject m atters.
Because the pressure to extend royal jurisdiction continued and litigants
persevered in requesting royal intervention, in the late f ourteenth c entury a
new system came into being. Its creation was justified by the argument that
although no new common law writs w ere to be established, the monarch
still had to attend to special circumstances that justified his attention. Royal
conscience, it was alleged, could be discharged only if the king did what he
ought to do, that is, defend the weak and dispense justice. To comply with
this duty, presented as a moral obligation, the king would institute new pro-
cedures. In exceptional cases, because justice so required, he would allow
his chancellor to hear litigants and grant them an extraordinary remedy if
existing common-law writs supplied none.
As a result of t hese developments, litigants who could use writs already
recognized by the Chancery took their cases to the ordinary royal courts
(common-law courts). Those who could not find an appropriate solution in
the registry of writs addressed the Chancery and requested its extraordinary
intervention.
This development introduced a new system of conflict resolution. This
system was distinguished from common law because its operation, at least
initially, was divergent. While by that stage (the fourteenth century) common-
law courts were routinely open to all those who could find an appropriate
writ in the registry of writs, the new system gave remedies only in excep-
tional cases and it had no preset list of c auses of action.
This new system, emerging in the fourteenth c entury, was called “equity,”
and the court that adjudicated these extraordinary remedies was identified
as the Chancery court. Meant to deal with exceptional situations, equity was
intentionally fashioned as a flexible system with fluidly defined rules. It de-
pended on the discretionary powers of the chancellor, who was empowered by
the king to solve difficult cases in which common law supplied no appro-
priate solution. This, however, did not mean that equity was a completely arbi-
trary system. Initially most Chancery officials were university trained and
many of them were ecclesiastics. As a result, they frequently, directly or implic-
itly, a dopted the criteria, doctrines, and procedure of canon and Roman law.
In the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries, equity was where the most
exciting legal developments took place. Filling the vacuum left by the
110 A Short History of European Law
Royal Legislation
Coinciding with the institutionalization of common law and the formation
of equity, English monarchs proceeded to legislate. From as early as the reign
of Henry II and throughout the M iddle Ages and the early modern period,
The Birth of an English Common Law 111
Other scholars point out that even as early as the thirteenth c entury judges
habitually discussed what the statutes prescribed. They suggest that lawyers
training in the Inns of Court were taught to comment on royal legislation
and that statute books w ere copied for their use. Some even argue that the
study of statutes was the centerpiece in lawyer’s education. If legislation was
such a marginal component of the legal system, how could this be explained?
Is it possible that our image of early common law was influenced too much
by seventeenth-century developments that sought to decenter the king and
make this law customary?
with ensuring justice (the Continent), and a judge that oversaw procedure
(mainly pleading) and delegated decision making in juries (England),
held true.
These differences, however, did not imply that the system that emerged
in England was completely new. Many historians point, for example, to the
striking similarities between common and ancient Roman law. They sug-
gest that in both places conflict resolution and the courts were at the center
of the legal system. In both places, trials were conceptually divided between
a first stage, in which the debated question between the parties was framed
(before a praetor in Rome, and during pleading before a judge in England),
and a second stage, in which nonprofessionals (iudex in Rome, jurors in
England) evaluated the facts of the matter and rendered judgment. In both
places, by granting remedies, praetors in Rome and the king’s officials
in England, created rights. Th ese remedies—which took the form of writs in
England, formulas in Rome—were initially ad hoc solutions to particular
problems but, over time, praetors and officials tended to repeat them. Repeti-
tion eventually led to the creation of a closed list of remedies, which in Rome
found expression in edicts elaborated by praetors and in England in a public
registry of writs. A fter formulas and writs fossilized, legal creation was
channeled through other means: jurisprudence and legislation in Rome, leg-
islation and equity in England.15
As a result, despite what is commonly assumed, ius commune and common
law were perhaps not twins, but they were certainly siblings. As one histo-
rian put it, taking into account the “basic principles, organizing ideas, tech-
niques of argumentation, and habits of thought,” one “might want to call
the common law simply a variant, admittedly an eccentric variant, of the
multitude of legal systems that ultimately derived from ius commune.”16 Said
differently, Norman monarchs might have been successful at promoting their
own jurisdiction in unprecedented ways, but the legal system they instituted
was heir to a European past and engaged in their European present. As will
be argued in Chapter 8, if E ngland seriously parted ways from Europe, this
may have happened not during the M iddle Ages but instead during the six-
teenth and seventeenth centuries, when common law was reinvented by
legal experts who sought to curb royal ambitions.
part four
natural that the idea of a common European / Christian law would also
come u nder attack.
While criticizing jurists for failing to account for how society and lan-
guage had changed since Roman times, humanists also censored them for
misunderstanding the nature of the legal sources they analyzed. Ius commune
jurists w ere mostly interested in harmonizing different pieces of Roman law.
Their methodology, Scholasticism, was based on the assumption that these
sources w ere coherent rather than contradictory. Even though this method
had proved useful to the development of ius commune, humanists insisted
that it was nevertheless very wrong. The Corpus Iuris Civilis that ius commune
jurists studied, and most particularly the Digest, which included the opinions
of Roman jurists, in fact comprised a wide, almost accidental, array of frag-
ments. Written by different p eople at different points in time, these fragments
were not consistent. Instead, each obeyed the logic of its time, place, and au-
thors, and the different fragments often contradicted one another.
Humanists therefore argued that the basic methodological assumptions of
ius commune jurists could no longer hold water. To truly understand Roman
law, what jurists needed to do was historicize and contextualize it. They
would have to account for the differences between Rome and their society
and consider Roman law as a historical phenomenon that had undergone
constant changes and mutations. This would require that jurists divide
Roman law into several periods and distinguish the different places in which
the various fragments w ere produced and the identity of their authors.
Jurists would also need to acknowledge the existence of multiple schools of
thought and the presence of contradictory solutions.
was superior to all others, including royal mandates, and all inhabitants of
the kingdom, including the king, must obey it.
In trying to affirm the specificity of French law, humanists also turned
their attention to feudal law. There they found elements that were surprisingly
useful for advancing their political and religious agendas. Most important
among them was the idea that relations between lords and vassals depended
on a pact. This pact was perhaps established between two radically unequal
partners, but it nevertheless included mutual obligations. B ecause political
subjection was based on a pact, it was possible to claim that monarchs who
did not fulfill their end of the pact were tyrants and could be legitimately
resisted and replaced. This theory would eventually become a radical phi-
losophy validating both resistance and revolution. Among other t hings, it
would justify, in seventeenth-c entury E ngland and eighteenth-century
France, the execution of kings.
this vision, local law was not the product of negotiated solutions to particular
problems that w ere reached when necessary, but instead it was made of a se-
ries of norms (customs) that had evolved in the community over time.
This interpretation changed the essence of what village assemblies and
juries did. Rather than searching to adopt a practical compromise that would
preserve the peace as has been the case in the High M iddle Ages, these as-
semblies were now reimagined as bodies responsible for identifying and ap-
plying preexisting norms. From the fourteenth c entury onward, instead of
asking what the correct solution to a particular case should be, or whether
the solution was just or consensual, jurists observing or advising village as-
semblies began inquiring what their customs mandated. They asked w hether
the jurors or the members of the assembly were sufficiently familiar with
communal arrangements and whether their telling of these arrangements was
true and accurate. To decide on such issues, jurists considered the statements
collected from different p
eople and, contrasting one with the other, they
reached a conclusion regarding what the local customs “truly” prescribed.
The law that they searched for was a stable, old, and permanent law, which
they believed was part of communal heritage, even communal property. This
law contained privileges that belonged to all communal members.
Following their conviction that local law represented enduring, even im-
memorial, customs, jurists began formalizing this law by using increasingly
abstract and general categories. They systematized a wide range of solutions
and began arguing that these solutions had always existed in precisely the
same manner. The aim was to distill a local law that could exist indepen
dently of the circumstances of the case and time and that could fit any
number of similar situations. The road from abstraction to centralization was
swift but meaningful. By the late fourteenth and fifteenth centuries, the geo
graphical projection of certain norms, now identified as customary, was
expanded from a single locality to entire regions.
The influence of ius commune jurists on t hese developments was substan-
tial, but equally important was the emergence of royal bureaucracies and the
redefinition of relations between local and central powers. As smaller units
such as villages became integrated into larger polities such as kingdoms,
the identification of what t hese smaller units consisted of, and what w ere
the privileges of their inhabitants, became matters of concern. It was now
necessary for locals to obtain recognition of what they thought w ere their
traditions and for central powers to know what the limitations on their
freedom to act would be. As a result of these requirements, policies were
128 A Short History of European Law
devised to identify and register the local normative order, sometimes in order
to conserve it, sometimes in order to change it. Efforts were also invested in
facilitating the work of royal and regional governments by standardizing
customs and expanding their reach, in order to diminish the complexity of a
legal system in which each village had its own practices and norms.
If politics mattered, so did the availability of jurists and of new techniques
of recording, mainly, the passage from orality to written forms. But if cus-
toms seemed to vindicate the importance of a popular law, created without
the intervention of jurists or kings, they also paradoxically testified to the
powerful presence of ius commune. Although German historians once argued
that Germanic territories turned to Roman law only in the fifteenth and
sixteenth centuries, a period they identified as “the Reception,” and ex-
plained this reception by suggesting that Germanic customary law was far
too chaotic and fragmented to be useful, it is now clear that many Germanic
territories w ere deeply influenced by ius commune long before the sixteenth
century. In the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries, ius commune jurists in-
deed collaborated in the formation and formalization of Germanic customary
law, which scholars no longer believe was the expression of popular wisdom.
Rather than two regimes in opposition, in the late medieval period, in Ger-
many and elsewhere, customary law and ius commune merged together as
ius commune jurists labored to collect, register, but also change and modify
the local law. This legacy of collaboration would again become crucial in the
nineteenth century, when German jurists codifying their laws would turn to
Roman law in order to develop mechanisms that would allow them to com-
prehend and describe the so-called customary law of the various German
states and territories (see Chapter 12).
By reducing customs to written texts, these kings aspired to control the local
normative order and indeed change it. Royal commissioners who engaged in
this task understood what was at stake. They constantly imposed their opinion
on locals as to how norms should be identified and written down, what should
be added and what subtracted. Royal officials also favored the unification of
various customary regimes and selected those customs that should be appli-
cable everywhere in the kingdom. The writing down of customs, royal jurists
hoped, would also stop their evolution by fixing them conclusively. No longer
would customs change, no longer would negotiations be possible. Most im-
portantly, the local norms that became royal law after they were written down
would no longer depend on the community. Instead, they would obtain their
validity and would be legitimized and obeyed because the king had so willed.
In the long run, rather than being an instrument for preservation, the
writing down of customary law was a means to introduce change. It ush-
ered in, not the preservation of communal privileges and liberties, as Ho-
tman had wished, nor the permanence of orality, but the beginning of a new
age that featured the growing intervention of kings in the normative order.
In the aftermath of its official recording, local law would no longer depend
on the community. It would instead be imposed on locals by outsiders who
would tell them what their own customs dictated. Paradoxically, the one
point on which both humanists and kings converged was the hope that cus-
tomary law would replace ius commune. For Hotman this would be a means
to return to a genuine French law and resist royal intervention in the nor-
mative order. For kings, this would be a way to augment their powers u nder
the pretense that they conserved the ancient law rather than created a new
one. But the hope that customs would replace ius commune w ere frustrated.
Not only did Ius commune survive the fifteenth-and sixteenth-century crisis,
but the writing down of customs manifested its hegemonic presence.
8
the country. Parliament declared the crown vacant and called upon William
and Mary to occupy it. The invitation, however, was conditional. The terms
under which the kingship of William and Mary would be accepted were de-
tailed by Parliament. The 1689 document that came to be known as the Bill
of Rights, listed, among other things, important checks on what the kings
could do.
Historians look back to this period to explain the origin of a new mo-
dernity that was said to have emerged in England in the sixteenth and
seventeenth centuries. They explain the ideologies, strategies, interests, cul-
tures, and practices that justified this upheaval and trace the individuals
and networks that were responsible for their genesis. In what follows, I ask
which legal structures facilitated t hese developments and how law changed as
a result.
cism against the monarchy in the midst of an acute religious and political
upheaval. This was a serious threat to common law, whose expansion during
the twelfth, thirteenth, and fourteenth centuries was directly tied to the
prestige of the monarchy. This expansion was based on the assumption that
litigants would find justice more fair, impartial, and efficient in royal courts
than in all other judicial and administrative instances. If royal jurisdiction
grew during this formative period, it was b ecause the king was willing to
engage in dispensing justice and b ecause he was asked to do so by his vas-
sals. The more they turned to royal jurisdiction, bypassing feudal and
urban courts, the faster writs were created, and the greater was the reach of
common law.
In the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, however, who the king (or
queen) should be became a matter of debate. Growing discord regarding how
to identify the legitimate claimant to the crown was accompanied by dis-
agreement over w hether the reigning monarch acted as he should, or whether
he had abused his powers (a question asked with regard to both Charles I
and James II). Also discussed w ere other essential questions such as w
hether
kings w ere subject to the law or superior to it, and w
hether they could change
the law or required the consent of Parliament. Conflicts between common-
law and equity judges added to t hese tensions, as they brought royal officials
into conflict with one another, allowing for interpretations that were often
outright contradictory and that moved much of the political debate into the
realm of the courts. Should common law, which had its own professionals
and rules that mostly backed Parliament, prevail over equity— mostly
manned by Roman and canon-law jurists who backed the king—or should
the inverse be true? Could a king who was dissatisfied with the legal system
overhaul, or even replace it? Would such a move be permissible or completely
illegal? During the seventeenth century, the conclusion that the monarch
was a tyrant led to the execution of one king (Charles I) and the removal of
another (James II).
These developments questioned some of the basic assumptions regarding
the superiority of royal justice. With the monarchy discredited, legal experts
searched to rescue common law from its traditional dependence on the crown
so that criticism against the monarch would not harm the reputation of the
legal system. They also sought to subject equity to common law. In order to
obtain t hese results, they set out to reinvent what common law was and why
and how it was important.
136 A Short History of European Law
The final aim of this new reinterpretation was not only to disassociate law
from the king, arguing that he was not charged with its creation, but also to
place common-law judges at the heart of the juridical system. According to
this understanding, these judges w ere no longer royal servants who dispensed
justice for the king by following his instructions (the writs). Instead, they
were charged with identifying preexisting norms (customs) and applying
them. They w ere a bastion both ensuring the survival of the authentic law
of the land and resisting royal pressure to change it (when such royal pres-
sure existed). Common-law judges were also members of an autonomous
body that was perhaps administratively dependent on the king but that le-
gally obeyed only the law.
To sustain this amazing transformation and create this fiction, Coke and
other legal experts had to modify not only the character of common law but
also their understanding of history. The argument that common law was a
customary law that predated the arrival of the Normans required, among
other things, rewriting the history of the Norman Conquest. In their effort
to do so, these experts suggested that there was no real conquest, e ither
because the Normans were (or could be seen as) legitimate heirs to the throne
or because they never acted as true conquerors. Rather than abolish the rights
of natives, as was customary in cases of conquest, the Normans w ere willing
to submit to the existing normative order, acting as lawful heirs who con-
tinued rather than disrupted the normal state of affairs. Converting the
Norman Conquest into a “non-event,” these experts thus argued that from
a legal point of view it marked no transformative moment. Legally, it was
as if it had never happened, because it had not changed the basic tenets of
English law.
In some odd way, this reinterpretation reiterated the assertions already
made by the first Norman kings, who indeed suggested that their principal
aim was to guarantee the continuation of the legal order. Yet it ignored the
legal revolution that had taken place in England in the twelfth, thirteenth,
and f ourteenth centuries, indeed the birth of common law. It suggested in-
stead that the institution of royal courts and the development of a system of
writs featured a continuity with ancient times rather than introduced a pro-
found change.
If negating the conquest upheld the antiquity as well as the continuity of
common law, it was also a powerful argument against the ambitions of
seventeenth-century monarchs. Upon his ascension to the English crown
Crisis and Reinvention of Common Law 139
There is ample evidence, for example, that the Norman kings who invaded
ngland followed t hese strategies that, under the guise of continuity, initi-
E
ated a process of change. Most noteworthy in this regard were the “Laws of
Edward the Confessor.” Th ese laws, which were said to reproduce the “laws
of the land” in writing in order to preserve them, assert that in 1070 the Nor-
mans decided to write down the existing norms by asking a group of local
jurors to declare what they included. Historians, however, conclude that this
description of how this legislation came about was completely fictional. In-
stead of being the result of public participation, the Laws of Edward w ere
probably authored in the twelfth century by a single jurist, contracted by
the king. Despite claims to the contrary, their aim was not to guarantee con-
tinuity but to capture only t hose laws that favored the Normans. Glanvil’s
and Bracton’s description of common law as customary might have responded
to similar impulses.4 Like their colleagues working on the Continent, whose
juridical culture they shared, Glanvil and Bracton most probably perceived
English law as “customary” not b ecause it was created by the community—
both Glanvil and Bracton clearly credited the king—but because it was
shared among royal councilors and legal professionals. The customs they de-
scribed, in short, w ere those created by the courts, not the community.
