John Dewey Pragmatism
John Dewey Pragmatism
John Dewey Pragmatism
A Pragmatist Perspective
Antti Gronow
University of Helsinki
The article discusses the pragmatist view of social institutions which underscores
that institutions are based on habitual action. That habits can be shared is
sometimes thought to be a problematic assumption but I argue that sharing is the
default setting in the case of habits as well. These ideas, which were first presented
by so-called classical pragmatists, also get support from contemporary research
related to the postulation of so-called common ground. I also discuss Thorstein
Veblen’s theory of institutions and some of the empirical implications of the insights
of pragmatist social theory.
The concept of pragmatism has been used in such diverse settings that it can
cause one to question “whether the label serves any real purpose” (Haack 2004,
5). Despite this diversity, there are certain philosophical principles shared by many
(if not most) pragmatists. The philosophical “push” behind pragmatism was a
realisation that knowledge has no certain foundations but that this was no reason
for despair. This realisation was originally a reaction against the Cartesian quest
for solid foundations in a situation of imagined “paper doubt”. This phrase, originally
used by C. S. Peirce, refers to a situation imagined by Descartes where he
supposedly questioned all of his beliefs at once. In Peirce’s view, all-encompassing
doubt is not feasible (nothing good will come out of it) or even possible (one cannot
doubt all of one’s beliefs). In its place, he postulated that there are real situations of
uncertainty and one can never be certain that the present beliefs and habits one
happens to hold rest on solid, infallible foundations. In fact, such foundations do
not exist because there is always the possibility of encountering novel and changed
situations, which can cause doubt because our habits and beliefs do not meet the
changed requirements of those situations.
1 See also Misak’s (2000) discussion of the epistemological arguments for democracy offered by
pragmatists.
27
The Habits of Consumption
whereas Dewey’s ideas on habitual action and its relation with the environment are
fruitful. Despite the social science ideas of Mead and Dewey, pragmatism and
sociology have had an uneasy relationship. Often viewed as purely an American
enterprise, pragmatism has sometimes been met with a European shrug. However,
there are famous exceptions. Èmile Durkheim, one of the undisputed fathers of
sociology, found pragmatism a challenge to the tradition of Western rationalism.
According to him, the acceptance of “the form of irrationalism represented by
pragmatism” would mean that “the whole French mind would have to be radically
changed” (Durkheim 1983, 1). He also argued that pragmatism “claims to explain
truth psychologically and subjectively” (ibid., 67). Durkheim’s interpretation derived
from seeing pragmatism as a representative of utilitarian thought; thus, pragmatism
presumably derives truth from mere psychological satisfaction. This is a crude
caricature of most forms of pragmatism. As Joas (1993, 59-60) – a major figure
in the renaissance of pragmatism – argues, “pragmatism is above all a reflection
on the fact that the subject is embedded in praxis and sociality prior to any form
of conscious intentionality of action.” Accordingly, our embedding in practical and
social relations is the main focus here, not explaining truth psychologically. In
pragmatism, truth is rather about facing up to the problems of action in all of their
social and material facets. Furthermore, Durkheim characterized pragmatism as a
monism of action, that is, as a denial of conscious rationality. According to Joas,
this characterization actually characterises behaviourism rather than pragmatism.
Indeed, pragmatism has never denied that there is a place for conscious, reflexive
thought. This place, however, is not to be found outside of action, as I explain in
the next section. Joas concludes his verdict on Durkheim’s arguments by saying
that they are based on “the false Cartesian alternative of action as purely physical
movement versus thought as a purely mental construct” (ibid., 71).