It is possible that the idea that common law was customary, in the sense
that it was created by the community and predated the Norman Conquest,
emerged in E ngland in the mid-fifteenth c entury. It can be traced back to
specific authors who suggested that the true lex terrae included the customs
of the land.5 From there to the conclusion that the English “had made
their own laws out of their wisdom and experience” was a short but mean-
ingful step.6
The Second Move: Making Common Law the Law of the Land
If common law had to change its nature to fit the narrative of continuous
confirmations of a customary law, of equal importance to the theory pro-
posed by seventeenth-century legal experts was the obligation to make
common law the law of the land. This move required classifying canon, local,
urban, and feudal law, even equity, e ither as inferior to common law or suf-
ficiently influenced by it to form part of its system. Or it proposed that
common law was authorized to oversee other jurisdictions. A fter all, it rep-
resented royal justice, and the king was superior to all other powers.
Crisis and Reinvention of Common Law 143
Thereafter, legal experts began arguing that common-law courts w ere the
most important courts of the land and that common law itself was the most
important legal system in existence. Coke referred to this point when, having
admitted that more than one hundred courts existed in England, each re-
sponding to a different set of rules and principles, he nevertheless concluded
that common law was the most important b ecause it was “the law of the
land” (lex terrae). He might have meant that this was the only law common
to the entire realm (which it was), but in the following years his words were
credited with a new meaning—literally, that common law was the only law
in the land.
This interpretation was followed by subsequent scholars. In the nineteenth
century, Frederic William Maitland (1850–1906), a notable lawyer, professor,
and legal historian, went so far as to conclude that by the end of the Middle
Ages most feudal courts had adopted the procedures of royal courts, as well as
borrowed substantive solutions from them. According to his understanding,
by that time feudal courts were but mere local projections of a general
common law. Reaching a somewhat similar conclusion, the English Eccle-
siastical Courts Commission stated in 1883 that the work of ecclesiastical
courts was “guided” but not “determined” by canon law. According to this
version, as early as the fourteenth century kings and barons had subjected
canon law to the “laws of England.” As a result, since that period English
customs had acted as a constitutional check of sorts, ensuring that canon
law, now identified as a foreign law, would not penetrate the island if its
instructions contradicted common law.
to affect the rulings of their judges. Local regulations often forbade using
courts other than the feudal court, though some historians suggest that t hese
prohibitions are evidence that people were d oing just that.
Scholars also assert that if there was on occasion similarity between what
feudal courts determined and what common law mandated, it could well be
the case that, rather than one imitating the other, they responded to similar
social, economic, and political constraints. Furthermore, judges in feudal
courts sought to identify the most convenient and consensual solution to the
specific problems they were called to resolve. Their rulings were not moti-
vated by some preexisting system of rules, not even customs, but instead de-
pended on place, parties, and time. There w ere hundreds of feudal courts in
England, each of them dissimilar to the others. If there was no uniformity
within each court or across the many feudal courts, why assume that they
were all part of a common-law system? If influence flowed at all, it flowed
from feudal courts to common-law courts. A fter all, each time feudal or local
norms w ere upheld by royal courts, royal jurisdiction perhaps won additional
legitimacy, but so did local legal arrangements. These cases, in which the
declaration of witnesses or the presentation of collections of customs (identi-
fied as custumals) were integrated into royal jurisprudence, showed the endur-
ance and resilience of a local system of norms that dictated solutions different
from rather than similar to those proposed by the royal courts.
Because local norms maintained their power, during the early modern
period locals often struggled to identify what t hese norms were; they de-
stroyed evidence such as collections of customs or attempted to rewrite them.
Although they were not always successful, on many occasions they man-
aged to influence legal arrangements that w ere said to have existed from time
immemorial but could be entirely new. These strugg les w ere extremely
local and produced a radically diverse system of norms, yet for t hose who
upheld t hose norms, they w ere just as valid, perhaps even more so, than
common law.
Similarly, research on English ecclesiastical courts suggests that u ntil the
Reformation these courts followed canon law. A fter the English monarch
broke with Rome and instituted a national Church in E ngland, canon law
was presented as a foreign law imposed on the English by the pope. Yet it
continued to operate. The only immediate, noticeable change after the Ref-
ormation was the establishment of new appeal procedures that replaced the
traditional plea to the pope with a local instance. A separate English eccle-
Crisis and Reinvention of Common Law 145
siastical law never came into being, nor was the jurisdiction of the Church,
which continued distinct from the common-law courts, ever abolished.
As for equity, it is currently argued that it had begun converging with
common law in the sixteenth century, but that in the seventeenth century
while these debates took place it was still considered a separate system. In-
deed, it was separate enough to bring about the wrath of Parliament and
common-law courts or, on the contrary, to lead monarchs such as James
to instruct that equity should be superior to, rather than subjected to,
common law.
Common law, in short, might have been an important, even essential,
component of the English legal system, but until the seventeenth c entury, at
least, it never operated on its own. It was not superior to other jurisdictions,
and was not placed hierarchically at the top of the judicial system. Common-
law courts, for example, could not see appeals on other jurisdictions. Further-
more, t here is reason to believe that influence between the various parallel
systems that existed in England must have flown in all directions rather
than only (or even mainly) from common-law to other courts, leading histo-
rians to the conclusion that common law neither absorbed nor affected all
other jurisdictions.
The myth of continuous confirmations, however, did not say much about
the contents of the alleged pact. To identify what it included, seventeenth-
century legal experts who believed in the orality of customary law neverthe-
less looked for documentary evidence. They located many historical texts
that, according to them, contained elements central to this pact. Most em-
blematic among them was the Magna Carta (1215). From the seventeenth
century onward, the Magna Carta would come to symbolize the monarchy’s
promise to uphold the existing law and agree to limit its powers by providing
trial by peers, prohibiting arbitrary arrest, and securing the consent of the
kingdom for the levying of new taxation.
obliged to respect it. These customary laws that framed the relations between
kings and their subjects now protected the lives and properties of all En
glishmen. They w ere an inheritance that the present generation must enjoy,
preserve intact, and pass on. That the Magna Carta included none of the
elements that were read into it no longer mattered.
this tendency led judges such as Edward Coke to make frequent use of
precedent, even suggesting that they should have an authority of their own.
Adhering to the idea that experts should trust their own art, in his opinion
in the famous Calvin case,8 Coke ruled that to determine what the law dic-
tated, one had to observe examples, precedents, and judgments rendered in
similar cases.
Nonetheless, it was not u ntil the eighteenth c entury that binding prece
dent was introduced in both common-law and equity courts, compelling
judges to follow the relevant decisions made in the past. A means to ensure
that judges’ identification of customary law would accumulate over time,
mandatory precedent also changed the nature of judicial decision making.
Rather than being ad hoc solutions, judicial decisions w ere now reconceptu-
alized as constructing a long chain of rulings that, over many generations,
declared and clarified the essence of common law. This transformation
authorized our present-day conception of common law as a judge-made
law, that is, a system whose principles can be deduced by studying cases.
foundly influential. Indeed, jurists and ideas coming from the Continent
were of such importance that much of the activity of sixteenth-and
seventeenth-century actors described in this chapter can be interpreted as a
response to this influence or at least as dialoguing with it. Sixteenth-and
seventeenth-century English actors may have gradually perceived the En
glish and Continental systems as distinct, but they were also aware of their
constant proximity and their potential permeability.
Nonetheless, despite t hese striking similarities, and despite the continued
use of French and Latin terms, expressions, and doctrines in E ngland, during
the early modern period the myth of English exceptionalism held strong.
It survives to this day, notwithstanding scholarly research that insists on
common roots and that suggests that if England took a different path,
this happened mainly in the early modern, not medieval times, and was
the result not so much of what Eng lish law actually was but of how it was
reimagined.
9
in the Americas in the 1520s and 1530s, was said to have commented that
when he heard about the requirement, he did not know w hether to laugh
or cry. But however absurd the document might have been, we have ample
evidence that it was carried around by many conquistadors and indeed read
to the indigenous peoples before hostilities began.
rather than based on law or reason it was anchored in faith. E ither one be-
lieved it or one did not.
Having discarded all t hese traditional justifications for Spaniards’ ex-
tending their jurisdiction to the Americas, Vitoria came up with a new
proposition. Following the teaching of Thomas Aquinas he suggested that,
in their condition as humans, both Spaniards and the native inhabitants of
the New World formed legitimately organized societies and both were there-
fore under obedience to natural law. This natural law, which he also called
the law of nations (ius gentium), was universal. It could apply to all h uman
communities whether their members knew about it or not, consented or not,
inhabited Europe or not, w ere Christian or not.
Natural law, Vitoria affirmed, recognized several fundamental freedoms.
Believing in the sociability of man, on the one hand, and as a Spaniard legally
experiencing t hese freedoms, on the other, Vitoria argued that men enjoyed
the freedom to communicate, travel, conduct commerce, and dwell wher-
ever they wanted to. This freedom allowed Spaniards to arrive, settle, and
trade in the Americas. It also sustained their liberty to tell the truth, which
as far as Vitoria was concerned included above all the duty to preach the
gospels and bring the message of the Christian God to natives. Th ese w ere
the freedoms Spaniards exercised, Vitoria concluded, when they sailed to
the Americas, traded with natives, established fortified settlements, and en-
deavored to convert the local population. B ecause Spaniards were autho-
rized by natural law to do all this, if the natives refused to allow it or reacted
with violence, they contravened natural law and could be legitimately at-
tacked. Vitoria also explained that natural law included other provisions
authorizing Spaniards, for example, to protect Indian converts to Chris
tianity, elect a Christian king to rule over them, defend natives against tyr-
anny, and help their friends and allies.
In the long run Vitoria’s analysis produced the same results as previous
explanations, namely, it authorized Spaniards to wage just war against na-
tives. Yet his approach was nevertheless revolutionary. It introduced the
idea that a natural ius gentium regulated relations between Europea ns and
natives. It imposed a system of rights and duties that did not require in-
tervention of a superior authority such as the pope or the emperor or agree-
ment among interested parties. The law of nations that Vitoria subscribed
to was derived directly from nature and applied automatically and equally
to all peoples. It could be discovered by observing h uman societies, but (fol-
From Ius Gentium to Natural Law 159
lowing Aristotle and Aquinas) it was above all inscribed in man’s heart by
his creator and it was part of the rational understanding with which God
had endowed h umans.
did the same to advocate the freedom of the seas (1609) and to study the
laws of war and peace (1625). The British crown and British colonialists also
espoused this new language to refer to their commitments to natives and in
their relations with other European powers. As ius gentium penetrated
England, eventually English legal experts recognized the law of nations as
being part of common law.
The success of these new ideas was tied to the need to solve concrete ques-
tions, but it was also motivated by the search for norms that would be consen-
sual among Europeans who were now bitterly confronted not only politically
but also religiously. The breaking down of the Christian unity, the growing
number of reformed denominations, and the wars that ensued encouraged
the quest for a new normativity that could rule over relations not only between
Europeans and natives but also among rival Europeans themselves.
By the end of this process, most Europeans agreed that law regulated re-
lationships between them outside of Europe and with non-European na-
tives. They also agreed that this law, which they identified either as the law of
nations or as natural law (or both), included several unquestionable principles.
Initially Europeans searched for t hese principles in Scripture, tradition, or
Roman law, but eventually they came to justify them by reference to reason
and reason alone. They concluded that, because they were reasonable, the
rules they proposed were sufficiently self-evident that they no longer required
external validation.
vive and reproduce. Yet b ecause men began fighting, the need arose to di-
vide this common inheritance among them. This had led to the emergence
of private property and to the notion that what one has in his possession
should remain his. Similarly, to argue for the freedom of the seas, Grotius
first defined property as something that people could possess, and then he
demonstrated that the sea, because it could not be taken over and occupied,
could never be appropriated. The conclusion he reached was that Portuguese
claims for monopoly over sea routes from Europe to Asia were absurd and
that, as a result, the Dutch could establish their own trade in the region.
Grotius’s wish to cite authorities and yet also move to logical, common-
sense explanations that did not depend on these rules having been pro-
nounced before in reputable sources, was probably tied to the conditions of
the period. The Reformation and the proliferation of Protestant denomina-
tions forced Europea ns to search for a common language that would no
longer be based on religious precepts but instead would be organized around
shared experiences. The absence of an overreaching authoritative voice within
Europe, such as the popes and emperors once provided, diminished the fea-
sibility of depending on sovereign will to resolve issues between different
communities. European expansion further pushed scholars t oward secular-
ization because of the need to find a normative system that could be shared
with non-Europeans and non-Christians. But if the Reformation, the af-
firmation of states, and the expansion w ere vital to t hese processes of rein-
vention of natural law, so was the so-c alled seventeenth-century scientific
revolution, which led to the elaboration of new epistemologies suggesting
that true knowledge could be acquired only by means of observation. Having
first collected factual data, h
umans could then process it, striving to under-
stand what it meant by employing reason.
The most extreme example of how this new method was to affect scholars,
including jurists, was the work of the French philosop her René Descartes
(1596–1650). In his Meditations on First Philosophy (1641), Descartes ar-
gued that to reach truly logical conclusions, man had to forget all that he
knew. Adopting the policy of “systematic doubt,” Descartes called upon
contemporaries to examine even the most basic assumptions, including the
postulation that they existed. According to Descartes, only by getting rid
of the conventions that obscured h uman’s ability to reason and by setting
one’s mind f ree would humans be able to guarantee that their knowledge and
understanding of the world were truly based on facts and reason. On the
162 A Short History of European Law
basis of a very primary and verified truth—the truth of his own existence—
Descartes would commence gradually rebuilding all other certainties.
Although Descartes described at length the effort h umans would have to
invest in overcoming their own prejudices, he was nevertheless convinced
that if they domesticated their body and their senses, h umans would be ca-
pable of true reason. This belief was shared by many of his contemporaries,
who were convinced not only that pure reason existed but that it was shared
by all h umans. If exercised correctly, it would lead them all to the same
conclusion.
By the late seventeenth century, scholars and jurists began applying this
new epistemology to their analysis of society. Developing philosophies that
we now identify as “Enlightened,” many argued that, like h umans, society
needed to abandon its veneration of tradition and instead return to simplicity
and nature, that is, to pure reason. Only after intellectuals understood what
nature dictated would it be possible for jurists to translate these findings into
a new, perfect normative order that would guarantee happiness.
Thus, if the search for order in overseas expansion was one motive to
pursue self-evident truths, another was the aim to reform Europe itself. In
order to accomplish this task, in the late seventeenth century political phi
losophers and jurists across the Continent set out to discover what nature
dictated. They hypothesized about how humans behaved before tradition and
history obscured their capacity to reason, and they attempted to reconstruct
humans’ primitive state before society was created. Fabricating in their minds
abstract individuals who had no past, present, or cultural traits, these scholars
imagined a natural man who was unchangeable, timeless, and universal. A
presocial being, this man subsisted before family and society came into ex-
istence. Because he was reasonable, however, his decision to enter into social
relations must be explained by reference to the advancement of his own goals
and the satisfaction of his basic needs.
Most scholars went along with this exercise of imagining a remote, hy
pothetical, presocial past, but they differed as to what w ere the terms man
agreed to when he entered society. According to Thomas Hobbes (1588–1679),
because the presocial state featured a permanent situation of anarchy and
war, when he entered society, man consented to surrender many of his natural
liberties in exchange for safety. According to John Locke (1632–1704), b ecause
the presocial state was fairly comfortable and orderly, when entering society
man agreed to very few concessions and preserved most of his natural rights
From Ius Gentium to Natural Law 163
intact. Locke believed, not that man entered society out of fear, as Hobbes
suggested, but instead that he freely chose society with the aim of further
safeguarding and developing his rights. As a result of this analysis, while for
Hobbes the social contract included the duty to obey the state, for Locke it
was a means to protect rights as well as defend individual self-interest.
These debates, extremely serious yet with a completely fictional basis,
were mostly used by seventeenth-and eighteenth-century scholars to scru-
tinize their present-day society. Rather than being ideologically neutral, they
were profoundly political; they either justified or questioned the emerging
social, economic, and political structures. But regardless of the position they
chose to take, early modern scholars no longer invoked the power of God
or the mandates of tradition. Instead they referred to reason and reason alone.
At the center of their narrative was man, whom they portrayed as an indi-
vidual who acted out of self-interest. This individual was capable of making
informed decisions, and his decisions ended up constituting the social order.
Modernity
10
g overnment. How they proceeded and what it meant for the development of
European law are the subjects of this chapter, in which I ask which legal an-
tecedents authorized these developments and how what transpired affected
European law.
in their new governments all the powers they did not reserve for themselves.
It was thus essential that checks on government would be made explicit.
A fter a prolonged and heated debate, representatives of the newly founded
states a dopted a Constitution that defined common institutions and set rules
regarding relations between the states. Drafted in 1787, the Constitution
instituted a federal structure with an executive branch (president), a bicam-
eral legislative branch (Congress), and a judiciary. In the name of “we, the
people of the United States,” it mandated that the legislature would be
made of a Senate and a House of Representatives, whose members would
receive salaries and enjoy certain immunities. The executive power was given
to a president, whose powers were detailed. The Constitution also instituted
a Supreme Court with remunerated judges.
The first ten amendments to the federal Constitution (the Bill of Rights)
listed the protected rights that the government could not violate. Th ese in-
cluded freedom of religion, speech, assembly, and petition, the right to form
militias and bear and keep arms, the requirement that the government se-
cure consent for the lodging of soldiers, security against unreasonable searches
and seizures, several protections in the field of criminal law (no indictment
without g rand jury, no double jeopardy, no self-incrimination, guarantee of
due process, no cruel and unusual punishments), and the right to trial by jury
in both criminal and civil cases. The Bill of Rights also contained two
amendments that addressed general principles. The first stated that the rights
included in the bill were not exclusive and that other rights could be retained
by the people even though they were not enumerated (Ninth Amendment).
The second stated that powers not specifically delegated to the United States
or explicitly prohibited to the individual states were reserved for the states or
“the people.”
polity that featured a division of l abor between federal and state govern-
ments and made the citizens of each state entitled to treatment as citizens
in all other states.
Although these innovations w ere important, what was particularly revo-
lutionary was not the constitutions’ contents but the transformation of law
itself. As narrated in Chapter 8, the English conceived of their constitution as
ancient. According to the narrative that emerged in the seventeenth c entury, it
depended on a pact that was medieval in origin. Having survived numerous
confirmations, this pact was part of a customary law that was said to be both
ancient and oral. A few emblematic documents such as the Magna Carta or
the (English) Bill of Rights of 1689 confirmed the existence of this pact, but
these documents did not create it, they only reproduced parts of it in written
form. The English constitution was extremely casuistic. Rather than including
an enumeration of principles, or a global vision of what the social order should
be, it contained a wide array of particular, ad hoc arrangements.
Under the English system, furthermore, individual rights were protected
by the courts, which provided remedies against their infringement, but there
were no legal checks on Parliament. Parliament was said to be sovereign and,
in theory, could pass legislation that infringed even the most basic rights.
The expectation was that this would not happen because the House of Com-
mons represented the people and was to guarantee their rights. A system of
checks and balances was also supposed to ensure that Parliament (both the
House of Commons and the House of Lords) would behave, but there was
nothing built into the English constitutional system other than self-restraint
(or the upcoming elections) to ensure that rights would be respected.
The Thirteen Colonies adopted a radically different constitutional ar-
rangement. Although sharing the belief in an ancient political pact that guar-
anteed their rights, they searched for a distinct solution. Mixing customary
arrangements with innovations that were justified by reason, they proceeded
to adopt a series of elements that would constitute a new pact (Constitution)
between them and their government. In other words, they asserted their
absolute power to do and undo society and its laws.
Alleging continuity with the English tradition—in their foundational
documents colonists accused the English monarch of breaking the pact that
they wished to preserve—in practice t hese colonists turned the English tra-
dition upside down. They made several important structural innovations.
First, they began by affirming in the Declaration of Independence their right
to constitute a new polity that would be based on a new social pact. They
North American Developments 171
something that each person owned by birthright and because nature so dic-
tated. A mix and match of traditional common-law entitlements and ab-
stract principles based on natural law, the Declarations of Rights (1776) of
Virginia and Pennsylvania, for example, stated that these rights were to
guide (rather than be the result of ) the formation of new structures. Worded
sometimes as reflecting truth (“all men are born equally free and indepen
dent”) but sometimes as conveying an aspiration (“elections ought to be
free”), the two declarations asserted that men have certain inherent natural
rights of which they cannot be deprived, such as life, liberty, property, hap-
piness, and safety; that all power is vested in the p
eople and that government
is or ought to be instituted for the common benefit, protection, and security
of the people, nation, or community and must adhere to justice, moderation,
temperance, frugality, and virtue. Both declarations also instituted a certain
freedom of worship and expression and upheld the right to fair trial.
Yet the task of reproducing not only traditional rights but also natural
law and self-evident principles in writing and then transforming them into
a legally binding document proved extremely dangerous. This was particu-
larly evident with regards to the Bill of Rights. Originally meant to serve as
a statement of principles, mostly expressing a set of standards against which
to measure the legitimacy of government and with which to educate citi-
zens and remind them of what needed protection, it took a while before the
bill was understood to convey legal prescriptions. Applied in the nineteenth
century to the federal government and only a fter World War II to state gov-
ernments, many questions had to be answered. Was the enumeration of
rights a recognition that t hose rights already (naturally) existed, or did it
transform those rights into legally binding commitments? And what hap-
pened to rights that were not included in the list? Did they cease to exist, or
was their force the same as always, despite their omission from this founda-
tional document? If nothing changed because of the writing down (because
natural rights depended on a higher external norm that predated the Bill of
Rights and existed independently of it), what was the purpose of the Bill
of Rights? If the Bill of Rights did make a difference, how could the natural
rights, which w ere not enumerated, not suffer from their exclusion? And what
about rights that did not yet exist but might come into being in the f uture?
Although the Ninth Amendment referred to this question by stating that
the enumeration was not meant to deny the existence of additional, unlisted,
fundamental rights, lawyers and scholars have since asked what to do with this
amendment.4 Was it proof that the writing down of rights was only a means to
North American Developments 173
English Antecedents
To explain why the colonists chose to rebel and how they framed their new
government, most historians point to the great affinity between develop-
ments in seventeenth-century E ngland and the eighteenth-century colonies.
Facing a legitimacy crisis and royal absolutism, seventeenth-century English
opponents proceeded to undertake their own revolution. During this revo-
lution they stated that, from time immemorial, England had an ancient
constitution that defined a pact of protection and obedience between the
monarch and his vassals. This constitution placed checks on the king while
also guaranteeing the rights of his subjects. Seventeenth-century English ac-
tors found written proof of this compact in the Magna Carta and other en-
actments. The most noteworthy elements of this ancient constitution w ere the
rights to no taxation without representation, due process, and trial by jury.
Developments in the colonies followed a similar course. A legitimacy crisis
backed by claims that Parliament and monarch did not have the powers they
pretended to have led colonists to vindicate their ancient rights. Allegedly
in order to protect these rights, they broke ties with Britain and instituted a
government that would be limited by a constitution. The constitutional ar-
rangements they a dopted w ere different, and so w
ere the tools designed to
protect them, yet the method was similar, b ecause in both places the opposi-
tion a dopted the claim that the king could not rule by fiat or prerogative
but must obtain consent to his laws, which must obey fundamental rules.
Most historians judged this close affiliation between events in England
and events in the colonies as natural, even self-explanatory, b ecause it was
normal that colonies inhabited by British migrants and ruled by the British
would use a common-law framework both to rebel against the old and to
construct a new polity. But t hese conclusions regarding the naturalness of
the relations between English and colonial developments included several
assumptions whose veracity was not evident. Foremost among them was the
conviction that the legal system operating in colonial North America was
North American Developments 175
Enlightenment Roots
The Enlightenment was an intellectual movement that took hold in various
parts of Europe in the eighteenth c entury. As described in Chapter 9, in its
core was a firm belief in rationality as well as in h uman capacity to reform
the legal order. Following in the footsteps of earlier generations, enlightened
178 A Short History of European Law
thinkers concurred that society came into being after individuals living in a
state of nature negotiated a “social pact.” Th ese negotiations involved rea-
sonable individuals who were moved by the wish to improve their condi-
tions. They therefore agreed to certain stipulations that exchanged benefits
with restrictions and duties. B ecause t hese individuals w
ere capable of un-
derstanding how society functioned, they could plan their activities. By em-
ploying reason, they could discover the laws of nature and apply them to
their institutions and laws. The Enlightenment, in other words, affirmed
human agency and insisted that h umans were rational beings who w ere con-
scious of their rights (and duties) and were willing to limit them only for a
very important and worthwhile cause.
Through debates as to which system would lead to the greatest happiness,
the Enlightenment sought to liberate men from relying on ancient traditions
and authorities. As Immanuel Kant beautifully put it in 1784, the Enlight-
enment was to mark the end of men’s dependence on knowledge obtained
by others and designate the move to think for oneself, relying only on one’s
own ability.7
Reverberating throughout Europe, t hese proposals found a warm recep-
tion on both sides of the Atlantic. In Europe they eventually produced what
we now identify as the French Revolution. In Anglo-A merica they led to the
colonists’ decision to part from their motherland as well as design new struc-
tures of government that would protect their rights more efficiently. Ap-
pealing to such principles first in the Declaration of Independence, which
included a summary of enlightened theories, it was in the federal Constitu-
tion of 1787 that the representatives of the new independent states spelled
out their program. This program, they declared, was not mandated from
above or dependent on tradition but instead came from a rational analysis
done by “we, the people.”
The Enlightenment allowed late eighteenth-century actors to believe that
they had the power to remake society by following both their experience
and their reason. It also endowed them with the conviction that these mea
sures (which, in reality, were extremely revolutionary) required no justifi-
cation. Presenting them as the reasoned outcome of a law of nature, late
eighteenth-century actors declared them to be self-evident truths. Their only
justification was the fictitious tale, philosophical rather than historical, about
how societies came to be, which was conveniently reproduced in the Dec-
laration of Independence.
North American Developments 179
Equally popular was the adoption of constitutions that were not dramati-
cally different from the American one. Th ese usually expounded a scheme
of government that, although often distinct from the one espoused by the
former Thirteen Colonies, nevertheless included the separation of powers as
well as, more recently, judicial review. Th ese constitutions w
ere understood
to embody a superior level of normativity that other laws or governmental
action could not violate.
Although this American contribution to European law was not completely
autochthonous—after all, it was based on English legal traditions, Euro
pean debates on natural law and the law of nations, and Enlightenment
philosophy—it is nevertheless clear that the representatives of the Thirteen
Colonies were the first to convert these ideals into formally sanctioned legal
structures. They w ere also the first to decide that the most basic elements of
collective life (the structures of government) would be decided by votes in
assemblies that allegedly reflected and refined the desires of “the people.”
The constitutions they imagined w ere the product of both tradition and
reason, but their ultimate goal was to ensure the happiness of all.
These developments set an example that others could emulate. The list of
countries that w ere directly or indirectly affected by them, that proceeded to
declare their independence or adopt constitutions, was massive. Among them
(the list is not exhaustive and contains anachronistic names) w ere Belgium,
Haiti, most former Spanish colonies in the Americas (Gran Colombia, Vene-
zuela, Argentina, Chile, Costa Rica, El Salvador, Guatemala, Honduras,
Mexico, Nicaragua, Peru, Bolivia, Uruguay, Ecu ador, Colombia, Para-
guay, and the Dominican Republic), Liberia, Hungary, New Zealand, Ger-
many, Italy, Japan, the former Czechoslovakia, and the former Rhodesia.
By the end of this process, American revolutionaries’ powerful message
regarding their rights indeed became the self-evident truth they had prema-
turely imagined. This truth—that communities have the right of self-
determination, that they can construct new polities, modify the conditions
of the social pact, design an effective government, institute a constitution
that would limit the actions of the legislative and the executive, and pro-
ceed to identify and defend their rights—are presently considered so con-
sensual that they no longer require justification.
11
On July 14, 1789, an angry mob stormed the Bastille, a fortress on the
eastern side of Paris, in an episode that came to mark the beginning of the
French Revolution. Since then many scholars have attempted to decipher
how the Revolution came about and what its short-and long-term conse-
quences w ere. They have described how the king was forced to relinquish
much of his control, how peasants began attacking seigneurial properties,
how new constitutional arrangements were developed, and how King Louis
XVI was sentenced and executed. They have narrated how the Revolution
grew more radical and more violent over time and how t hose who resisted it
were persecuted. Symbolized by the invention of the guillotine, persecution
led to the execution of many, most particularly in a stormy era identified as
“the Terror.” A fter several constitutions and a period that featured extensive
violence and chaos, in 1799 Napoleon Bonaparte ascended to power. Some
scholars saw the coming of Napoleon as signaling the end of the Revolu-
tion. O thers saw it as leading to the spread of the Revolution’s main princi
ples throughout Europe.
In what follows, I concentrate on the legal significance of what transpired.
I argue that the French Revolution featured a radical transformation, perhaps
the most radical transformation that European law has ever experienced.
Turning existing traditions upside down or inside out—contrary to what
happened in the Thirteen Colonies, where most actors appealed to natural
law yet also wished to continue upholding many traditions—the French de-
clared the need for a complete overhaul of the legal and political system.
183
184 A Short History of European Law
This would include not only constitutional changes (as in the Thirteen Col-
onies, where pre-independent law often continued intact despite the political
upheaval) but a modification of the entire legal system. Discarding customs
and existing structures, the declared aim was to create a new order, where
norms would no longer be inherited from the past. Instead they would herald
a f uture in which all decisions regarding both public and private law would
be mandated by natural law and reason, and guided by the w ill of the na-
tion. This vision, which was sometimes more radical than the actual legal
changes, transformed the French Revolution into an earthquake that allowed
for the emergence of law as we know it t oday.
consent, and freedom of speech and the press. It listed a series of constitu-
tional elements, including the assertions that sovereignty resided in the na-
tion, legislation expressed the general will, and the armed forces were to
protect the common good rather than the king. The declaration also estab-
lished as a general principle that what was not prohibited by legislation was
allowed and that no one could be constrained from doing anything unless
legislation so mandated.
These legal arrangements w ere entirely new, yet the declaration pre-
sented them as requiring no explanation or justification other than that
they were “natural, inalienable and sacred . . . simple and incontestable
principles,” which the representatives of the French p eople “set forth in a
solemn declaration . . . under the auspices of the Supreme Being.”1 Like the
representatives of the Thirteen Colonies, the authors of the Declaration of
Rights appealed to self-evident truths, suggesting that the changes they in-
troduced were in reality a restoration. According to the preamble to the
declaration, it was precisely the ignorance, neglect, or contempt for t hese
self-evident truths that had led to the public calamities and corruption the
members of the Assembly sought to correct.
In 1790 the National Assembly abolished all ecclesiastical taxes, confis-
cated Church property, and forced the clergy to become state employees. The
assembly then proceeded in a very short time span to adopt several consti-
tutions. In what was to become an extremely volatile period of politic al
experimentation, with one constitution replacing another and each sub-
stantially modifying the structures of government, different revolutionary
groups and individuals sought to identify the structures that would best fit
their image of an ideal society.
In 1791 the National Assembly voted on the first new constitution, which
included many of the initial foundational changes. Its preamble stated that
the aim of the document was to abolish irrevocably institutions that under-
mined the liberty and equality of man. In the f uture t here would be no dis-
tinctions based on birth and no privileges other than the ones bestowed on
all Frenchmen. L abor would be liberated too—instead of being limited to
guild members, all employment would be made available without distinc-
tion other than virtue and talent. The aim was to guarantee the natural and
civic rights of all Frenchmen, including the right to hold jobs, a fair distri-
bution of taxation according to financial ability, equal punishment for equal
crimes, freedom of movement and protection from arrest, freedom of speech
186 A Short History of European Law
and press, freedom of assembly, and freedom to address the authorities. The
1791 constitution protected the inviolability of property, stating that no
one could limit this right unless public security or the rights of third parties
were in jeopardy. It declared France a single indivisible polity and announced
that sovereignty, which was inalienable, resided in the nation. Ensuring the
separation of powers, the constitution instituted an executive (exercised by
the king), a legislative branch (composed of deputies elected by the people,)
and a judiciary (also elected). French citizens w ere divided into active citi-
zens who could vote b ecause they were males over 25 years old and paid a
certain amount of taxes and passive citizens who could not vote.
In yet another radical transformation, in 1792 France was reconstituted
as a republic, whose assembly was to be elected by universal male suffrage.
In 1793 Louis XVI was executed and a new constitution was adopted. Ac-
cording to this constitution, the National Assembly would be elected by all
male citizens and was to suggest laws that regional “primary assemblies”
would have to ratify. The National Assembly would appoint the executive
from lists of candidates proposed by these primary assemblies. Debates in
the National Assembly would be open to the public and would be decided
by the majority of members present. The 1793 constitution ended with sev-
eral clauses enumerating the main rights of Frenchmen, including equality,
liberty, security, property, f ree exercise of religion, the right to education and
public assistance, freedom of the press, and the right to hold popular assem-
blies as well as enjoy all the other rights of man. The constitution also guar-
anteed “respect” for “loyalty, courage, age, filial love, misfortune, and all
other virtues.”
Radical in its conception of popular sovereignty, the 1793 constitution was
ratified by popular referendum, yet its implementation was delayed and then
set aside indefinitely u
ntil peace would be achieved. In 1795 yet another
constitution was adopted. It sought to grant greater power to a five-person
executive called the Directorate as well as obtain control over the political
process while augmenting the protection of private property and the in-
violability of private residences, which could not be entered or searched
without an appropriate warrant. The 1795 constitution also forbade the for-
mation of corporations and associations that w ere contrary to public order,
and the creation of societies concerned with politic al questions. Politic al
rights, it stated, should be exercised only in primary and communal assem-
blies subject to the law. Any other unauthorized gathering would be consid-
The French Revolution 187
customary law). The new French system now i magined instituting a national
law—there would be only one law in France, and this law would apply to all
Frenchmen equally. No longer would it be the case, as Voltaire (1694–1778)
had once argued, that when traveling through France, one changed laws
more often than horses.3
The normative order that emerged from the French Revolution therefore
established that laws would be made by the elected representatives of the na-
tion. Guided by reason and based on the assumption that contemporaries
could—indeed, on occasions must—intervene in the legal order, legislation
would seek to improve or even redesign society. It would apply only within
the territory of the state but it would apply to all citizens equally. All t hese
traits, which describe our present-day understanding of what law is, w ere
perhaps not born with, but certainly for the first time were legally instituted
with, the French Revolution.
Beyond its enormous contribution to the redefinition of the normative
order, the French Revolution also pioneered three other changes that were
fundamental to the emergence of legal modernity. The first was the unifica-
tion of the legal subject, allowing us to imagine identical individuals who
all carried the same rights and duties. The second was the unification of
various rights over things into “property rights” the way we know them t oday.
The third was the unification of power and the creation of an undivided
sovereignty.
regardless of his or her distinct history and traits and despite having obvious
particularities, would be considered identical to all others. This new indi-
vidual would be decontextualized by way of a legal fiction that, in the name
of equality, would ignore all factors that made him or her particular or would
classify them as inconsequential.