Habits in Pragmatism
In social theory, the concept of habit can be used to discuss at least two interrelated
dilemmas: the relationship between volition and action or the relationship between
action and social structures. The first question is addressed by Erkki Kilpinen
in this volume and will not be discussed at length here. However, it is worth
pointing out that, as a general philosophical current, pragmatism stresses the
practical results of our beliefs. The general lesson of pragmatism is a lesson on
action theory and the way in which action and rationality present themselves in
self-correcting situations of doubt. The issue of self-corrective rationality refers
to reflecting on one’s reactions to environmental stimuli as a way to correct these
reactions if they lead to problems. As Joas (1993, 19) argues, for pragmatists truth
“no longer expresses a correct representation of reality in cognition, which can be
conceived of using the metaphor of a copy; rather, it expresses an increase of the
power to act in relation to an environment” – which is potentially a source of action
28
Gronow
problems. This does not mean that the idea of a copy would be lost, for, as William
James (1975, 102; emphasis added) argues, “To copy a reality is, indeed, one very
important way of agreeing with it, but it is far from essential. The essential thing is
the process of being guided.” Thus, mental imagery is in the business of guiding our
conduct, not in copying it from some perspective that would be totally independent
of what we are doing (broadly speaking). To many non-philosophers this issue
can seem trivial. However, it has far-reaching implications: we encounter the world
through our bodily experience and not only at the level of language, for example.
That is why habitual dispositions do much of the explaining in pragmatism. Habits
are often taken to be mere restrictive factors (e.g., of rational action) but this need
not be the case because one can also see them as “positive agencies.” “The more
numerous our habits the wider the field of possible observation and foretelling,” as
Dewey (2002, 175) argued. This means that habits enable different lines of conduct,
even lifestyles or “careers,” when habits couple themselves with other habits.
2 The extent of such constitution through active engagement is a factor which is not constant.
Thus, in some situations there can be more of such constitution than in others.
29
The Habits of Consumption
Habits and their overt manifestations are often taken to be the same thing.
However, such alignment can be problematic because, as Hodgson (2006) argues,
the implication is that habits cease to exist if no overt activity is visible. Do habits
simply disappear when they are not manifest? This conclusion would amount to a
denial of the continuity of action – and continuity of action is what habits are about.
Thus, habits do not refer to discrete acts but to attitudes or dispositions to act in
a specific fashion: “The essence of habit is an acquired predisposition to ways
or modes of response, not to particular acts except as, under special conditions,
these express a way of behaving” (Dewey 2002, 42). Habits are thus general “policy
recommendations” rather than individual acts (cf. Joas & Kilpinen 2006).
The pragmatist description of action does not deny reflexivity its important role
but it situates it in concrete action situations. This is why it can be called situated
creativity (an expression used by Joas 1996). One can also argue that creativity
is a phase of action, albeit a very important one. To use concepts proposed by
Elder-Vass (2007, 341), one can distinguish between a decision-taking phase and
an action-implementing phase. Reflexivity is especially, if not exclusively, related
to the former phase, and thus it is not present at all times. However, I would hasten
to add that even this decision-taking phase is a process situated within action, not
something external to it. Therefore, both of these phases are, strictly speaking,
action-implementing. In reading Dewey, one gets the impression that he sometimes
30
Gronow
overlooks the role that anticipating the possibilities for action plays in reflection,
since he tends to emphasize the need for habit-change only when habits are facing
acute problems. Anticipating problems, and not only waiting for problems to come
about, surely is a central part of our reflective thought processes. Furthermore, in
situations of current action problems, the failure of habits does not automatically
and mechanically lead to novel solutions. Rather, this process is always mediated
through images of the future consequences of possible action scenarios. And at
any moment, the attempted resolution can also fail. The term “crisis” can lead one
to think only of major turning points in life or major societal changes (e.g. disasters,
wars). Naturally, these major events are included in the category of a crisis, but
action also encounters obstacles in daily life that are much more mundane. These
obstacles can involve, for example, disagreements with other actors and ensuing
negotiations with them, or new work tasks with new responsibilities. If nothing else
changes, then our “inner environment” poses challenges through the aging and
inevitable decay of our bodies. Conflicts between habits and their environments
are always more or less present due also to the multiple stimuli that we encounter.
These stimuli are not only environmental, but they also originate in the associations
that our minds formulate.
The idea that we mainly adopt a reflexive attitude in relation to action crises can
sound too instrumental to those ears not accustomed to using action as their starting
point. What about daydreaming and mental associations? These phenomena are
naturally real enough, as anyone who has ever had a sleepless night will testify; how
to stop oneself from thinking, that is the question! Veblen used the concept of idle
curiosity to refer to the natural tendency to be interested in what happens around
us, without necessarily having any instrumental aims. However, pure fantasy will
not get us very far and thus it has to join hands with our existing habits. Even the
mental associations of a sleepless night are likely to be a nuisance when some
non-habitual task is imminent (e.g. problems with a relationship, a demanding
project). Pragmatism does not present a functionalistic account of structures (more
on this issue later), but it does imply a somewhat functionalistic account of human
deliberation: habits are adaptations in relation to the environment, and conscious
deliberation mainly arises when these adaptations do not work for some reason.