If ignoring differences was one requirement, the need to piece together a
new legal subject was another. What this entailed can be best explained by
using an example. U nder the Old Regime, a nobleman who resided in a city
and was employed in the military held various legal personalities. As a no-
blemen, he enjoyed one legal regime, as a resident of a city, another and, as
a military man, yet a third. Each legal regime implied a different set of privi-
leges and duties. This diversity in law was maintained through the existence
of various jurisdictions. The nobles had their own authorities and tribunals
in which they adjudicated conflicts, and so did the city and the military.
These authorities and courts were responsible for enforcing the particular re-
gime that applied to the members of the group, one that sometimes was
bothersome but on most accounts was considered advantageous.
Wearing multiple hats—as in Gilbert and Sullivan’s The Mikado, where
Pooh-Bah was the first lord of the treasury, lord chief justice, commander
in chief, lord high admiral, master of the buckhounds, groom of the back-
stairs, archbishop, and lord mayor—our nobleman could alternatively
invoke his different legal personalities, but he could not combine their ele
ments. Either he was treated as a nobleman and received the rights that
applied to nobles and carried the duties of his estate, or he enjoyed the privi-
leges of his city and was under the protection of its authorities, or he ap-
pealed to the military jurisdiction. U nder the Old Regime this multiplicity
represented reality, not a comic or absurd situation.
The nearest example for such a situation today would be when the same
physical person (an individual) acts for a company (his or her first legal per-
sonality) or for him / herself as a private individual (his or her second legal
personality). If he / she is a trustee, he / she may have a third legal person-
ality when acting for the person or company, for which he / she is a trustee.
But what this person cannot do even today is combine his or her rights as
president of the company with his or her rights as a trustee or as a private
individual. As far as the law is concerned, although we all know that the very
same physical individual fulfills all these roles, he or she embodies three di-
verse legal personalities, and each action is ascribed to only one of his or her
personalities, as if the others did not exist.
The French Revolution 191
One of the first goals of revolutionary legislation was to change this situ-
ation, which many perceived as both chaotic and extremely prejudicial. Law-
makers wished to distinguish between jurisdiction and property, that is, the
right to exercise power (such as the powers of lords in their seigniorial do-
main) and the right to own land. They also hoped to reform the land market
and transform peasants into small proprietors, improve the state of agricul-
ture, protect property against abuse, and appeal to principles of reason and
simplicity.
Embracing the idea that property rights should be as complete and free
as possible, French revolutionary legislation imagined a new, modern prop-
erty that would include all the entitlements previously divided among many
individuals. Thereafter there would be a sole owner with the right to direct,
use, and collect income. This owner would be f ree of state regulation and of
impositions by third parties, and his rights would not be limited u nless con-
siderations of public utility and the rights of others justified it. Property, as
the Declaration of the Rights of Man and Citizen proclaimed in article 14,
would be “natural and imprescriptible” as well as “sacred and inviolable.”
Or, as the French civil code of 1804 would eventually determine, property
would become “the right to enjoy and to dispose of things in the most ab-
solute manner provided that one does not make use of them in a manner
prohibited by laws or regulations.” 4
make and change the law without needing to obtain the consent of others.
Unlimited in his actions and free of constraints other than divine and natural
law (including the Law of Nations), sovereignty, Bodin argued, was a neces-
sary condition for the survival of all polities.
Although they w ere relatively novel, even scandalous, when proposed,
Bodin’s theories, which w ere also discussed by Grotius, Hobbes, Locke, and
Pufendorf, to mention just a few examples, were brought into fruition by
the French Revolution. One of the first moves of revolutionary legislation
was to insist on creating a sovereignty that would be indivisible. Gradually
eliminating the powers possessed by officeholders who purchased their of-
fices, by lords, and by the Church, it collected these pieces of jurisdiction
together to create a new type of public authority that would be charged with
all public power and would be placed hierarchically at the top. The consti-
tution of 1791 pointed to this by asserting that “sovereignty is one, indivis-
ible, unalienable and imprescriptible.”5
As with developments in the Thirteen Colonies, many of t hese ideas w ere
not French in origin nor did they find receptive audiences only in that
country. However, the particular preconditions in France and the way the
Revolution developed made arguments and goals that w ere also present else-
where exceptionally powerful there. To understand why this was the case, it
is essential to trace the effects of Enlightenment philosophy, the propensity
of French monarchs to claim and use legislative power, and the way the con-
frontation with the king took shape.
The Enlightenment
The intellectual movement known as the Enlightenment took hold in various
parts of Europe in the late seventeenth and the eighteenth c entury. Believing
that society is ruled by natural laws, late seventeenth-century thinkers sug-
gested that society was instituted by rational individuals who chose to live
together in an organized structure. These individuals bargained with one an-
other, consenting to cede certain things in exchange for receiving o thers.
Although t hese thinkers disagreed on what the conditions for the formation
of society were, they nevertheless conceded that societies were consciously
and purposely created by man and that, as a result, they w ere regulated by
a foundational social pact. The implication was that certain norms embedded
in this primordial pact could not be modified without refounding society.
194 A Short History of European Law
By the eighteenth c entury, alongside t hese convictions came the belief that
uman society could improve if its organization and laws were more attuned
h
to nature. Thereafter, methods of inquiry applied to the hard sciences could
also serve to explain society. Like nature (and in its condition as part of na-
ture), society was subject to regular and uniform laws, which men could
understand by employing reason. Discovering t hese laws was essential b ecause
this knowledge allowed men to plan their activities and their societies by
forming appropriate institutions and devising rules to lead them to greater
happiness. And if men created the foundational social pact, they also could
change it by reaching a new agreement if circumstances so required. By the
eighteenth century, in other words, the original pact no longer simply re-
strained what people and governments could or could not do; it could also
become an instrument of change. Thereafter, people living together in a
polity were seen as having the power to make and unmake their association,
as well as modify the terms of their agreements.
Radical strains within enlightened thought suggested that the existing
social pact restricted rather than advanced human happiness. To redo so-
ciety, what was needed was a profound change, not cosmetic innovations.
To imagine a better f uture, it was necessary to destroy the past. The best
known among proponents of such radical moves was Jean-Jacques Rousseau
(1712–1778). In his Social Contract (1762) Rousseau concluded that society
corrupted rather than improved man, and he advocated its refoundation on
the basis of a better agreement. The new social contract he proposed would
not subject man to state, king, or government, as the present one did, but
instead would subject man only to the community of which he was a member.
According to Rousseau, this structure would ensure that all men would be
both equal and sovereign, and it would guarantee true happiness.
These visions, which embodied enlightened beliefs, might have also been
influenced by the constitutions and bills of rights that the representatives
of the rebellious Thirteen Colonies adopted in the 1770s and 1780s. These
documents—which some have described as a portfolio deliberately pre-
pared, copied, and translated in order to legitimize the uprising and rally
international support—were widely available in France. They w ere read and
discussed by crown officials and intellectuals, some of whom came to believe
that the events taking place in North America w ere the beginning of a trans-
formation that would spread across the civilized world. This transformation,
they hoped, would usher humanity into a new century, in which the experience
of the Thirteen Colonies would serve as the experimental grounds.
The French Revolution 195
regarding this point were the magistrates of the Parlement of Paris, which
in 1753 declared that t here was a contract between the king and his subjects
according to which if the subjects obeyed the king, he had to obey the law.
The struggle over registration of royal decrees by the parlements allowed
some members of the French elite to resist the expansion of royal preroga-
tives under the guise of obedience to the normative order and defense of tra-
ditional liberties. Particularly active in the 1770s and 1780s, the Parisian
Parlement insisted that royal actions could not contravene not only the fun-
damental laws of the kingdom but also the “rights of the nation,” which the
Parlement was charged with protecting. The radicalization of the conflict led
the monarch to reform the parlements (in 1771) and abolish them (in 1788).
The role that parlements appropriated in the name of the provinces and
the nation was clearly summarized on May 3, 1788, one year before the Rev-
olution began. In The Declaration of Fundamental Laws, the magistrates of
the Paris Parlement expressed their conviction that France had a customary
ancient constitution that the king must uphold. According to their under-
standing, the most fundamental norms included in that constitution were
succession to the crown by a male heir according to primogeniture, the right
of the nation to grant taxation freely as decided by its representatives in
the Estates General (that is, no taxation without parliamentary consent),
obedience to the customs and rights of the provinces, the irrevocability of
magistrates (who were not nominated by the king but instead purchased or
inherited their offices), and magistrates’ right to verify the king’s legislative
acts and register them only if they conformed to the “basic laws of the prov-
ince” and the “fundamental laws of the state.” Also enumerated in the 1788
declaration w ere the rights of citizens to be summoned only before their
“natural judges” and to see a magistrate immediately a fter their arrest (a
right somewhat akin to habeas corpus).
The parlements w ere extremely successful at curbing royal power, yet by
the time the Revolution took place they w ere greatly discredited. Identified
as bastions of provincialism and manned by jurists many of whom were no-
blemen who had purchased or inherited their offices, the parlements were
criticized and ridiculed rather than admired. The Parlement of Paris was par-
ticularly censured for taking what was considered a conservative stand in
favor of continuity, as embodied, for example, in its demand to call for a
meeting of the Estates General in its old form, which gave the clergy and
nobility (most parlement members belonging to the nobility) an advantage
The French Revolution 199
over the commoners (the Third Estate). The Parlement, in short, was no
longer considered a channel for advancing demands but instead was seen as
a petty institution that mostly protected the interests of its members.
Although parlements were eventually seen as undesirable, the lesson they
taught remained intact. Law was (or could be) a formidable tool to limit the
pretensions to absolutism. Following this lesson, the various revolutionary
factions and individuals who searched for a new social pact sought to iden-
tify legal mechanisms that would curb executive claims to powers. They did
so by instituting a National Assembly with legislative powers, elected by the
people and for the people. Paradoxically, another important lesson they
learned was the failure of the monarchy to win its b attle against the parle-
ments. Judges, contemporaries understood, had tremendous powers to limit
what governments could do. As a result, they must be deprived of any law-
making capacities and transformed into passive implementers of laws decided
upon and perhaps even interpreted elsewhere. On both accounts, these les-
sons indicated the need to clearly separate the powers of the executive, the
legislative, and the judiciary.
by the general will of the French could potentially be valid for other coun-
tries and constituencies. Not only could this law be exported, it must be,
because h uman happiness depended on the expansion of reason and on all
societies obeying it.
The universality of this message would eventually justify the revolutionary
wars as well as Napoleon’s efforts to implement at least some of the revolu-
tionary legislation across Europe, but it was present even in the early years.
Typical in this regard was the 1789 adoption of the Declaration of the Rights
of Man and Citizen. Protecting citizens, that is, members of the French
political community, but also man in general, the declaration created an
instrument that would be relevant both to “we the p eople” (as the represen-
tatives of the Thirteen Colonies had done) and humanity at large. It enumer-
ated rights that w ere general and forward-looking, including the right to
freedom and equality, liberty, property, security, and resistance to oppres-
sion. Also listed were some of the structures of good government, which
were to guarantee t hose rights everywhere.
As happened with the U.S. Bill of Rights, much of what was enumerated
in the French declaration was a direct result of the political confrontations
that unfolded in the 1770s, 1780s, and 1790s. The declaration focused on af-
firming the equality of all men, which for French contemporaries implied
the end of the particular privileges of the nobility and the clergy. Also cen-
tral to the declaration was protection against a royal government that, ac-
cording to contemporary allegations, pretended to be sovereign when it was
not, arrested people without cause, assumed the culpability of enemies, and
constantly changed the punishments that could be inflicted. Safeguarding
freedom of speech, ensuring that the armed forces would be used only to
protect rather than to attack the common good, the demand that all taxa-
tion be authorized by consent, and guaranteeing judicial freedom w ere all
also important.
Although explained by the particularities of the moment, the French dec-
laration pretended to announce principles that were general and timeless,
that is, ahistorical and unchangeable. To ensure its global applicability, the
language used was extremely abstract. It decontextualized rights and discon-
nected them from the particularities of place, time, or legal tradition. The first
article of the declaration, for example, stipulated that man is born free and
should remain free. The second stated that the aim of every political associa-
tion is the maintenance of the natural rights of man, mainly liberty, property,
security, and resistance to oppression. The fourth determined that liberty
The French Revolution 201
consists of being able to do anything that does not harm others. Subsequent
articles declared that laws could forbid only t hose actions that are harmful
to society and that there is a presumption of innocence.
This abstract language reflected the belief that the rights enumerated w ere
indeed common to all men and all societies whatever their particular nature
might be, but it was also a useful tool. The more abstract a description,
the more potentially inclusive and the more open to a variety of interpreta-
tions it was. Returning to the first article, which stated that all men w ere
born free, this abstract language acted as a safety valve of sorts. It allowed
experts writing then and since to ask what was included in the category
“men.” Did it, for example, include women? Did it include children? Were
all men included or only those who w ere reasonable (however reason was
defined)? W ere slaves included? Each author and period gave t hese questions
a distinct solution. In the long run, this abstract language facilitated the ad-
aptation of this declaration to the requirements of a constantly changing
society, in which it was easier to achieve agreement on principles than on
what they meant and how they w ere to be implemented.
A Revolutionary Moment?
In England, the Thirteen Colonies, and France, resistance to monarchy led to
the invocation of an ancient constitution that the monarch was accused of
betraying, and the subsequent affirmation of parliamentary powers. In all
three places, contemporaries claimed to be acting as guardians of both law
and rights. Yet what this law was, and where these rights were located, was
distinct in each case. Rights went from being traditional privileges that w ere
owned by community members b ecause the king so promised (England), to
rational entitlements that should pertain to members but also all h umans ac-
cording to the law of nature (the Thirteen Colonies and France). Law also
changed in the process as it passed from customary and inheritable arrange-
ments (England and the Thirteen Colonies) to new solutions that, seeking to
guarantee the greatest happiness possible, w
ere theoretically based on investi-
gating both nature and society and concluding what was reasonable and what
just (France and to a lesser degree the Thirteen Colonies).
Regardless of these differences, what was most striking about the revolu-
tions that swept England, the Thirteen Colonies, and France was not only
what they achieved but the diverse attitudes that accompanied them. Despite
the enormity of what was proposed, seventeenth-century English actors chose
to present their revolution as a continuity. The representatives of the Thir-
teen Colonies, who also innovated, insisted on the superiority of their partic
The French Revolution 203
ular traditions, which they sought to uphold, while also invoking the dic-
tates of natural law as if both things w
ere one and the same. Disregarding all
continuities between past and present (even when they were noticeable),
most French actors stated that they favored a radical break.
Despite these images, events in England and the Thirteen Colonies were
clearly revolutionary, and in France the aspiration to refound the social pact
and begin a new age was not always obtained. Some measures, such as the
institution of a legislative assembly or the adoption of trial by jury, were truly
revolutionary, yet others w ere much less radical or were only partially imple-
mented. The desire to do away with all the privileges of the nobility and with
all professional guilds, to mention just two cases, did not fully prosper, as
some nobles continued to receive payments due to privileges that w ere feudal
in origin, and some guilds maintained their professional monopolies. Partly
due to the need for political compromise, partly because returning to a blank
slate was impossible, as happened in the English and the American revolutions,
the French Revolution also allowed for both continuity and change.
Although a complete overhaul of the system was never achieved in France,
the legal transformations resulting from the French Revolution w ere never-
theless dramatic. While in England a royal system of courts was refashioned
as the customary law of the land, and in the Thirteen Colonies constitutional
structures w ere radically affected even if law itself was not, in France a legal
system based on ius commune, customs, and royal legislation came to rely
mostly on legislation by the National Assembly. Also in France, a normative
universe dedicated to preserving the status quo was redesigned intention-
ally to introduce change.
As a result of t hese innovations, and independently of where we live, most
of us are to some degree or another heirs to the French Revolution. Devel-
opments in the Thirteen Colonies allowed p eople to imagine the right to
constitute polities and decide on their structure, and they envisioned con-
stitutions as superior laws that limited the sovereignty of Parliament. Mean-
while, developments in France led to the formation of a new type of legal
system, based on the power of legislation created in a representative assembly
by the w ill of the p eople and guided by reason. This system, which produced
what most of us t oday identify as “law,” was nationally bound and was de-
signed to introduce change.
part six
Napoleonic Codification
From as early as 1790, French jurists suggested that because revolutionary
law was theoretically based on reason, it could be easily systematized, al-
lowing for the creation of a single yet holistic legal text that, applied all over
France, would guarantee the reign of liberty, equality, and fraternity. The
ideal text would be clear, concise, and accessible, its comprehension requiring
no expert knowledge or preparation. It would consist of a guidebook that
would be kept in every h ousehold to be used by rational individuals to plan
their activities. The text would also educate citizens as to their rights and
duties.
The hope was to create a code that would be substantially different from
previous codes that were elaborated in Europe in the late eighteenth c entury,
such as the Feudal Code of Venice (1780), the Leopoldine Code of Tuscany
Codifying the Laws of Europe 209
(1786), the various codes elaborated in Austria, and the General Code for
the Prussian States promulgated 1794. While previous codes aimed to com-
pile, simplify, and systemize existing norms, the new code proposed by
French jurists was meant to innovate. It was to introduce a new, complete,
and definitive legal order that would replace all that existed before and that
would be based not on tradition but on the will of the people, as well as on
reason.
Various commissions were appointed to elaborate drafts of such a text,
yet the projects they authored w
ere rejected by the National Assembly, mostly on
the grounds that they were e ither too long and complicated, insufficiently
conceptualized, and overly anchored in past traditions or, on the contrary,
excessively short and vague. It was only after Napoleon ascended to power
that members of a new commission proposed a text that a legislative body
controlled by Napoleon promulgated in 1804 as Le code civil des français,
better known as the Code Napoléon. The text covered private law and in-
cluded 2,281 articles dealing with the law of persons and property.
The Napoleonic Code was not all that it was supposed to be. Although
containing some of the most important innovations introduced by revo-
lutionary legislation, such as equality before the law, protection of private
property, secularization of marriage, legalization of divorce, and freedom of
religion, the code also closely adhered to Old Regime structures in many
other domains. With a mixture of Roman, customary, and revolutionary
law, rather than departing from a clean slate, which was the stated inten-
tion, in practice it was an amalgam of both old and new.
If the code contained many Old Regime norms, it also was not as easy to
read and understand as expected. In order to reproduce all of private law in
a short text, the commission elaborating the code made use of general princi
ples and often adopted extremely abstract language, which diminished
intelligibility and precision. The hope that the code would eliminate depen
dency on lawyers and legally trained judges was thus frustrated. Instead, even
after the promulgation of the code, law continued to be the exclusive domain
of experts who were familiar with legal texts and cognizant of their possible
meanings.
Jean-Étienne Portalis (1746–1807), a member of the drafting committee,
was aware of these shortcomings, as w ere other contemporary jurists and sub-
sequent historians. He seemed convinced that however much one would
try, it would be impossible to produce a code that would cover everything
210 A Short History of European Law
European heritage also shared by Germans? Th ose adhering to the first in-
terpretation were thereafter identified as “Germanists.” Th ose who supported
the second vision were classified as “Romanists.”
Having positioned themselves against Roman law, Germanists proceeded
to discover and reconstruct the so-called authentic, medieval, Germanic
traditions that predated the arrival of Roman law and that, according to
them, were responsible for the emergence of present-day structures.3 Many
Germanists identified t hese older traditions with non-erudite, popular law.
Among t hose participating in this quest to recover customary practices were
the Brothers Grimm. Best known as collectors and publishers of folk tales,
such as Cinderella, Hansel and Gretel, and Snow White, Wilhelm (1786–1859)
and Jacob (1785–1863) Grimm w ere jurists who studied with Savigny. As part
of their interest in rescuing a genuinely German past, they set off to the coun-
tryside to record popular traditions. Their efforts resulted in the famous
collection known as the Tales of the B rothers Grimm, but also in lesser-known
yet extremely important compilations of local legal customs.
While Germanists wished to rescue tradition, Romanists, von Savigny
among them, sought to understand the interaction between German and
Roman law. They studied Roman law in order to understand the concepts and
principles that helped fifteenth-and sixteenth-century German jurists orga
nize and systematize local law. This method, known as the Pandect-Science,
led Romanist jurists to insist that what Roman law did to German law in
the fifteenth c entury could be done again in the nineteenth c entury. By using
Roman law rather than pure logic, jurists could again systematize and orga
nize German law without being unfaithful to it. For German Romanists,
Roman law was not a foreign legal system. Instead it was a repository of
methods and instruments that would enable them to describe the existing
law with precision and consistency. The study of Roman law was thus a means
for constructing a truly German yet rational, modern, and bureaucratic law
that was fit for the demands of the nineteenth c entury.
To understand the meaning of possession, for example, Romanists turned
to Roman remedies that protected it, as well as the defenses that litigants
could invoke. Examining additional sources such as edicts, formulas, legisla-
tion, the opinion of jurists, and the texts of the Corpus Iuris Civilis, Roman-
ists came up with the basic rules for possession, which stated that posses-
sion depended on one’s having control over the t hing as well as having the
intention to hold it as an owner in good faith.
214 A Short History of European Law
nevertheless true that most English and American legal professionals turned
their back on codification. Suggesting that it was both unnecessary and
unwise, or favoring a different type of codification more appropriate to
common-law countries, they engaged in heated debates regarding the ques-
tion w
hether codification was a suitable tool for reforming the law.
decisions or the acts and statutes were more authoritative. Was their power
dependent on their common-law origins (the judicial decision that declared
their existence), their initial enactment by Parliament, or their reenactment
in an act or a codifying statute that now declared them valid?
Eventually lawyers who wanted to understand the law referred most fre-
quently to treatises written by lawyers, judges, and university professors. Be-
ginning with William Blackstone and his Commentaries on the Laws of
England (1765–1769) and continuing with other notable scholars, such as
Frederick Pollock (1945–1937), who authored various treaties on the laws of
contract, partnership, and torts as well as The History of English Law before
the Time of Edward I (1895), English legal experts set out to arrange English
law systematically according to general categories. Describing and, to a de-
gree, rationalizing the law, they enumerated and summarized principles,
listed precedents, and prepared indexes. Dividing writs according to their
subject m
atter (contract, torts, guardianship, as in the case of Pollock), they
often used Roman law principles to describe what the writs instituted.
Although t hese books had no binding force, they became a common, some-
times even authoritative, point of reference that both lawyers and nonlawyers
used, and that judges also followed.
They w ere to replace tradition with new enactments that, even if they re-
produced past solutions (which they often did), would be promulgated by
the nation’s representatives in Parliament because they w ere reasonable.
Thereafter the norms’ validity would depend not on tradition but on their
having been promulgated by an assembly that represented the will of the
people and that was sovereign and could change the law. Codes were sup-
posed to be comprehensive statements of the law and replace all previous
enactments. Using general abstract principles, codes were to be interpreted
according to their logical meaning, not past experience, jurisprudence, or
doctrine. U nder this system, judges theoretically were to exercise absolutely
no discretion. All they could do was implement a law that, by definition,
had a single reasonable interpretation. No general pronouncements creating
new norms were tolerated.
The basic assumption of most English lawyers regarding what law was
and where it came from was radically distinct from what is described above.
By the nineteenth century, most English lawyers believed that the English
legal system was based on common law, which was a customary law that
grew organically within the community. Tied to the particular conditions
of England, it was anchored in experience, not reason. B ecause it naturally
sprang from societal interactions, it was concrete and casuistic rather than
abstract and general, inductive rather than deductive. It consisted of an enu-
meration of cases that reproduced and explained what judges had decided
in the past. L awyers’ task was to compare cases and, highlighting similari-
ties or distinctions, find a fair solution. While judges were central to legal
creation, legislators were not. Although legislators represented “the people,”
their duty was to uphold rather than make the law. They w ere to ensure that
the traditional rights of Englishmen w ere respected, and they could do so
by legislating as long as they did not attempt to innovate. English legal ex-
perts also tended to believe that their system was superior to all o thers
because, legislation was formal and inflexible, whereby a customary law made
by judges allowed for constant updating and better defended the rights and
liberties of individuals. The English system, in short, guaranteed freedom,
which the Continental systems, most particularly the French, did not. Many
Englishmen also rejected association with ideas that could be identified as
French, most particularly those originating in the French Revolution.
These characteristics of common law as understood by nineteenth-century
Eng lish lawyers made recourse to codification extremely difficult. The
222 A Short History of European Law
common law these actors imagined left relatively little room for legislation
and certainly left none for enactments designed to overhaul the existing
order. This common law also made it difficult to formulate abstract and gen-
eral propositions, or to adopt reason rather than experience as a guide. It is
therefore not surprising that some English lawyers concluded that it was
“naïve to think that the common law could be codified without undergoing
a sea change.”2 Common-law lawyers also rejected the claim that codifica-
tion made the law more coherent and more secure. Identifying judges as
the best legal experts, many distrusted Parliament’s ability to reproduce or
create law effectively. Some also claimed that Continental codes were a
failure. Enormous effort was required to elaborate them, but they did not
obtain the desired results. They did not create a truly new system, nor w ere
they particularly easy to use.
Despite such claims, codification did find enthusiasts in England. Mau-
rice Amos was one, but the most famous proponent of codification in
England was Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832). Founder of a school known as
utilitarianism, in his Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation
(1789) Bentham argued that the purpose of society is to produce the greatest
happiness for the greatest number of people. Human beings, he observed, are
moved by natural and rational self-interest. A law such as common law,
based on oral customs and controlled by judges, cannot guarantee this end.
What is required instead is legal security and clarity, and this can be best
achieved by combining empiricism with rational analysis.
Bentham advocated the elaboration of codes that would be promulgated
by the legislature and that would be comprehensive (with no gaps), exclusive
(what was not included would not be part of the law), systematic, and simple.
From as early as the 1810s, Bentham was also engaged in developing a con-
stitutional code that, taking into consideration h uman nature and h uman
reason, would be potentially appropriate to any nation or government.
During the nineteenth century England remained largely immune to
codification, but several codes w
ere nevertheless elaborated in British India.
L ater applied to other Eng lish colonies, these included a code of civil
procedure (1859), a penal code (1860), and code of penal procedure (1861).
Historians have explained that this divergence between metropolitan and
colonial developments—England rejecting codification and India em-
bracing it—made perfect sense. Many English lawyers believed codification
was an extreme remedy in legal systems that were chaotic. This description,
Codifying Common Law 223
Louisiana
General surveys of American codification tend to assume that the adoption
of codes in Louisiana was self-explanatory. Given its French heritage, they
argue, it was only natural that the territory of Orleans (the name Louisiana
had before it became a state) chose to codify its civil laws by elaborating a
Civil Digest (1808). It was equally natural that, after Louisiana became a state
(1812), it enacted a fully fledged Civil Code (1825). These measures expressed
224 A Short History of European Law
local residents’ adhesion to their French colonial past and their rejection of
federal efforts to introduce common law into their territory. This rejection
also found expression in the vote of the Territorial Legislature in 1806 to
maintain the existing legal system, and in the 1812 state constitution, which
denied the Assembly the power to adopt a different legal system.
If allegiance to tradition was one reason for the adoption of codes in Lou-
isiana, another was the allegedly messy legal situation. According to most
scholars, codification was needed in Louisiana b ecause local law was par-
tially French and partially Spanish and most of it was not available in
English translation. Chaotic and incomprehensible (at least to outsiders), it
required a short restatement in codes that would also translate local norms
into English.
Yet to argue that what happened in Louisiana was natural is to under-
mine the importance of what had transpired. The decisions taken by locals
in 1806 (to maintain the previous legal system), 1808 (to adopt a digest), 1812
(to deny the Territorial Legislature the power to adopt a different system),
and 1825 (to adopt a civil code) were more than a stubborn insistence on tra-
dition. They involved conscious and strategic moves allowing local actors
not so much to conserve the existing system as to engage in its reinvention.
These actors intensified rather than gradually abandoned their dependence
on French law, while also progressively sidetracking their Spanish heritage.
How and why this happened remains largely a mystery. In 1806, asked
what their law was, the local authorities identified as their own the Justinian
Corpus Iuris Civilis, the writing of ius commune jurists, and various Spanish
compilations and ordinances. Although they did not mention French law at
all, the Civil Digest proposed in 1808 had elements of both Spanish and
French law and it was arranged according to the Code Napoléon. This de-
parture from strict adherence to Spanish law was noted by some of the judges
who applied the digest. Th ese judges, who tended to interpret it as a mere
restatement of Spanish law, refused to take into account the French elements
that it included. The judges also rejected the idea that the digest would re-
place existing law and felt at liberty to use uncodified Spanish law when it
was convenient or needed.
Continuing dependence on sources other than the digest, most of which
were available only in Spanish, led to the decision to replace the digest by a
code. Yet the code adopted in 1825 was not a simple amplification of the
digest. Instead, although again including elements of both Spanish and
Codifying Common Law 225
French law, the French elements w ere substantially more dominant than
the Spanish. The strong affiliation with French law—in part an invented
tradition—was clear, for example, in article 3521, which stated that, after its
promulgation, all preceding Spanish, Roman, and French law as well as all
legislative enactments adopted by local legislators would be repealed. The
code further mandated that precodification law could not be invoked in the
courts under any circumstances.
Rather than “naturally” following its traditional law, Louisiana therefore
underwent a transformation that made it less Spanish and more French over
time. From this perspective, the Gallicization of Louisiana’s law was as much
a result of its incorporation into the United States as it was of its colonial
past. As a means that locals a dopted to halt the penetration of common law,
there was nothing inevitable about these developments, in which the past as
well as the present, and visions of the f uture, played equal roles.
The Louisiana story is further complicated by the fact that adherence to
Continental law covered only parts of civil law. In other parts, as well as in
criminal, evidentiary, and commercial law, common law reigned without
much contestation. Here as elsewhere, attempts to codify these fields mostly
failed. Despite the success at passing the civil code, the Louisiana legisla-
ture rejected drafts of a penal code and a code of penal procedure. The civil
procedure code adopted in 1823 had elements of both Continental and
common law and, according to some, was interpreted by judges as reflecting
English rather than Continental norms. All t hese developments suggest that
there was more to the Louisiana story than what met the eye.
New York
The New York codification story usually begins in 1846 when state legisla-
tors decided to revise, reform, simplify, and abridge the law. The following
year David Dudley Field was appointed to head the codifying committee.
Field planned five codes for New York: a political code (with rules regarding
government), civil and a criminal procedure codes, and penal and civil codes.
Field, who was said to be inspired by the French experience, hoped to create
codes that would be brief and synthetic and that would eliminate archaic
regulation. Considering both common and statutory law, he also sought to
identify general principles from which all other legal solutions could be
deduced.
226 A Short History of European Law
rowing of the New York codes, assuming rather than verifying that it re-
quired a radical reform. One f actor particularly forgotten was that many of
the states and territories that enacted the New York codes were in the midst
of sometimes heated debates over which legal system they should adopt. Cal-
ifornia, for example, was a former Spanish and Mexican territory; the Da-
kotas, Montana, and Idaho as well as most of the midwestern states, were a
French possession and large parts of their territories w ere u
nder the control
of indigenous tribes that followed their own legal systems. Were their ex-
isting laws so inadequate? Did the bias of common-law lawyers classify them
as such or did locals feel the need for reform? Who exactly decided on this
adoption and why?
In the 1770s the Continental Congress meeting in Philadelphia declared
that the new territories northwest of the Ohio River would be subject to
common law. During the nineteenth century, American authorities who
assumed control over former French, Spanish, or indigenous territories
adopted a similar approach, generally believing that one of their most ur-
gent tasks was to replace the previous legal system(s) with common law. These
officials portrayed replacement as necessary and pressing because, according
to them, all other legal systems (which they now paradoxically classified as
foreign despite being local) were arbitrary to the point that they were not
systems at all. Attempts to introduce legal change, however, often met with
resistance. Research on upper Louisiana (present-day Missouri) has demon-
strated, for example, that residents did not share these pejorative visions of
their law and instead believed their system to be orderly and just.
In California, where a sizable and stable community of Spanish and Mex-
ican residents predated the arrival of Anglo immigrants from the East, many
demanded the continuation of the Spanish legal system. Others debated the
possibility of creating a mixed normative order that would include the English
law of evidence, English commercial law, and English penal law, yet civil
and procedural codes of Spanish and French inspiration. In 1850, nonetheless,
a committee mainly manned by common-law experts recommended the
wholesale adoption of common law.
Similar debates took place at the Congress of the Republic of Texas in
1836. Eventually legislators t here formally a dopted common law for civil
disputes as well as criminal offenses, yet local courts continued to use
the Spanish civil procedure, which they considered a better fit for local
conditions. This practice was formally sanctioned in 1840, when the local
228 A Short History of European Law
legislature declared that the adoption of common law did not include the
common-law system of pleading.
There is no convincing explanation as to why common law succeeded in
replacing previous systems. Neither do we have sufficient knowledge of how
this process took place and how locals reacted. Most historians point to the
prejudice of common-law lawyers turned U.S. officials who assumed that
common law was civilized and all other systems were not. Historians also
mention power relations that favored Anglo immigrants from the East over
established residents, and explain that the Anglos preferred common law
because it allowed them to dispossess natives, w hether indigenous, Spanish,
or French.
The growing hegemony of common law perhaps explains why the New
York codes found reception elsewhere. Rather than curing chaos or civilizing
a defective normative world, the New York codes w ere mostly welcomed in
territories that, having had a different legal tradition (or various traditions),
were now transitioning to common law. Rather than being a remedy, the
codes w ere an instrument for imposing a new law, and rather than being
contradictory to common law in spirit and design—as most assumed codes
were—they were a strategic and useful device by which to impose it.
In 1951, France, West Germany, Italy, the Netherlands, Belgium, and Lux-
embourg formed the European Coal and Steel Community (ECSC). The aim
was to place management of these important natural resources u nder common
control so as to encourage economic growth and interstate collaboration. Five
years later in a series of treaties signed in Rome (1957), the six countries
proceeded to establish the European Atomic Energy Community (Euratom)
and the European Economic Community (EEC; also known as the Common
Market). With a much wider scope than the ECSC, the EEC set some basic
rules that were to facilitate trade relations, such as abolishing tariffs between
the states and setting common trade and agricultural policies.1
These developments w ere focused on economic growth, but the intention
of t hose involved was also to enable greater political u nion. This was the
European response to both the horrors of the Second World War and the
intensification of the Cold War. To facilitate this task, the institutional
structures created in the 1950s for the three organizations (ECSC, Euratom,
and the EEC) were unified in 1967, thereafter forming a single institutional
configuration called the European Community (EC).2 This configuration
was given an executive, a legislature, and a judiciary branch that included a
commission located in Brussels (executive), a parliament that resided in Stras-
bourg and collaborated with a legislative council (of ministers of member
states), and a court of justice, which sat in Luxembourg. The community also
had an assembly (the European Council) that included all heads of member
states, who met regularly to discuss European policies.3
231
232 A Short History of European Law
but they also echo concerns existing elsewhere. Despite these disagreements
and the unknown future that lies ahead, from a legal point of view the for-
mation of the European Union was incredibly important, as it was responsible
for the rebirth of a new common European law, indeed a new, modern ius
commune.
by all member states, as well as legal customs. These are usually interpreted
as including notions such as the rule of law, adherence to public interna-
tional law, and respect for fundamental rights.