Owing to this adaptive character, habits are often self-perpetuating once they have
been constituted. For example, habits affect our perceptual awareness by selecting
familiar stimuli and this is why one can be immune to stimuli that contradict existing
habits. Does this lead one to conclude that habits are determinants of action? For
some purposes such wording might be acceptable but in general one can argue,
as I mentioned, that habits should be perceived as phases of action rather than
its determinants. Saying that someone did something as a matter of habit can
naturally act as an explanation in some specific case. However, there are two
reasons for cautioning against a view of habits as determinants of action. First,
pragmatists often emphasize the processual nature of action: action is a process
31
The Habits of Consumption
in which habits and deliberations take turns. Second, human beings – and other
animals, one might add – are always active. Thus, there are no passive states of
inactivity but rather different kinds of action. According to Shilling (2008, 12), a
consequence of this active view is that instead of explaining the initiation of action,
one should focus on “the characteristics of how people act in particular situations.”
One of the most thorough reviews of the uses of the concept of habit in
sociology has been presented by Camic (1986). According to his analysis, one
can distinguish a continuum of different kinds of habits. On the lower levels of this
continuum, one finds dispositions to perform elementary and specific activities,
whereas on the upper reaches habit refers to a broader conduct of life or to the
idea of character (ibid., 1045-1046). Even though Camic (1988, 958) claims that
Meadian uses of the term lie on the lower levels, not all have agreed. Baldwin
(1988) argues that pragmatists also think of habits in broader ways. In this broader
sense, “[c]omplex chains of activity may be based on organized sets of habits”
(ibid., 955). For example, to state the matter in Meadian parlance, the social
attitudes of the environment and our associations and responses towards this
environment can be integrated in a generalised other (cf. Camic’s broad sense
of habits). This integrated unity is not a matter-of-course but rather something to
strive for. Even though Baldwin’s assessment that pragmatists also view habits in
the broader conduct-of-life-perspective is not incorrect, it has to be admitted that
this perspective is underdeveloped in pragmatist social theory and needs more
focus in the future.
Camic’s (1986) diagnosis for the loss of “habit” from the tool-kit of sociology
had to do with a general aversion to behaviourism. There are undoubtedly some
affinities between behaviourism and pragmatism. Both take seriously the argument
that action matters and that there are stimuli in our environments. However, these
thought currents are not the same thing. For pragmatists, stimuli relate to what we
are doing and have been doing. For example, perceptions are very selective in the
sense that we often pick out those features of the environment that we expect to
find. Therefore the relationship between stimuli and reactions is not as mechanical
as it is for behaviourists. Rather, the “stimulus and response reciprocally affect one
another” (Cook 2006, 70). Or, as Mead (1925, 270) argued, “The percept is relative
to the perceiving individual, but relative to his active interest, not relative in the
sense that its content is a state of his consciousness.” Thus, a justifiable aversion
to behaviourism is not an argument against pragmatism.
32
Gronow
pragmatists (especially Mead and Dewey) undoubtedly underscore the way in which
habitualised action is the key to social reproduction. However, Bourdieu’s concept
of habitus is related to socioeconomic factors, whereas pragmatists discuss issues
of habituality in general. Analysing power relations, socioeconomic factors and
social differentiation is certainly one of the main concerns of social theory and
sociology. Thus, in the sociological context pragmatist ideas could, and should,
be enriched with notions of power and socioeconomic differences. Nevertheless,
there is a case to be made for a general discussion of habits as well because not
all habits are related to socioeconomic divisions. Many of them naturally have such
a basis, but it should be investigated empirically, and not decided on the level of
theory, whether this is true in the case of a particular habit.3
Sharing habits?