Initially granted fairly limited powers, over the years the European Court
of Justice emerged as a principal promoter of European law and European
integration. In what was to become one of its most important decisions,
in 1963 its judges ruled that European law could be directly applicable in
member states’ territories without requiring local reception or reenactment
(Van Gend en Loos v. Nederlandse Administratie Belastingen). In another key
decision dated 1964 (Costa v. ENEL) the court held that European law had
primacy over national law. Thereafter, and acting as a constitutional court
of sorts and exercising a faculty somewhat akin to judicial review, the Euro
pean Court of Justice determined that national laws that were incompatible
with European law could be deemed inapplicable. It instructed all courts of
member states to implement this decision, setting aside any provisions of
national law that conflicted with European rules. The Court of Justice also
guided European institutions and members states on how European law
should be interpreted, adopting, among other things, the rule that national
laws, even t hose preceding the formation of European law, should be inter-
preted as consistent rather than conflicting with European law.
Initially the decisions granting European law immediate applicability in
the territory of member states and a superior position vis-à-vis national law
were greatly criticized. However, over time member states’ national courts
acquiesced and adhered to t hese doctrines. Their acceptance, which was
gradual and is still contested on occasions and is conditional on o thers, truly
revolutionized European law. It allowed European law to become operative
on the national level, and it empowered private litigants to monitor state
compliance with it. Thereafter, European citizens could invoke European
law in their national courts while they litigated with one another and with
organs and institutions of their own state.
National courts’ application of European law eventually became so rou-
tinized and so pronounced that many scholars now argue that every national
court in the Union is also a European court of justice in the sense that it
applies and interprets (and thus also makes) European law. The guardian-
ship of European law by national courts ensures the rule of law within the
European Union and guarantees the subjection of national governments
to their European legal obligations. Yet national courts’ involvement in the
236 A Short History of European Law
confronted actors with diverse agendas and interests. Th ese actors e ither
wished to enhance the institutionalization of Europe and expand its powers,
or wished to halt it. Although all of them might have employed a language
that was politic al, the tools they used were legal. Th
ese tools allowed the
creation of a European legal system that, having originated in international
treaties and statutory law (enacted by the European Parliament and the
Council) and having been mandated among sovereign powers, came to pen-
etrate into national spaces and depend heavily on judge-made law. This
penetration and the judge-made law that enabled it were generated by de-
mands for remedies from European citizens; such demands fuel the work of
European and national courts and allow them both to examine compliance
with European law and to introduce new norms. A mix and match between
Continental and common-law traditions, between international and national
law, the new European order is therefore an odd creature that does not sub-
scribe clearly to a single genealogy or trajectory.
Scholars disagree about why t hese important transformations (from in-
ternational to domestic, and from legislation to judge-made law) happened.
Some suggest that the powers taken on by the European Court of Justice w ere
not foreseen in the original treaties that founded the European Community.
These powers were the outcome of a vision shared by a group of lawyers
working in European institutions and the judges sitting on the European
Court of Justice. Starting in the 1970s t hese individuals intentionally and
energetically supported European integration. Seeking to fill important
voids in the 1957 Treaties of Rome, they invented an efficient mechanism
to force compliance on national governments by recruiting the help of their
citizens.
But even if the European Commission and the European Court of Jus-
tice strategically used judicial review to expand their powers and accelerate
European integration, it is still unclear why national courts collaborated.
A fter all, by adhering to the interpretation of the European Court of Jus-
tice, national courts played an important political and social role in pro-
moting integration.
Many historians suggest that the transformation of European law into a
superior, constitutional-like law was not foretold, but o thers insist that seeds
of these developments were already planted in the founding treaties. Rather
than being forced into this situation, according to this interpretation, national
governments acquiesced to the growing powers of Europe, e ither because
238 A Short History of European Law
be automatically applicable locally. If each country had its own norms, willed
by its p eople, how could a shared European law emerge? If most Continental
countries recognized legislation and codification as exclusive normative
sources, how could judge-made law be enforceable? Was the emergence of
European law the end of the legacy of the French Revolution? And how
should common-law lawyers react to a system that was neither national nor
customary nor based on judge-made law?
Some historians have suggested that the wish for greater collaboration
among the countries joining the Community / Union reminded at least some
Europeans of their common past. It allowed them to point to a period when
many Europeans had shared not only a common law (ius commune) but also
a common religious creed and a belief in the primacy of natural law. If, once
upon a time, a shared ius commune could bring together thousands of dis-
tinct local arrangements by offering overreaching principles, conceptual cat-
egories, methods of analysis, and shared norms, why could the same not
happen now? If a common metaculture allowed Europeans in the past to
perceive themselves as members of a single civilization, why would the case be
different in the present? Cannot a contemporary European juridical science
provide mechanisms to structure a legal system that admits of both diver-
gence and convergence?
While many scholars have sought to discover, under what some have
identified as the bewildering and idiosyncratic mass of casuistry and deeply
entrenched legal nationalism, the common legal foundation of Europe, others
have concentrated on the present. They argue that despite divergent histo-
ries, constitutional arrangements, and legal technologies, most Europeans are
now in basic agreement regarding the most essential values and goals. This
agreement, which mainly operates on the philosophical level, nevertheless has
significant legal consequences b ecause substantial coincidence exists among
specific solutions that the diverse European countries have given to similar
questions. Driven also by economic considerations, the gradual unification
of law across Europe took place long before the formal political and economic
project of commonness was proposed. B ecause differences in needs and de-
sires w
ere becoming smaller across Europe, the laws of the different European
countries progressively and naturally converged despite the preeminence of
national legislation.
Thus, while the European Court of Justice was busy naming and recog-
nizing the general principles of European law, European scholars sought to
240 A Short History of European Law
identify the basic legal tenets that most European countries shared. Most
famous among these attempts was the draft of a Common Frame of Refer-
ence (DCFR) by a committee appointed by the European Commission. The
committee was charged with identifying as well as sometimes creating a
framework of common rules that European and national legislators, courts,
and individuals could adopt in legislation, interpretation, or commercial
activity. The committee’s work gradually covered areas such as marketing
relations, service contracts, sales law, lease of goods, unjustified enrichment,
and transfer of property. Somewhat similarly, the Common Core of Euro
pean Private Law project, established in 1993 at the University of Trent (Italy),
aimed to identify commonalities in member states’ private law, including
contracts, torts, and property. Participants in the projects described their
quest as “a promising hunt for analogies hidden by formal differences” linked
to no political agenda and seeking no particular outcome.10
Although many of t hese efforts at harmonization w ere encouraged or even
supported by the institutions of the European Union and by various member
states, attempts to elaborate a common European civil code, which in 1989
the European Parliament declared was desirable, have thus far failed. Those
who lament this failure believe the code is necessary because it would en-
hance collaboration and integration across Europe. For t hose who criticized
the efforts at enacting a code, it was preferable to allow for legal convergence
to happen gradually and naturally rather than to impose it through legis-
lation. A few point out that even if legislation were the correct vehicle to
introduce changes, it is unclear whether codification is preferable to a re-
statement. Some suggest that the best way to achieve conversion would be
through the creation of a new European common legal science, not additional
European legislation. Arguing that the making of rules should be transparent
and as apolitical as possible, yet another group seeks to identify procedures
that would guarantee that the new European civil code, if enacted, would
focus on obtaining a greater social good. Finally, some scholars question the
constitutionality of a European civil code altogether, arguing that the Euro
pean Community lacks competence to move in this direction.
Even though many European jurists believe in the inevitability of either
a natural or an imposed convergence, o thers affirm that even in cases in
which specific solutions are deemed comparable, it is vital to remember that
multiple legal systems operate in Europe. Particularly important in this
regard is the distinction between Continental Europe, which followed ius
Epilogue 241
commune, and E ngland, which had its own common law. The distinction
between these two systems, it has been argued, is truly insurmountable.
Legal epistemologies m atter more than the specific solutions that each of
these systems adopted. On the epistemological level, Continental and English
law are recognizably distinct, with different approaches to what law is, who
made it, and how it could change. Whereas Continental systems focus on
reason, common law is anchored in experience; whereas Continental systems
give primacy to legislation, common law prefers judge-made law.
To such claims, those favoring integration respond by arguing that the
stark differences between Continental and common law are mostly fictional.
Theoretically, Continental law might restrict judges, forcing them to follow
the letter of the law while ignoring all other possible inputs from doctrine
or jurisprudence. Yet, in practice, Continental judges have huge discretion
in their interpretation of the law; they often incorporate doctrinal assess-
ments and precedents into their thinking and hand down decisions that
change rather than interpret the law. Similarly, theoretically common law
might allow judges to innovate, yet in practice it now relies heavily on par-
liamentary legislation as well as precedent. Furthermore, some areas of
Continental law, such as administrative law, depend greatly on judge-made
law. Meanwhile, some areas of common law, such as criminal law, are based
on legislation.
Insisting that theoretical distinctions should not be taken too seriously,
that they are stereotypes rather than reflections of reality, and that these
distinctions mainly reproduce ideological positions, not empirical analysis,
these jurists also point out that there are important ways in which both
systems have been gradually converging even conceptually, evolving into a
middle ground. This convergence has abolished (or at least minimized) many
of the differences between the Continental and the English systems, not only
on the level of concrete solutions (which are often identical) but also with
regard to how they view legislation and judge-made law, now seen in both
systems as complementary rather than opposites. Indeed, the best proof for
such a peaceful coexistence is European law itself. Rather than working
against one another, in the case of European law, these distinct normative
sources (legislation and judge-made law) together have created a new order
that is neither Continental nor English, neither traditional nor completely
modern, but instead constantly reinventing itself as it adapts to new circum-
stances, conditions, and constraints.
242 A Short History of European Law
1. Roman Law
1. Goethe was said to have referred to the “enduring life of Roman law, which,
like a diving duck, hides itself from time to time, but is never quite lost, al-
ways coming up again alive.” Johann Wolfgang von Goethe, Conversations of
Goethe with Eckermann and Soret, trans. John Oxenford, 389–390 (London:
George Bell, 1875), conversation that took place on April 6, 1829.
2. Historians of Roman law have long disagreed w hether pontifices only gave
authoritative responses regarding the law that other officials implemented or
whether they also applied it as judges. Some have suggested a compromise
that made the pontifices sometimes legal experts, sometime judges, depending
on the case.
3. While this is the standard narrative, some historians have asked w hether this
portrayal is accurate or w hether it was largely invented by later Romans on
whose testimonies we depend to reconstruct what transpired during the ar-
chaic period.
4. Initially there were only two praetors, but their number grew over time. Rather
than being members of an institution, each praetor worked independently.
Eventually praetors were also nominated in Roman settlements outside
Rome, such as Sicily and Hispania. Praetors were identified as “urban” a fter
the introduction in 242 bce of a new type of praetor (praetor peregrinus) who
oversaw cases involving non-Roman citizens.
5. Historians disagree as to when and why the division of the process into two
parts took place. They point out that references to iudex already existed in
245
246 Notes to Pages 18–39
the Twelve Tables, though it is unclear that the work of this individual was
necessarily preceded by the work of an official similar to the praetor.
6. On the status of foreigners under Roman law, see below.
7. Papinian was a famous jurist who was also an imperial official. Among his
most celebrated works are thirty-seven books of questions (Quaestiones) and
nineteen books of responsa, as well as several treatises.
8. This was the definition of jurisprudence in the Institute, the second-century
ce manual for students authored by Gaius. It was reproduced in the Justinian
so-called sixth-century Corpus Iuris Civilis.
9. Roman provincial governors, who oversaw conflicts in the provinces between
Romans and non-Romans, also participated in the elaboration of ius gentium.
10. This name was given in the sixteenth century to the three books described below,
and often also to the Novellae, a fourth book including new imperial legisla-
tion. Though widely known as such, this title is nevertheless anachronistic.
11. Because the Digest included excerpts, historians often warn against trusting
it too much. The excerpts did not clarify the context in which the opinion
was given, and they w ere often fragmentary. Scholars of Roman law also sug-
gest that the opinions included dated from different periods and that the
Digest deliberately underrepresented disagreement among them.
12. As w ill be explained in Chapter 5, not all of the so-called Corpus Iuris Civilis
survived, forcing jurists to endeavor to reconstruct it from a multiplicity of
fragments. As for the validity of the Corpus in the Eastern empire, historians
have asserted that its diffusion there was also somewhat limited and that in
many places it did not in practice replace the preexisting local law.
1. Christianity also expanded in the Hellenistic east. Although it is not the main
subject of this book, which follows only Latin Christendom, what happened
in the East w ill be briefly mentioned at the end of the chapter.
2. Christianity would eventually be open not only to the Israelites but also to
all others willing to enter the covenant. This development is usually attrib-
uted to the teaching of Paul, one of the apostles.
3. The Council of Carthage selected the twenty-seven books that would make
the New Testament alongside the forty-six books of the Old Testament. This
selection was confirmed by the Council of Trent (1545–1563), which redefined
Christian dogma in the wake of the Protestant Reformation.
4. This was the original definition of what Catholicism meant before the Prot-
estant Reformation. By calling the Church “Catholic” (that is, universal), it
adopted the convention that there was only one belief within the Church.
Notes to Pages 41–75 247
1. This period was characterized as “an age with no jurists” by Manlio Bellomo
in his The Common Legal Past of Europe, 1000–1800 (Washington, DC: Cath-
olic University of America Press, 1995), 34.
2. See Chapter 5.
3. See Chapter 4.
4. Although the abandonment of ordeal seemed to have greatly influenced the
use of juries in criminal cases, its effect on civil cases is unclear.
1. Ius commune was a term originally used to designate the parts of canon law
that w
ere common to all Christians. However, it eventually referred to the
248 Notes to Pages 77–94
combination of Roman, feudal, and canon law that controlled European law
from the twelfth to the nineteenth centuries (if not beyond).
2. See Chapter 1.
3. This task of reconstructing the Corpus has usually been associated with one
person (Irnerius), one city (Bologna), and one period (the second half of the
eleventh century). This image, however, is somewhat misleading, as we know
that more than a single person in a single location was involved. Some scholars
have even expressed doubts whether Irnerius himself was part of this enter-
prise, or only his students.
4. I refer here to what would later be known as the noblesse de robe, the nobility
of those wearing the clothes (robes) associated with a law degree, as distin-
guished from the noblesse d’ épée (sword), which was based on descent and
(theoretically) military achievements.
5. Rogerius, “Questions on the Institutes,” in University of Chicago Readings in
Western Civilization, vol. 4: Medieval Europe, ed. Julius Kirshner and Karl F.
Morrison (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1986), 215–218. According to
some, this text was not gloss proper but instead a questio, that is, a different
form of juristic engagement that sought to answer a particular question.
6. We know very little about Gratian and his work. Historians currently debate
whether he authored the entire compilation or only part of it. They all agree,
however, that even if he was the author, he did not do this work alone, and
that he also heavily relied on compilations proposed by previous scholars.
7. The Corpus Iuris Canonici was the body of Church law that, to a large de-
gree, was followed u ntil 1917.
8. See Chapter 3.
9. Directum was the antecedent of the Italian diritto, the French droit, the Spanish
derecho, and the Portuguese direito. It also gave birth to the idea of the right
(versus the wrong) direction or simply of being correct.
10. Historians usually count among the present-day European countries that w ere
affected by ius commune Italy, France, Spain, Portugal, Germany, Belgium,
The Netherlands, Switzerland, Iceland, Slovakia, the Czech Republic, Hun-
gary, Austria, Romania, Poland, Denmark, Norway, and Sweden. Most also
include England, at least to some degree: see Chapter 6.
11. This was what the Ordenamiento de Alcalá (1348) and the Leyes de Toro (1505)
attempted to do.
16. Charles Donahue, “Ius Commune, Canon law, and Common Law in
England,” Tulane Law Review 66 (1991–1992): 1745–1780, at 1748.
1. Fifth-century St. Vincent of Lérins is credited for having coined this fiction.
This was the original meaning of Catholicism before the Protestant Refor-
mation, when this term became associated instead with the part of the Church
that remained under papal authority in order to distinguish it from the other
part that did not.
2. Paradoxically, the school began in Italy and its first proponent (Andreas
Alciatus) was Italian, but many of its adherents (such as Guillaume Budé,
Jacques Cujas, and François Hotman) were French and its most important
centers of creation (Orleans and Bourges) w ere in France.
3. The Dutch method of law (usus modernus Pandectarum) might have combined
mos gallicus and mos italicus. This method was mostly a product of the seven-
teenth and eighteenth centuries and was geared t oward finding practical so-
lutions to everyday situations. Its practitioners were willing to generalize and
draw principles as Italian scholars did, yet they cared about the historical evo-
lution of law and admitted the omnipresence of contradictions between dif
ferent solutions, as French legal humanists did.
1. See Chapter 6.
2. William Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of E ngland (Oxford: Clar-
endon Press, 1765–1769), introduction, third section, 65.
3. Mark Kishlansky, A Monarchy Transformed: Britain, 1603–1714 (London: Pen-
guin, 1996), 37.
4. Glanvil was said to have authored the Tractatus de legibus e consuetudinibus
regni Angliae (ca.1187–1189) while Bracton was said to have authored De leg-
ibus et consuetudinibus Angliae (ca. 1220s–1250s). Both books are considered
the most important early essays describing common law (see Chapter 6).
5. Among such authors were John Fortecue, Christopher St. German, Anthony
Fitzherbert, and Robert Brooke.