For social scientists, one of the most interesting questions of the phenomenon of
habituality is the way in which habits are related to social entities. It is easy to see
habits as individual phenomena, a part of our action. But if habits are in essence
related individual action, in what sense can they be shared? Turner (1994) has
argued that many practice theories are not capable of explaining how practices are
shared and this same critique can be made in relation to theories of habits. If habit
is a property of an individual – that is, it is in his or her action – then it surely seems
somewhat paradoxical to speak of sharing habits. Surely one cannot share one’s
action: if you and I were to go hiking together, you still would not be walking in my
shoes! According to Kilpinen (2009, 113), however, this problem only arises if we
view practices and habits as some sort of baggage or possessions to carry around:
“Turner’s idea about tradition-cum-habit being something that an individual carries
with oneself and then transmits – like a father gives an inherited gold watch to his
son – is not necessarily a defining characteristic of traditions.” Kilpinen argues
that rather than viewing practices and habits according to the logic of possessive
individualism (as something we could literally possess) we are better off if we follow
a so-called participatory notion. Habits need not be exactly the same for everyone
involved; a “‘working agreement’ about basics is all that is needed” (ibid.).
Thus, in Kilpinen’s view, habits are shared in that they allow for participation in
common activities. This does not necessitate that habits be completely identical in
every detail of their execution. For example, one can say that people are habitually
predisposed to shake hands with certain kinds of people, with strangers met in
formal occasions, for example, without necessarily shaking hands with the same
particular people. In addition to offering an explanation for the way in which habits
3 For a more thorough discussion of the relationship between the ideas of pragmatists and those
of Bourdieu, see Ostrow (1990), Aboulafia (1999), Colapietro (2004) and Gronow (2011; ch. 4).
33
The Habits of Consumption
are shared, such a view has the advantage that it leaves room for individual
interpretation: it does not make the unconvincing claim that units of cultural
reproduction – habits – are monolithic and shared by all of those living within a
certain cultural sphere. Rather than falling for such an essentialist view of culture,
using the concept of habit points to seeing things in terms of populations: there is
variation between habits (even related habits) and if they are shared, this is to the
extent that they encourage participation in common activities. This is somewhat
tangential but evolutionary biology states that particular individuals belong to the
same species if they can reproduce and breed offspring.4 Analogously one could
argue that two people share a habit if they are capable of participating in the same
action process.
However, one can still wonder what the mechanism behind sharing habits is
even if they are shared in such a participatory manner. People certainly participate
in common activities – but how do we know that these activities are based on
common habits? One possible answer is that habits are shared in the same manner
that all things human are shared: through taking the attitudes of others towards our
common environment. Thus, there are no special mechanisms related particularly
to sharing habits. And even more importantly, what is shared is not a particular
action but a disposition to do so. Of the classical pragmatists, G. H. Mead presented
a theory of intersubjectivity (see Gronow 2008a) or primary sociality (Joas 1996).
Mead postulated that as children develop psychologically, they gradually learn to
anticipate the reactions of other people towards their own action. This is what he
meant by the expression “taking the attitudes of the other towards oneself.” This
indicates that the sharing of habits is a general social psychological process in
which one anticipates the attitudes or dispositions (i.e., habits) of others and acts
accordingly. This anticipation is also closely related to the environments of action,
which are often manifestations of social institutions. For example, having been to
a hospital before, one anticipates certain responses from the people encountered
there and acts as a patient (with other patients) without anyone explicitly advising
us on the moral career of a patient.
34
Gronow
So far so good – but what does this have to do with the problem of sharing
habits? What I am trying to show is that sharing all sorts of things in and through
on-going participation in communal action is something that human beings do by
default. Graeber (2011, ch. 5) has gone so far as to argue that human interaction
is based on the well-known communistic principle “from each according to their
abilities, to each according to their needs”. This does not mean that we would
be communists in all of our economic relations (these relations actually are, in
Graeber’s analysis, often based on reciprocal exchange and hierarchies). It simply
points to the fact that we often take pleasure in sharing things (information, food etc.)
without taking any account of the things being shared. This is the case especially
with family and friends but to a certain extent with other people as well. To return
to my main argument, we interpret the meaning of social situations by what we
postulate to be the common ground in each situation. This is how habits are shared
5 However, there are plenty of examples of people trying to postulate explicit and binding collective
intentions. For example, just think of social movements and the way in which their representatives
try to state matters in terms of what “they” want etc. On collective intentions from a somewhat
controversial philosophical perspective, see Searle (1995).