6. John David in his Iris Reports (1613), as cited in Alan Cromartie, “The Idea of
Common Law as Custom,” in The Nature of Customary Law, ed. Amanda
Perreu-Saussine and James Bernard Murphy (Cambridge: Cambridge Uni-
versity Press, 2007), 203–227 at 214.
Notes to Pages 149–176 251
7. Only in the twentieth century did judges clearly affirm that the prominence
of legislation limited their activities b ecause they could not apply or develop
the common law in ways that were inconsistent with the law as laid down in
statutes (acts of Parliament).
8. See Chapter 6.
1. This was an indirect reference to the historical process identified as the “Re-
conquest” (reconquista). It suggested that from the eleventh to the fifteenth
century, the Christian kingdoms of Iberia fought Muslim occupiers in
order to reconstitute the political structures that existed before the Muslims
invaded the peninsula in 711. This ideological reading of the past, however,
has been discredited by most historians, who no longer present the Muslims
as invaders nor the Christians as pursuing a religious agenda meant at
recuperation.
2. This was not the only possible conclusion. Michel de Montaigne (1533–1592), for
example, suggested that what was natural for some, might not be natural for
others. He expressed these views in his famous essay On Cannibals (ca. 1577),
which appeared as chapter 30 in his book of essays, available in multiple editions
and also online at https://w ww.gutenberg.org/files/3600/3600-h/3600-h.htm.
3. Tamar Herzog, Defining Nations: Immigrants and Citizens in Early Modern
Spain and Spanish America (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2003).
1. The states that added a Bill of Rights to their constitutions w ere Virginia,
Pennsylvania, Maryland, Delaware, North Carolina, Vermont, Massachu
setts, and New Hampshire. Other states, though not including a separate
Bill of Rights, did mention or enumerate rights in their constitutions.
2. The following citations are from the Declaration of Independence.
3. Preamble to the Constitution of the United States.
4. “The enumeration in the Constitution, of certain rights, s hall not be construed
to deny or disparage others retained by the people.”
5. William Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of E ngland (Oxford: John
Hatchard and Son, 1822 [1765–1769]), 105.
6. Historians currently debate whether these clauses in colonial charters gave
colonists rights overseas or only bestowed on them the right to be treated as
subjects if and when they returned to E ngland.
252 Notes to Pages 178–213
1. Preamble of the 1789 French Declaration of the Rights of Man and Citizen.
2. As mentioned in Chapter 10, natural law was uncodified. It was a notion that
many philosophers, jurists, theologians, and other intellectuals accepted, but
they disagreed on what it included. Rather than an enumeration of norms or
a system of specific solutions, natural law was a frame of reference.
3. “It is said that there are 144 customs in France that have the power of law:
these laws are almost all different. A man who travels in this country changes
law almost as many times as he changes h orses.” Voltaire, “Courtisans let-
trés: Coutoumes,” in Oeuvres complètes de Voltaire, vol. 7: Dictionnaire phi-
losophique I (Paris: Chez Furne, 1835).
4. The French Civil Code, art. 544. On the French civil code, see Chapter 12.
5. Title 3, art. 1.
6. Only in 1958 would the French state introduce a version of judicial review that
allowed the magistrates of a special body (Conseil Constitutionnel) to review
the constitutionality of laws prior to their promulgation. In 2010 t hese ar-
rangements were extended to allow litigants to invoke unconstitutionality
during ordinary proceedings at the court, which would suspend its delibera-
tions and send the constitutional issue to the Conseil for its decision.
4. Before the BGB, as many as thirty diverse legal systems might have operated
in Germanic territories, using at least three legal languages (Latin, German,
and French). Some regions followed local codes, o thers were under French
control u
ntil 1871 and thus followed the French Civil Code, and yet o thers
observed Roman, canon, or customary law.
5. The countries that were said to have been influenced by the BGB included
Greece, Austria, Switzerland, Portugal, Italy, the Netherlands, the former
Czechoslovak ia, the former Yugoslavia, Hungary, Estonia, Latvia, Ukraine,
Japan, Brazil, Mexico, Peru, Taiwan, South K orea, Thailand, and, for a while,
China.
6. See Chapter 1, note 1.
1. Maurice Amos, “The Code Napoleon and the Modern World,” Journal of Com-
parative Legislation and International Law 10, no. 4 (1928): 222–236, at 222.
2. H. R. Hahlo, “Codifying the Common Law: Protracted Gestation,” Modern
Law Review 38, no. 1 (1975): 23–30, at 23.
3. These states and territories included California, Iowa, Minnesota, Indiana,
Ohio, Washington Territory, Nebraska, Wisconsin, Kansas, Nevada, Dakotas,
Idaho, Arizona, Montana, North Carolina, Wyoming, South Carolina, Utah,
Colorado, Oklahoma, and New Mexico.
Epilogue
1. The 1950s also featured failed attempts to create a European Defense Com-
munity (EDC) and a European Political Community (EPC).
2. The treaty that instituted this single structure, known as the Merger Treaty,
was signed in Brussels in 1965 but came into effect in 1967. Because the treaty
merged three entities (the ECSC, the EEC, and Euratom), the more appro-
priate name for the new structure was “European Communities” in plural. Yet
most people referred to this complex structure as the European Community
(in singular).
3. From its initiation, the European Community had two councils. One, the
Council of the European Community (later, of the European Union) is a
meeting of the national ministers of member states. In this forum, ministers
vote on legislation proposed by the European Commission on matters related
to their particu lar ministry. For example, the Agricultural and Fisheries
Council is the meeting of the ministers of agriculture and it votes on legisla-
tion on matters of agriculture; the Foreign Affairs Council unites the national
254 Notes to Pages 232–240
Introduction
Ecklund, John E. The Origins of Western Law from Athens to the Code of
Napoleon. Clark, NJ: Talbot, 2014.
Grossi, Paolo. A History of European Law. Translated by Laurence Hooper.
Chichester, UK: Wiley-Blackwell, 2010.
Hespanha, Antonio Manuel. A cultura jurídica europeia: Síntese de un milénio.
Coimbra, Portugal: Almedina, 2012.
Kelly, J. M. A Short History of Western Legal Theory. New York: Oxford Univer-
sity Press, 1992.
Lesaffer, Randall. European Legal History: A Cultural and Political Perspective.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009.
Merryman, John Henry. The Civil Law Tradition: An Introduction to the Legal
Systems of Europe and Latin America. 3rd ed. Stanford, CA: Stanford
University Press, 2007.
Mousourakis, George. Roman Law and the Origins of the Civil Law Tradition.
Cham, Switzerland: Springer, 2015.
Robinson, O. F., T. D. Fergus, and V. M. Gordon. Eur opean L egal
History: Sources and Institutions. 2nd ed. London: Butterworths,
1994.
Schioppa, Antonio Padoa. Storia del diritto in Europa: Dal medioevo all’età
contemporanea. Bologna: Il Mulino, 2007.
Van Caenegem, R. C. An Historical Introduction to Private Law. Translated by
D. E. L Johnston. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992.
255
256 Further Reading
Chapter 1
Ando, Clifford. Law, Language, and Empire in the Roman Tradition. Philadel-
phia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 2011.
Blume, Fred H., trans. “Annotated Justinian Code.” University of Wyoming
George W. Hopper Law Library. http://uwyo.edu/lawlib/blume-justinian.
Crawford, M. H., ed. Roman Statutes. London: Institute of Classical Studies, 1996.
Crook, John Anthony. Law and Life of Rome. London: Thames and Hudson,
1967.
du Plessis, Paul J. Studying Roman Law. London: Bristol Classical Press, 2012.
du Plessis, Paul J., Clifford Ando, and G. Tuori, eds. The Oxford Handbook of
Roman Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016.
Frier, Bruce W. The Rise of the Roman Jurists: Studies in Cicero’s Pro Caecina.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1985.
Frier, Bruce W., ed., and Fred H. Blume, trans. The Codex of Justinian: A New
Annotated Translation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2016.
Gordon, W. M., and O. F. Robinson, trans. The Institutes of Gaius. Ithaca, NY:
Cornell University Press, 1988.
Honoré, Tony. Justinian’s Digest: Character and Compilation. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2010.
Johnston, David. The Cambridge Companion to Roman Law. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2015.
———. Roman Law in Context. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999.
Jolowicz, H. F., and Barry Nicholas. Historical Introduction to the Study of
Roman Law. 3rd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1972.
Krueger, Paul. Justinian’s Institutes. Translated by Peter Birks and Grant
McLeod. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1987.
Krueger, Paul, Theodor Mommsen, Rudolf Schoell, and Wilhelm Kroll, eds.
Corpus Iuris Civilis. 3 vols. Berlin: Weidmann, 1928.
Kunkel, Wolfgang. An Introduction to Roman L egal and Constitutional History.
Translated by J. M. Kelly. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1966.
Lambiris, Michael. The Historical Context of Roman Law. North Ryde, Aus-
tralia: LBC Information Services, 1997.
Metzger, Ernest. Litigation in Roman Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2005.
———. “An Outline of Roman Civil Procedure.” Roman Legal Tradition 9
(2013): 1–30.
Mousourakis, George. Roman Law and the Origins of the Civil Law Tradition.
Cham, Switzerland: Springer, 2015.
Further Reading 257
Chapter 2
Ando, Clifford. The M atter of the Gods: Religion and the Roman Empire. Berkeley:
University of California Press, 2009.
Bartlett, Robert. The Making of Europe: Conquest, Colonization and Cultural
Change, 950–1350. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993.
Biondi, Biondo. Il diritto romano cristiano. 3 vols. Milan: Giuffrè, 1952–1954.
Brown, Peter. The Rise of Western Christendom: Triumph and Diversity, A.D.
200–1000. Cambridge, MA: Wiley-Blackwell, 1995.
Fletcher, Richard. The Conversion of Europe: From Paganism to Christianity,
371–1386 AD. London: HarperCollins, 1997.
Freeman, Charles. A New History of Early Christianity. New Haven, CT: Yale
University Press, 2009.
Grubbs, Judith Evans. Law and F amily in Late Antiquity: The Emperor Constan-
tine’s Marriage Legislation. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995.
Heather, Peter. Empires and Barbarians: The Fall of Rome and the Birth of
Europe. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010.
Humfress, Caroline. Orthodoxy and the Courts in Late Antiquity. Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2007.
258 Further Reading
Lenski, Noel. “Constantine and Slavery: Libertas and the Fusion of Roman and
Christian Values.” Atti dell’Accademia Romanistica Costantiniana 18 (2012):
235–260.
MacCormack, Sabine. “Sin, Citizenship, and Salvation of the Souls: The Impact
of Christian Priorities on Late-Roman and Post-Roman Society.” Compara-
tive Studies in Society and History 39, no. 4 (1997): 644–673.
MacMullen, Ramsay. “What Difference Did Christianity Make?” Historia:
Zeitschrift für Alte Geschichte 35, no. 3 (1986): 322–343.
Salzman, Michele Renee. “The Evidence for the Conversion of the Roman Empire
to Christianity in Book 16 of the ‘Theodosian Code.’ ” Historia: Zeitschrift
für Alte Geschichte 42, no. 3 (1993): 362–378.
Thompson, John A. F. The Western Church in the Middle Ages. London: Arnold,
1998.
Vuolanto, Ville. “Children and the Memory of Parents in the Late Roman
World.” In Children, Memory, and Family Identity in Roman Culture, edited by
Véronique Dasen and Thomas Späth, 173–192. Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2010.
Chapter 3
Chapter 4
Berman, Harold J. Law and Revolution: The Formation of the Western L egal
Tradition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1983.
Bisson, Thomas N. The Crisis of the Twelfth Century: Power, Lordship, and the
Origins of European Government. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press,
2009.
Bloch, Marc. Feudal Society. Translated by L. A. Manyon. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 1961.
Blumenthal, Uta-Renate. The Investiture Controversy: Church and Monarchy
from the Ninth to the Twelfth Century. Philadelphia: University of Pennsyl-
vania Press, 1988.
260 Further Reading
Chapter 5
Ascheri, Mario. The Laws of Late Medieval Italy (1000–1500): Foundations for a
European Legal System. Leiden: Brill, 2013.
Bartolus de Saxoferrato. Tractatus Tyberiadis seu de fluminibus, bks. 1–3: De
alluvione, de insula, de alveo; Tractatus de insigniis et armis. Turin: Bottega
d’Erasmo, 1964. Available in abbreviated form at http://lafogonera.blogspot
.com.es/2007/11/de-insula-brtolo-de-sassoferrato-1313.html.
Bellomo, Manlio. The Common L egal Past of Europe, 1000–1800. Washington,
DC: Catholic University of America Press, 1995.
Brundage, James A. Medieval Canon Law. London: Longman, 1995.
Cairns, John W., and Paul J. du Plessis, eds. The Creation of the Ius Commune:
From Casus to Regula. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2010.
Further Reading 261
Scott, Samuel Parsons, trans., and Robert I. Burns, ed. Las Siete Partidas.
Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 2001.
Vinogradoff, Paul. Roman Law in Medieval Europe. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1929.
Winroth, Anders. The Making of Gratian’s Decretum. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2000.
Chapter 6
Liebermann, Felix, ed. Die Gesetze der Angelsachsen. 4 vols. Halle, Germany:
Max Niemeyer, 1903–1916.
McSweeney, Thomas. “English Judges and Roman Jurists: The Civilian
Learning b ehind England’s First Case Law.” Temple Law Review 84, no. 4
(2012): 827–862.
Milsom, S. F. C. Historical Foundations of the Common Law. 2nd ed. London:
Butterworths, 1981.
Musson, Anthony. Medieval Law in Context: The Growth of L egal Consciousness
from Magna Carta to the Peasant’s Revolt. Manchester, UK: Manchester
University Press, 2001.
Plucknett, Theodore F. T. A Concise History of the Common Law. 5th ed. Boston:
Little, Brown and Co., 1956.
———. Statutes and Their Interpretation in the First Half of the Fourteenth
Century. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1922.
Pollock, Frederick. Oxford Lectures and Other Discourses. London: Macmillan,
1890.
Pollock, Frederick, and Frederic William Maitland. The History of English Law
before the Time of Edward I. 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1899.
Price, Polly J. “Natural Law and Birthright Citizenship in Calvin’s Case (1608).”
Yale Journal of Law & the Humanities 9, no. 1 (1997): 73–145.
Richardson, H. G., and G. O. Sayles. Law and Legislation from Aethelberht to
Magna Carta. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1966.
Seipp, David J. “Jurors, Evidences, and the Tempest of 1499.” In “The Dearest
Birthright of the P eople of E ngland”: The Jury in the History of the Common
Law, edited by John W. Cairns and Grant McLeod, 75–92. Oxford: Hart,
2002.
———, comp. “Medieval English Legal History: An Index and Paraphrase of
Printed Year Book Reports, 1268–1535.” http://w ww.bu.edu/law/faculty
-scholarship/legal-history-the-year-books.
———. “The Reception of Canon Law and Civil Law in the Common Law
Courts before 1600.” Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 13, no. 3 (1993):
388–420.
Stanojevic, Obrad. “Roman Law and Common Law: A Different Point of
View.” Loyola Law Review 36, no. 2 (1990): 269–274.
Van Caenegem, R. C. The Birth of English Common Law. Cambridge: Cam-
bridge University Press, 1973.
Watson, Alan. “Roman Law and English Law: Two Patterns of Legal Develop-
ment.” Loyola Law Review 36, no. 2 (1990): 247–268.
Further Reading 265
Wormald, Patrick. The Making of English Law: King Alfred to the Twelfth
Century. Oxford: Blackwell, 1999.
Chapter 7
Chapter 8
Lewis, Andrew. “ ‘What Marcellus Says Is Against You’: Roman Law and
Common Law.” In The Roman Law Tradition, edited by A. D. E. Lewis and
D. J. Ibbetson, 199–208. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994.
“The Magna Carta Project.” http://magnacartaresearch.org.
Maitland, Frederic William. English Law and the Renaissance (The Rede Lecture
for 1901). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1901.
———. Select Pleas in the Manorial and Other Seigniorial Courts. London: B.
Quaritch, 1889.
“Petition of Rights.” Reproduced in The Roots of the Bill of Rights, 5 vols.,
compiled by Bernard Schwartz, 1:19–21. New York: Chelsea House, 1971.
Pocock, J. G. A. The Ancient Constitution and the Feudal Law: English Historical
Thought in the Seventeenth Century. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1957.
Rodgers, C. P. “Humanism, History and the Common Law.” Journal of L egal
History 6, no. 2 (1985): 129–156.
Sherman, Charles P. “A Brief History of Medieval Roman Canon Law in
England.” University of Pennsylvania Law Review and American Law Register
68, no. 2 (1920): 233–258.
Smith, David Chan. Sir Edward Coke and the Reformation of the Laws: Religion,
Politics and Jurisprudence, 1578–1616. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2014.
Tubbs, J. W. The Common Law Mind: Medieval and Early Modern Conceptions.
Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2000.
Williams, Ian. “ ‘He Creditted More the Printed Booke’: Common L awyer’s
Receptivity to Print, c. 1500–1640.” Law and History Review 28, no. 1 (2010):
39–70.
———. “The Tudor Genesis of Edward Coke’s Immemorial Common Law.”
Sixteenth Century Journal 43, no. 1 (2012): 103–123.
Wood, Andy. The Memory of the P eople: Custom and Popular Senses of the Past in
Early Modern England. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013.
Wormald, Patrick. The Making of English Law: King Alfred to the Twelfth
Century. Oxford: Blackwell, 1999.
Chapter 9
Arneil, Barbara. John Locke and America: The Defense of English Colonialism.
Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996.
Brett, Annabel S. Changes of State: Nature and the Limits of the City in Early
Modern Natural Law. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2011.