35
The Habits of Consumption
To conclude this section I offer some brief examples of empirical work relying
on the notion of habit. Routines are probably the most studied aspect in relation
to habits but they are often approached from a psychological perspective (see,
e.g., Wood et al. 2002). Identifying habits with routines, however, faces the danger
of making habits too thing-like. After all, the pragmatist way of using the concept
emphasizes the processual character of habits and the way in which they interact
and are intertwined with conscious control. Nevertheless, studying habits as
routines can be done if it is done with caution and bearing in mind that even routines
are rarely mindless. For example, Katainen (forthcoming) has studied smoking and
manual work. She argues that the smoking habits of manual workers is so deeply
engrained because it gives them a certain sense of autonomy in relation to their
relatively constrained work. Pragmatism can also draw one’s attention to crises of
habits in different phases of people’s life-course. For instance, using a Meadian
framework, Ketokivi (2008) has studied the reorganization of family relationships
as a biographical crisis. Another, related theme, is to pursue the pragmatist roots
of ethnomethodology since the latter points out that social order is creatively
maintained in everyday life (Emirbayer & Maynard 2011). Such research could also
be combined with research into the importance of the common ground conducted
in cognitive science (Tomasello 2008). The common ground is, after all, usually
taken for granted and a phenomenon intertwined with habituality. In addition, the
relationship between socioeconomic habits (Bourdieu’s concept of habitus) and
more general habits is a theme that should be studied empirically (see Gronow
2011, 117-118).
6 In addition, not everyone is equally capable of grasping the common ground. For example,
people diagnosed with autism probably have major problems in this regard.
36
Gronow
So far I have mainly discussed the nature of habits in general and the way in
which they are shared. Next I will argue that shared, social habits are one of the
keys in understanding the enduring aspects of social reality – that is, institutions.
To do so, I introduce some of the ideas of Thorstein Veblen, who is the founding
father of so-called institutional economics.7 Economists who worked in the U.S.
in the first half of the twentieth century and emphasized the role of institutions are
often grouped under the label Old Institutionalism. Veblen was the main theoretical
inspiration behind this school. Besides pragmatism, he was also influenced by
evolutionary theory and instinct psychology (Hodgson 2004). Veblen was highly
critical of many presuppositions in economics. His main criticisms had to do with
the hedonistic conception of the individual, the atomistic conception of society, and
the presupposing of a false role for causality and teleology in explaining individual
action and social processes (Kilpinen 2000). These criticisms help us to understand
Veblen’s own habitual view of institutions.
For many economists, the human being is an inactive being who acts only when
a negative or a positive stimulus drives him or her to do so (Veblen 2002, 73-74).
According to Veblen, the problem with this view is not the postulation of wrong
motives for action, but the supposition that action as such needs any motives at
all. In line with the pragmatist action theory introduced above, Veblen thought
that motives for action do not precede action but rather enter the scene in the
middle of ongoing action processes, or habits. Because of their focus on discrete
acts, “neoclassical economists do not in fact analyze action” (ibid., 78). Second,
methodological individualism easily leads to an atomistic conception of society
whereby society is understood merely as the sum of independent individuals
(ibid., 139). In contrast to some later sociological ideas (Talcott Parsons being an
example), the enrichment of neoclassical action theory with the normative context
is not enough because it leaves the underlying view of action untouched. Third,
neoclassical economics denies the continuity and teleology of action with the
argument that every choice situation is a discrete event. Structures or institutions,
as Veblen called them, however, are cumulative causal processes and do not
have any teleology in and of themselves. Invisible hands or other such ahistorical
teleological mechanisms are in fact animistic remnants in Veblen’s discussion.
7 See, for example, the recent collection of Veblen’s writings edited by Camic and Hodgson
(Veblen 2011).
37
The Habits of Consumption
Hodgson’s (2006, 138) definition for institutions says that they are “systems
of established and prevalent social rules that structure social interactions.” He
also emphasises that rules should be understood as dispositions. I would hasten
to add, however, that if habits are the mechanism through which institutions are
maintained, then the important issue has to do with dispositions instead of rules.