268 Further Reading
The Bull Inter Caetera. Reproduced in Sources Relating to the History of the Law
of Nations, 3 vols., edited by Wilhelm G. Grewe, 2:68–70. Berlin: De
Gruyter, 1988.
Cavallar, Georg. “Vitoria, Grotius, Pufendorf, Wolff and Vattel: Accomplices of
European Colonialism and Exploitation or True Cosmopolitans,” Journal of
the History of International Law 10, no. 2 (2008): 181–209.
Daston, Lorraine, and Michael Stolleis, eds. Natural Law and Laws of Nature in
Early Modern Europe: Jurisprudence, Theology, Moral and Natural Philosophy.
Farnham, UK: Ashgate, 2008.
d’Entrèves, A. P. Natural Law: An Introduction to Legal Philosophy. London:
Hutchinson and Co., 1951.
Fitzmaurice, Andrew. Sovereignty, Property and Empire, 1500–2000. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2014.
Grotius, Hugo. The Freedom of the Seas or the Right Which Belongs to the Dutch
to Take Part in the East Indian Trade, 1609. Translated by Ralph van Deman
Magoffin and edited by James Scott Brown. New York: Oxford University
Press, 1916.
———. On the Law of War and Peace, 1625. Translated by A. C. Campbell.
London: Boothroyd, 1814.
Herzog, Tamar. Defining Nations: Immigrants and Citizens in Early Modern
Spain and Spanish America. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2003.
———. “Did European Law Turn American? Territory, Property and Rights in
an Atlantic World.” In New Horizons in Spanish Colonial Law: Contribu-
tions to Transnational Early Modern Legal History, edited by Thomas Duve
and Heikki Pihlajamäki, 75–95. Frankfurt: Max Planck Institute for
European Legal History, 2015.
Kingsbury, Benedict, and Benjamin Straumann, eds. The Roman Foundations of
the Law of Nations: Alberico Gentili and the Justice of Empire. Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2010.
Locke, John. Two Treatises of Government. London: Awnsham Churchill,
1698.
MacMillan, Ken. Sovereignty and Possession in the English New World: The Legal
Foundations of Empire, 1576–1640. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2006.
Marcoci, Giuseppe. L’ invenzione di un imperio: Politica e cultura nel mondo
portoghese (1450–1600). Rome: Caroci Editore, 2011.
Pagden, Anthony. The Burdens of Empire: 1539 to the Present. New York:
Cambridge University Press, 2015.
Parry, J. H. The Age of Reconnaissance. Cleveland: World Publishing Co., 1963.
Further Reading 269
Pufendorf, Samuel von. Of the Law of Nature and Nations. 2nd ed. Translated
by Basil Kennett and William Percivale. Oxford: Printed by L. Lichfield for
A. and J. Churchil, 1710.
The Requirement. Reproduced in Fontes Historiae Iuris Gentium: Quellen
zur Geschichte des Völkerrechts / Sources Relating to the History of the Law
of Nations, 3 vols., edited by Wilhelm G. Grewe, 2:103–109. Berlin: De
Gruyter, 1988.
Rommen, Heinrich A. The Natural Law: A Study in Legal and Social History and
Philosophy, 1936. Translated by Thomas R. Hanley. Indianapolis: Liberty
Fund, 1998.
Tuck, Richard. Natural Rights Theories: Their Origin and Development. Cam-
bridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979.
Tully, James. A Discourse on Property: John Locke and His Adversaries. Cam-
bridge: Cambridge University Press, 1980.
Vattel, Emer de. The Law of Nations or the Principles of Natural Law Applied to
the Conduct and to the Affairs of Nations and of Sovereigns, 1758. Translated
by Charles G. Fenwick. Washington, DC: Carnegie Institute of Wash-
ington, 1916.
Vitoria, Francisco de. Political Writings. Edited by Anthony Pagden and Jeremy
Lawrance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991.
Chapter 10
Chapter 11
Hancock, Ralph C., and L. Gary Lambert, eds. The Legacy of the French
Revolution. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1996.
Hardman, John, ed. The French Revolution Sourcebook. London: Arnold, 1999.
Hulsebosch, Daniel, J. “The Revolutionary Portfolio: Constitution-Making and
the Wider World in the American Revolution.” Suffolk University Law
Review 47 (2014): 759–822.
Hunt, Lynn, ed. and trans. The French Revolution and Human Rights: A Brief
Documentary History. Boston: Bedford Books, 1996.
Jones, Colin. The G reat Nation: France from Louis XV to Napoleon, 1715–1799.
New York: Columbia University Press, 2002.
Polasky, Janet. “The Legacy of the French Revolution.” In The Transformation of
Modern France: Essays in Honor of Gordon Wright, edited by William B.
Cohen. Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1997.
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. The Social Contract or Principles of Political Right, 1762.
Translated by H. J. Tozer. Hertfordshire, UK: Wordsworth Editions, 1998.
Royer, Jean-Pierre, et al. Histoire de la justice en France du XVIIIe siècle à nos
jours. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1995.
Schama, Simon. Citizens: A Chronicle of the French Revolution. New York:
Alfred A. Knopf, 1989.
Seligmann, Edmond. La justice en France pendant la Révolution (1789–92). Paris:
Plon-Nourrit, 1901.
Sewell, William H. A Rhetoric of Bourgeois Revolution: The Abbé Sieyes and What
Is the Third Estate? Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1994.
Stewart, John Hall. A Documentary Survey of the French Revolution. New York:
Macmillan, 1951.
Van Kley, Dale, ed. The French Idea of Freedom: The Old Regime and the
Declaration of Rights of 1789. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1994.
Woloch, Isser. The New Regime: Transformations of the French Civic Order,
1789–1820’s. New York: W. W. Norton, 1994.
Chapter 12
Foster, Nigel, and Satish Sule. German L egal System and Laws. 4th ed. Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2010.
Freund, Ernst. “The New German Civil Code.” Harvard Law Review 13, no. 8
(1900): 627–637.
German Civil Code, English-language edition provided by Langenscheidt
Translation Service. http://w ww.gesetze-im-internet.de/englisch_bgb
/englisch _bgb.html.
Gordley, James “Myths of the French Civil Code.” American Journal of Com-
parative Law 42, no. 3 (1994): 459–505.
Halpérin, Jean-Louis. “Le droit privé de la Révolution: Héritage législatif et
héritage idéologique.” Annales historiques de la Révolution française 328
(2002): 135–151.
John, Michael. Politics and the Law in Late Nineteenth-Century Germany: The
Origins of the Civil Code. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989.
Kozolchyk, Boris. Comparative Commercial Contracts: Law, Culture and
Economic Development. St. Paul, MN: West Academic, 2014.
Kroppenberg, Inge, and Nicolaus Linder. “Coding the Nation: Codification
History from a (Post-)Global Perspective.” In Entanglements in Legal
History: Conceptual Approaches, edited by Thomas Duve, 67–99. Frankfurt:
Max Planck Institute for European Legal History.
Levasseur, Alain A. “Code Napoleon or Code Portalis?” Tulane Law Review 43,
no.4 (1969): 762–774.
Martin, Xavier. Mythologie du Code Napoléon: Aux soubassements de la France
moderne. Bouère, France: Éditions Dominique Martin Morin, 2003.
Schwartz, Bernard, ed. The Code Napoleon and the Common-Law World: The
Sesquicentennial Lectures Delivered at the Law Center of New York University,
December 13–15, 1954. New York: NYU Press, 1956.
Smithers, William W. “The German Civil Code (Das Bürgerliche Gesetzbuch):
Sources—Preparation—Adoption.” American Law Register 50 no. 12 (1902):
685–717.
Vanderlinden, Jacques. Le Concept de code en Europe occidentale du XIIIe au
XIXe siècle: Essais de définition. Brussels: Université Libre de Bruxelles, 1967.
von Savigny, Friedrich Karl. Of the Vocation of Our Age for Legislation and
Jurisprudence, 1814. Translated by Abraham Hayward. London: Littlewood,
1831.
Whitman, James Q. The Legacy of Roman Law in the German Romantic Era:
Historical Vision and Legal Change. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press, 1990.
Wieacker, Franz. A History of Private Law in Europe with Particular Reference to
Germany, 1952. Translated by Tony Weir. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995.
274 Further Reading
Chapter 13
Banner, Stuart. “Written Law and Unwritten Norms in Colonial St. Louis.”
Law and History Review 14, no. 1 (1996): 33–40.
Batiza, Rodolfo. “The Louisiana Civil Code of 1808: Its Actual Sources and
Present Relevance.” Tulane Law Review 46, no. 4 (1971).
Billings, Warren M. “The Transfer of English Law to Virginia, 1606–50.” In The
Westward Enterprise: English Activities in Ireland, the Atlantic, and America,
1480–1650, edited by K. R. Andrews, N. P. Canny, and P. E. H. Hair,
215–244. Liverpool: Liverpool University Press, 1978.
Brown, Elizabeth Gaspar. “Legal Systems in Conflict: Orleans Territory,
1804–1812.” American Journal of Legal History 1, no. 1 (1957): 35–75.
Cook, Charles M. The American Codification Movement: A Study of Antebellum
Legal Reform. Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1981.
Curtis, Christopher M. “Codification in V irginia: Conway Robinson, John
Mercer Patton, and the Politics of Law Reform.” Virginia Magazine of
History and Biography 117, no. 2 (2009): 140–180.
Evans, Beverly D. “The Code Napoleon.” Georgia Historical Quarterly 6, no. 1
(1922): 28–34.
Farmer, Lindsay. “Reconstructing the English Codification Debate: The
Criminal Law Commissioners, 1833–45.” Law and History Review 18, no. 2
(2000): 397–426.
Fisch, William B. “The Dakota Civil Code: More Notes for an Uncelebrated
Centennial.” North Dakota Law Review 45 (1968): 9–55.
Herman, Shael. “The Fate and the F uture of Codification in America.” Amer-
ican Journal of Legal History 40, no. 4 (1996): 407–437.
Kilbourne, Richard Holcombe. A History of the Louisiana Civil Code: The
Formative Years, 1803–1839. Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University,
1987.
Kolsky, Elizabeth. “Codification and the Rule of Colonial Difference: Criminal
Procedure in British India.” Law and History Review 23, no. 3 (2005):
631–683.
Langum, David J. Law and Community on the Mexican California Frontier:
Anglo-American Expatriates and the Clash of L egal Traditions, 1821–1846.
Norman: University of Oklahoma Press, 1987.
Masferrer, Aniceto. “Defense of the Common Law against Postbellum Amer-
ican Codification: Reasonable and Fallacious Argumentation.” American
Journal of L
egal History 50, no. 4 (2008–2010): 355–430.
McKnight. Joseph W. “The Spanish Legacy to Texas Law.” American Journal of
Legal History 3, no. 3–4 (1959): 222–241, 299–323.
Further Reading 275
Miller, Perry. “The Common Law and Codification in Jacksonian Americ a.”
Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society 103, no. 3 (1959):
463–468.
Morriss, Andrew. “Codification and Right Answers.” Chicago-Kent Law Review
74, no. 2 (1999): 355–391.
Morrow, Clarence J. “Louisiana Blueprint: Civilian Codification and L egal
Method for State and Nation.” Tulane Law Review 17, no. 3 (1943):
351–415.
Palmer, Vernon Valentine. “The French Connection and the Spanish Percep-
tion: Historical Debates and Contemporary Evaluation of French Influence
on Louisiana Civil Law.” Louisiana Law Review 63, no. 4 (2003): 1067–1126.
Parise, Agustín. “Codification of the Law in Louisiana: Early Nineteenth-
Century Oscillation between Continental European and Common Law
Systems.” Tulane European and Civil Law Forum 27 (2012): 133–164.
Reinmann, Mathias. “The Historical School against Codification: Savigny,
Carter, and the Defeat of the New York Civil Code.” American Journal of
Comparative Law 37, no. 1 (1989): 95–119.
Ross, William E. “History of Virginia Codification.” Virginia Law Register 11,
no. 2 (1905): 79–101.
Schwartz, Bernard, ed. The Code Napoleon and the Common Law World: The
Sesquicentennial Lectures Delivered at the Law Center of New York University,
December 13–15, 1954. New York: NYU Press, 1956.
Weiss, Gunther A. “The Enchantment of Codification in the Common Law
World.” Yale Journal of International Law 25, no. 2 (2000): 435–532.
Wheeler, Charles B. “The Code Napoleon and Its Framers.” American Bar
Association Journal 10, no. 3 (1924): 202–206.
Witt, John Fabian. “The King and the Dean: Melvin Belli, Roscoe Pound and
the Common Law Nation.” In Patriots and Cosmopolitans: Hidden Histories
of American Law, 211–278. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 2007.
Young, Edwin W. “The Adoption of the Common Law in California.” Amer-
ican Journal of Legal History 4, no. 4 (1960): 355–363.
Epilogue
More than with any other of my works in the past, I am conscious that this book
was made possible by the generosity, friendship, and collegiality of numerous
individuals who agreed to read, patiently and closely, the various chapters and
gave me extremely wise, practical, informed, and detailed advice. I would not
have dared to publish it without their help. Sincere, heartfelt, and deep kudos
are due to Clifford Ando, David Bell, Charles Donahue, Andrew Fitzmaurice,
Ruby Gropas, Daniel Hulsebosch, Richard Hyland, Elizabeth Kamali, Dennis P.
Kehoe, Amalia Kessler, Bruce Mann, Tom McGinn, Miguel Moura e Silva, Vlad
Perju, Jack N. Rakove, Richard J. Ross, and Simon Teuscher. Special thanks to
David J. Seipp, who not only read my text but also answered my multiple ques-
tions. I am particularly indebted to António Manuel Hespanha, who, since my
graduate-student days in Paris and over the last twenty-five years, has been an
informal mentor and a true friend. There are endless ways in which Hespanha’s
scholarship has informed, affected, and intersected with mine. This book is but
one. I am also grateful to the Radcliffe Institute for Advanced Study at Harvard
University, which has allowed me to have the time and resources to write this
book. Last but not least, I would like to thank Yuval Erlich for all these years,
which have transformed my life into a wonderful ongoing adventure. Patiently
hearing too much about the past and lightly laughing over my obsessions, during
the last thirty years, besides being my husband and best friend, Yuval has be-
come my closest and most attentive reader. Each time I write a book I promise to
him that it w
ill be my last. Maybe this time I will comply.
279
Index
Napoleonic Code and, 209; natural law Parliament, European, 232, 233, 234, 237,
and, 201, 202 240
National Conference of Commissioners partnership, 22, 110, 220
on Uniform State Law, 229, 242 peasants, 66, 71, 91
natural law, 8, 152, 172; age of revolution “personal law,” 52, 54
and, 163–164, 171; French Revolution Petition of Rights (1628), 148
and, 187, 199, 201–202, 252n2 (ch. 11); pleading, 98–99, 102, 103, 106, 114, 228
ius gentium (law of nations) and, Poland, 42, 80, 211, 248n10
153–154, 158, 159–160, 179–180; ius Pollock, Frederick, 220
naturale in Roman law, 27; as reign of pontifices (priests), 15, 17, 245n2
self-evident truth, 159–163 popes / papacy, 42, 49, 69, 77, 79, 119;
natural rights, 162–163, 200, 202 desire for primacy, 76; false papal
Negotiable Instruments Law (1882), 229 decrees, 49–50; “Inter Caetera” bull
Netherlands, 42, 124, 159–160; in (1493), 154–155, 156; ordo iudiciarius and,
Carolingian Empire, 67; in ECSC and 85; universities and, 80
EEC, 231; in Eurozone, 254n6; in Portalis, Jean-Étienne, 209–210
Frankish empire, 59; French law codes Portugal, 80, 152, 155; in European
in, 211; French Revolution opposed by, Community, 232; in Eurozone, 254n6;
208; ius commune in, 248n10; in French Revolution opposed by, 208; ius
“Schengen area,” 254n5 commune in, 248n10
New York, codification of law in, 223, praetors, 16–17, 20, 25, 115; Christian
225–228 bishops fashioned a fter, 40; edicts and,
nobility, types of, 81, 248n4 19, 26; jurists and, 21; legal actions as
“formulas” and, 18; praetor peregrinus,
obligations, 22, 23, 54, 60, 65, 215 27, 153, 245n4
omission (failure to do the right t hing), 82 precedent, 149–150
“On Christian Liberty” (Luther), 123 Proculians, 24
On the Law of War (Gentili), 159 property law, 31, 111
orality / oral traditions, 15, 52, 54, 130, 146 property rights, 83, 84, 175, 189
oratio principis, 25 Protestant Reformation, 95, 119,
ordeal, 55, 56, 85, 247n4 (ch. 3) 246nn3–4; in England, 131, 144;
ordo iudiciarius (inquisitorial process), humanism and, 123–124; ius commune
56, 85 ruptured by, 122–123; reinvention of
Orthodox Christian Church, 32, 247n7 natural law and, 161
public law, 76
Pandect-Science, 213, 214 Pufendorf, Samuel von, 193
Papinian, 23, 246n7
parlement, France, 197–199 Quadripartitus, 94
Parliament, English, 107, 111, 133, 135, 145,
173; American colonies and, 167, 174, reason, 8, 23, 163, 199, 201, 208, 241
181, 203; codification of law and, 219, “reason of state,” 196
220, 221, 222; common law and, 177; remedies, 54, 93, 94; in common law and
constitutional system and, 170; English equity, 98, 99, 100, 101–102, 108, 109,
civil war and, 132; as guardian of 112, 115, 132, 230, 237; in Roman law 14,
customary law, 148–150; Magna Carta 15, 17, 19–20
and, 146; statutory law and, 218 Renaissance, 75, 120
288 Index