Rules are intimately related to dispositions but dispositions can be present without
proper rules behind them. Of course one can then argue, as Hodgson does, that
institutions are, at least in principle, codifiable as rules. This is indeed true, but in
many cases any codification only takes place after established habits have been
put into question. If one defines institutions through rules, this leads too easily into
38
Gronow
Naturally not all dispositions are related to institutions, but only those are that
are sufficiently established and exhibit temporal constancy. An institution that is
completely transformed overnight simply is not the same institution anymore. In
addition, institution-related dispositions are thus also prevalent; they are social
ways of responding to environmental cues and not just individual habits. It would
also be possible to distinguish the origin of institutions and the way in which they are
maintained once in place. This distinction can be useful for analytic purposes but in
many cases it can be difficult to discern the exact places and dates of institutional
origin. The more informal an institution is, the more obscure its origin; it is simply
what the people in question feel they (and possible their ancestors) have always
done (although they have not necessarily done so). Shared dispositions are the
reason why one engages habitually, without thinking twice, in joint activities with
others. This presents us with a self-reinforcing cycle: sharing a disposition and
39
The Habits of Consumption
being proficient in doing something makes it easy to take the habit in question for
granted. Breaking this cycle leads to unpleasant cognitive dissonance.
Conclusion
My intention has been to show that the pragmatist concept of habit has relevance
for discussions on the nature of social reproduction, or, more specifically, on
the nature of institutions. Whether habits can be shared is an issue that has
perplexed some previous commentators. These commentators have shared (no
pun intended) an implicit notion of what sharing habits means; it has been a notion
of possessive individualism – habits are shared like things or they are not shared
at all. These commentators also often presume that we are first and foremost
individuals doomed to our individual subjectivity. Recent research by Tomasello
points towards a participatory notion of intersubjectivity, which indicates that acting
together, and interpreting the action of other people based on the common ground,
are the default setting of human beings. This setting is also the mechanism for
sharing habits as dispositions. As Mead and other classical pragmatists argued,
meaning is about shared action tendencies, and if this is the case with meaning
in general, then habits are not that much different – they are not a special case
in need of an explanation as to how their sharing comes about. However, if one
wants to analyse some specific habit and its diffusion across some population from
a social network perspective, for example, then it can be useful to enquire into the
more detailed mechanisms that are responsible for its diffusion.8
8 Social network research has pointed out that there can be different mechanisms behind the
diffusion of different kinds of things (Borgatti 2005).
40
Gronow
Pragmatism certainly is not the only relevant perspective out there, nor is it a
theory of everything. For example, in relation to institutions one can argue that there
are also regulative (legalistic rules), normative, discursive (see Gronow 2008b) and
material aspects of institutions. To what extent these other perspectives deserve
a hearing depends on the research question at hand. One criticism of pragmatism
has to do with the general nature of its theory of action; for some, it can seem too
general, even so general as to exemplify the perspective known as philosophical
anthropology. This criticism has some relevance but it sidesteps the fact that all
empirical operationalizations have to be made from some theoretical or philosophical
perspective. Pragmatism offers one such perspective – and it has advantages in
relation to competing paradigms. One major advantage is that it makes possible a
dialogue between the social and the natural sciences (Lyng and Franks 2002) as
it draws our attention to the fact that bodily involvement with and in the world sets
“transactional limits” (i.e., what can be done) to processes of ideational or discursive
construction (Franks 2003, 616). After the so-called cultural turn some sociologists
have seen these limits as more malleable and more arbitrary than they actually are.
Another, related benefit, has to do with pragmatism’s take on action as constitutive
of social structures rather than antithetical to them (irrespective of whether one
wants to conceptualise structures as institutions – as I have done following Veblen
– or not). It is a particular kind of action, habitual action, in which the seeds of
structuration inhere. However, more precise definitions of social structures and
institutions are sometimes called for, especially if one wants to operationalize these
concepts empirically.
41
The Habits of Consumption
References
42
Gronow
43
The Habits of Consumption
Veblen, T. 2002 (1919). The Place of Science in Modern Civilization and Other Essays. New
Brunswick and London: Transaction Publishers.
Veblen, T. 2011. Essential Writings of Thorstein Veblen. Edited by C. Camic and G. M. Hodgson.
London & New York: Routledge.
Wood, W., J. M. Quinn & D. A. Kashy 2002. Habits in Everyday Life: Thought, Emotion, and
Action. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 83, 1281–1297.
44